the role of testimony and testimonial analysis in human rights advocacy and research' in state...

33
Patel, Ian (2012) 'The Role of Testimony and Testimonial Analysis in Human Rights Advocacy and Research' in State Crime: Journal of the International State Crime Initiative, London, Pluto Press, 1.2, 2012. 1 THE ROLE OF TESTIMONY AND TESTIMONIAL ANALYSIS IN HUMAN RIGHTS ADVOCACY AND RESEARCH Ian Patel Ian Patel is a Postdoctoral Research Fellow in the School of Law, King’s College London. Abstract: This article addresses the prominence of testimony evidence in the practice and theory of human rights. It examines the use of testimony in legal mechanisms, by international advocacy organizations, and in academic human rights research. It reflects on the reasons behind the prominence of testimony, treating it as a source of evidence, an advocacy tool, and a trope within human rights discourse. This article places testimony in political context, and explores the political implications of the fact that the narrative accounts of victims of state crime are utilized by international advocates/experts as a primary source of evidence. As an original theoretical discussion, this article critiques what it perceives to be the dominant epistemology of testimony in a human rights context. It concludes that the meaning and uses of testimony in a human rights context are curated by international experts, a trend that risks the disenfranchisement of witnesses from the meaning and uses to which their testimony is assigned. Keywords: testimony; selfnarration; liberalism; research methods; victim representation; sources of evidence

Upload: ian-patel

Post on 05-Aug-2015

150 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

DESCRIPTION

Abstract: This article addresses the prominence of testimony evidence in the practice and theory of human rights. It examines the use of testimony in legal mechanisms, by international advocacy organizations, and in academic human rights research. It reflects on the reasons behind the prominence of testimony, treating it as a source of evidence, an advocacy tool, and a trope within human rights discourse. This article places testimony in political context, and explores the political implications of the fact that the narrative accounts of victims of state crime are utilized by international advocates/experts as a primary source of evidence. An original theoretical discussion, this article critiques what it perceives to be the dominant epistemology of testimony in a human rights context. It concludes that the meaning and uses of testimony in a human rights context are curated by international experts, a trend that risks the disenfranchisement of witnesses from the meaning and uses to which their testimony is assigned. Keywords: testimony; self-narration; liberalism; research methods; victim representation; sources of evidence

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: The Role of Testimony and Testimonial Analysis in Human Rights Advocacy and Research' in State Crime: Journal of the International State Crime Initiative, Pluto Press, 1.2, Autumn

Patel,  Ian  (2012)  'The  Role  of  Testimony  and  Testimonial  Analysis  in  Human  Rights  Advocacy  and  Research'  in  State  Crime:  Journal  of  the  International  State  Crime  

Initiative,  London,  Pluto  Press,  1.2,  2012.    

  1  

THE ROLE OF TESTIMONY AND

TESTIMONIAL ANALYSIS IN

HUMAN RIGHTS ADVOCACY

AND RESEARCH Ian  Patel  

 

 

Ian  Patel  is  a  Postdoctoral  Research  Fellow  in  the  School  of  Law,  King’s  College  London.  

 

 

Abstract:  This  article  addresses  the  prominence  of  testimony  evidence  in  the  practice  and  theory  of  human  rights.  It  examines  the  use  of  testimony  in  legal  mechanisms,  by  international  advocacy  organizations,  and  in  academic  human  rights  research.  It  reflects  on  the  reasons  behind  the  prominence  of  testimony,  treating  it  as  a  source  of  evidence,  an  advocacy  tool,  and  a  trope  within  human  rights  discourse.  This  article  places  testimony  in  political  context,  and  explores  the  political  implications  of  the  fact  that  the  narrative  accounts  of  victims  of  state  crime  are  utilized  by  international  advocates/experts  as  a  primary  source  of  evidence.  As  an  original  theoretical  discussion,  this  article  critiques  what  it  perceives  to  be  the  dominant  epistemology  of  testimony  in  a  human  rights  context.  It  concludes  that  the  meaning  and  uses  of  testimony  in  a  human  rights  context  are  curated  by  international  experts,  a  trend  that  risks  the  disenfranchisement  of  witnesses  from  the  meaning  and  uses  to  which  their  testimony  is  assigned.  

 

Keywords:  testimony;  self-­‐narration;  liberalism;  research  methods;  victim  representation;  sources  of  evidence  

 

 

Page 2: The Role of Testimony and Testimonial Analysis in Human Rights Advocacy and Research' in State Crime: Journal of the International State Crime Initiative, Pluto Press, 1.2, Autumn

Patel,  Ian  (2012)  'The  Role  of  Testimony  and  Testimonial  Analysis  in  Human  Rights  Advocacy  and  Research'  in  State  Crime:  Journal  of  the  International  State  Crime  

Initiative,  London,  Pluto  Press,  1.2,  2012.    

  2  

 

 

Introduction:  Testimony  As  Narrative  Research  Evidence    

In  the  past  thirty  years,  narrative-­‐based  research  –  that  is  to  say,  research  whose  primary  empirical  data  is  comprised  of  narrative(s)  –  has  risen  to  prominence  in  a  number  of  fields.  This  has  been  identified  as  a  “narrative  turn”  in  the  social  sciences.  More  precisely,  (most)  narrative  research  draws  on  the  accounts  of  specific  individuals  which  are  referred  to  generically  in  terms  such  as  self-­‐narration,  life  history,  autobiographical  narration,  biographical  analysis,  oral  history,  and  testimony.1  

In  the  field  of  human  rights  research  and  advocacy,  narrative-­‐based  documentary  evidence  and  testimony  in  general  have  also  increasingly  been  accorded  value.2  This  may  seem  a  rather  truistic  point  to  make.  From  the  abolitionist  movement  onwards,  human  rights  campaigns  have  always  relied  on  publicity,  and  have  therefore  circulated  eyewitness  testimony  as  a  device  to  immediately  arrest  the  attention  of  the  reader  or  viewer.3  We  all  know  –  equally  –  the  empirical  force  behind  testimony  as  it  registers  in  our  consciousness.  Like  seeing,  hearing  is  believing.  Yet  in  what  follows  I  will  suggest  that  the  role  of  testimony  in  the  context  of  human  rights  goes  far  beyond  a  visual  technological  device  to  grab  people’s  attention.  Richard  Rorty  famously  observed  that  rights  claims  are  made  at  an  idiomatic  level  as  “sad  and  sentimental  stories”  (Rorty  2003:  122).  I  want  to  explore  the  implications  of  Rorty’s  statement  here.  

Although  the  demand  for  measureable  outcomes  in  human  rights  initiatives  has  led  to  the  packaging  of  data  into  easily  digested  statistical  tables,  there  has  also  been  a  reliance  on  testimony  as  a  mainstay  in  sourcing  evidence.  This  has  led  Leigh  Payne  to  ask  whether  the  field  of  human  rights  is  experiencing  a  surfeit  of  stories,  a  “stockpiling”  of  testimony.4  There  are  of  course  different  types  of  testimony  evidence.  Legal  testimony  in  an  international  criminal  trial  is  different  to  an  instance  of  common  law  confession  evidence;  a  semi-­‐structured  interview  with  a  survivor  of  state  violence  is                                                                                                                            

1  In  this  article  I  adopt  the  term  “self-­‐narration”  over  these  variations.  This  is  not  because  I  believe  that  first-­‐person  accounts  present  a  coherent  “self”.  Rather,  I  favour  self-­‐narration  because  it  alludes  to  an  underlying  assumption  in  most  narrative  research  that  a  first-­‐person  account  provides  valuable  insight  into  that  person’s  experiential  realities.  Since  narrative  accounts  are  often  framed  by  a  demand  for  coherent  “self”-­‐presentation,  “self-­‐narration”  is  a  choice  term  capturing  the  demand  for  narrative  coherence  and  the  experiential  reality  supposedly  identifiable  in  narration.    2  By  “human  rights  advocacy”  I  am  referring  particularly  to  international  NGO  networks  and  their  attendant  campaigns,  reports  and  media  resources.  By  “human  rights  research”  I  am  referring  to  international  criminal  justice,  truth  and  reconciliation  commissions,  transitional  justice,  restorative  justice,  and  research  on  post-­‐conflict  societies  and  on  civil  reconstruction  in  post-­‐conflict  situations.  3  See  section  on  “Visual  Anthropology”  in  American  Anthropologist  108.1  (2008).  4  Payne’s  observation  was  made  as  a  respondent  to  a  panel  on  “Testimonial  analysis,  use,  and  aftermath”  at  Ways  of  Knowing  After  Atrocity:  A  Colloquium  on  the  Methods  Used  to  Research,  Design  and  Implement  Transitional  Justice  Processes,  Oxford  Transitional  Justice  Research,  University  of  Oxford,  June  2012.

Page 3: The Role of Testimony and Testimonial Analysis in Human Rights Advocacy and Research' in State Crime: Journal of the International State Crime Initiative, Pluto Press, 1.2, Autumn

Patel,  Ian  (2012)  'The  Role  of  Testimony  and  Testimonial  Analysis  in  Human  Rights  Advocacy  and  Research'  in  State  Crime:  Journal  of  the  International  State  Crime  

Initiative,  London,  Pluto  Press,  1.2,  2012.    

  3  

different  to  a  “life  history”  of  a  refugee;  and  a  UK  victim  impact  police  statement  is  different  to  a  focus  group  transcript  of  regional  CSO  leaders.  

At  particular  issue  in  this  article  is  the  reliance  on  “marginalized”,  “silenced”,  “oppressed”  narratives  in  the  theory  and  practice  of  human  rights,  and  the  uses  to  which  such  narratives  are  directed.  I  use  the  term  “self-­‐narration”  in  this  essay  to  refer  to  narratives  told  in  the  first  person  by  a  narrator  who  recounts  the  extreme  experiences  of  conflict  situations.  I  use  the  terms  “testimony”  and  “testimony  paradigm”  to  indicate  the  legal  prominence  of  self-­‐narration  within  human  rights  advocacy  and  research  as  well  as  its  attendant  epistemology.  “Self-­‐narration  as  testimony”  is  a  phrase  used  to  indicate  the  promotion  of  self-­‐narration  as  a  species  of  testimony  within  human  rights  research  and  advocacy.  

The  deliberation  and  houseroom  given  to  the  self-­‐narration  of  victims  and  survivors  of  state  crime  has  been  an  important  part  of  procedural  justice.  While  the  psychological  benefits  of  “speaking  out”  remain  in  question,  there  is  nevertheless  much  to  suggest  the  use-­‐value  of  testimony  for  testifiers  themselves,  who  can  experience  a  sense  of  (albeit  a  nebulous  term)  acknowledgement.  Accordingly,  testimony  is  often  viewed  in  terms  of  the  recent  incremental  advances  in  victim-­‐centred  justice.  

In  a  broader  sociological  sense,  testimony  is  seen  to  provide  an  “on  the  ground”  perspective,  and  in  this  regard  has  become  a  key  heuristic  among  researchers  in  their  attempt  to  understand  the  experience  of  conflict.  Indeed  it  is  difficult  to  challenge  the  reliance  on  testimony  evidence  without  risking  the  criticism  that  in  doing  so  one  represses  the  voices  of  those  who  have  suffered  oppression.  From  an  academic  vantage,  challenging  testimony  evidence  risks  appearing  obscurantist  or  recalling  a  Derridean  critique  of  language  that  denies  narratives  consensual  meaning.  Although  this  article  fundamentally  takes  issue  with  the  reliance  and  promotion  of  self-­‐narration  as  a  species  of  sociological  and  legal  evidence  in  a  human  rights  context,  my  intention  is  not  to  delegitimize  narrative-­‐based  evidence.  Rather,  I  wish  to  suggest  the  ways  in  which  our  ideas  about  self-­‐narration  as  a  form  of  testimony  invite  certain  assumptions  about  the  act  of  account-­‐giving  itself  that  complicate  our  attempts  at  interpretation.  Specifically,  I  want  to  interrogate  the  interpretative  move  by  which  instances  of  self-­‐narration  are  “given  voice”  –  that  is,  are  made  to  fit  a  framework  of  testimonial  analysis  –  a  move  which  neutralizes  the  researcher’s  frame  of  interpretation.  This  article,  then,  moves  between  the  epistemic  status  of  first-­‐person  narrative  accounts  and  the  practical  uses  and  effects  of  testimony  evidence  in  the  field  of  human  rights.  

My  intention  is  to  show  that  self-­‐narration  is  evidentiary  and  meaningful  as  testimony;  yet,  at  the  same  time,  I  want  to  suggest  that  it  is  the  object  of  certain  misplaced  assumptions  that  lead  in  some  cases  to  tendentious  standards  of  interpretation.  My  purpose  in  this  article  is  to  approach  the  dominant  international  model  of  human  rights  interpretation  not  simply  as  an  ideologically  freighted  enterprise,  but  as  a  series  of  epistemological  claims.  In  doing  so,  this  article  touches  on  a  different  question:  can  Western  academics  and  practitioners  reasonably  hope  to  engage  with  the  narratives  of  their  respondents  in  a  way  that  is  dialogic  as  opposed  to  conscribing  or  prescriptive,  yet  at  the  same  time  empirically  valid?  

Page 4: The Role of Testimony and Testimonial Analysis in Human Rights Advocacy and Research' in State Crime: Journal of the International State Crime Initiative, Pluto Press, 1.2, Autumn

Patel,  Ian  (2012)  'The  Role  of  Testimony  and  Testimonial  Analysis  in  Human  Rights  Advocacy  and  Research'  in  State  Crime:  Journal  of  the  International  State  Crime  

Initiative,  London,  Pluto  Press,  1.2,  2012.    

  4  

Testimony  evidence  in  a  human  rights  context  is  presented  as  an  end  in  itself,  as  something  which  bears  inherent  use-­‐value.  Yet  human  rights  organizations  collect  testimony  in  terms  of  its  exchange-­‐value,  too.  The  testimony  of  witnesses  forms  “thick  rivers  of  fact”,  which  might  be  siphoned  and  filtered  into  evidence  by  future  legal  mechanisms  or  political  movements  (Cmiel  1999:  1246).5  Human  rights  advocacy  also  makes  use  of  testimony  as  a  campaign  tool  that  harnesses  the  affective  spectacle  of  testimony  and  the  reactive  emotion  it  can  provoke  in  readers,  listeners,  and  viewers.  

Existing  critiques  of  testimony  evidence  tend  to  question  either  its  supposed  utility  or  its  supposed  ideological  disinterestedness.  Recent  examples  of  the  public  circulation  of  testimony,  in  for  instance  the  former  Yugoslavia  and  Rwanda,  have  shown  that  the  dissemination  of  documentary  evidence  does  not  necessarily  provoke  international  political  action  or  local  mobilization.  Political  critiques  of  testimony  evidence  have  addressed  what  is  claimed  to  be  the  top-­‐down,  expert  arbitration  of  testimony.  They  take  to  task  the  unequal  dynamic  of  power  between  expert  interpreters  of  testimony  on  the  one  hand  and,  on  the  other,  those  persons  whose  narratives  are  utilized  as  evidence  (Pittaway  et  al.  2010;  Mander  2010).6  

This  article  proceeds  in  a  different  manner,  by  challenging  certain  epistemological  and  hermeneutic  assumptions  in  dominant  interpretations  of  self-­‐narration  as  testimony.  This  analysis  might  be  described  as  endogenous  to  human  rights,  in  the  sense  that  it  examines  the  internal  assumptions  of  human  rights  claims  and  human  rights  as  a  Western  epistemic  knowledge.  While  this  article  recalls  existing  work  on  “epistemic  communities”  and  “hermeneutic  injustice”,  it  concentrates  not  simply  on  the  shared  epistemic  assumptions  within  networks  and  powerful  geopolitical  constituencies,  but  on  epistemological  assumptions  about  narrative  accounts  as  a  species  of  evidence  (Haas  1992;  Fricker  2007).  

I  suggest  that  the  assumptions  behind  the  dominant  epistemology  of  testimony  are  in  the  first  place  fallacious,  and  in  the  second  place  ideologically  encoded.  I  do  not  call  for  self-­‐narration  to  be  subject  to  stricter  standards  of  proof,  or  for  that  matter  to  any  new  interpretative  frame.  Rather,  my  focus  is  on  the  actions  of  human  rights  experts,  who  (I  suggest)  make  their  narrative  subjects  the  mouthpiece  of  pre-­‐existing  human  right  credos.  

