the idea of a social scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/winch+the-idea-of-a-social... · the...

160

Upload: doanthuy

Post on 13-Feb-2018

216 views

Category:

Documents


1 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER
Page 2: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

THE IDEA OFA SOCIAL SCIENCE

and its Relation to Philosophy

SECOND EDITION

byPETER WINCH

LONDON

Page 3: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

First published in Great Britain 1958by Routledge & Kegan Paul

and in the United States of Americaby Humanities Press International, Inc.,

Atlantic Highlands, NJ 07716

This edition published in the Taylor & Francis e-Library, 2003.

Second impression 1960Third impression (with some corrections) 1963

Fourth impression 1965Fifth impression 1967Sixth impression 1970

Seventh impression 1971Eighth impression 1973Ninth impression 1976Tenth impression 1977

Eleventh impression 1980 Second edition published 1990 by Routledge in Great Britain and

Humanities Press International, Inc.in the United States of America

© Peter Winch 1958, 1990

All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted orreproduced or utilized in any form or by any electronic, mechanical,

or other means, now known or hereafter invented, includingphotocopying and recording, or in any information storage or

retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers.

British Library Cataloguing in Publication DataA catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library.

ISBN 0-203-01449-9 Master e-book ISBN

ISBN 0-203-16090-8 (Adobe eReader Format)ISBN 0 415-05431-1 (Print Edition)

Page 4: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

v

CONTENTS

PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION ix

I. PHILOSOPHICAL BEARINGS

1. Aims and Strategy 1

2. The Underlabourer Conception of

Philosophy 3

3. Philosophy and Science 7

4. The Philosopher’s Concern with Language 10

5. Conceptual and Empirical Enquiries 15

6. The Pivotal Role of Epistemology in

Philosophy 18

7. Epistemology and the Understanding of

Society 21

8. Rules: Wittgenstein’s Analysis 24

9. Some Misunderstandings of Wittgenstein 33

II. THE NATURE OF MEANINGFULBEHAVIOUR

1. Philosophy and Sociology 40

2. Meaningful Behaviour 45

3. Activities and Precepts 51

4. Rules and Habits 57

5. Reflectiveness 62

Page 5: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

vi CONTENTS

III. THE SOCIAL STUDIES AS SCIENCE

1. J.S.Mill’s ‘Logic of the Moral Sciences’ 66

2. Differences in Degree and Differences in

Kind 71

3. Motives and Causes 75

4. Motives, Dispositions and Reasons 80

5. The Investigation of Regularities 83

6. Understanding Social Institutions 86

7. Prediction in the Social Studies 91

IV. THE MIND AND SOCIETY

1. Pareto: Logical and Non-Logical Conduct 95

2. Pareto: Residues and Derivations 103

3. Max Weber: Verstehen and Causal

Explanation 111

4. Max Weber: Meaningful Action and

Social Action 116

V. CONCEPTS AND ACTIONS

1. The Internality of Social Relations 121

2. Discursive and Non-Discursive ‘Ideas’ 128

3. The Social Sciences and History 131

4. Concluding Remark 136

BIBLIOGRAPHY 137

INDEX 141

Page 6: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

Denn wenn es schon wahr ist, dass moralischeHandlungen, sie mögen zu noch so verschiednenZeiten, bey noch so verschiednen Völkern vorkommen,in sich betrachtet immer die nehmlichen bleiben: sohaben doch darum die nehmlichen Handlungen nichtimmer die nehmlichen Benennungen, und es istungerecht, irgend einer eine andere Benennung zugeben, als die, welche sie zu ihren Zeiten, und beyihrem Volk zu haben pflegte.

(It may indeed be true that moral actions are alwaysthe same in themselves, however different may be thetimes and however different the societies in which theyoccur; but still, the same actions do not always havethe same names, and it is unjust to give any action adifferent name from that which it used to bear in itsown times and amongst its own people.)

(GOTTHOLD EPHRAIM LESSING: Anti-Goeze).

Page 7: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER
Page 8: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

ix

PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION

My reason for declining the publisher’s invitationto revise this book before its next printing is

certainly not that I wish to stand by every word that itcontains, just as it is written. That would be hardlycredible, and certainly not at all creditable, over thirtyyears after its original composition. But a revision of theexisting text would require me to reoccupy theperspective that was mine when I wrote it; and I couldnot do that even if I wanted to. It is not that I think thedeep-seated errors and confusions which I tried toexpose are no longer active. But if I were going to tacklethem now I should naturally wish to address them in theform they take in current thinking; and of course manythings have changed both in philosophy and in the socialsciences in the intervening years. I too have moved on abit. And the interest in the nature and conditions ofvarious forms of human understanding which was thenexpressed in this study of a certain prevalent conceptionof the social sciences has since taken me into ratherdifferent areas of enquiry. For such reasons and others arevision is not something I feel it would be profitable toundertake; whereas a rewriting of the whole book wouldtake me away from other concerns which I find moreimmediately pressing. So I am writing this Preface tosuggest some of the things I should want to saydifferently if I were rewriting the book.

The central core of the argument is really stated inChapter III, Sections 5 and 6. The title of Section 6 is

Page 9: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

x PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION

‘Understanding Social Institutions’. It is important thatI use the word ‘understanding’ at this crucial juncturerather than ‘explaining’. In saying this I do not meannow to allude to the distinction made by Max Weberbetween ‘causal explanation’ and ‘interpretiveunderstanding’ (discussed in Chapter IV, Section 3).The point I have in mind is a rather different one.Methodologists and philosophers of science commonlyapproach their subject by asking what is the characterof the explanations offered in the science underconsideration. Now of course explanations are closelyconnected with understanding. Understanding is thegoal of explanation and the end-product of successfulexplanation. But of course it does not follow that thereis understanding only where there has beenexplanation; neither is this in fact true. I expecteveryone would accept this.

But I should like to go further with a step on whichthe argument of the book in a way hinges. Unless thereis a form of understanding that is not the result ofexplanation, no such thing as explanation would bepossible. An explanation is called for only where thereis, or is at least thought to be, a deficiency inunderstanding. But there has to be some standardagainst which such deficiency is to be measured: andthat standard can only be an understanding that wealready have. Furthermore, the understanding wealready have is expressed in the concepts whichconstitute the form of the subject matter we areconcerned with. These concepts on the other hand alsoexpress certain aspects of the life characteristic ofthose who apply them. These close interconnectionsare the main subject for exploration in the book. As I

Page 10: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

xiPREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION

have said, the most important links are set out inChapter III, Sections 5 and 6.

I think I still want to stand by the main structure ofwhat I wrote in those Sections. But there are twoimportant ways in which I should now want to expressmyself differently in the development of the argument.These concern my use of the words ‘cause’ and ‘rule’.The discussion of the distinction between the natural andthe social sciences in the book revolves round the conceptof generality and the different ways in which thischaracterizes our understanding of natural and socialphenomena respectively. I expressed this difference bysaying that our understanding of natural phenomena is interms of the notion of cause, while our understanding ofsocial phenomena involves the categories of motives andreasons for actions. Furthermore, I argued, whereas thecategory of cause involves generality by way of empiricalgeneralizations, that of a reason for action involvesgenerality by way of rules. And these notions—ofgeneralization and of rule—differ from each other inimportant logical respects.

Unfortunately I undertook no serious investigation ofthe notion of cause. The background to what I wroteabout the distinction between ‘cause’ and ‘motive’ wasJohn Stuart Mill’s virtual assimilation of both thesenotions into a Humean account of causality in which thefundamental category was that of a regularityestablished by empirical observation. Perhaps this waspolemically justified in so far as the main targets of mycriticisms were writers who made a similar assimilation.I did, it is true, express reservations about Hume’saccount (e.g. in Chapter V, Section 1). But this was notexplored to any significant degree. The result was that I

Page 11: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

xii PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION

found myself at times denying that human behaviour canbe understood in causal terms, when I should have beensaying that our understanding of human behaviour is notelucidated by anything like the account given of ‘cause’by Hume (and Mill). Now this account is of course alsoinadequate as an elucidation of our understanding of thephenomena of nature. So to state the distinction betweenthe social and natural sciences in such terms as thesewould have required some investigation of the differentreasons for the inadequacy of the Humean account asapplied to the natural scientific use of the word ‘cause’and for its inadequacy as applied to talk about ‘reasons’and ‘motives’ for human actions.

But it would probably have been better not to try toexpress the distinction in such terms at all. The importantpoint to remember here is that the word ‘cause’ (andrelated words) are used in a very wide variety of differentways in different contexts. Hume’s account applies perhapspretty well to some of these uses, to others hardly at all. Wedo use causal language when we are exploring people’smotives. ‘What made him do that?’ ‘What was the cause ofhis doing that?’) ‘It was a combination of ambition, greedand jealousy.’ And there is of course absolutely nothingwrong with this way of talking; it cannot be said to bemerely metaphorical. It follows that causal notions doapply to human behaviour. But it would be a great mistaketo think that, in saying this, we are saying anythingsubstantial about the form of explanation andunderstanding of his behaviour that is in question. Moreparticularly, because we also speak, for example, of thecause of the engine’s failure to start being dirty sparkingplugs, it would be quite wrong to infer that we are dealingwith an explanation of the same kind as that offered in the

Page 12: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

xiiiPREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION

previous example. The phrase ‘causal explanation’, wemight perhaps say, indicates what is being explained—roughly, the source or origin of something—and so far sayslittle or nothing about how it is being explained, or aboutwhat the explanation looks like.

There is a rather parallel distortion in the way Iwrote about ‘rules’ in what I said about ourunderstanding of human behaviour. My strategy was tosketch what I took to be the central feature ofWittgenstein’s discussion of the notion of following arule, in its application to the use of language, and toapply that discussion to human behaviour much moregenerally. That still seems to me a good strategy: notleast because it is a central feature of whatWittgenstein writes about language that this can onlybe seen for what it is if looked at in the more generalcontext of behaviour in which it is embedded. Butunfortunately I was far from sufficiently careful in theway I expressed the relevance of the notion of a rule,both to language and to other forms of behaviour.

In Chapter I, Section 8, where I first discussed thematter seriously, I did not explicitly write that all uses oflanguage are rule-governed. But in Chapter II, Section 2I was much less circumspect: the claim (which I thinkright) that being committed to some future action bywhat I do now is formally similar to being committed toa subsequent use of a word by a definition, is followedby: ‘It follows that I can only be committed tosomething in the future by what I do now if my presentact is the application of a rule’ (p. 50). But this does notfollow from anything said in the previous section, nor doI think it true as it stands. Things become worse inChapter II, Section 3, where I claimed that ‘all

Page 13: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

xiv PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION

behaviour which is meaningful (therefore all specificallyhuman behaviour) is ipso facto rule-governed’ (p. 52). Idid, it is true, attempt to qualify this later in the Sectionby distinguishing different kinds of rules, but I do notnow think this enough to put things right.

One of the best statements of the truth of the matter,it seems to me, is in Sections 81 and 82 ofWittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations, Part I:

F.P.Ramsey once emphasized in conversation withme that logic was a ‘normative science’. I do not knowexactly what he had in mind, but it was doubtlessclosely related to what only dawned on me later:namely, that in philosophy we often compare the use ofwords with games and calculi which have fixed rules,but cannot say that someone who is using languagemust be playing such a game.

* * *What do I call the rule by which he proceeds?—The

hypothesis that satisfactorily describes his use ofwords, which we observe; or the rule which he looks upwhen he uses signs; or the one which he gives us inreply if we ask him what the rule is?—But what ifobservation does not enable us to see any clear rule,and the question brings none to light?—For he didindeed give me a definition when I asked him what heunderstood by ‘N’, but he was prepared to withdrawand alter it.—So how am I to determine the ruleaccording to which he is playing? He does not know ithimself.—Or, to ask a better question: What meaning isthe expression ‘the rule by which he proceeds’supposed to have left to it here?