This  article  begins  from  the  understanding  that  human  rights  researchers  and  advocates  (myself  included)  act  “as  collectors,  filterers,  translators,  and  presenters  of  information  regarding  alleged  violations”  (Metzl  1996:  705).  Human  rights  may  exist  as  a  moral  call  or  appeal,  but  in  application  it  is  codified  as  a  collection  of  norms  and  abstract  designates  and  categories.  The  abstract  schema  of  human  rights  is  given  specificity  by  reference  to  case  studies,  but  I  would  suggest  that  its  emphasis  on  the  individual  as  the  unit  of  human  rights  is  ratified  by  the  “voice”  of  the  human  rights  claimant.  When  human  rights  researchers  and  advocates  utilize  testimony  evidence,  however,  they  ferry  its  knowledge  and  curate  its  meaning,  and  in  doing  so  trammel  the  narrative  accounts  of  others  with  

                                                                                                                         

5  An  example  of  such  an  organization  is  the  Abdorrahman  Boroumand  Foundation,  which  collects  testimonies  from  relatives  and  friends  of  those  killed  or  disappeared  in  the  Islamic  Republic  of  Iran.    6  For  an  excellent  critical  analysis  of  international  advocacy  networks,  see  Subotic  (2012).  

Page 5: The Role of Testimony and Testimonial Analysis in Human Rights Advocacy and Research' in State Crime: Journal of the International State Crime Initiative, Pluto Press, 1.2, Autumn

Patel,  Ian  (2012)  'The  Role  of  Testimony  and  Testimonial  Analysis  in  Human  Rights  Advocacy  and  Research'  in  State  Crime:  Journal  of  the  International  State  Crime  

Initiative,  London,  Pluto  Press,  1.2,  2012.    

  5  

their  own  normative  understanding.  The  epistemology  of  testimony  as  understood  by  many  practitioners  and  experts  tends  to  mask  this  process  of  collecting,  filtering,  and  translating.  

This  masking  occurs  in  the  assumption  that  an  instance  of  testimony  evidence  is  the  unique  particular  which  proves  the  general  normative  rule.  Human  rights  testimony  and  human  rights  norms  come  into  use  correspondingly  as  a  person  petitions  for  rights  previously  denied  them.  Human  rights  advocates  are  able  to  refer  to  victims’  accounts  of  their  experiences  as  “testimony”  as  opposed  to  mere  “narratives”  because  of  the  assumption  that  self-­‐narration  is  emblematic  of  human  right  norms.  A  witness’s  account  of  events  gives  us  much  contextual  and  cultural  content,  but  crucially  it  is  also  understood  to  be  the  sign  of  the  self-­‐determining  human  rights  claimant,  functioning  therefore  as  a  kind  of  testimony.  By  the  same  token,  individual  self-­‐narration  is  often  made  to  serve  a  collective  or  community  function,  a  process  supported  by  the  assumption  that  the  narrating  “I”  is  surrogate  to  a  collective  “we”.  

The  interpretive  move  by  which  an  instance  of  self-­‐narration  is  converted  into  victim  testimony  is  too  often  elided  by  the  epistemology  of  the  interpreter  herself  –  an  epistemology  which  merges  epistemic  claims  with  morality  and  politics.  The  further  move  by  which  victim  testimony  is  integrated  into  a  wider  programme  of  political  action,  in  which  human  rights  is  promoted  and  enforced  across  the  world,  also  tends  to  be  elided.  

Focussed  on  the  evidentiary  framing  of  human  rights  interpretation,  this  article  is  not  a  comment  on,  for  instance,  local  NGO  organizations  that  collect  testimony.  Rather,  I  focus  on  international  and  Western  academic  application  of  such  testimony.  When  referring  to  examples  of  international  or  academic  application  of  testimony  evidence  I  am  not  taking  issue  simply  with  the  understanding  of  individual  international  experts  within  these  arenas.  I  am  also  taking  into  consideration  their  place  in  an  international  order  of  liberal  states  which,  through  the  vehicles  of  humanitarian  advocacy  and  international  human  rights  law,  acts  or  attempt  to  act  on  behalf  of  victims  of  conflict.  

This  article  begins  by  examining  the  broader  epistemological  implications  of  the  rise  of  narrative  research,  specifically  in  the  field  of  human  rights  advocacy  and  research,  and  then  reveals  the  extent  to  which  the  epistemology  of  testimony  and  the  liberal  project  of  human  rights  are  mutually  dependent.  A  critical  analysis  of  the  epistemology  of  testimony  in  human  rights  advocacy  and  research  is  both  timely  and  necessary.  A  survey  of  33  human  rights  fellows  found  that  68  per  cent  indicated  the  semi-­‐structured  interview  as  their  choice  research  method  (Reed  and  Padskocimaite  2012:  4).7  Like  other  types  of  evidence  based  in  self-­‐narration,  interview  evidence  is  employed  as  an  indicator  of  “people’s  perceptions,  meanings,  definitions  of  situations  and  constructions  of  reality”  (Punch  2005:  168).  While  there  is  a  great  deal  of  literature  on  technical  aspects  of  qualitative  

                                                                                                                         

7  The  most  popular  methods  were:  semi-­‐structured  interview  (61  per  cent),  case  study  (45  per  cent),  ethnography  (36  per  cent),  archival  research  (27  per  cent)  and  statistical  analysis  (21  per  cent).    

Page 6: The Role of Testimony and Testimonial Analysis in Human Rights Advocacy and Research' in State Crime: Journal of the International State Crime Initiative, Pluto Press, 1.2, Autumn

Patel,  Ian  (2012)  'The  Role  of  Testimony  and  Testimonial  Analysis  in  Human  Rights  Advocacy  and  Research'  in  State  Crime:  Journal  of  the  International  State  Crime  

Initiative,  London,  Pluto  Press,  1.2,  2012.    

  6  

interviewing,  little  work  has  been  done  on  the  epistemological  assumptions  implicit  in  such  qualitative  research.8  

Since  the  epistemology  of  testimony  is  a  relatively  under-­‐researched  area,  I  hope  this  article  will  clarify  some  of  the  ways  in  which  certain  key  terms  in  the  field  of  human  rights  –  testimony,  truth-­‐telling,  recognition  –  are  underpinned  epistemologically.  I  hope  this  discussion  will  be  of  use  to  others  working  on  research  methods  in  the  field  of  human  rights,  and  will  be  a  contribution  to  existing  literatures  on  rights  consciousness,  evidentiary  sources,  victim  empowerment,  and  victim  representation.  

 

 

The  Turn  to  Narrative  in  the  Social  Sciences    

Before  engaging  the  epistemology  of  testimony,  it  is  first  necessary  to  chart  briefly  the  rise  of  narrative  in  the  social  sciences.  The  “narrative  turn”  in  the  social  sciences  was  a  turn  towards  self-­‐narration  as  a  species  of  evidence.  

In  Doing  Narrative  Research  (2008),  the  authors  write  that:  “In  the  last  two  decades,  narrative  has  acquired  an  increasingly  high  profile  in  social  research…  [It]  is  a  popular  portmanteau  term  in  contemporary  western  social  research”  (Andrews  et  al.  2008:  2).9  This  emphasis  on  narrative  as  a  qualitative  frame  has  given  rise  to  several  general  texts  for  social  researchers,  as  well  as  others  that  examine  its  influence  within  specific  disciplinary  areas,  such  as  sociology,  education  studies,  cognitive  science,  healthcare,  and  social  work,  among  others.10  The  narrative  paradigm  is  not  qualitatively  prescriptive,  since  methodologically  it  belongs  to  the  “highly  epistemologically-­‐contested  field  of  discourse  analysis”  (Andrews  et  al.:  1–2).  

Where  in  other  fields  self-­‐narration  is  valued  as  a  measure  of  psychological  states  of  being  –  the  eponymous  “self”  of  self-­‐narration  –  in  the  field  of  human  rights  research  a  further  component  is  integrated  into  self-­‐narration’s  epistemic  status.11  I  will  attempt  to  reveal  the  ways  in  which  human  

                                                                                                                         

8  As  China  Miéville  (2006:  2)  has  observed,  with  respect  to  international  law,  within  most  textbooks  “theoretical  assumptions  are  generally  unacknowledged  and  implicit”.  9  Amanda  Anderson  (2006:  3),  for  instance,  writes  that  by  the  late  1980s,  there  was  an  established  critical  “interest  in  first-­‐person  perspectives  and  in  the  lived  experiences  of  diverse  social  groups”.    10  General  texts  include  Clandinin  and  Connelly  (2000),  Elliot  (2005)  and  Chamberlayne  et  al.  (2000).  11  Many  disciplines  have  come  to  value  what  many  see  as  the  narrative  constitution  of  psychology  and  identity.  As  a  typical  critical  statement  in  this  vein  has  it:  “[W]e  lead  our  lives  as  stories,  and  our  identity  is  constructed  by  both  stories  we  tell  ourselves  and  others  about  ourselves  and  by  the  master  narratives  that  consciously  or  unconsciously  serves  as  models  for  ours”  (Rimmon-­‐Kenan  2002:  11).  Jerome  Bruner  (2002:  89)  describes  selves  as  stories  that  “impose  a  structure,  a  compelling  reality  on  what  we  experience”.  In  more  general  terms,  philosopher  Marya  Schechtman  (1996:  93)  advocates  a  “narrative  

Page 7: The Role of Testimony and Testimonial Analysis in Human Rights Advocacy and Research' in State Crime: Journal of the International State Crime Initiative, Pluto Press, 1.2, Autumn

Patel,  Ian  (2012)  'The  Role  of  Testimony  and  Testimonial  Analysis  in  Human  Rights  Advocacy  and  Research'  in  State  Crime:  Journal  of  the  International  State  Crime  

Initiative,  London,  Pluto  Press,  1.2,  2012.    

  7  

rights  advocacy  and  research  promotes  narrative  as  a  type  of  evidence  that  pertains  not  simply  to  the  psychological  realities  of  a  victim,  survivor  or  witness,  but  one  which  also  serves  a  testimonial  function.  

 

 

First-­‐Person  Accounts:  From  Storytelling  to  Empirical  Resource    

First-­‐person  accounts  have  undergone  something  of  a  reappraisal  in  the  hierarchy  of  credibility.12  Non-­‐fiction  storytelling  in  the  humanities  has  traditionally  been  placed  in  a  tradition  of  rhetoric  or  polemic,  but  more  recently  it  has  come  to  be  valued  as  an  empirical  resource.  Following  Iris  Young’s  dictum  that  “storytelling”  can  be  “an  important  bridge  between  the  mute  experience  of  being  wronged  and  political  arguments  about  justice”,  there  has  been  much  critical  attention  focussed  on  the  relationships  between  storytelling,  jurisprudence,  and  social  justice  (Young  2000:  72).13  As  Sidonie  Smith  and  Kay  Schaffer  (2004:  1)  write,  the  1990s  has  not  only  been  labelled  “the  decade  of  human  rights”,  but  also  the  “decade  of  life  narratives”.  First-­‐person  life  narratives  “begin  to  voice,  recognize,  and  bear  witness  to  a  diversity  of  values,  experiences,  and  ways  of  imagining  a  just  social  world  and  of  responding  to  injustice,  inequality,  and  human  suffering”  (Smith  and  Schaffer  2004:  1).  

In  an  important  sense,  then,  the  reliance  of  human  rights  advocates  and  researchers  on  the  personal  accounts  of  individuals  has  been  politically  motivated.  As  Richard  Weisberg  has  observed,  narrative-­‐based  research  tends  to  emphasize  the  ability  of  self-­‐narration  to  undermine  the  authoritative  discourses  of  those  in  power.  Within  Western  culture,  many  of  us,  including  prominent  researchers,  have  been  

 

far  less  sceptical  of  individual  eye-­‐witness  accounts  than  of  the  manner  in  which  institutional  forces  ignored,  warped  and  distorted  them  for  their  own  purposes…  in  the  context  of  our  own  generation,  the  eye-­‐witness  gains  credibility  just  as  the  political  or  institutional  or  cultural  account  is  precisely  devalued.  (Weisberg  1991:  i–iii)  

 

                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                         

self-­‐constitution  view”,  and  maintains  that  people’s  lives  are  narrative  in  form.  A  person  “creates  his  identity  by  forming  an  autobiographical  narrative  –  a  story  of  his  life”.  In  the  same  vein,  Charles  Taylor  (1989:  47)  suggests  that  a  “basic  condition  of  making  sense  of  ourselves”  demands  that  “we  grasp  our  lives  in  a  narrative”.    12  For  a  discussion  of  the  notion  of  a  hierarchy  of  credibility,  see  Sanders  (1987:  238).  13  See  also  Braithwaite  (2007),  Beverley  (1992),  Bell  (2010),  Pranis  (2001),  Neimeyer  and  Tschudi  (2003).  

Page 8: The Role of Testimony and Testimonial Analysis in Human Rights Advocacy and Research' in State Crime: Journal of the International State Crime Initiative, Pluto Press, 1.2, Autumn

Patel,  Ian  (2012)  'The  Role  of  Testimony  and  Testimonial  Analysis  in  Human  Rights  Advocacy  and  Research'  in  State  Crime:  Journal  of  the  International  State  Crime  

Initiative,  London,  Pluto  Press,  1.2,  2012.    

  8  

In  the  face  of  authoritarian  regimes  which  have  silenced  the  accounts  of  individuals  by  destruction  or  by  disseminating  their  own  propagandizing  discourse,  the  personal  accounts  of  witnesses  of  state  crime  among  others  have  provided  a  hugely  important  counter-­‐narrative.  Self-­‐narration,  on  this  basis,  was  formulated  as  valuably  indicative  of  the  experience  of  witnesses  to  events.  

With  this  promotion  of  self-­‐narration  in  the  field  of  human  rights  came  a  type  of  essentialism  about  what  it  meant  to  give  an  account  of  oneself.  This  was  not  a  humanist  stress  on  the  immutable  value  of  self-­‐narration  so  much  as  a  proclamation  of  its  discursive  integrity  from  social  and  political  forces.  Analyses  that  utilize  testimony  evidence,  in  other  words,  often  presuppose  self-­‐narration  as  the  self-­‐sufficient  practice  by  which  human  beings  exercise  in  language  what  is  significant  to  or  about  them.  Narrative  is  reified  as  the  essential  practice  of  self-­‐knowing,  leaving  its  structures,  co-­‐optive  influences,  and  social  relations  unproblematic  to  it.  As  the  human  function  best  placed  to  act  as  a  vehicle  of  critique  to  hegemonic  systems  of  meaning,  which  “silence”  or  overwrite  the  human  speaking  voice,  narrative  is  afforded  the  worth  of  a  universal,  innate  human  capacity.  Such  essentialism  is  maintained  even  when  narrative  is  held  in  relation  to  historico-­‐cultural  formations.  The  ability  to  narrate  is  often  presented  as  the  practice  of  a  universal  and  unchanging  dignity  that  is  naturalized  as  a  narrative  human  condition.  For  example,  the  abolitionist  slogan  “Am  I  not  a  man  and  a  brother?”  works  publicly  as  a  political  and  moral  appeal,  but  in  an  epistemological  sense  it  also  works  metaphysically  to  confirm  a  (socially  interdependent)  human  condition.14  

 

 

Self-­‐Narration  As  Testimony    

From  the  discussion  above,  we  can  now  identify  a  further  inflection  given  to  self-­‐narration  as  an  empirical  resource.  As  a  witness  or  victim  or  survivor  of  human  rights  violations,  one’s  account  of  one’s  experiences  is  presumed  to  carry  a  testimonial  freight  by  dint  simply  of  its  existence.  Felman  and  Laub  (1992:  5)  have  described  “testimony”  as  “a  crucial  mode  of  our  relation  to  events  of  our  times…  our  era  can  precisely  be  defined  as  the  age  of  testimony”.  If  ours  is  an  “age  of  testimony”,  it  is  because  we  live  in  “an  age  in  which  witnessing  itself  has  undergone  a  major  trauma”  (Felman  1991:  76).  The  in  extremis  pain  of  recent  history  establishes  the  need  for  testimony  and  the  ethical  right  of  traumatized  human  subjects  to  be  heard  and  thus  acknowledged.  On  this  basis,  survivors  of  historical  suffering,  and  their  stories  of  survival,  demand  to  be  granted  an  epistemic  status  by  precisely  those  structures  of  knowledge  and  power  that  have  failed  them.15  The  crises  of  recent  history  have,  in  other  words,  instituted  a  crisis  of  reference.  Amid  the  unmeaning  of  war  and  

                                                                                                                         

14  This  rather  complex  relationship  between  self-­‐narration  and  philosophical  notions  of  selfhood  is  explored  in  Wright  (2006).  15  For  a  discussion  of  institutional  failure  and  a  concomitant  “rejection  of  the  claims  of  collective  belonging”,  see  Turner  (1996:  47).  