Had I paid proper heed to these remarks (and others insimilar vein) I might have avoided the impression

Page 14: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

xvPREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION

sometimes given in this book of social practices,traditions, institutions etc. as more or less self-containedand each going its own, fairly autonomous, way. Aparticularly unfortunate example of this occurs in amuch quoted and much criticized passage in Chapter IV,Section 1. On p.100 I wrote that ‘criteria of logic are nota direct gift of God, but arise out of, and are onlyintelligible in the context of, ways of living or modes ofsocial life’. That still seems to me basically right. But Ithen went on to develop the thought in a misleadingway. ‘It follows that one cannot apply criteria of logic tomodes of social life as such. For instance, science is onesuch mode and religion is another; and each has criteriaof intelligibility peculiar to itself’. There are severalthings wrong with that way of putting the matter. Forone thing it is quite wrong to suppose that all the aspectsof human life to which the thought is supposed to applyare on the same footing. I myself stressed this point in apaper which I wrote not long after this book (‘Natureand Convention’, reprinted in Peter Winch, Ethics andAction, Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1972, especially pp.58–9), where I argued that it is misleading to callscience and morality, in the same breath as it were,‘forms of activity’. A similar point could be made(though not quite in the same way) about science andreligion. Again, and connectedly, the suggestion thatmodes of social life are autonomous with respect to eachother was insufficiently counteracted by my qualifyingremark (on p. 101) about ‘the overlapping character ofdifferent modes of social life’. Different aspects ofsocial life do not merely ‘overlap’: they are frequentlyinternally related in such a way that one cannot even beintelligibly conceived as existing in isolation from

Page 15: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

xvi PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION

others. (Rush Rhees has an important discussion of thispoint in his paper ‘Wittgenstein’s Builders’ in hisDiscussions of Wittgenstein, Routledge & Kegan Paul,1969.)

Proper attention to the passage from PhilosophicalInvestigations I have referred to might have helped meto see more clearly the importance of these and relatedpoints and saved me from the crudities of the way Istated my case in Chapter IV, Section 1. This would nothave weakened my argument against Pareto in thatSection, but strengthened it. In effect I was criticizinghim for an over-idealization of logic, without havingescaped sufficiently myself from the very same tendencyto over-idealization. The logico-conceptual difficultieswhich arise when ways of thinking which have theirroots in different reaches of human life are brought tobear on each other cannot be resolved by any appeal toa formal system—whether a God-given system oflogical principles or a system of modes of social life,each with criteria of intelligibility peculiar to itself.

Equally, greater clarity about the way the notion of arule relates to human behaviour would, if anything, havestrengthened the force of the contrasts I drew betweenthe social and natural sciences. Some of my pointswould have had to be formulated rather differentlyhowever. For instance, I would not have been able to saybaldly, as on p.62: It is only because human actionsexemplify rules that we can speak of past experience asrelevant to our current behaviour.’ The point I wanted tomake could only be adequately expressed at somelength, but an approximation might be: The kinds ofrelevance past experience has to current behaviour canbe brought out only in so far as that behaviour

Page 16: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

xviiPREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION

exemplifies rules or is, in relevant respects, analogous tobehaviour which exemplifies rules.

So, though I think that the points I have made so fardo concern important shortcomings in the way in whichI developed the contrast between the natural and socialsciences in this book, the main outlines of that contrastseem to me to stand. But this does not mean that I thinkthere is nothing at all amiss with the overall thrust of theargument. At the beginning of Chapter V, Section 2 Isuggested that ‘social interaction can more profitably becompared to the exchange of ideas in a conversationthan to the interaction of forces in a physical system’ (p.128). That still seems to me right enough as far as itgoes. The trouble is, however, that I was too single-mindedly concerned with the negative side of the claim,with the result that I never seriously followed up myown suggestion to look at the comparison betweensocial life and the exchange of ideas in a conversation.

Had I done so, I might have been struck by thefragility of the ethico-cultural conditions which makesuch an exchange of ideas possible. In essays writtenafter the publication of The Idea of a Social Science—for instance, those numbered 2 to 5 in Ethics andAction—I have tried to explore some of the ways inwhich ethical conceptions enter into our understandingof social life. But these essays, like the present book,still do not come seriously to grips with the problemscreated by what I just called the ‘fragility’ of theconditions under which ethical conceptions can beactive in social life. This does not just constitute a gapin the argument, but results in serious distortions; theseare already becoming apparent in the final Chapter ofthis book.

Page 17: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

xviii PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION

Section 2 of this Chapter misidentifies the realproblem about the overall drift of the book’s argumentas being one of ‘over-intellectualizing’ social life; in sodoing, it in effect shies away from the role played bybrute force in such a life. Thus, in the final paragraphof that Section, I tried to accommodate phenomenasuch as war to the picture I had been painting byinsisting, vaguely, that there still subsist ‘internalrelations’ between human combatants in a sense whichis not true of a struggle between wild animals. But thisof course does nothing to defend the rather cosypicture suggested by the way I had compared socialrelations to a conversational interchange. To take thecomparison seriously would be to ask such questionsas: what role in such an interchange of ideas is playedby strategies of deceit, blackmail, emotional bullying,punches on the nose, etc. Clausewitz’s mot about waras the continuation of diplomacy by other means hasits own point; but it does not weaken the enormouscontrast between human relations ruled by ideas ofjustice and those governed by force. The nature of thecontrast is important to the subjects discussed in thisbook; but the book itself, unfortunately, has nothing tosay about them. A contemporary writer in whose workthese questions have been central is Jürgen Habermas,though his way of treating them would not be mine.Another recent writer who, as it seems to me, has donemore than anyone to reveal the depth of such issues isSimone Weil. I have discussed what she says aboutthem in Simone Weil, The Just Balance (CambridgeUniversity Press, 1989).