Page 9: The Role of Testimony and Testimonial Analysis in Human Rights Advocacy and Research' in State Crime: Journal of the International State Crime Initiative, Pluto Press, 1.2, Autumn

Patel,  Ian  (2012)  'The  Role  of  Testimony  and  Testimonial  Analysis  in  Human  Rights  Advocacy  and  Research'  in  State  Crime:  Journal  of  the  International  State  Crime  

Initiative,  London,  Pluto  Press,  1.2,  2012.    

  9  

atrocity,  and  among  the  fragmentary  detritus  of  documentary  evidence  left  by  that  devastation,  testimony  rises  to  the  fore  as  a  kind  of  “traumatic  realism”  (Rothberg  2000).16  

When  a  narrative  account  is  identified  as  testimony  in  a  human  rights  context  this  tends  to  be  a  deliberate  attempt  to  identify  that  narrative  account  as  (i)  a  species  of  empirical  evidence,  and  (ii)  one  that  carries  with  it  a  certain  moral  imperative  contained  in  the  act  of  bearing  witness.  Testimony,  in  this  sense,  is  seen  to  marry  legal  with  moral  and  affective  forms  of  persuasion.  

Put  crudely,  in  its  very  broadest  sense,  testimony  means  “people  telling  other  people  things”.17  Most  testimony  (in  this  broad  sense)  involves  some  kind  of  narrative.  Furthermore,  some  type  of  self-­‐narration  –  “I  was  there;  this  is  what  I  saw;  and  now  I’m  telling  you  what  I  saw”  –  is  implicit  in  most  kinds  of  testimony.  This  kind  of  minimal  testimony  can  provide  a  wealth  of  factual  information  for  those  wishing  to  collect  verifiable  evidence  about  a  situation.  Self-­‐narration  in  the  field  of  human  rights  is  carrying  a  heavier  burden,  however.  Because  the  experiences  at  stake  are  so  unique  and  extreme,  self-­‐narration  in  such  contexts  is  urged  to  cleave  to  a  more  declarative  and  revelatory  script.  The  formula  in  this  latter  case  might  read  something  like:  “I  was  there;  this  is  what  I  saw,  lived  through,  and  experienced;  this  is  the  effect  it  had  on  me  and  who  I  am;  and  this  is  why  I’m  telling  you  about  it.”  Because  self-­‐narration  in  a  human  rights  context  is  so  freighted  with  experiential  extremities,  it  is  elevated  to  a  form  of  knowledge  in  itself.  Testimony  is  the  name  we  give  to  this  form  of  knowledge.  The  interpreter  assigns  a  value  to  the  content  of  such  testimony  beyond  what  is  empirically  relevant  to  the  existing  body  of  documentary  evidence.  To  take  a  fictional  example:  “Security  forces  came  to  our  house  and  arrested  me,  though  they  did  not  have  a  warrant.  My  father-­‐in-­‐law  became  short  of  breath  and  fainted  from  the  shock  of  it.”  That  the  speaker  in  this  fictional  example  was  arrested  without  a  warrant  has  legal  and  political  implications,  but  the  hurt  of  the  family  member,  and  the  emotional  effect  of  this  hurt  on  the  speaker,  too  has  legal  and  political  implications.  Those  who  are  called  upon  to  speak  of  their  experiences  are  thus  poised  to  answer  to  these  dual  functions  of  empirical  knowledge  and  experiential  knowledge.  

 

 

 

 

                                                                                                                         

16  “Traumatic  realism”,  Michael  Rothberg  (2000:  140)  writes,  “is  marked  by  the  survival  of  extremity  into  the  everyday  world.”  Recent  historical  suffering  has  been  so  extreme  as  to  empty  out  previous  models  of  realism  based  on  moral  and  political  traditions  complicit  in  that  suffering.  In  this  vacuum  a  “traumatic”  realism  survives  as  the  first  point  of  reference  by  which  to  rebuild.  Rothberg  also  places  traumatic  realism  beside  “a  demand  for  documentation…and  a  demand  for  the  risky  public  circulation  of  discourses  on  the  event”  (2000:  7).  17  For  existing  discussions  on  the  epistemology  of  testimony,  see  Coady  (1992),  Lackey  (2008),  Lackey  and  Sosa  (2006),  Graham  (1997),  Fricker  (1994).  On  testimony  as  an  acquired  source  of  knowledge,  see  Lackey  (1999).  On  testimony-­‐based  belief,  see  Stevenson  (1993)  and  Sosa  (1994).  Also  see  Hume’s  ([1777]  1972)  influential  account  of  testimony.  

Page 10: The Role of Testimony and Testimonial Analysis in Human Rights Advocacy and Research' in State Crime: Journal of the International State Crime Initiative, Pluto Press, 1.2, Autumn

Patel,  Ian  (2012)  'The  Role  of  Testimony  and  Testimonial  Analysis  in  Human  Rights  Advocacy  and  Research'  in  State  Crime:  Journal  of  the  International  State  Crime  

Initiative,  London,  Pluto  Press,  1.2,  2012.    

  10  

Table  1      Epistemological  assumptions:  self-­‐narration  as  testimony  

 

Political  assumptions  

Testimony:  

1.   Speaks  truth  to  power,  thereby  promoting  justice.  

2.   Confirms  the  individual’s  standing  as  a  claimant  to  human  rights  protections.  

3.   Bears  witness  to  injustice.  

4.   Promotes  an  accurate  historical  record.  

 

Social  assumptions:  

Testimony:  

1.   Promotes  mutual  understanding.  

2.   Gives  verbal  form  to  identity.  

3.   Is  the  currency  of  forgiveness  and  reconciliation.  

4.   Aids  mutual  recognition.  

 

Psychological  assumptions:  

Testimony:  

1.   Provides  a  verbal  transcription  of  lived  experience.  

2.   Promotes  individual  healing.  

3.   Reveals  individual  experiences  and  social  (as  opposed  to  ideological)  norms.  

4.   Presents  a  singular  cohering  self-­‐portrait.  

 

 

The  epistemology  of  testimony  is  a  paradigm  that  views  first-­‐person  narratives  as  a  kind  of  a  lattice  of  legal  and  political  meaning.  Under  this  paradigm  self-­‐narration  is  a  knowledge  that  both  verifies  certain  facts  about  a  situation  and  satisfies  the  need  for  representation  of  the  extreme  experiences  to  which  victims  of  state  crime  are  subject.  

Page 11: The Role of Testimony and Testimonial Analysis in Human Rights Advocacy and Research' in State Crime: Journal of the International State Crime Initiative, Pluto Press, 1.2, Autumn

Patel,  Ian  (2012)  'The  Role  of  Testimony  and  Testimonial  Analysis  in  Human  Rights  Advocacy  and  Research'  in  State  Crime:  Journal  of  the  International  State  Crime  

Initiative,  London,  Pluto  Press,  1.2,  2012.    

  11  

This  integration  of  self-­‐narration  into  a  testimony  paradigm  is  complex  and  needs  more  critical  attention.  I  believe  the  epistemological  claims  made  on  behalf  of  self-­‐narration  take  their  cue  from  traditions  within  criminology  –  specifically,  the  need  for  empirical  investigation  into  the  experiences  of  victims  (Green  1990;  Hillyard  1993).18  I  believe  self-­‐narration  in  human  rights  research  has  been  subject  to  a  process  of  epistemological  overcompensation,  however.  Self-­‐narration  as  empirical  resource  has  been  conflated  with  the  idea  of  self-­‐narration  as  testimony,  meaning  that  self-­‐narration  has  come  to  serve  as  the  basis  of  a  knowledge  that  is  somehow  both  empirical  and  political,  both  affective  and  petitioning.  

In  most  cases,  of  course,  self-­‐narration  in  a  human  rights  context  does  indeed  warrant  deliberation  from  a  number  of  perspectives  and,  too,  provides  a  compelling  knowledge  of  conflict  situations.  I  want  to  question  however  the  purposiveness  the  testimony  paradigm  confers  on  all  instances  of  self-­‐narration.  Self-­‐narration  utilized  as  evidence  in  a  human  rights  context  tends  to  be  presented  as  serving  a  truth-­‐telling  function.  As  we  shall  see,  however,  not  all  acts  of  self-­‐narration  can  responsibly  be  said  to  sound  the  proclamation  of  certain  enshrined  political  goods.  Because  self-­‐narration  as  testimony  need  not  pertain  to  empirically  verifiable  facts  to  be  valid,  but,  rather,  can  qualify  as  such  simply  as  an  account  of  individual  experience,  the  purposiveness  implied  to  self-­‐narration  is  left  unquestioned.  As  legal  critic  Jan-­‐Melissa  Schramm  (2000:  5)  explains:  

 

[T]his  is  the  essential  ambiguity  of  the  term  “testimony”  –  that  it  not  only  encompasses  narratives  of  experience  which  need  lay  no  immediate  claim  to  issues  of  truth  or  falsehood,  but  that  it  seeks  to  be  regarded  as  a  species  of  evidence.  Seen  as  evidence,  testimony  serves  as  a  vehicle  for  the  attestation  of  the  “real”  because  of  its  roots  in  ancient  notions  of  legal  and  religious  authority.  

 

While  contiguous  to  legal  definitions,  the  general  term  “testimony”  can  be  seen  as  a  type  of  evidence  whose  weight  of  proof  is  not  solely  dependent  on  empirically  verifiable  standards.  The  open  reference  of  its  epistemology  has  allowed  human  rights  advocacy  and  research  to  direct  testimony  as  it  pleases,  towards  ends  rooted  not  simply  in  a  conclusive  empirical  world,  but  in  “real”  political  goods.  

This  process  by  which  self-­‐narration  is  presented  as  conforming  to  existing  human  rights  norms  can  be  blunt  and  heavy-­‐handed,  and  on  other  occasions  it  is  masked  by  a  researcher’s  objective  methodology.  Whether  this  is  critical  complacency  or  something  more  pernicious  is  a  question  too  complex  to  address  here.  

 

                                                                                                                         

18  Criminologists  have  paid  special  attention  to  the  narratives  of  offenders:  see  Bennett  (1981)  and,  more  recently,  Presser  (2009).  In  a  basic  sense,  offender  narratives  shed  light  on  the  norms  held  by  an  offender  as  they  differ  from  those  of  the  wider  moral  and  legal  community  in  which  the  offender  lives.  

Page 12: The Role of Testimony and Testimonial Analysis in Human Rights Advocacy and Research' in State Crime: Journal of the International State Crime Initiative, Pluto Press, 1.2, Autumn

Patel,  Ian  (2012)  'The  Role  of  Testimony  and  Testimonial  Analysis  in  Human  Rights  Advocacy  and  Research'  in  State  Crime:  Journal  of  the  International  State  Crime  

Initiative,  London,  Pluto  Press,  1.2,  2012.    

  12  

 

The  Framing  of  Testimony    

We  can  now  move  on  to  consider  how  self-­‐narration  as  testimony  is  presented  and  by  whom.  I  would  suggest  that  in  the  field  of  human  rights  advocacy  in  particular  testimony  is  often  presented  as  ratifying  an  existing  normative  discourse  about  human  rights.  This  process  in  effect  disenfranchises  original  narratives  of  their  own  terms  of  reference  in  favour  of  normative  international  discourses  on  human  rights.  

Most  commonly,  human  rights  supporters  use  narratives  to  promote  recognition  of  others  living  under  repressive  circumstances.  As  Osler  and  Zhu  (2011:  225)  have  put  it,  by  promoting  and  adopting  “narratives  as  a  pedagogical  tool”  we  support  “recognition  of  our  common  humanity  and  responsibility  to  others  in  distant  places,  beyond  the  limiting  framework  of  the  nation  state”.  This  is  a  hugely  important  task,  and  narrative  can  indeed  be  used  to  further  such  a  purpose.  Yet  often  human  rights  advocacy  fails  to  interrogate  the  frame  by  which  such  narratives  are  interpreted.  Too  often,  the  frame  in  which  testimony  evidence  is  viewed  and  presented  is  an  internationally  codified,  liberal  conception  of  human  rights.  Osler  and  Zhu,  for  example,  betray  a  lack  of  critical  awareness  when  they  state:  “Using  the  framework  of  the  UDHR,  we  argue  that  the  study  and  creation  of  life  histories  can  aid  understanding  of  universal  human  rights  within  different  cultural  settings”  (Osler  and  Zhu  2011:  124).  The  discourse  of  the  UDHR  might  well  be  comparable  to  a  piece  of  testimony  evidence,  but  human  rights  advocates  often  (wittingly  or  unwittingly)  reproduce  and  perpetuate  liberal  human  rights  norms  in  the  act  of  “giving  voice”  to  the  narratives  of  others.  

Professional  advocacy  networks  promoting  human  rights  internationally  are  strategic  procurers  of  testimony  evidence.  As  Schaffer  and  Smith  (2004:  14–15)  have  summarised:  

 

In  the  midst  of  the  transits  that  take  stories  of  local  struggle  to  readerships  around  the  world,  NGOs  and  activists  enlist  stories  from  victims  as  a  way  of  alerting  a  broader  public  to  situations  of  human  rights  violations.  They  also  solicit  and  package  stories  to  attract  readerships.  The  kinds  of  stories  they  choose  –  sensationalized,  sentimentalized,  charged  with  affect  –  target  privileged  readers  in  anticipation  that  they  will  identify  with,  contribute  to,  and  become  advocates  for  the  cause.  The  frames  they  impose  on  stories  are  designed  to  capture  the  interest,  empathy,  and  political  responsiveness  of  readers  elsewhere,  in  ways  they  have  learned  will  “sell”  to  publishers  and  audiences.  NGOs  harness  their  rights  agendas  to  the  market  and  its  processes  of  commodification.  

 

Human  rights  advocacy,  then,  can  be  bluntly  utilitarian  in  its  use  of  victims’  stories,  in  the  name  of  making  public  “authentic”  accounts  of  political  oppression.  Advocacy  in  this  sense  refers  to  the  organizational  effect  of  advocacy,  as  opposed  to  the  individual  understanding  of  the  advocate.  Given  the  exigencies  of  advocacy  campaigns  it  is  perhaps  inevitable  that  human  rights  advocacy  groups  seek  to  make  an  explicit  connection  between  testimony  evidence  and  the  rights  agenda  to  which  

Page 13: The Role of Testimony and Testimonial Analysis in Human Rights Advocacy and Research' in State Crime: Journal of the International State Crime Initiative, Pluto Press, 1.2, Autumn

Patel,  Ian  (2012)  'The  Role  of  Testimony  and  Testimonial  Analysis  in  Human  Rights  Advocacy  and  Research'  in  State  Crime:  Journal  of  the  International  State  Crime  

Initiative,  London,  Pluto  Press,  1.2,  2012.    

  13  

they  are  committed.  I  wish  to  further  explore  however  the  manner  in  which  the  epistemology  of  testimony  is  seen  to  legitimize  the  “enlisting”  of  testimony.  

To  uncover  the  epistemology  of  testimony  we  need  to  turn  to  academic  constructs  and  applications  of  testimony.  In  human  rights  research,  testimony  evidence  belongs  to  qualitative  data,  in  counter-­‐distinction  or  complementary  to  quantitative  data.  Such  testimony  evidence  is  gained  most  commonly  by  “collecting  textual  data  through  interviews  and/or  observation  of  individuals  or  groups  of  people”  (Pham  and  Vinck  2007:  234).  Archival  evidence  and  court  and  tribunal  evidence  may  also  be  utilized.  Some  common  testimony  evidence  collection  tools  include:  “informant  interviews,  focus  group  discussions,  participant  observation  and  direct  observation”  (ibid.:  234).  Qualitative  interviewing  has  its  own  categories:  “open-­‐ended”,  “structured”,  “semi-­‐structured”,  and  so  on.  This  data  may  also  be  integrated  into  a  process  of  “systematic  data  collection  of  information  or  knowledge  using  scientific  approaches”  (ibid.:  232).  Often,  testimony  evidence  is  converted  into  datasets  which  are  then  subject  to  “coding”,  “the  process  of  classifying  and  quantifying  information  for  the  purpose  of  statistical  analysis”  (Sikkink  2011:  135).  Testimony  evidence  can  be  presented  alongside  statistical  data  garnered  from,  for  instance,  population-­‐based  surveys  or  structured  questionnaires.  