PW

Page 18: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

1

CHAPTER ONE

PHILOSOPHICAL BEARINGS

1. Aims and Strategy

THAT the social sciences are in their infancy hascome to be a platitude amongst writers of

textbooks on the subject. They will argue that this isbecause the social sciences have been slow to emulatethe natural sciences and emancipate themselves fromthe dead hand of philosophy; that there was a timewhen there was no clear distinction betweenphilosophy and natural science; but that owing to thetransformation of this state of affairs round about theseventeenth century natural science has made greatbounds ever since. But, we are told, this revolution hasnot yet taken place in the social sciences, or at least itis only now in process of taking place. Perhaps socialscience has not yet found its Newton but the conditionsare being created in which such a genius could arise.But above all, it is urged, we must follow the methodsof natural science rather than those of philosophy if weare to make any significant progress.

I propose, in this monograph, to attack such aconception of the relation between the social studies,philosophy and the natural sciences. But it should not beassumed on that account that what I have to say must be

Page 19: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

2 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

ranked with those reactionary anti-scientific movements,aiming to put the clock back, which have appeared andflourished in certain quarters since science began. Myonly aim is to make sure that the clock is telling theright time, whatever it may prove to be. Philosophy, forreasons which may be made more apparentsubsequently, has no business to be anti-scientific: if ittries to be so it will succeed only in making itself lookridiculous. Such attacks are as distasteful andundignified as they are useless and unphilosophical. Butequally, and for the same reasons, philosophy must beon its guard against the extra-scientific pretensions ofscience. Since science is one of the chief shibboleths ofthe present age this is bound to make the philosopherunpopular; he is likely to meet a similar reaction to thatmet by someone who criticizes the monarchy. But theday when philosophy becomes a popular subject is theday for the philosopher to consider where he took thewrong turning.

I said that my aim was to attack a current conceptionof the relations between philosophy and the socialstudies. Since that conception involves two terms, whatmay appear to some a disproportionately large portionof this book must be devoted to discussing matterswhose bearing on the nature of the social studies is notimmediately evident. The view I wish to commendpresupposes a certain conception of philosophy, aconception which many will think as heretical as myconception of social science itself. So, howeverirrelevant it may at first appear, a discussion of thenature of philosophy is an essential part of the argumentof this book. This opening chapter, then, cannot safelybe skipped as a tiresome and time-wasting preliminary.

Page 20: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

3PHILOSOPHICAL BEARINGS

This may be more convincing if I briefly outline thegeneral strategy of the book. It will consist of a war ontwo fronts: first, a criticism of some prevalentcontemporary ideas about the nature of philosophy;second, a criticism of some prevalent contemporaryideas about the nature of the social studies. The maintactics will be a pincer movement: the same point willbe reached by arguing from opposite directions. Tocomplete the military analogy before it gets out ofhand, my main war aim will be to demonstrate that thetwo apparently diverse fronts on which the war is beingwaged are not in reality diverse at all; that to be clearabout the nature of philosophy and to be clear aboutthe nature of the social studies amount to the samething. For any worthwhile study of society must bephilosophical in character and any worthwhilephilosophy must be concerned with the nature ofhuman society.

2. The Underlabourer Conception of Philosophy

I will call the conception of philosophy which I wantto criticize the ‘underlabourer conception’, in honourof one of its presiding geniuses, John Locke. Thefollowing passage from the Epistle to the Reader whichprefaces Locke’s Essay Concerning HumanUnderstanding, is often quoted with approval bysupporters of the underlabourer conception.

The commonwealth of learning is not at this timewithout master-builders, whose mighty designs, inadvancing the sciences, will leave lasting monuments tothe admiration of posterity: but everyone must not hope

Page 21: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

4 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

to be a Boyle or a Sydenham; and in an age thatproduces such masters as the great Huygenius and theincomparable Mr. Newton, with some others of thatstrain, it is ambition enough to be employed as anunder-labourer in clearing the ground a little, andremoving some of the rubbish that lies in the way toknowledge.

Locke’s view is echoed in A.J.Ayer’s distinctionbetween the ‘pontiffs’ and the ‘journeymen’ ofphilosophy; it is translated into the idiom of muchmodern philosophical discussion by A.G.N.Flew, in hisintroduction to Logic and Language (First Series); andit has many points of contact with Gilbert Ryle’sconception of philosophy as ‘informal logic’ (Cf.Gilbert Ryle: Dilemmas, Cambridge).

I will try to isolate some of the outstanding featuresof this view which are most relevant for my presentpurpose. First, there is the idea that ‘it is by itsmethods rather than its subject-matter that philosophyis to be distinguished from other arts or sciences’ (3).That obviously follows from the underlabourerconception; for according to it philosophy cannotcontribute any positive understanding of the world onits own account: it has the purely negative role ofremoving impediments to the advance of ourunderstanding. The motive force for that advance mustbe sought in methods quite different from anything tobe found in philosophy; it must be found, that is, inscience. On this view philosophy is parasitic on otherdisciplines; it has no problems of its own but is atechnique for solving problems thrown up in the courseof non-philosophical investigations.

Page 22: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

5PHILOSOPHICAL BEARINGS

The modern conception of what constitutes the‘rubbish that lies in the way to knowledge’ is verysimilar to Locke’s own: philosophy is concerned witheliminating linguistic confusions. So the picture we arepresented with is something like this. Genuine newknowledge is acquired by scientists by experimentaland observational methods. Language is a tool which isindispensible to this process; like any other toollanguage can develop defects, and those which arepeculiar to it are logical contradictions, oftenconceived on the analogy of mechanical faults inmaterial tools. Just as other sorts of tool need aspecialist mechanic to maintain them in good order, sowith language. Whereas a garage mechanic isconcerned with removing such things as blockages incarburettors, a philosopher removes contradictionsfrom realms of discourse.