I  list  these  qualitative  research  methods  mainly  to  contextualize  my  analysis,  since  my  focus  lies  more  in  the  epistemological  assumptions  which  orientate  such  methods.  Crucially,  empirical  surveys,  scholarly  articles,  and  NGO  reports  are  all  littered  with  quotations  from  respondents  in  a  way  that  is  not  critically  explained  or  justified  methodologically.19  While  methodology  chapters  justify  the  variant  of  interview  or  observation  used  and  its  coding  method  –  or  the  manner  in  which  a  report’s  quantitative  data  complements  its  qualitative  data  or  vice  versa  –  these  do  little  to  explain  the  epistemology  orientating  them.  

Of  particular  concern  is  the  way  in  which  testimony  evidence  is  framed  by  and  thus  conscripted  to  pre-­‐existing  norms  about  account-­‐giving  as  a  human  rights  practice  in  itself.  In  March  2012  Human  Rights  Watch  published  a  report  entitled  “I  Had  to  Run  Away”:  The  Imprisonment  of  Women  and  Girls  for  “Moral  Crimes”  in  Afghanistan.  The  report  is  based  on  58  interviews  of  women  and  children  accused  of  “moral  crimes”.  As  a  Human  Rights  Watch  report,  its  recommendations  are  pitched  directly  to  Afghanistan’s  Supreme  Court,  the  Attorney  General,  the  Afghan  Independent  Human  Rights  Commission  (AIHRC),  the  United  Nations,  and  “International  Donors”,  among  others.  Its  recommendations  –  framed  by  domestic  constitutional  and  legal  issues,  and  relevant  international  human  rights  law  and  treaties  –  are  made  concrete  and  given  experiential  reference  by  the  testimonies  of  those  interviewed.  The  exact  phrase  “I  had  to  run  away”  does  not  actually  appear  in  the  report,  and  appears  to  have  been  coined  to  highlight  a  general  rule  about  the  report’s  data.  “Of  the  42  married  women  and  girls  interviewed  for  this  report,  22  were  arrested  as  a  direct  result  of  having  run  away  in  order  to  flee  abuse  by  their  husband  or  family  members  of  their  husband”  (HRW  2012:  39).  

                                                                                                                         

19  For  an  example  of  a  highly  accomplished  piece  of  research  which  nevertheless  falls  into  this  trap,  see  Stover  et  al.  (2011).  

Page 14: The Role of Testimony and Testimonial Analysis in Human Rights Advocacy and Research' in State Crime: Journal of the International State Crime Initiative, Pluto Press, 1.2, Autumn

Patel,  Ian  (2012)  'The  Role  of  Testimony  and  Testimonial  Analysis  in  Human  Rights  Advocacy  and  Research'  in  State  Crime:  Journal  of  the  International  State  Crime  

Initiative,  London,  Pluto  Press,  1.2,  2012.    

  14  

The  story  is  told  of  a  woman  named  Gulara,  who  was  married  against  her  will  at  age  15:  

 

Her  husband  had  been  promised  to  another  girl  when  he  was  born  but  his  father,  for  reasons  unknown  to  Gulara,  decided  to  break  the  engagement  and  marry  his  son  to  her  instead.  She  said  this  caused  disagreements  within  her  husband’s  family,  but  her  family  was  unaware  of  this  when  they  agreed  to  the  marriage.  She  told  Human  Rights  Watch:    I  had  so  many  problems  with  domestic  violence.  Everyone  in  my  husband’s  family  was  treating  me  in  a  really  bad  way.  When  we  got  engaged,  it  was  my  father-­‐in-­‐law  who  came  to  our  house  and  asked  for  me  for  his  son.  But  the  father-­‐in-­‐law  himself  was  beating  me  a  lot  from  just  the  time  I  got  married.    She  said  she  was  also  beaten  by  her  brother-­‐in-­‐law.  Gulara  went  to  a  shelter  to  try  to  get  help  with  these  problems  and  asked  them  to  help  her  obtain  a  divorce.  Instead,  Gulara  says  that  the  shelter  returned  her  to  her  husband  after  he  promised  not  to  repeat  his  prior  actions.  However,  the  situation  worsened.    My  husband  said,  “Now  you  have  found  the  ways  and  the  places  where  you  can  go  and  complain  about  us.”  My  situation  day-­‐by-­‐day  got  worse  and  then  I  was  forced  to  run  away.  (HRW  2012:  51)  

 

What  is  quoted  of  Gulara’s  narrative  amounts  to  90  words.  It  is  debatable  whether  this  length  of  quotation,  together  with  the  direct  quotation  from  other  respondents,  is  appropriate  to  the  interview  data  as  the  primary  source  of  evidence.  The  shifts  of  focus  within  the  report  –  from  the  temporal  and  circumstantial  specificities  of  individual  self-­‐narration;  to  the  regional  political  concerns  of  prosecutors  and  police;  to  the  macro-­‐discourses  of  ICCPR,  CEDAW,  and  ICESCR  –  will  be  a  familiar  hermeneutic  to  most  readers.  I  would  suggest  that  the  amalgamated  phrase  “I  had  to  run  away”,  as  the  eponymous  statement  of  the  report  itself,  is  the  trope  by  which  the  report  signals  its  political  legitimacy  and  methodological  integrity.  This  is  despite  the  fact  that  the  testimonies  used  in  the  report  are  summarily  converted  into  an  international  language  of  civil  and  political  rights.  While  this  may  be  a  laudable  enterprise,  such  an  epistemology  declares  legitimate  what  should  be  open  to  critique.  

The  mechanisms  favoured  by  the  dominant  institutions  and  state  parties  in  the  promotion  of  human  rights  and  transitional  justice  are  overwhelmingly  legalistic,  and  more  specifically  centre  on  the  rule  of  law,  constitutional  reform,  and  democratic  enfranchisement.  Human  rights  advocacy  and  research  are  at  once  beholden  to  and  complicit  in  these  institutions  and  state  parties.  In  this  legalistic  landscape,  and  amid  the  demands  from  donors  for  outcomes  and  measurable  results,  it  might  be  said  to  be  a  curious  turn  of  fate  that  human  rights  research  and  advocacy  would  continue  to  rely  heavily  on  that  most  qualitative  of  evidentiary  sources,  the  narrative  account.  In  this  sense,  the  rise  of  so-­‐called  “history  from  below”  analysis  may  serve  as  a  useful  reference  in  our  understanding  of  the  sustained  promotion  of  testimony  evidence.  

Page 15: The Role of Testimony and Testimonial Analysis in Human Rights Advocacy and Research' in State Crime: Journal of the International State Crime Initiative, Pluto Press, 1.2, Autumn

Patel,  Ian  (2012)  'The  Role  of  Testimony  and  Testimonial  Analysis  in  Human  Rights  Advocacy  and  Research'  in  State  Crime:  Journal  of  the  International  State  Crime  

Initiative,  London,  Pluto  Press,  1.2,  2012.    

  15  

In  its  human  rights  variation,  “justice  from  below”  wishes  to  critique  what  it  sees  as  the  top-­‐down  promotion  of  justice,  by  suggesting  that  formal  legal  institutions  and  sanctioned  transitional  mechanisms  form  a  dominant  script,  which  detaches  scholars  and  practitioners  from  local  needs,  definitions  of  justice,  and  relevant  cultural  practices  (McEvoy  and  McGregor  2008).  Because  justice-­‐from-­‐below  advocates  aim  to  enfranchise  unheard  accounts  into  the  currency  of  human  rights  evidence,  their  ability  to  be  self-­‐critical  can  be  diminished  by  what  they  see  (correctly)  as  a  pressing  moral  and  political  need.  Just  as  “history  from  below”  has  been  criticized  (ironically)  for  co-­‐opting  grassroots  movements  into  dominant  historical  paradigms,  “justice  from  below”  has  been  criticized  for  promoting  expert  arbitration  of  justice  processes.  As  Tshepo  Madlingozi  (2010:  225)  has  written:  

 

Whether  it  is  through  field  reports,  policy  papers,  or  academic  papers  and  manuscripts,  transitional  justice  experts’  professional  advancement  is  based  on  being  able  to  “speak  about”  and  “speak  for”  victims.  Despite  the  constant  references  to  the  need  to  have  “victims’  voice  be  heard”,  to  have  “victim-­‐centered  or  bottom-­‐up  transitional  justice  processes”,  and  to  have  “victim  empowerment”,  transitional  justice  scholars  and  practitioners  have  not  genuinely  interrogated  how  their  programmes  and  interventions  have  led  to  the  disempowerment  or  empowerment  of  victims.  

 

For  our  purposes,  Madlingozi  establishes  that  the  epistemology  of  testimony  assumes  the  dependency  of  account-­‐givers  on  the  expert  agency  of  professional  interpreters.  Rather  than  promoting  or  empowering  account-­‐givers’  critical  understanding  of  their  own  socio-­‐political  context,  justice-­‐from-­‐below  analysis  performs  a  top-­‐down  orchestration  of  narrative  meaning  in  the  very  act  of  supposed  liberation.  To  return  to  the  notion  of  a  hierarchy  of  credibility,  in  the  final  account  it  is  the  human  rights  advocate  herself  who  outranks  the  narrative  voice  on  which  she  relies  as  evidence.  The  agency  by  which  a  narrative  is  given  meaning  is  not  borne  by  the  author  of  the  narrative,  but,  rather,  by  their  advocate.  Miranda  Fricker  has  written  persuasively  on  the  notion  of  “hermeneutical  injustice”.  This  occurs  when  a  person  is  in  effect  written  out  of  the  deliberative  process  by  which  norms  are  instituted  and  meaning  constructed.  This  process  belongs  to  an  unequal  distribution  of  “the  shared  resources  for  social  interpretation”  (Fricker  2009:  148).  In  the  case  of  testimony  evidence,  the  authors  of  the  testimonies  themselves  are  too  often  left  un-­‐empowered,  and  thus  unable  to  participate  in  the  deliberative  process  by  which  rights  claims  are  formulated,  despite  the  fact  that  their  own  story  is  a  source  of  evidence  supporting  the  rights  claim  itself.  

Much  post-­‐conflict  human  rights  research  challenges  the  centralization  of  a  state  regime  by  examining  local  experiences.  Because  such  research  starts  from  a  specific  instance  before  moving  to  more  general  concerns,  it  risks  making  an  individual’s  narrative  answerable  to  the  particular  credo  or  critical  telos  of  the  researcher  herself.  To  take  a  more  specific  example,  there  is  a  certain  logic  followed  by  human  rights  research  which  draws  on  the  accounts  of  survivors  of  a  regime:  a  Survivor  must  ipso  facto  be  the  bearer  of  an  important  testimonial  account.20  Those  researchers  engaged  on                                                                                                                            

20  As  Roger  Luckhurst  has  written  in  The  Trauma  Question  (2008:  2),  “extremity  and  survival  are  the  privileged  markers  of  identity.  Concentration  camp  inmates,  Vietnam  and  Gulf  veterans,  victims  of  

Page 16: The Role of Testimony and Testimonial Analysis in Human Rights Advocacy and Research' in State Crime: Journal of the International State Crime Initiative, Pluto Press, 1.2, Autumn

Patel,  Ian  (2012)  'The  Role  of  Testimony  and  Testimonial  Analysis  in  Human  Rights  Advocacy  and  Research'  in  State  Crime:  Journal  of  the  International  State  Crime  

Initiative,  London,  Pluto  Press,  1.2,  2012.    

  16  

a  justice-­‐from-­‐below  analysis  must  check  the  logic  which  suggests  that  localized  conflict  is  best  understood  through  local  accounts.  As  Phil  Clark  has  shown  in  his  research  on  the  Rwandan  genocide,  many  survivors  were  in  hiding  during  the  atrocities  and  were  unable  to  shed  light  on  local  killing  practices  (Clark  2010).  Epistemologically  speaking,  a  narrative  account  is  a  discrete  and  unique  entity,  and  a  rather  poor  vehicle  for  making  generalizations  about  a  complex  historical  period  or  conflict.  This  is  not  to  say,  of  course,  that  survivors  cannot  ameliorate  the  historical  record.  Neither  is  it  the  case  that  retrospective  accounts  inevitably  parrot  state-­‐authored  discourses  or  act  as  ciphers  of  a  state.  Yet  narrative  evidence  is  far  more  fragile  –  more  rhetorically  conditioned  –  than  it  is  convenient  to  recognize.  

From  here,  I  want  to  suggest  my  own  theory  of  the  epistemological  assumptions  by  which  testimony  evidence  is  allowed  to  be  so  (mis)used.  At  this  point  the  reader  might  ask  what  I  am  arguing  for  in  the  interpretation  of  testimony  evidence.  Do  I  wish  to  argue  for  testimony  evidence  as  non-­‐purposive  self-­‐narration  as  opposed  to  purposive  testimony  –  and,  if  so,  what  does  this  mean?  I  do  not  have  space  here  to  propose  a  theory  of  self-­‐narration  as  unsusceptible  to  end  goals  such  as  reconciliation,  collective  memory,  and  so  on.  Rather,  I  want  to  interrogate  the  notion  of  human  rights  researchers  as  legitimate  interlocutors  with  the  narratives  of  their  respondents.  Testimony  evidence  in  human  rights  advocacy  and  research  is  formalized  in  quasi-­‐legal  fashion,  as  if  the  researcher  were  prosecutor  and  the  respondent  his  witness.  Yet  testimony  evidence  is  made  to  serve  expressly  political  ends  beyond  the  legal  sphere.  This  is  not  however  something  I  want  to  redress  in  formal  legal  terms.  Rather,  I  want  to  question  the  expressly  political  ends  to  which  testimony  evidence  is  subject  –  ends  which  reach  far  beyond  the  legal  notions  of  representation  in  which  human  rights  advocates  trade.  Furthermore,  I  want  to  suggest  that  a  particular  epistemology  of  testimony  is  the  means  by  which  human  rights  advocates  mask  this  process  of  political  co-­‐option.  

There  are  inherent  qualities  that  tend  to  be  vouchsafed  implicitly  to  self-­‐narration  by  those  who  advocate  first-­‐person  narratives  as  a  species  of  testimony  evidence.  The  assumptions  underwriting  testimony  evidence  in  human  rights  advocacy  are  of  course  wide-­‐ranging,  and  examples  can  be  found  of  rigorous  contextualizing  as  well  as  breezy  complacency.  A  danger  facing  all  those  engaged  in  narrative  research  is  the  assumption  that  a  person’s  account  presents  a  fully  formed  and  coherent  “self”  communicated  in  toto  by  the  act  of  narration.  (This  tends  to  be  circumvented  within  human  rights  research  by  the  implicit  claim  that  respondent  narratives  are  purposed  by  their  authors  to  articulate  what  is  most  important  to  them.)  The  pitfalls  of  retrospective  narration  and  of  memory  in  general  are  well  accounted  for  –  as  one  might  expect,  since  much  testimony  evidence  is  retrospective  (Holocaust  evidence  being  a  case  in  point).21  Yet  other  problems  are  more  often  than  not  left  unidentified.  A  set  of  difficulties  follows  the  deracination  of  an  account  from  its  rhetorical  contingencies,  eliding  the  fact  that  every  account  is  audience-­‐driven.  That  is  to  say,  every  self-­‐

                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                         

atrocities,  traumatized  parents  and  survivors  of  disaster  are  the  subject  of  intensive  political,  sociological,  biological,  psychiatric,  therapeutic  and  legal  investigation  and  dispute.”  21  To  take  a  popular  example,  Primo  Levi’s  memoirs  operate  according  as  much  to  the  personal  psychological  needs  of  remembrance  as  they  do  to  the  needs  of  historical  accuracy.  More  concerning,  however,  is  the  state  of  Israel’s  intercession  in  the  interpretation  of  Shoah  texts.  

Page 17: The Role of Testimony and Testimonial Analysis in Human Rights Advocacy and Research' in State Crime: Journal of the International State Crime Initiative, Pluto Press, 1.2, Autumn

Patel,  Ian  (2012)  'The  Role  of  Testimony  and  Testimonial  Analysis  in  Human  Rights  Advocacy  and  Research'  in  State  Crime:  Journal  of  the  International  State  Crime  

Initiative,  London,  Pluto  Press,  1.2,  2012.    

  17  

narrating  account  addresses  itself  to  a  “call  to  account”  by  an  “other”  (audience),  and  to  this  extent  every  account  is  inevitably  persuasive,  tactical,  interlocutory,  purposive  and  appeal-­‐based  in  answering  this  other.  Interviewers,  for  instance,  need  to  be  mindful  of  the  way  in  which  respondents  will  tend  to  reproduce  existing  discourses  about,  say,  political  oppression  and  political  hope  –  often  in  ways  which  reflect  the  interviewer’s  own  lexicon,  political  discursive  allegiances,  and  turns  of  phrase.22  

 

 

Testimony  Evidence  in  Formal  Mechanisms    

International  criminal  justice  and  truth  commissions  have  also  given  a  special  place  to  testimony  evidence.  Since  the  “paper  trail”  is  often  hard  to  follow  after  a  regime,  the  accounts  of  victims  and  perpetrators  take  on  a  particular  significance.23  Since  “international  tribunals  base  their  factual  determinations  virtually  exclusively  on  eyewitness  testimony”,  and  rely  on  victims  and  perpetrators  indirectly  as  embodiments  of  national  suffering  or  iniquity  respectively,  the  accounts  of  individuals  can  sometimes  appear  to  be  at  the  very  heart  of  international  criminal  justice  and  truth  commissions  (Combs  2010:  14).  In  truth  commissions,  “[p]roof  of  accountability  is  not  required  or  provided  other  than  through  the  testimony  of  the  perpetrator  himself”  (Duff  et  al.  2007:  295).  Particularly  in  the  South  African  example,  truth  commissions  have  on  occasion  promoted  the  accounts  of  victims  in  their  capacity  to  further  the  causes  of  social  reconciliation,  national  unity  and  “healing”.  What  is  more,  testimony  within  participatory  processes  such  as  truth  commissions,  in  which  actors  have  been  predetermined  as  either  “victims”  or  “offenders”,  is  subject  to  a  pre-­‐existing  consensus  of  what  defines  suffering,  damage,  wrongdoing,  persecution,  reconciliation,  and  so  forth.  In  this  way,  self-­‐narration  can  be  harnessed  ideologically  to  further  the  ends  of,  say,  the  discourse  of  the  ICCPR.  While  it  may  seem  obvious  that  different  mechanisms  will  produce  different  “truths”,  the  exigencies  of  transitional  politics  mean  that  this  potential  for  plurality  goes  unacknowledged,  as  a  particular  mechanism’s  “truth”  becomes  the  official  account  of  a  historical  period  or  conflict.  

David  Mendeloff  (2004:  358)  has  usefully  brought  together  the  various  ends  to  which  first-­‐person  accounts  are  directed  as  a  species  of  testimony  evidence.  The  list  is  extensive  but  deserves  to  be  recounted  at  length  in  order  to  give  the  reader  the  full  scope  of  the  presumed  uses  of  testimony  evidence  in  a  human  rights  context.  Both  in  academic  constructs  and  within  the  mechanisms  themselves,  “truth-­‐telling”  or  testimony  evidence  has  been  presented  as  promoting:  

                                                                                                                         

22  Translation  theory  has  much  to  say  in  this  context,  too,  since  much  human  rights  research  works  with  translated  data.  Translation  issues  are  however  too  complex  to  address  here.  23  The  Nuremberg  Tribunal  had  a  wealth  of  Nazi  documentation  to  draw  on  as  evidence,  yet  more  recent  regimes  have  been  more  adept  at  destroying  incriminating  document  evidence.  

Page 18: The Role of Testimony and Testimonial Analysis in Human Rights Advocacy and Research' in State Crime: Journal of the International State Crime Initiative, Pluto Press, 1.2, Autumn

Patel,  Ian  (2012)  'The  Role  of  Testimony  and  Testimonial  Analysis  in  Human  Rights  Advocacy  and  Research'  in  State  Crime:  Journal  of  the  International  State  Crime  

Initiative,  London,  Pluto  Press,  1.2,  2012.    

  18  

 

• Justice  • Accountability  • Peace  • Discrediting  of  old  regimes/elites  • Official  historical  record  • Settling  of  conflict  over  past  • Healing  of  individual  victims  • Group  reconciliation  • New  shared  history  • Exposing  institutional  pathologies  • Individual  criminal  accountability  • Human  rights  education  • Rule  of  law  • Democracy  • End  to  human  rights  abuses    

Advocates  of  testimony  evidence  have  a  tendency  to  promote  self-­‐narration  as  a  kind  of  political  discourse.  The  experts  delivering  mechanisms  like  truth  commissions  are  engaged  in  a  process  of  prescriptive  translation,  whereby  testimony  is  not  only  made  legible  as  a  kind  of  political  discourse,  but  is  in  effect  made  answerable  and  accountable  to  the  goods  it  is  presumed  to  promote.  

For  a  specific  example  of  the  strictures  to  which  self-­‐narration  is  subject  in  order  to  be  recognized  as  evidence,  we  can  turn  to  the  ongoing  Khmer  Rouge  Tribunal  (or  ECCC)  in  Cambodia.  All  Civil  Parties  must  complete  a  Victim  Information  Form  to  be  accepted  by  the  court.  There  has  been  little  critical  attention  paid  to  the  format  of  this  form.  Beyond  requesting  basic  information  about  the  potential  Civil  Party,  only  in  Part  B  of  the  form,  “Information  about  the  alleged  crimes”,  is  space  given  over  for  Civil  Parties  to  describe  the  crimes  they  suffered.  This  space,  I  would  estimate,  allows  a  maximum  description  of  20  words.  Other  details  about  crimes  suffered  are  given  in  multiple-­‐choice  Yes/No  answers.  The  only  other  opportunity  Civil  Parties  have  to  tell  their  story  is  an  optional  “Supplementary  Information  Form”,  which  provides  space  for  a  narrative  of  around  1,000  words.  Very  few  Civil  Parties  will  be  asked  to  testify  in  court.  The  percentage  of  those  Civil  Parties  in  the  second  case  who  are  given  this  opportunity  is  likely  to  be  around  2  per  cent.  Yet  this  has  not  prevented  an  access  of  legal  scholarship  discussing  victim  participation  at  the  court  –  both  celebrating  advances  already  made  and  criticizing  their  limitations  –  yet  none  of  these  interrogated  the  narrative  form  of  victim  participation  as  such  (Diamond  2010–11;  Pham  et  al.  2009).  

 

 

 

 

Page 19: The Role of Testimony and Testimonial Analysis in Human Rights Advocacy and Research' in State Crime: Journal of the International State Crime Initiative, Pluto Press, 1.2, Autumn

Patel,  Ian  (2012)  'The  Role  of  Testimony  and  Testimonial  Analysis  in  Human  Rights  Advocacy  and  Research'  in  State  Crime:  Journal  of  the  International  State  Crime  

Initiative,  London,  Pluto  Press,  1.2,  2012.    

  19  

Questioning  the  Coherence  of  Testimony  Evidence    

I  do  not  wish  here  to  iterate  the  political  critique  of  human  rights  advocacy  as  an  imperialist  liberal  cultural  enterprise,  or  to  rehearse  the  ethical  questions  surrounding  the  implications  of  speaking  for  another.  Rather,  I  want  to  challenge  the  primacy  of  testimony  as  an  empirical  constant.  Before  interrogating  the  ideological  motivations  behind  the  epistemology  of  testimony,  it  is  first  necessary  to  examine  in  yet  more  detail  the  assumptions  of  this  epistemology.  Next,  I  want  to  examine  the  politics  of  recognition  and  recognition  generally  as  a  human  rights  good  that  necessitates  the  subjection  of  testimony  to  external  norms.  

What  is  particularly  relevant  regarding  the  epistemology  of  testimony  evidence  is  the  issue  of  explicitness.  Legal  testimony  requires  a  level  of  explicitness,  of  disclosure,  that  is  suspended  in  other  contexts.  In  non-­‐legal  circumstances,  what  is  broadly  called  “testimony”  can  rely  on  implicitly  conveyed  information  leaving  the  listener  or  reader  to  make  assumptions  extra-­‐verbally  communicated  (technically,  this  is  referred  to  as  the  conversational  implicature)  (Grice  1989).  In  the  legal  situation,  as  Duncan  Prichard  (2004:  114)  writes,  since  “we  cannot  rely  on  the  veracity  of  such  implicatures”,  meaning  “it  will  be  necessary  for  the  lawyers  concerned  to  extract  fully  what  an  agent’s  testimony  is  so  that  there  will  be  no  subsequent  ambiguity”.  

I  am  suggesting  that  human  rights  advocacy  and  research  often  makes  explicit  on  behalf  of  others  what  it  sees  to  be  a  coherent  human  rights  discourse  latent  within  first-­‐person  accounts.  In  order  to  achieve  such  explicitness  it  must  implicitly  advance  norms  of  coherence  within  self-­‐narration  in  the  act  of  testimonial  analysis.  If  such  an  epistemological  agenda  is  legitimized  by  implicit  appeal  to  the  explicitness  norm  outlined  above,  it  is  lent  further  support  by  the  assumptions  of  narrative  research  in  the  social  sciences.  As  the  authors  of  Beyond  Narrative  Coherence  (2010)  write:  

 

The narrative turn in the social sciences, beginning in the early 1980s and gathering momentum in the 1990s, almost exclusively assumed that there is a vital and many-layered relationship between narrative and coherence. Narratives were conceptualized in terms of coherence: linguistic, temporal, sequential and so on… Coherence was assumed as a norm for good and healthy life stories. (Hyvärinen et al. 2010: 1)

 

Part  of  the  human  rights  researcher’s  job  is  to  bring  the  purposive  direction  of  a  first-­‐person  account  into  the  light  –  applying  norms  of  coherence  as  he  does  so  –  and  at  the  same  time  to  appeal  to  the  political  goods  to  be  had  by  such  a  revelation.  This  is  equal  to  subjecting  narrative  evidence  to  a  coherence  paradigm.  As  the  same  authors  write:  

 

The coherence paradigm generally implies that (i) good and competent narratives always proceed in a linear, chronological way, from a beginning and middle to an end, which also constitutes a thematic closure; (ii) the function of narrative and story-telling is primarily to

Page 20: The Role of Testimony and Testimonial Analysis in Human Rights Advocacy and Research' in State Crime: Journal of the International State Crime Initiative, Pluto Press, 1.2, Autumn

Patel,  Ian  (2012)  'The  Role  of  Testimony  and  Testimonial  Analysis  in  Human  Rights  Advocacy  and  Research'  in  State  Crime:  Journal  of  the  International  State  Crime  

Initiative,  London,  Pluto  Press,  1.2,  2012.    

  20  

create coherence in regard to experience, which is understood as being rather formless… (iii) persons live better and in a more ethical way if they have a coherent life-story and coherent narrative identity (or, in contrast, narrative is understood as being detrimental because it creates such coherence). (Hyvärinen et al. 2010: 1–2)

 

This  is  a  major  criticism  of  all  narrative-­‐based  social  science  research,  but  one  that  is  currently  being  redressed  by  practitioners  in  the  field.  Evidence  on  the  effects  of  trauma  has  done  much  to  problematize  the  coherence  norm  (Andrews  2010:  148).24  But  in  the  field  of  human  rights  advocacy,  without  sustained  challenge,  it  remains  implied  that  self-­‐narration  naturally  coheres  to  human  rights  norms.  

Despite  misgivings  about  the  uses  to  which  self-­‐narration  as  testimony  has  been  steered  and  the  epistemological  assumptions  to  which  it  is  subject,  it  is  not  enough  simply  to  throw  out  narrative  practice  and  interpretation  with  this  dirty  bathwater.  As  Norman  Denzin  (1989:  62)  suggests,  we  are  not  tasked  with  identifying  narrative  coherence  to  be  either  an  illusion  or  a  reality,  but,  rather,  we  must  inquire  into  “how  individuals  give  coherence  to  their  lives…  [the]  sources  of  this  coherence,  [and]  the  narratives  that  lie  behind  them”.  

If  we  are  to  see  self-­‐narration  as  a  sub-­‐set  of  testimony  –  that  is,  as  a  truth-­‐telling  action  that  carries  a  special  authority  –  we  must  temper  this  special  status  with  an  examination  of  the  political  and  epistemological  assumptions  that  accompany  narrative  as  a  species  of  evidence.  I  suggest  that  too  often  self-­‐narration  as  testimony  is  conscripted  to  act  as  a  mouthpiece  to  a  liberal  discourse,  a  process  that  is  masked  by  appeal  to  testimony  evidence  as  an  inherent  political  good.  

 

 

 

 

 

 

                                                                                                                         

24  In  the  face  of  mental  disorders  exhibited  by  veterans  of  the  Vietnam  war,  PTSD  was  formally  recognized  by  the  American  Psychiatric  Association  (APA)  in  1980  and  added  to  the  Diagnostic  and  Statistical  Manual  of  Mental  Disorders  (DSM).  Formally  defined,  PTSD  relates  to  an  extraordinary  experience  involving  “actual  or  threatened  death  or  serious  injury,  or  a  physical  threat  to  the  physical  integrity  of  the  self”.  See  American  Psychiatric  Association  (2000:  467–8).  On  occasion  legal  practitioners  are  now  advised  by  experts  on  the  effects  of  trauma.  In  January  2012,  clinical  psychologist  Dr  Jane  Herlihy,  who  directs  The  Centre  for  the  Study  of  Emotion  and  Law,  travelled  to  Phnom  Penh  to  advise  Co-­‐Lead  Civil  Party  Lawyers  among  others  of  the  implications  of  civil  party  participation,  and  particularly  the  risks  of  re-­‐traumatization,  in  the  light  of  failings  during  the  first  case.  

Page 21: The Role of Testimony and Testimonial Analysis in Human Rights Advocacy and Research' in State Crime: Journal of the International State Crime Initiative, Pluto Press, 1.2, Autumn

Patel,  Ian  (2012)  'The  Role  of  Testimony  and  Testimonial  Analysis  in  Human  Rights  Advocacy  and  Research'  in  State  Crime:  Journal  of  the  International  State  Crime  

Initiative,  London,  Pluto  Press,  1.2,  2012.    

  21  

Conscripting  Local  Voices  into  Liberal  Discourse    

To  return  to  the  framing  of  testimony  within  a  liberal  human  rights  discourse,  testimony  tends  to  be  promoted  as  a  form  of  truth-­‐telling  about  the  subject.  Liberal  traditions  of  self-­‐representation,  legal  autonomy,  negative  freedoms,  and  civil  and  political  rights  have  together  provided  the  normative  foundation  of  modern  Western  ideas  about  human  rights,  and  too  often  set  the  frame  of  interpretation  of  self-­‐narration  in  human  rights  advocacy  and  research.  This  may  only  be  indirect  –  only  an  assumption  –  yet  it  gives  a  powerful  inflection  to  interpretations  of  testimony  evidence.  Since  self-­‐narration  is  realized  by  individuals,  narrative  voices  are  assumed  to  confirm  certain  attendant  truths  about  the  individual  as  such  at  the  same  time  as  they  describe  specific  experiences  and  beliefs.  It  is  in  this  sense  that  self-­‐narration  interpreted  at  the  level  of  testimony  can  be  said  to  conscript  narratives  to  a  liberal  human  rights  cause.  

Giving  an  account  of  oneself  in  a  human  rights  context  tends  to  be  seen  as  a  form  of  self-­‐representation.  Narratives  of  victims  are  taken  to  implicitly  recall  liberal  ideas  of  freedom,  what  the  1948  Universal  Declaration  of  Human  Rights  (UDHR),  Article  19,  calls  “the  right  to  freedom  of  opinion  and  expression;  this  right  includes  freedom  to  hold  opinions  without  interference  and  to  seek,  receive  and  impart  information  and  ideas  through  any  media  and  regardless  of  frontiers”.25  

The  central  epistemological  assumption  underwriting  testimony  evidence  has  its  basis  in  a  notion  of  liberal  self-­‐determination:  I  am  free  to  give  an  account  of  myself  and  in  so  doing  proclaim  the  value  of  my  life.  As  the  sign  of  those  rights  I  am  born  into,  I  am  free  to  vindicate,  reflect  on,  or  celebrate  my  lived  experiences,  this  narrative  acting  as  a  testimony  which  in  itself  can  be  seen  as  a  form  of  legal,  moral,  and  political  standing.  