I turn now to a further, connected, implication of theunderlabourer conception. If the problems ofphilosophy come to it from without, it becomesnecessary to give some special account of the role ofmetaphysics and epistemology within philosophy. Forthough it may be plausible to say that the problems ofthe philosophy of science, the philosophy of religion,the philosophy of art, and so on, are set for philosophyby science, religion, art, etc., it is not at all obviouswhat sets the problems for metaphysics andepistemology. If we say that these disciplines areautonomous with regard to their problems, then ofcourse the underlabourer conception collapses as anexhaustive account of the nature of philosophy. Somewriters have suggested that metaphysics andepistemology are just the philosophies of science and

Page 23: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

6 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

of psychology respectively in disguise, but I have neverseen this view defended in any detail and it is certainlynot prima facie plausible to anyone who is at allfamiliar with the history of these subjects. Others againhave said that metaphysical and epistemologicaldiscussions are an entirely spurious form of activityand do not belong to any respectable discipline at all.But they treat of questions which have a habit ofrecurring and such a cavalier attitude soon begins toring somewhat hollow. It is in fact a good deal lesspopular than once it was.

Another widely held view is that championed, forinstance, by Peter Laslett in his editorial introductionto Philosophy, Politics and Society (13). According tothis view, the preoccupation with epistemologicalquestions, which has for some time characterizedphilosophical discussion in this country, is to beconstrued as a temporary phase, as a period ofexamining and improving the tools of philosophy,rather than as the very stuff of philosophy itself. Theidea is that, when this work of re-tooling has beendone, it is the duty of the philosopher to return to hismore important task—that of clarifying the conceptswhich belong to other, non-philosophical disciplines.

In the first place this interpretation is unhistorical,since epistemological questions have always beencentral to serious philosophical work, and it is difficultto see how this could be otherwise. More importantly,Laslett’s view involves a reversal of the true order ofpriority within philosophy: epistemological discussionis represented as important only in so far as it serves afurther end, namely to advance the treatment ofquestions in the philosophies of science, art, politics,

Page 24: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

7PHILOSOPHICAL BEARINGS

etc. I want to argue, on the contrary, that thephilosophies of science, art, politics, etc.—subjectswhich I will call the ‘peripheral’ philosophicaldisciplines—lose their philosophical character ifunrelated to epistemology and metaphysics. But beforeI can show this in detail, I must first attempt toexamine the philosophical foundations of theunderlabourer conception of philosophy.

3. Philosophy and Science

That conception is in large part a reaction against the‘master-scientist’ view of the philosopher, according towhich philosophy is in direct competition with scienceand aims at constructing or refuting scientific theoriesby purely a priori reasoning. This is an idea which isjustly ridiculed; the absurdities to which it may leadare amply illustrated in Hegel’s amateur pseudo-scientific speculations. Its philosophical refutation wasprovided by Hume:

If we would satisfy ourselves…concerning the natureof that evidence, which assures us of matters of fact,we must enquire how we arrive at the knowledge ofcause and effect. I shall venture to affirm, as a generalproposition, which admits of no exception, that theknowledge of this relation is not, in any instance,attained by reasonings a priori; but arises entirely fromexperience, when we find that any particular objects areconstantly conjoined with each other. Let an object bepresented to a man of never so strong natural reasonand abilities; if that object be entirely new to him, hewill not be able, by the most accurate examination ofits sensible qualities, to discover any of its causes oreffects. (12: Section IV, Part I.)

Page 25: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

8 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

Now this is admirable as a critique of a priori pseudo-science. But the argument has also frequently beenmisapplied in order to attack a priori philosophizing ofa sort which is quite legitimate. The argument runs asfollows : new discoveries about real matters of fact canonly be established by experimental methods; nopurely a priori process of thinking is sufficient for this.But since it is science which uses experimentalmethods, while philosophy is purely a priori, it followsthat the investigation of reality must be left to science.On the other hand, philosophy has traditionallyclaimed, at least in large part, to consist in theinvestigation of the nature of reality; either, therefore,traditional philosophy was attempting to do somethingwhich its methods of investigation could never possiblyachieve, and must be abandoned; or else it wasmistaken about its own nature, and the purport of itsinvestigations must be drastically reinterpreted.

Now the argument on which this dilemma is based isfallacious: it contains an undistributed middle term.The phrase ‘the investigation of the nature of reality’ isambiguous, and whereas Hume’s argument appliesperfectly well to what that phrase conveys whenapplied to scientific investigation, it is a mere ignoratioelenchi as applied to philosophy. The differencebetween the respective aims of the scientist and thephilosopher might be expressed as follows. Whereasthe scientist investigates the nature, causes and effectsof particular real things and processes, the philosopheris concerned with the nature of reality as such and ingeneral. Burnet puts the point very well in his book onGreek Philosophy when he points out (on pages 11 and12) that the sense in which the philosopher asks ‘What

Page 26: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

9PHILOSOPHICAL BEARINGS

is real?’ involves the problem of man’s relation toreality, which takes us beyond pure science. ‘We haveto ask whether the mind of man can have any contactwith reality at all, and, if it can, what difference thiswill make to his life’. Now to think that this questionof Burnet’s could be settled by experimental methodsinvolves just as serious a mistake as to think thatphilosophy, with its a priori methods of reasoning,could possibly compete with experimental science onits own ground. For it is not an empirical question atall, but a conceptual one. It has to do with the force ofthe concept of reality. An appeal to the results of anexperiment would necessarily beg the importantquestion, since the philosopher would be bound to askby what token those results themselves are accepted as‘reality’. Of course, this simply exasperates theexperimental scientist—rightly so, from the point ofview of his own aims and interests. But the force of thephilosophical question cannot be grasped in terms ofthe preconceptions of experimental science. It cannotbe answered by generalizing from particular instancessince a particular answer to the philosophical questionis already implied in the acceptance of those instancesas ‘real’.