When  human  rights  advocates  and  researchers  imply  that  the  narratives  of  victims  cohere  to  such  a  formulation,  they  are  merely  reproducing  epistemological  assumptions  about  subjectivity  in  the  modern  world.  As  modern  liberal  theory  would  have  it:  “In  speaking  for  themselves,  and  by  contracting  a  social  whole  with  others  who  also  represent  themselves,  subjects  move  from  a  domain  of  exploitation,  illusion  and  heteronomy  to  a  spontaneous  order  of  equal  and  self-­‐determining  individuals”  (Colebrook  2005:  5).26  The  modern  liberal  subject  is  scripted  and  must  cleave  to  certain  norms  in  its  self-­‐expression.  If  the  testimonial  analysis  of  a  human  rights  advocate  is  concerned  to  corroborate  liberal  goods,  it  may  be  necessary  to  deracinate  a  respondent’s  narrative  account  from  the  practices  or  technologies  in  which  it  is  rooted,  in  order  to  give  voice  to  an  underlying  script  about  liberal  subjectivity.  

                                                                                                                         

25  As  Paul  Eakin  (2001:  113)  has  written,  “autobiography”,  despite  its  regulation  by  “normative  models  of  personhood”,  lends  itself  to  “egalitarian  individualism”:  “As  we  might  say  in  the  States,  the  right  to  write  our  life  stories  is  a  natural  extension  of  the  right  to  life,  liberty,  and  the  pursuit  of  happiness.”  26  See  also  Jean-­‐Jacques  Rousseau  (1968:  143).  

Page 22: The Role of Testimony and Testimonial Analysis in Human Rights Advocacy and Research' in State Crime: Journal of the International State Crime Initiative, Pluto Press, 1.2, Autumn

Patel,  Ian  (2012)  'The  Role  of  Testimony  and  Testimonial  Analysis  in  Human  Rights  Advocacy  and  Research'  in  State  Crime:  Journal  of  the  International  State  Crime  

Initiative,  London,  Pluto  Press,  1.2,  2012.    

  22  

Human  rights  texts,  in  the  liberal  tradition,  are  those  in  which  the  speaking  human  voice  is  free  to  affirm  itself  as  a  mode  of  authority  in  itself.  Implicit  to  such  human  rights  discourse  is  a  knowledge-­‐claim  about  what  the  speaking  voice  at  its  humanist  best  should  sound  like.  In  liberal  ideology,  the  human  rights  “voice”  as  experiential  uniqueness  and  as  agentic  self-­‐representation  collude  to  form  a  single  rhetoric:  it  is  exactly  the  humble,  vulnerable,  hard-­‐won,  confessional  human  voice  that  is  authorized  to  sound  the  victory  of  liberal  individualist  freedom.  As  Paul  Fairfield  (2000:  174)  has  written:  “It  has  been  a  guiding  intuition  of  liberal  morality  that  the  self  possesses  a  capacity  for  autonomous  agency  and  self-­‐creation.”  This  autonomous  agency  is  more  precisely  defined  as  a  person’s  ability,  protected  as  a  right,  to  reflect  on  the  norms  to  which  they  are  subject.  As  Habermas’s  well-­‐known  statement  has  it,  “the  modern  legal  order  can  draw  its  legitimacy  only  from  the  idea  of  self-­‐determination:  citizens  should  always  be  able  to  understand  themselves  also  as  authors  of  the  law  to  which  they  are  subject  as  addressees”  (Habermas  1996:  449).  The  difficulty,  in  the  context  of  our  discussion,  is  that  the  authors  of  first-­‐person  “victim  narratives”  are  not  given  the  opportunity  to  reflect  on  the  dominance  of  Western  liberal  subjectivity,  yet  remain  open  to  conscription  to  the  liberal  cause  nevertheless.  

In  the  liberal  tradition,  the  subject’s  self-­‐determination  can  be  seen  as  co-­‐extensive  with  his  self-­‐authoring:  “Liberals  traditionally  have  defended  the  right  of  the  individual  to  become  its  own  author”  (Fairfield  2000:  174).  Despite  “limitations”,  liberalism  justifies  itself  by  “positing  individual  self-­‐creation  as  a  worthy  ideal”,  in  which  individuals  become  “the  principal    author  of  their  own  lives”  (ibid.).  This  self-­‐narrating  faculty  is  not  simply  something  to  be  negatively  protected  by  a  liberal  dispensation,  but  is  the  site  of  an  individual’s  moral  accountability:  “Moral  agents  are  free,  and  are  even  under  an  obligation,  to  assume  responsibility  for  their  own  narrative  history  as  well  as  for  their  particular  actions”  (ibid.:  168).  Liberal  conceptions  of  the  self  invest  a  strong  belief  in  the  autonomous  power  of  self-­‐narration.  

If  the  liberal  subject  is  conceived  according  to  an  idea  of  the  self  as  agent,  and  testimony  evidence  (as  I  am  suggesting)  is  made  to  fit  a  model  of  liberal  subjectivity,  at  what  point  is  agency  conferred  on  the  authors  of  testimony?  It  may  be  impossible  for  human  rights  experts  to  secure  the  subjects  of  testimony  the  material  agency  that  comes  from  living  under  democratic  and  non-­‐repressive  conditions,  but  surely  it  is  possible  for  such  experts  to  further  their  hermeneutical  agency,  in  the  form  of  participation  in  the  meaning  of  their  narrative  history?  

It  is  not  an  exaggeration  to  say  that  human  rights  advocacy  relies  on  testimony  evidence  as  one  of  its  central  tropes,  and  that  testimony  is  seen  to  correspond  to  certain  negative  freedoms.  The  content  of  what  we  might  say  under  duress  of  torture  or  coercive  interrogation  techniques  is  atrocious  precisely  because  of  the  value  we  accord  to  our  self-­‐declarations  as  the  index  of  our  humanity  (and,  increasingly,  identity).  The  unrecognizable,  coerced  narrative  about  oneself  that  might  be  obtained  by  torture  is  a  kind  of  echo  that  lends  one’s  self-­‐narration  as  a  free  juridical  subject  a  more  sombre  timbre.  The  case  of  the  Pakistani-­‐born  American  citizen  Aafia  Siddique,  whose  arrest  is  reported  to  have  been  premised  on  that  fact  that  her  second  husband’s  uncle,  Khalid  Sheikh  Mohammed,  had  named  her  as  an  al-­‐Qaeda  operative  during  his  interrogation  by  the  CIA,  has  an  immediate  complication  in  this  sense.  Her  name  was  revealed  by  Mohammed  under  (questionable)  

Page 23: The Role of Testimony and Testimonial Analysis in Human Rights Advocacy and Research' in State Crime: Journal of the International State Crime Initiative, Pluto Press, 1.2, Autumn

Patel,  Ian  (2012)  'The  Role  of  Testimony  and  Testimonial  Analysis  in  Human  Rights  Advocacy  and  Research'  in  State  Crime:  Journal  of  the  International  State  Crime  

Initiative,  London,  Pluto  Press,  1.2,  2012.    

  23  

interrogation  techniques  (likely  to  have  included  so-­‐called  waterboarding)  designed  to  force  confession.27  This  case,  in  which  a  person  is  likely  to  have  been  made  to  speak  under  duress,  recalls  the  doctrine  of  the  “fruit  of  the  poisonous  tree”.  This  doctrine  stipulates  that  information  revealed  by  a  confession  obtained  by  police,  where  this  confession  is  later  ruled  to  have  been  improperly  obtained,  is  inadmissible  evidence.  If  the  “tree”  itself  is  poisonous,  then  anything  produced  by  that  tree  –  its  “fruit”  –  must  too  be  toxic  and  therefore  disregarded.28  Self-­‐narration  in  the  context  of  human  rights,  then,  is  always  a  strange  kind  of  fruit.  In  liberal  discourse  it  is  upheld  as  the  emblem  of  a  subject’s  self-­‐determination.  But  this  emblematic  status  has  an  underside  as  forced  or  coerced  speech.29  

In  the  context  of  the  evolution  of  human  rights,  Joseph  Slaughter  (1997:  407)  has  proposed  that  “human  rights  in  general,  and  human  rights  law  in  particular,  can  be  understood  in  terms  of  narrative  genres  and  narrative  voices”.  Drawing  on  the  work  of  Adeno  Addis,  Slaughter  traces  an  “individualist”  credo  in  international  human  rights  law  dependent  on  an  Enlightenment  (Descartes  and  Rousseau)  conception  of  the  universal  knowable  subject.30  This  juridical  subject  is  a  victoriously  autonomous  self,  “the  hero  of  her  own  personal  narrative  of  human  dignity,  enlightenment,  and  liberation”  (Slaughter  1997:  411).  This  self-­‐declarative  narrative  presents  itself  as  discrete  from  the  normative  social  world  that  precedes  and  exceeds  it.  

For  Slaughter,  the  subject  enshrined  in  human  rights  discourse  should  be  defined  in  terms  of  her  ability  to  “speak”  as  a  subject  rather  than  in  terms  of  an  inherent  humanness:  “As  conceptions  of  the  speaking  subject  change,  whether  over  time  or  across  cultures,  so  too  must  conceptions  of  human  rights  that  guarantee  the  subject’s  ability  to  narrate  herself”  (ibid.:  412).  We  are  shocked  into  social  relationality  and  responsibility  by  our  ability  to  speak  (or  have  our  speech  silenced  or  coerced):  “the  testimony  offered  by  victims  of  human  rights  abuses  tends  to  suggest  that,  even  if  the  subject  is  ultimately  unknowable,  the  individual,  through  self-­‐narration,  experiences  herself  as  a  distinct  spatio-­‐historical  being”  (ibid.:  429).  If  human  rights  exist  on  a  “continuum  of  narratability”,  human  rights  violations  “target  the  voice”  –  and,  therefore,  “the  voice  should  be  the  focus  of  international  human  rights  instruments”  (ibid.:  407).  This  notion  concentrates  self-­‐narration  as  the  focus  of  political  norms:  “As  we  better  understand  what  a  subject  needs  to  be  able  to  tell  her  story,  we  can  evaluate  entitlements  and  prohibitions  for  their  effectiveness  in  guaranteeing  the  ability  to  self-­‐narrate”  (ibid.:  430).  For  Slaughter,  human  rights  norms  must  be  redefined  in  terms  of  the  “liberty  to  tell  one’s  story”  (ibid.:  415).  

                                                                                                                         

27  At  the  time  of  Khalid  Sheikh  Mohammed’s  interrogation  (2002–03),  however,  such  techniques  had  not  been  ruled  illegal  by  the  Attorney  General.  See  Mark  Tran  (2008).    28  This  legal  metaphor  represents  a  general  principle  in  United  States  law;  in  English  law,  on  the  contrary,  such  evidence  is  not  inadmissible.  See  Paul  Mirfield  (1997:  336).  29  The  idea  that  a  right  (autonomous  speech)  attains  its  meaning  in  the  “mirror”  of  its  counter-­‐value  (coerced  or  forced  speech).  For  a  discussion  of  such  binary  coding  and  more  general  discussion  of  “systems  theory”,  which  helps  explains  the  processes  of  reduction  and  totalization  by  which  the  law  operates,  see  Emilios  Christodoulidis’s  chapter  “Luhmann’s  Systems  Theory”  (1998:  89–91).  30  For  further  discussion,  see  Addis  (1992).  

Page 24: The Role of Testimony and Testimonial Analysis in Human Rights Advocacy and Research' in State Crime: Journal of the International State Crime Initiative, Pluto Press, 1.2, Autumn

Patel,  Ian  (2012)  'The  Role  of  Testimony  and  Testimonial  Analysis  in  Human  Rights  Advocacy  and  Research'  in  State  Crime:  Journal  of  the  International  State  Crime  

Initiative,  London,  Pluto  Press,  1.2,  2012.    

  24  

One  may  think  that  Slaughter  over-­‐emphasizes  the  importance  of  self-­‐narration  when  he  refers  to  it  as  the  measure  of  human  rights.  In  one  sense,  Slaughter’s  claim  chimes  nicely  with  the  rise  of  victim-­‐centred  justice,  which  emphasizes  victim  participation  (testimony)  as  central  to  victims’  procedural  justice.  By  promoting  self-­‐narration  in  this  way,  Slaughter  in  fact  perpetuates  the  notion  of  self-­‐narration  as  synonymous  with  testimony.  Yet  if  we  are  to  believe  Slaughter  when  he  says  that  self-­‐narration  is  the  sign  of  the  liberal  subject  itself  –  and  therefore  inescapable  given  that  liberalism  is  the  dominant  global  political  order  –  one  may  in  fact  do  well  to  promote  “effectiveness  in  guaranteeing  the  ability  to  self-­‐narration”,  howsoever  we  wish  to  define  the  terms  of  such  a  guarantee.  

In  this  sense  it  is  no  surprise  that  post-­‐1990  Nelson  Mandela  –  at  once  liberal  politico  and  local  voice  of  victimhood  –  would  become  a  figurehead  for  the  export  of  human  rights  and  transitional  justice  across  the  globe.  In  1995,  for  instance,  the  Washington  DC  Institute  of  Peace  produced  a  three-­‐volume  work  entitled  Transitional  Justice:  How  Emerging  Democracies  Reckon  With  Former  Regimes,  with  a  foreward  by  Mandela.  In  his  foreward,  Mandela  speaks  a  justice  script  whose  legitimacy  is  confirmed  by  readers’  knowledge  of  Mandela  as  a  local  testifier  to  apartheid  oppression:  “In  nearly  all  instances,  the  displaced  regimes  were  characterised  by  massive  violations  of  human  rights  and  undemocratic  systems  of  governance.  In  their  attempt  to  combat  real  or  perceived  opposition,  they  exercised  authority  with  very  little  regard  to  accountability”  (Mandela  1995:  xxi).  Mandela’s  aim  in  this  statement  is  to  make  undemocratic  and  repressive  rule  conform  to  a  standardized  justice  script,  made  in  the  name  of  “an  international  community  predicated  on  human  dignity  and  justice”  (ibid.).  Figures  like  Mandela  and  Aung  San  Suu  Kyi  are  paraded  around  the  Western  world  because,  among  other  reasons,  they  appear  to  be  a  combination  of  local  experience  and  global  liberalism,  and  will  speak  to  that  effect.  

We  have  been  discussing  the  imperative  to  self-­‐narrate  in  the  liberal  tradition.  Slaughter’s  notion  that  self-­‐narration  presents  distinct  spatio-­‐historical  realities  confirms  it  as  an  important  evidentiary  resource  for  coming  to  terms  with  human  lives  and  the  political  realities  that  shape  them.  Yet,  as  we  have  seen,  we  must  question  the  extent  to  which  the  epistemology  of  testimony  follows  a  different  pattern,  by  which  the  meaning  and  supposed  utility  of  narrative  accounts  are  orchestrated  on  behalf  of  their  authors  by  expert  intermediaries.  

In  the  case  of  human  rights  advocacy  and  research  which  utilizes  the  stories  of  others,  we  must  remain  alert  to  this  credo  of  self-­‐narration  as  liberal  subjectivity,  yet  we  are  dealing  with  its  corollary  –  namely,  an  institutionalization  of  testimony  by  which  its  final  meaning  and  value  is  realized  by  a  second  party.  In  this  sense,  transitional  justice  –  which  among  other  things  heralds  a  nation’s  entrée  into  the  international  order  of  liberal  states  –  seems  particularly  relevant  to  our  discussion.  The  transitional  justice  enterprise  involves  the  dissemination  of  individuals’  stories.  As  Madlingozi  (2010:  211)  puts  it,  

 

the  transitional  justice  entrepreneur  gets  to  be  the  speaker  or  representative  on  behalf  of  victims,  not  because  the  latter  invited  and  gave  her  a  mandate  but  because  the  

Page 25: The Role of Testimony and Testimonial Analysis in Human Rights Advocacy and Research' in State Crime: Journal of the International State Crime Initiative, Pluto Press, 1.2, Autumn

Patel,  Ian  (2012)  'The  Role  of  Testimony  and  Testimonial  Analysis  in  Human  Rights  Advocacy  and  Research'  in  State  Crime:  Journal  of  the  International  State  Crime  

Initiative,  London,  Pluto  Press,  1.2,  2012.    

  25  

entrepreneur  sought  the  victim  out,  categorized  her,  defined  her,  theorized  her,  packaged  her,  and  disseminated  her  on  the  world  stage.  

 

Within  this  process,  “‘the  story’  is  the  central  device  in  sustaining  the  transitional  justice  industry”  (ibid.:  225).  The  story  is  also,  of  course,  an  individualizing  trope,  converting  victims  from  their  place  within  wider  social  movements  into  the  unit  of  human  rights,  the  individual.  

We  now  may  be  able  to  see  one  way  in  which  the  epistemology  of  testimony  supports  a  power  relation:  Alcoff  and  Gray  (1993:  278,  284),  for  instance,  in  their  treatment  of  survivor  discourse,  maintain  that  “[b]efore  we  speak  we  need  to  look  at  where  the  incitement  to  speak  originates,  what  relations  of  power  and  domination  may  exist  between  those  who  incite  and  those  who  are  asked  to  speak,  as  well  as  those  to  whom  the  disclosure  is  directed”.  Where  I  do  fall  in  with  the  political  critique  of  testimony  evidence,  then,  is  on  this  question  of  agency.  The  dissemination  of  the  narratives  of  victims  and  survivors  is  indeed  a  political  good,  but  this  needs  to  be  counterpoised  with  the  harms  of  victim  dependency  on  expert  interpretation.  

 

 

Testimony  Evidence  and  Norms  of  Recognition    

We  have  been  discussing  the  deep  epistemological  currents  running  through  the  liberal  enterprise  of  human  rights  advocacy.  We  can  now  move  to  consider  a  final  epistemological  assumption:  not  only  is  self-­‐narration  something  which  serves  a  truth-­‐telling  function,  it  is  also  assumed  to  be  beholden  to  a  logic  of  recognition.  Like  “truth-­‐telling”,  “recognition”  as  a  trope  of  human  rights  advocacy  and  research  is  dangerously  under-­‐theorized.  

Securing  victims  of  state  crime  with  a  sense  of  acknowledgement  and  recognition  has  been  a  central  concern  of  so-­‐called  victim-­‐centred  justice.  This  discussion  is  not  intended  to  detract  from  the  sense  of  recognition  that  has  been  felt  by  many  participants  in  transitional  justice  mechanisms  and  human  rights  projects.  Rather,  it  seeks  to  question  “recognition”  as  a  term  and  sub-­‐set  of  justice  in  international  formulations  of  human  rights.  

In  the  dominant  human  rights  paradigm,  “to  recognize”  is  a  transitive  verb  –  that  is  to  say,  a  person  is  recognized  to  be  something.  Those  who  have  suffered  a  particular  kind  of  violent  oppression  are  recognized  to  be  victims  of  human  rights  violations.  What  kind  of  normative  understanding  is  perpetuated  in  such  acts  of  recognition?  

Recognition,  we  might  say,  belongs  to  the  closed  economy  of  prevailing  political  categories  and  legal  norms.  To  be  recognized  within  such  conditions  is  at  the  same  time  to  be  regimented  within  a  particular  value-­‐order.  What  is  sustaining  to  the  subject  in  such  conditions  is  also  sustaining  to  the  prevailing  value-­‐order.  

Page 26: The Role of Testimony and Testimonial Analysis in Human Rights Advocacy and Research' in State Crime: Journal of the International State Crime Initiative, Pluto Press, 1.2, Autumn

Patel,  Ian  (2012)  'The  Role  of  Testimony  and  Testimonial  Analysis  in  Human  Rights  Advocacy  and  Research'  in  State  Crime:  Journal  of  the  International  State  Crime  

Initiative,  London,  Pluto  Press,  1.2,  2012.    

  26  

I  have  suggested  above  that  epistemology  is  often  the  means  by  which  political  allegiances  are  neutralized.  I  now  want  to  discuss  in  more  detail  this  merging  of  narrative,  epistemology,  testimony,  and  politics.  I  will  suggest  that  human  rights  advocacy  recognizes  self-­‐narration  as  an  expressly  political  account,  and  in  doing  so  regulates  such  narrative  evidence  according  to  its  own  norms.  

To  speak  of  testimony  as  “political  accounts”  is  also  to  confront  the  manner  in  which  human  rights  culture  and  institutions  stage,  instigate,  and  provide  space  for  (and,  more  often,  regulate,  orchestrate,  and  define)  the  reception  of  testimony  that  bears  on  experience  of  social  suffering  or  political  oppression.  As  Veena  Das  and  Arthur  Kleinman  (2001:  21)  have  suggested  in  a  discussion  about  such  testimony,  “at  the  macro  level  of  the  political  system”,  there  is  the  need  for  “the  creation  of  a  public  space  that  gives  recognition”  to  individuals’  accounts.  The  notion  that  the  international  community  has  a  responsibility  to  allow  houseroom  for  the  political  accounts  of  others  to  be  recognized  is  well-­‐known.  The  epistemology  of  human  rights  advocacy  adapts  this  theme  to  imply  that  testimony,  as  political  discourse,  has  a  responsibility  to  cohere  with  current  schemes  of  political  recognition.  

If  social  recognition  refers  to  established  norms  of  social  and  moral  personhood,  political  recognition,  in  the  above  sense,  refers  not  simply  to  these  same  norms,  but  to  the  paradigms  of  the  human  personality  protected  in  the  discourse  of  human  rights  that  exists  in  international  law.  Recognition,  in  the  texts  of  international  law,  belongs  to  the  “unified,  monadic,  self-­‐possessed  individual”  of  libertarian  philosophy  (Slaughter  2007:  19).  The  idea  that  self-­‐narration  concerning  social  suffering  or  oppression  must  frame  itself  in  established  political  languages  is  underwritten  by  an  assumption  that  the  author  of  such  a  narrative  is  speaking  as  a  political  subject.  As  a  political  subject,  one  speaks  a  language  of  “sameness”,  a  discourse  of  “common  modalities  of  the  human  being’s  extension  into  the  civil  and  social  order”  (ibid.:  17).  It  is  as  though  the  self-­‐narrating  subject  must  perform  the  equal  humanity  and  fundamental  dignity  of  the  human  personality  found  in  both  the  self  and  others,  so  that  this  abstraction,  protected  in  law,  can  be  recognized,  ratified,  achieved.  Slaughter  has  written  of  this  performativity  that  such  “acquisition  of  human  rights  fluency  climaxes  in  a  recognition  scene  in  which  the  individual  formally  recognizes  itself  as  a  subject  of  human  rights  –  as  one  subject  among  others”  (ibid.:  253).  The  self-­‐narrating  subject,  in  this  view,  recognizes  her  own  place  within  a  process  of  political  recognition  only  after  she  herself  has  performatively  taken  authorship  of  it.  

Given  that  testimony  is  an  established  road  to  political  recognition  and  hence  forms  of  enfranchisement,  to  risk  unintelligibility  and  misrecognition  might  be  seen  as  inadequate  to  the  task  of  political  action.  Incomplete  recognition  may  diminish  the  intelligibility  and  therefore  the  effectiveness  of  one’s  account.  To  qualify  as  political  discourse,  and  thus  utilizable  evidence,  testimony  is  made  to  traffic  in  normative  or  recognizable  discourse.  Since  narrative-­‐based  evidence  is  made  to  function  as  a  kind  of  testimony  within  public  processes  of  political  recognition,  it  is  urged  towards  making  its  narrative  subjects,  especially  the  “self”  at  the  centre  of  narration,  fully  recognizable.  Until  this  process  of  recognition  becomes  dialogical  as  opposed  to  unilateral,  victims  of  state  crime  will  continue  to  be  incorporated  into  a  dominant  paradigm  of  human  rights  in  the  act  of  recognition.  

Page 27: The Role of Testimony and Testimonial Analysis in Human Rights Advocacy and Research' in State Crime: Journal of the International State Crime Initiative, Pluto Press, 1.2, Autumn

Patel,  Ian  (2012)  'The  Role  of  Testimony  and  Testimonial  Analysis  in  Human  Rights  Advocacy  and  Research'  in  State  Crime:  Journal  of  the  International  State  Crime  

Initiative,  London,  Pluto  Press,  1.2,  2012.    

  27  

This  discussion  of  the  political  function  that  self-­‐narration  asks  or  is  asked  to  perform  might  lead  us  to  think  that,  in  effect,  there  are  two  ways  of  giving  an  account  of  oneself.  The  first  we  give  as  the  image  of  human  rights  law,  a  political  subject  mobilized  as  an  accountable  being  legally  and  institutionally.  This  first-­‐order  account  is  dependent  on  those  norms  which  form  and  inform  our  status  as  a  subject  and  provide  the  political  frames  available  to  us.31  Thus,  in  accounting  for  ourselves  politically,  we  might  call  upon  our  status  as  a  national  citizen  protected  by  standards  of  human  rights,  a  nationality  that  is  secured  in  turn  by  a  sovereignty  that  is  recognized  under  international  law.  If  we  position  ourselves  as  rightful  claimants  to  such  political  rights  following  our  citizenship,  we  are  by  the  same  token  accountable  to  the  established  legal  and  moral  order  that  underpins  such  rights.  Equally,  in  narrating  oneself  as  a  political  subject,  there  is  a  further  normative  expectation  that  one  speaks  into  embodiment  the  abstract,  legal  conception  of  the  individual.  One’s  self-­‐recognition  as  a  political  subject  is  simultaneously  made  to  uphold  “the  right  [of  everyone]  to  recognition  everywhere  as  a  person  before  the  law”  (Article  6,  UDHR).  To  become  a  claimant  to  certain  rights,  as  Seyla  Benhabib  (2001:  16)  has  written,  presupposes  a  “prior  claim  of  membership”.  In  having  a  relationship  to  such  rights,  she  maintains,  “one  is  already  a  member  of  an  organized  political  and  legal  community”,  and  such  entitlements  “create  reciprocal  obligations  among  consociates,  that  is,  among  those  who  are  already  recognized  as  members  of  a  legal  community”.  Moreover,  to  speak  about  oneself  in  the  language  of  rights  is  to  come  into  full  possession  of  those  rights  –  to  become  “integrated”  to  those  “practices  and  rules,  constitutional  traditions  and  institutional  habits,  which  bring  individuals  together  to  form  a  functioning  political  community”  (Benhabib  2001:  55).  

The  “second”  account  we  give  according  to  our  own  personal  conception  of  ourselves.  This  second-­‐order  narrative  is  accountable  to  one’s  sense  of  oneself  as  a  social  being  perhaps  but,  unlike  the  first  account,  it  serves  no  instrumental  or  pragmatic  function.  That  is,  second-­‐order  accounts  do  not  operate  under  a  regulatory  demand  but  are  better  positioned  to  risk  unintelligibility,  unofficial  status,  and  self-­‐criticism.  An  account  pragmatically  aimed  towards  securing  established  political  rights  or  “recognition”,  or  an  account  that  must  satisfy  a  real-­‐world  demand  made  of  it,  often  cannot  risk  second-­‐order  ambiguity,  self-­‐questioning,  or  paradox  (paradox  here  used  in  the  strict  sense  of  statements  made  against  or  “beyond”  received  paradigms).  Second-­‐order  accounts  stand  in  tension  with,  and  can  be  made  to  function  as  a  critique  of,  first-­‐order  accounts.  It  should  be  clear  that  human  rights  advocacy  –  because  of  its  commitment  to  effectiveness  –  is  primed  to  turn  second-­‐order  accounts  into  first-­‐order  ones.  Many  human  rights  researchers,  for  instance,  worry  that  respondents  are  telling  them  what  the  international  community  wants  to  hear.  And  can  we  blame  them  for  doing  so?  

 

 

                                                                                                                         

31  This  notion  of  “first-­‐order”  and  “second-­‐order”  self-­‐narration  is  indebted  to  Nancy  Fraser  (2010),  who  relates  these  terms  to  conceptions  of  justice.  

Page 28: The Role of Testimony and Testimonial Analysis in Human Rights Advocacy and Research' in State Crime: Journal of the International State Crime Initiative, Pluto Press, 1.2, Autumn

Patel,  Ian  (2012)  'The  Role  of  Testimony  and  Testimonial  Analysis  in  Human  Rights  Advocacy  and  Research'  in  State  Crime:  Journal  of  the  International  State  Crime  

Initiative,  London,  Pluto  Press,  1.2,  2012.    

  28  

Closing  Remarks    

In  the  field  of  human  rights  research,  there  remains  the  urgent  criminological  need  to  conduct  empirical  investigation  into  the  experiences  of  those  who  have  suffered  under  forms  of  political  oppression.  Narrative-­‐based  evidence  ought  to  remain  central  to  human  rights  research  in  the  light  of  this  need.  Yet  researchers  and  advocates  must  more  firmly  address  the  trend  by  which  the  narrative  accounts  of  witnesses  are  adapted  to  the  explicitness  and  tendentiousness  of  purposive  testimony.  

Where  human  rights  research  is  concerned,  special  attention  must  be  paid  to  epistemology.  This  discussion  has  revealed  the  urgent  need  for  an  epistemology  that  is  not  only  faithful  to  the  social  world  presented  in  the  narratives  of  victims,  but  one  that  is  framed  to  advance  victims’  consciousness  about  and  participation  in  the  political  meaning  of  their  narratives.  In  order  to  prevent  victims  of  state  crime  becoming  the  mouthpieces  of  a  self-­‐proclaiming  liberal  discourse,  human  rights  advocates  might  put  greater  effort  into  furthering  the  hermeneutical  participation  of  victims.  It  may  be  that  such  a  dialogical  project,  in  which  experts  and  respondents  together  construct  the  meaning  and  frames  of  reference  of  a  testimonial  account,  is  inappropriate  to  the  professional  practice  of  human  rights  advocacy.  In  this  case,  testimony  evidence  should  nevertheless  cease  to  be  used  as  a  device  against  censure  –  as  a  methodological  trope  designed  to  protect  the  credibility  and  progressiveness  of  an  advocacy  cause.  

 

 

References    

Addis,  A.  (1992)  “Individualism,  Communitarianism,  and  the  Rights  of  Ethnic  Minorities”,  Notre  Dame  Law  Review  67:  1233–61.  

Alcoff,  L.  and  Gray,  L.  (1993)  “Survivor  Discourse:  Transgression  or  Recuperation?”  Signs  18(2):  260–90.  

American  Psychiatric  Association  (2000)  Diagnostic  and  Statistical  Manual,  4th  rev  edn.  Washington,  DC:  APA.  

Anderson,  A.  (2006)  The  Way  We  Argue  Now:  A  Study  in  the  Cultures  of  Theory.  Princeton,  NJ:  Princeton  University  Press.  

Andrews,  M.  (2010)  “Beyond  Narrative:  The  Shape  of  Traumatic  Testimony”,  in  M.  Hyvärinen,  L.  Hydén,  M.  Saarenheimo  and  M.  Tamboukou,  eds,  Beyond  Narrative  Coherence  (Studies  in  Narrative).  Amsterdam:  John  Benjamins.  

Page 29: The Role of Testimony and Testimonial Analysis in Human Rights Advocacy and Research' in State Crime: Journal of the International State Crime Initiative, Pluto Press, 1.2, Autumn

Patel,  Ian  (2012)  'The  Role  of  Testimony  and  Testimonial  Analysis  in  Human  Rights  Advocacy  and  Research'  in  State  Crime:  Journal  of  the  International  State  Crime  

Initiative,  London,  Pluto  Press,  1.2,  2012.    

  29  

Andrews,  M.,  Squire,  C.  and  Tamboukou,  M.  (2008)  “Introduction:  What  is  Narrative  Research?”  in  M.  Andrews,  C.  Squire  and  M.  Tamboukou,  eds,  Doing  Narrative  Research.  London:  Sage,  pp.  1–22.  

Bell,  L.A.  (2010)  Storytelling  for  Social  Justice:  Connecting  Narrative  and  the  Arts  in  Antiracist  Teaching.  Oxford:  Routledge.  

Benhabib,  S.  (2001)  Transformations  of  Citizenship:  Dilemmas  of  the  Nation  State  in  the  Era  of  Globalization:  Two  Lectures.  Assan:  Koninklijke  Van  Gorcum.  

Bennett,  J.  (1981)  Oral  History  and  Delinquency:  The  Rhetoric  of  Criminology.  Chicago,  IL:  University  of  Chicago  Press.  

Beverley,  J.  (1992)  “The  Margin  at  the  Centre:  On  Testimonio  (Testimonial  Narrative)”,  in  S.  Smith  and  J.  Watson,  eds,  De/Colonizing  the  Subject:  The  Politics  of  Gender  in  Woman’s  Autobiography.  Minneapolis,  MN:  University  of  Minnesota  Press,  pp.  91–114.  

Braithwaite,  J.  (2007)  “Building  Legitimacy  Through  Restorative  Justice”,  in  T.R.  Tyler,  ed.,  Legitimacy  and  Criminal  Justice:  International  Perspectives.  New  York:  Russell  Sage  Foundation,  pp.  146–63.  