The whole issue was symbolically dramatized on acelebrated occasion in 1939 when Professor G.E.Moore gave a lecture to the British Academy entitled‘Proof of an External World’. Moore’s ‘proof’ ranroughly as follows. He held up each of his hands insuccession, saying ‘Here is one hand and here isanother; therefore at least two external objects exist;therefore an external world exists’. In arguing thusMoore seemed to be treating the question ‘Does an

Page 27: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

10 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

external world exist?’ as similar in form to thequestion ‘Do animals with a single horn growing outof their snout exist?’ This of course would beconclusively settled by the production of tworhinoceri. But the bearing of Moore’s argument on thephilosophical question of the existence of an externalworld is not as simple as the bearing of theproduction of two rhinoceri on the other question.For, of course, philosophical doubt about theexistence of an external world covers the two handswhich Moore produced in the same way as it coverseverything else. The whole question is: Do objectslike Moore’s two hands qualify as inhabitants of anexternal world? This is not to say that Moore’sargument is completely beside the point; what iswrong is to regard it as an experimental ‘proof, for itis not like anything one finds in an experimentaldiscipline. Moore was not making an experiment; hewas reminding his audience of something, remindingthem of the way in which the expression ‘externalobject’ is in fact used. And his reminder indicated thatthe issue in philosophy is not to prove or disprove theexistence of a world of external objects but rather toelucidate the concept of externality. That there is aconnection between this issue and the centralphilosophical problem about the general nature ofreality is, I think, obvious.

4. The Philosopher’s Concern with Language

So much, at present, for the relation betweenphilosophy and science. But I have yet to show why therejection of the master-scientist conception of the

Page 28: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

11PHILOSOPHICAL BEARINGS

philosopher need not, and should not, lead to theunderlabourer conception. I have spoken of Moorereminding us how certain expressions are in fact used;and I have emphasized how important in philosophy isthe notion of elucidating a concept. These are ways ofspeaking which prima facie fit the underlabourerconception very well. And in fact what is wrong withthat conception in general is to be looked for not somuch in any downright false doctrine as in asystematically mistaken emphasis.

Philosophical issues do, to a large extent, turn on thecorrect use of certain linguistic expressions; theelucidation of a concept is, to a large extent, theclearing up of linguistic confusions. Nevertheless, thephilosopher’s concern is not with correct usage as suchand not all linguistic confusions are equally relevant tophilosophy. They are relevant only in so far as thediscussion of them is designed to throw light on thequestion how far reality is intelligible1 and whatdifference would the fact that he could have a grasp ofreality make to the life of man. So we have to ask howquestions of language, and what kinds of questionabout language, are likely to bear upon these issues.

To ask whether reality is intelligible is to ask aboutthe relation between thought and reality. In consideringthe nature of thought one is led also to consider thenature of language. Inseparably bound up with

1I am aware that this is a somewhat old-fashioned sounding wayto talk. I do so in order to mark the difference between thephilosopher’s concern with reality and that of, e.g., the scientist. Itake this opportunity of saying that I owe the statement of thephilosopher’s kind of interest in language, in the next paragraph, toan unpublished talk by Mr. Rush Rhees on “Philosophy and Art”.

Page 29: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

12 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

the question whether reality is intelligible, therefore,is the question of how language is connected withreality, of what it is to say something. In fact thephilosopher’s interest in language lies not so much inthe solution of particular linguistic confusions for theirown sakes, as in the solution of confusions about thenature of language in general.

I will elaborate this point polemically, referring toT.D.Weldon’s Vocabulary of Politics. I choose thisbook because in it Weldon uses his interpretation of theconcern which philosophy has with language tosupport a conception of the relations betweenphilosophy and the study of society, which isfundamentally at variance with the conception to becommended in this monograph. Weldon’s view is basedon an interpretation of recent developments inphilosophy in this country. What has occurred, he says,is that ‘philosophers have become extremely self-conscious about language. They have come to realisethat many of the problems which their predecessorshave found insuperable arose not from anythingmysterious or inexplicable in the world but from theeccentricities of the language in which we try todescribe the world’ (35: Chapter I). The problems ofsocial and political philosophy, therefore, arise fromthe eccentricities of the language in which we try todescribe social and political institutions, rather thanfrom anything mysterious in those institutionsthemselves. In accordance with the underlabourerconception of philosophy, which Weldon is herefaithfully following, he regards philosophy as having apurely negative role to play in advancing ourunderstanding of social life. Any positive advances in

Page 30: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

13PHILOSOPHICAL BEARINGS

this understanding must be contributed by the methodsof empirical science rather than by those of philosophy.There is no hint that discussion of the central questionsof metaphysics and epistemology themselves may (as Ishall later argue) have light to throw on the nature ofhuman societies.

In fact those questions are cavalierly brushed asidein the very statement of Weldon’s position. To assumeat the outset that one can make a sharp distinctionbetween ‘the world’ and ‘the language in which we tryto describe the world’, to the extent of saying that theproblems of philosophy do not arise at all out of theformer but only out of the latter, is to beg the wholequestion of philosophy.

Weldon would no doubt reply that this question hasalready been settled in a sense favourable to hisposition by those philosophers who contributed to thedevelopments of which he is speaking. But even if weoverlook the important fact that philosophical issuescan never be settled in that way, that the results ofother men’s philosophizing cannot be assumed inone’s own philosophical work as can scientifictheories established by other men—even, I say, if weoverlook this, the work of Wittgenstein, the mostoutstanding contributor to the philosophicaldevelopment in question, is just misinterpreted if it istaken to support Weldon’s way of speaking. This isobvious enough in relation to Wittgenstein’s TractatusLogico-Philosophicus, as can be seen from tworepresentative quotations. ‘To give the essence ofproposition means to give the essence of alldescription, therefore the essence of the world’(36:5.4711). ‘That the world is my world shows itself

Page 31: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

14 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

in the fact that the limits of my language (of the onlylanguage I can understand) mean the limits of myworld’ (Ibid.: 5.62).

It is true that these ideas in the Tractatus areconnected with a theory of language whichWittgenstein afterwards rejected and which Weldonwould also reject. But Wittgenstein’s methods ofargument in the later Philosophical Investigations areequally incompatible with any easy distinction betweenthe world and language. This comes out clearly in histreatment of the concept of seeing an object assomething: for example, seeing the picture of an arrowas in flight. The following passage is characteristic ofWittgenstein’s whole approach:

In the triangle I can see now this as apex, that asbase—now this as apex, that as base,—Clearly thewords ‘Now I am seeing this as the apex’ cannot so farmean anything to a learner who has only just met theconcepts of apex, base, and so on.—But I do not meanthis as an empirical proposition.

‘Now he’s seeing it like this’, ‘now like that’ wouldonly be said of someone capable of making certainapplications of the figure quite freely.

The substratum of this experience is the mastery ofa technique.

But how queer for this to be the logical condition ofsomeone’s having such and such an experience! Afterall, you don’t say that one only ‘has toothache’ if oneis capable of doing such-and-such.—From this itfollows that we cannot be dealing with the sameconcept of experience here. It is a different thoughrelated concept.

It is only if someone can do, has learnt, is masterof, such-and-such, that it makes sense to say he has hadthis experience.

And if this sounds crazy, you need to reflect that the

Page 32: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

15PHILOSOPHICAL BEARINGS

concept of seeing is modified here. (A similarconsideration is often necessary to get rid of a feelingof dizziness in mathematics.)

We talk, we utter words, and only later get a pictureof their life. (37:II, xi.)

We cannot say then, with Weldon, that the problems ofphilosophy arise out of language rather than out of theworld, because in discussing language philosophicallywe are in fact discussing what counts as belonging tothe world. Our idea of what belongs to the realm ofreality is given for us in the language that we use. Theconcepts we have settle for us the form of theexperience we have of the world. It may be worthreminding ourselves of the truism that when we speakof the world we are speaking of what we in fact meanby the expression ‘the world’: there is no way ofgetting outside the concepts in terms of which we thinkof the world, which is what Weldon is trying to do inhis statements about the nature of philosophicalproblems. The world is for us what is presentedthrough those concepts. That is not to say that ourconcepts may not change; but when they do, thatmeans that our concept of the world has changed too.

5. Conceptual and Empirical Enquiries

This misunderstanding of the way in whichphilosophical treatments of linguistic confusions arealso elucidations of the nature of reality leads toinadequacies in the actual methods used for treatingsuch questions. Empiricists like Weldon systematicallyunderemphasize the extent of what may be said a

Page 33: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

16 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

priori: for them all statements about reality must beempirical or they are unfounded, and a prioristatements are ‘about linguistic usage’ as opposed tobeing ‘about reality’. But if the integrity of science isendangered by the over-estimation of the a priori,against which Hume legitimately fought, it is no lesstrue that philosophy is crippled by its underestimation:by mistaking conceptual enquiries into what it makessense to say for empirical enquiries which must waitupon experience for their solution.

The misunderstanding is well illustrated in thefollowing passage from Hume himself. He isdiscussing the extent and nature of our knowledge ofwhat will happen in the future and arguing that nothingin the future can be logically guaranteed for us by ourknowledge of what has been observed to happen in thepast.

In vain do you pretend to have learned the nature ofbodies from past experience. Their secret nature, andconsequently all their effects and influence maychange, without any change in their sensible qualities.This happens sometimes, and with regard to someobjects: Why may it not happen always and with regardto all objects? What logic, what process of argumentsecures you against this supposition? (12: Section IV,Part II.)

Hume assumes here that since a statement about theuniform behaviour of some objects is a straightforwardempirical matter which may at any time be upset byfuture experience, the same must be true of a statementabout the uniform behaviour of all objects. Thisassumption is very compelling. Its compellingness

Page 34: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

17PHILOSOPHICAL BEARINGS

derives from a healthy unwillingness to admit thatanyone can legislate a priori concerning the course offuture experience on the basis of purely logicalconsiderations. And of course we cannot thus legislateagainst a breakdown in the regular order of nature,such as would make scientific work impossible anddestroy speech, thought, and even life. But we can andmust legislate a priori against the possibility ofdescribing such a situation in the terms which Humeattempts to use: in terms, that is, of the properties ofobjects, their causes and effects. For were the order ofnature to break down in that way these terms would beno longer applicable. Because there may be minor, oreven major, variations within such an order without ourwhole conceptual apparatus being upset, it does notfollow that we can use our existing apparatus (andwhat other are we to use?) to describe a breakdown inthe order of nature as a whole.

This is not merely verbal quibbling. For the wholephilosophical purport of enquiries like Hume’s is toclarify those concepts which are fundamental to ourconception of reality, like object, property of an object,cause and effect. To point out that the use of suchnotions necessarily presupposes the continuing truth ofmost of our generalizations about the behaviour of theworld we live in is of central importance to such anundertaking.

The importance of this issue for the philosophy ofthe social sciences will become more apparent later on.I shall argue, for instance, that many of the moreimportant theoretical issues which have been raised inthose studies belong to philosophy rather than toscience and are, therefore, to be settled by a priori

Page 35: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

18 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

conceptual analysis rather than by empirical research.For example, the question of what constitutes socialbehaviour is a demand for an elucidation of theconcept of social behaviour. In dealing with questionsof this sort there should be no question of ‘waiting tosee’ what empirical research will show us; it is a matterof tracing the implications of the concepts we use.

6. The Pivotal Role of Epistemology within Philosophy

I can now offer an alternative view of the way in whichthe problems of epistemology and metaphysics arerelated to those in what I have called the peripheralphilosophical disciplines. Everything I have so far saidhas been based on the assumption that what is reallyfundamental to philosophy is the question regardingthe nature and intelligibility of reality. It is easy to seethat this question must lead on to a consideration ofwhat we mean by ‘intelligibility’ in the first place.What is it to understand something, to grasp the senseof something? Now if we look at the contexts in whichthe notions of understanding, of making somethingintelligible, are used we find that these differ widelyamongst themselves. Moreover, if those contexts areexamined and compared, it soon becomes apparent thatthe notion of intelligibility is systematically ambiguous(in Professor Ryle’s sense of the phrase) in its use inthose contexts: that is, its sense varies systematicallyaccording to the particular context in which it is beingused.

The scientist, for instance, tries to make the worldmore intelligible; but so do the historian, the religiousprophet and the artist; so does the philosopher. And

Page 36: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

19PHILOSOPHICAL BEARINGS

although we may describe the activities of all thesekinds of thinker in terms of the concepts ofunderstanding and intelligibility, it is clear that in verymany important ways, the objectives of each of themdiffer from the objectives of any of the others. Forinstance, I have already tried, in Section 3, to givesome account of the differences between the kinds of‘understanding of reality’ sought by the philosopherand the scientist respectively.