Bruner,  J.  (2002)  Making  Stories:  Law,  Literature,  Life.  New  York:  Farrar,  Straus  and  Giroux.  

Chamberlayne,  P.,  Bornat,  J.  and  Wengraf,  T.  (2000)  The  Turn  to  Biographical  Methods  in  the  Social  Sciences.  London:  Routledge.  

Christodoulidis,  E.  (1998)  Law  and  Reflexive  Politics.  Dordrecht:  Kluwer.  

Clandinin,  D.J.  and  Connelly,  F.M.  (2000)  Narrative  Inquiry:  Experience  and  Story  in  Qualitative  Research.  San  Francisco,  CA:  Jossey-­‐Bass.  

Clark,  P.  (2010)  The  Gacaca  Courts  and  Post-­‐Genocide  Justice  and  Reconciliation  in  Rwanda:  Justice  without  Lawyers.  Cambridge:  Cambridge  University  Press.  

Cmiel,  K.  (1999)  “The  Emergence  of  Human  Rights  Politics  in  the  United  States”,  The  Journal  of  American  History  86(3):  1231–50.  

Coady,  C.A.J.  (1992)  Testimony:  A  Philosophical  Study.  Oxford:  Clarendon  Press.  

Colebrook,  C.  (2005)  Philosophy  and  Post-­‐Structuralist  Theory:  From  Kant  to  Deleuze.  Edinburgh:  Edinburgh  University  Press.  

Combs,  N.A.  (2010)  Fact-­‐Finding  Without  Facts:  The  Uncertain  Evidentiary  Foundations  of  International  Criminal  Convictions.  Cambridge:  Cambridge  University  Press.  

Das,  V.  and  Kleinman,  A.  (2001)  Remaking  a  World:  Violence,  Social  Suffering,  and  Recovery.  Berkeley,  CA:  University  of  California  Press.  

Page 30: The Role of Testimony and Testimonial Analysis in Human Rights Advocacy and Research' in State Crime: Journal of the International State Crime Initiative, Pluto Press, 1.2, Autumn

Patel,  Ian  (2012)  'The  Role  of  Testimony  and  Testimonial  Analysis  in  Human  Rights  Advocacy  and  Research'  in  State  Crime:  Journal  of  the  International  State  Crime  

Initiative,  London,  Pluto  Press,  1.2,  2012.    

  30  

Denzin,  N.  (1989)  Interpretative  Biography.  Newbury  Park,  CA:  Sage.  

Diamond,  A.  (2010–11)  “Victims  Once  Again?  Civil  Party  Participation  before  the  Extraordinary  Chambers  in  the  Courts  of  Cambodia”,  The  Internet  Journal  of  Rutgers  School  of  Law  38.  

Duff,  A.,  Farmer,  L.,  Marshall,  S.  and  Tadros,  V.  (2007)  The  Trial  on  Trial  –  Volume  3:  Towards  A  Normative  Theory  of  the  Criminal  Trial.  Oxford  and  Portland,  OR:  Hart.  

Eakin,  P.  (2001)  “Breaking  Rules:  The  Consequences  of  Self-­‐Narration”,  Biography  24(1):  113–27.  

Elliot,  J.  (2005)  Using  Narrative  in  Social  Research:  Qualitative  and  Quantitative  Approaches.  London:  Sage.  

Fairfield,  P.  (2000)  Moral  Selfhood  in  the  Liberal  Tradition:  The  Politics  of  Individuality.  Toronto:  University  of  Toronto  Press.  

Felman,  S.  (1991)  “In  an  Era  of  Testimony:  Claude  Lanzmann’s  Shoah”,  Yale  French  Studies  79:  39–81.  

Felman,  S.  and  Laub,  D.  (1992)  Testimony:  Crises  of  Witnessing  in  Literature,  Psychoanalysis  and  History.  New  York  and  London:  Routledge.  

Fraser,  N.  (2010)  Scales  of  Justice:  Reimagining  Political  Space  in  a  Globalizing  World.  New  York:  Columbia  University  Press.  

Fricker,  E.  (1994)  “Against  Gullibility”,  in  B.K.  Matilal  and  A.  Chakrabarty,  eds,  Knowing  From  Words:  Western  and  Indian  Philosophical  Analysis  of  Understanding  and  Testimony.  Dordrecht:  Kluwer.  

Fricker,  M.  (2007)  Epistemic  Injustice:  Power  and  the  Ethics  of  Knowing.  Oxford:  Oxford  University  Press.  

Graham,  P.J.  (1997)  “What  is  Testimony?”  Philosophical  Quarterly  47(187):  227–32.  

Green,  P.  (1990)  The  Enemy  Without:  Policing  and  Class  Consciousness  in  the  Miners’  Strike.  Maidenhead:  Open  University  Press.  

Grice,  P.  (1989)  Studies  in  the  Way  of  Words.  Cambridge,  MA:  Harvard  University  Press.  

Haas,  P.  (1992)  “Introduction:  Epistemic  Communities  and  International  Policy  Coordination”,  in  Knowledge,  Power  and  International  Policy  Coordination,  special  issue,  International  Organization  46:  1–36.  

Habermas,  J.  (1996)  Between  Facts  and  Norms:  Contributions  to  a  Discourse  Theory  of  Law  and  Democracy.  W.  Rehg  (trans.)  Cambridge:  Polity  Press.  

Hillyard,  P.  (1993)  Suspect  Communities:  People’s  Experience  of  the  Prevention  of  Terrorism  Acts  in  Britain.  London:  Pluto.  

Page 31: The Role of Testimony and Testimonial Analysis in Human Rights Advocacy and Research' in State Crime: Journal of the International State Crime Initiative, Pluto Press, 1.2, Autumn

Patel,  Ian  (2012)  'The  Role  of  Testimony  and  Testimonial  Analysis  in  Human  Rights  Advocacy  and  Research'  in  State  Crime:  Journal  of  the  International  State  Crime  

Initiative,  London,  Pluto  Press,  1.2,  2012.    

  31  

Human  Rights  Watch  Report  (2012)  “I  Had  to  Run  Away”:  The  Imprisonment  of  Women  and  Girls  for  “Moral  Crimes”  in  Afghanistan.  Available  online  at  http://www.hrw.org/sites/default/files/reports/afghanistan0312webwcover_0.pdf  (assessed  2  July  2012).  

Hume,  D.  (1777)  Enquiries  Concerning  Human  Understanding  and  Concerning  the  Language  of  Morals.  L.A.  Selby-­‐Bigge  (ed.).  2nd  edn  (1972).  Oxford:  Oxford  University  Press.  

Hyvärinen,  M.,  Hydén,  L.,  Saarenheimo,  M.  and  Tamboukou,  M.  (2010)  “Beyond  Narrative  Coherence”,  in  M.  Hyvärinen,  L.  Hydén,  M.  Saarenheimo  and  M.  Tamboukou,  eds,  Beyond  Narrative  Coherence  (Studies  in  Narrative).  Amsterdam:  John  Benjamins,  pp.  1–17.  

Lackey,  J.  (1999)  “Testimonial  Knowledge  and  Transmission”,  Philosophical  Quarterly  49(197):  471–90.  

——  [Is  this  ok?]  (2008)  Learning  From  Words:  Testimony  as  a  Source  of  Knowledge.  Oxford:  Oxford  University  Press.  

Lackey,  J.  and  Sosa,  E.  (eds)  (2006)  The  Epistemology  of  Testimony.  Oxford:  Clarendon.  

Luckhurst,  R.  (2008)  The  Trauma  Question.  London:  Routledge.  

Madlingozi,  T.  (2010)  “On  Transitional  Justice  Entrepreneurs  and  the  Production  of  Victims”,  The  Journal  of  Human  Rights  Practice  2(2):  208–28.  

Mandela,  N.  (1995)  Foreword  to  N.  Kritz,  ed.,  Transitional  Justice:  How  Emerging  Democracies  Reckon  With  Former  Regimes,  2.  Washington,  DC:  Institute  of  Peace.  

Mander,  H.  (2010)  “‘Words  from  the  Heart’:  Researching  People’s  Stories”,  Journal  of  Human  Rights  Practice  2(2):  252–70.  

McEvoy,  K.  and  McGregor,  L.  (eds)  (2008)  Transitional  Justice  from  Below:  Grassroots  Activism  and  the  Struggle  for  Change.  Oxford:  Hart.  

Mendeloff,  D.  (2004)  “Truth-­‐Seeking,  Truth-­‐Telling,  and  Postconflict  Peacebuilding:  Curb  the  Enthusiasm?”  International  Studies  Review  6:  335–80.  

Metzl,  J.F.  (1996)  “Information  Technology  and  Human  Rights”,  Human  Rights  Quarterly  18(4):  705–46.  

Miéville,  C.  (2006)  Between  Equal  Rights:  A  Marxist  Theory  of  International  Law.  Chicago,  IL:  Haymarket.  

Mirfield,  P.  (1997)  Silence,  Confessions,  and  Improperly  Obtained  Evidence.  Oxford:  Clarendon.  

Neimeyer,  R.  and  Tschudi,  F.  (2003)  “Community  and  Coherence:  Narrative  Contributions  to  the  Psychology  of  Loss  and  Conflict”,  in  G.  Fireman,  T.  McVay  and  O.  Flanagan,  eds,  Narrative  

Page 32: The Role of Testimony and Testimonial Analysis in Human Rights Advocacy and Research' in State Crime: Journal of the International State Crime Initiative, Pluto Press, 1.2, Autumn

Patel,  Ian  (2012)  'The  Role  of  Testimony  and  Testimonial  Analysis  in  Human  Rights  Advocacy  and  Research'  in  State  Crime:  Journal  of  the  International  State  Crime  

Initiative,  London,  Pluto  Press,  1.2,  2012.    

  32  

and  Consciousness:  Literature,  Psychology  and  the  Brain.  New  York  and  Oxford:  Oxford  University  Press,  pp.  166–91.  

Osler,  A.  and  Zhu,  J.  (2011)  “Narratives  in  Teaching  and  Research  for  Justice  and  Human  Rights”,  Education,  Citizenship  and  Social  Justice  6.  

Pham,  P.  and  Vinck,  P.  (2007)  “Empirical  Research  and  the  Development  and  Assessment  of  Transitional  Justice  Mechanisms”,  The  International  Journal  of  Transitional  Justice  1:  231–48.  

Pham,  P.,  Vinck,  P.,  Balthazard,  M.,  Hean,  S.  and  Stover,  E.  (2009)  So  We  Will  Never  Forget:  A  Population-­‐Based  Survey  on  Attitudes  about  Social  Reconstruction  and  the  Extraordinary  Chambers  of  the  Court  of  Cambodia.  Berkeley,  CA:  Human  Rights  Center.  

Pittaway,  E.,  Bartolomei,  L.  and  Hugman,  R.  (2010)  “‘Stop  Stealing  Our  Stories’:  The  Ethics  of  Research  with  Vulnerable  Groups”,  Journal  of  Human  Rights  Practice  2(2):  229–51.  

Pranis,  K.  (2001)  “Restorative  Justice,  Social  Justice,  and  the  Empowerment  of  Marginalized  Populations”,  in  G.  Bazemore  and  M.  Schiff,  eds,  Restorative  Community  Justice:  Repairing  Harm  and  Transforming  Communities.  Cincinnati,  OH:  Anderson,  pp.  287–306.  

Presser,  L.  (2009)  “Narratives  of  Offenders”,  Theoretical  Criminology  13(177).  

Prichard,  D.  (2004)  “Testimony”,  in  A.  Duff,  L.  Farmer,  S.  Marshall  and  V.  Tadros,  eds,  The  Trial  on  Trial  –  Volume  1:  Truth  and  Due  Process.  Oxford  and  Portland,  OR:  Hart.  

Punch,  K.F.  (2005)  Introduction  to  Social  Research:  Quantitative  and  Qualitative  Approaches.  London:  Sage.  

Reed,  K.  and  Padskocimaite,  A.  (2012)  The  Right  Toolkit:  Applying  Research  Methods  in  the  Service  of  Human  Rights.  Berkeley,  CA:  Human  Rights  Center,  University  of  California.  

Rimmon-­‐Kenan,  S.  (2002)  “The  Story  of  ‘I’:  Illness  and  Narrative  Identity”,  Narrative  10(1).  

Rorty,  R.  (1993)  “Human  Rights,  Rationality,  and  Sentimentality”,  in  S.  Shute  and  S.  Hurley,  eds,  On  Human  Rights:  The  Oxford  Amnesty  Lectures  1993.  New  York:  Basic  Books,  pp.  111–34.  

Rothberg,  M.  (2000)  Traumatic  Realism:  The  Demands  of  Holocaust  Representation.  Minneapolis,  MN:  University  of  Minnesota  Press.  

Rousseau,  J.J.  (1968)  The  Social  Contract.  M.  Cranson  (trans.).  London:  Penguin.  

Sanders,  A.  (1987)  “Constructing  the  Case  for  the  Prosecution”,  Journal  of  Law  and  Society  14(2).  

Schaffer,  K.  and  Smith,  S.  (2004)  “Conjunctions:  Life  Narratives  in  the  Field  of  Human  Rights”,  Biography  27(1):  1–24.  

Schechtman,  M.  (1996)  The  Constitution  of  Selves.  Ithaca,  NY:  Cornell  University  Press.  

Page 33: The Role of Testimony and Testimonial Analysis in Human Rights Advocacy and Research' in State Crime: Journal of the International State Crime Initiative, Pluto Press, 1.2, Autumn

Patel,  Ian  (2012)  'The  Role  of  Testimony  and  Testimonial  Analysis  in  Human  Rights  Advocacy  and  Research'  in  State  Crime:  Journal  of  the  International  State  Crime  

Initiative,  London,  Pluto  Press,  1.2,  2012.    

  33  

Schramm,  J.  (2000)  Testimony  and  Advocacy  in  Victorian  Law,  Literature,  and  Theology.  Cambridge:  Cambridge  University  Press.  

Sikkink,  K.  (2011)  The  Justice  Cascade.  New  York  and  London:  Norton.  

Slaughter,  J.  (1997)  “A  Question  of  Narration:  The  Voice  in  International  Human  Rights  Law”,  Human  Rights  Quarterly  19(2):  406–30.  

——  (2007)  Human  Rights,  Inc.:  The  World  Novel,  Narrative  Form,  and  International  Law.  New  York:  Fordham  University  Press.  

Smith,  S.  and  Schaffer,  K.  (2004)  Human  Rights  and  Narrated  Lives:  The  Ethics  of  Recognition.  New  York:  Palgrave  Macmillan.  

Sosa,  E.  (1994)  “Testimony  and  Coherence”,  in  B.K.  Matilal  and  A.  Chakrabarty,  eds,  Knowing  From  Words:  Western  and  Indian  Philosophical  Analysis  of  Understanding  and  Testimony.  Dordrecht:  Kluwer,  pp.  59–69.  

Stevenson,  L.  (1993)  “Why  Believe  What  People  Say?”  Synthese  94(3):  429–51.  

Stover,  E.,  Balthazard,  M.  and  Koenig,  K.A.  (2011)  “Confronting  Duch:  Civil  Party  Participation  in  Case  001  at  the  Extraordinary  Chambers  in  the  Courts  of  Cambodia”,  International  Review  of  the  Red  Cross  93(882).  

Subotic,  J.  (2012)  “The  Transformation  of  International  Transitional  Justice  Advocacy”,  The  International  Journal  of  Transitional  Justice  6(1):  106–25.  

Taylor,  C.  (1989)  Sources  of  the  Self:  The  Making  of  the  Modern  Identity.  Cambridge:  Cambridge  University  Press.  

Tran,  M.  (2008)  “CIA  admit  ‘waterboarding’  al-­‐Qaida  suspects”,  The  Guardian,  5  February.  Available  online  at  http://www.guardian.co.uk/world/2008/feb/05/india.terrorism  (assessed  1  August  2011).  

Turner,  C.  (1996)  “Holocaust  Memories  and  History”,  Journal  of  the  History  of  the  Human  Sciences  9(4):  45–63.  

Weisberg,  R.  (1991)  “Editor’s  Preface”,  Cardozo  Studies  in  Law  and  Literature  3(2):  i–iii.  

Wright,  J.L.  (2006)  The  Philosopher’s  “I”:  Autobiography  and  the  Search  for  the  Self.  Albany,  NY:  State  University  of  New  York  Press.  

Young,  I.M.  (2000)  Inclusion  and  Democracy.  Oxford:  Oxford  University  Press.