It does not follow from this that we are just punningwhen we speak of the activities of all these enquirers interms of the notion of making things intelligible. Thatno more follows than does a similar conclusion withregard to the word ‘game’ when Wittgenstein shows usthat there is no set of properties common and peculiarto all the activities correctly so called (Cf. 37:I, 66–71). There is just as much point in saying that science,art, religion and philosophy are all concerned withmaking things intelligible as there is in saying thatfootball, chess, patience and skipping are all games.But just as it would be foolish to say that all theseactivities are part of one supergame, if only we wereclever enough to learn how to play it, so is it foolish tosuppose that the results of all those other activitiesshould all add up to one grand theory of reality (assome philosophers have imagined: with the corollarythat it was their job to discover it).

On my view then, the philosophy of science will beconcerned with the kind of understanding sought andconveyed by the scientist; the philosophy of religion willbe concerned with the way in which religion attempts topresent an intelligible picture of the world; and so on.And of course these activities and their aims will be

Page 37: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

20 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

mutually compared and contrasted. The purpose of suchphilosophical enquiries will be to contribute to ourunderstanding of what is involved in the concept ofintelligibility, so that we may better understand what itmeans to call reality intelligible. It is important for mypurposes to note how different is this from theunderlabourer conception. In particular, the philosophyof science (or of whatever enquiry may be in question)is presented here as autonomous, and not parasitic onscience itself, as far as the provenance of its problems isconcerned. The motive force for the philosophy ofscience comes from within philosophy rather than fromwithin science. And its aim is not merely the negativeone of removing obstacles from the path to theacquisition of further scientific knowledge, but thepositive one of an increased philosophical understandingof what is involved in the concept of intelligibility. Thedifference between these conceptions is more than averbal one.

It might appear at first sight as if no room had beenleft for metaphysics and epistemology. For if theconcept of intelligibility (and, I should add, theconcept of reality equally) are systematicallyambiguous as between different intellectualdisciplines, does not the philosophical task of givingan account of those notions disintegrate into thephilosophies of the various disciplines in question?Does not the idea of a special study of epistemologyrest on the false idea that all varieties of the notion ofintelligibility can be reduced to a single set ofcriteria?

That is a false conclusion to draw, though it doesprovide a salutary warning against expecting from

Page 38: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

21PHILOSOPHICAL BEARINGS

epistemology the formulation of a set of criteria ofintelligibility. Its task will rather be to describe theconditions which must be satisfied if there are to beany criteria of understanding at all.

7. Epistemology and the Understanding of Society

I should like here to give a preliminary indication ofhow this epistemological undertaking may beexpected to bear upon our understanding of sociallife. Let us consider again Burnet’s formulation of themain question of philosophy. He asks what differenceit will make to the life of man if his mind can havecontact with reality. Let us first interpret this questionin the most superficially obvious way: it is clear thatmen do decide how they shall behave on the basis oftheir view of what is the case in the world aroundthem. For instance, a man who has to catch an earlymorning train will set his alarm clock in accordancewith his belief about the time at which the train is dueto leave. If anyone is inclined to object to thisexample on the grounds of its triviality, let him reflecton the difference that is made to human life by thefact that there are such things as alarm clocks andtrains running to schedule, and methods ofdetermining the truth of statements about the times oftrains, and so on. The concern of philosophy here iswith the question: What is involved in ‘havingknowledge’ of facts like these, and what is the generalnature of behaviour which is decided on inaccordance with such knowledge?

The nature of this question will perhaps be clearer ifit is compared with another question concerning the

Page 39: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

22 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

importance in human life of knowing the world as itreally is. I am thinking of the moral question which soexercised Ibsen in such plays as The Wild Duck andGhosts: How far is it important to a man’s life that heshould live it in clear awareness of the facts of hissituation and of his relations to those around him? InGhosts this question is presented by considering a manwhose life is being ruined by his ignorance of the truthabout his heredity. The Wild Duck starts from theopposite direction: here is a man who is living aperfectly contented life which is, however, based on acomplete misunderstanding of the attitude to him ofthose he knows; should he be disillusioned and havehis happiness disrupted in the interests of truth? It isnecessary to notice that our understanding of boththese issues depends on our recognition of the primafacie importance of understanding the situation inwhich one lives one’s life. The question in The WildDuck is not whether that is important, but whether ornot it is more important than being happy.

Now the interest of the epistemologist in suchsituations will be to throw light on why such anunderstanding should have this importance in a man’slife by showing what is involved in having it. To use aKantian phrase, his interest will be in the question:How is such an understanding (or indeed anyunderstanding) possible? To answer this question it isnecessary to show the central role which the conceptof understanding plays in the activities which arecharacteristic of human societies. In this way thediscussion of what an understanding of realityconsists in merges into the discussion of thedifference the possession of such an understanding

Page 40: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

23PHILOSOPHICAL BEARINGS

may be expected to make to the life of man; and thisagain involves a consideration of the general nature ofa human society, an analysis, that is, of the concept ofa human society.

A man’s social relations with his fellows arepermeated with his ideas about reality. Indeed,‘permeated’ is hardly a strong enough word: socialrelations are expressions of ideas about reality. In theIbsen situations which I just referred to, for example, itwould be impossible to delineate the character’sattitudes to the people surrounding him except in termsof his ideas about what they think of him, what theyhave done in the past, what they are likely to do in thefuture, and so on; and, in Ghosts, his ideas about howhe is biologically related to them. Again, a monk hascertain characteristic social relations with his fellowmonks and with people outside the monastery; but itwould be impossible to give more than a superficialaccount of those relations without taking into accountthe religious ideas around which the monk’s liferevolves.

At this point it becomes clearer how the line ofapproach which I am commending conflicts withwidely held conceptions of sociology and of the socialstudies generally. It conflicts, for instance, with theview of Emile Durkheim:

I consider extremely fruitful this idea that social lifeshould be explained, not by the notions of those whoparticipate in it, but by more profound causes which areunperceived by consciousness, and I think also thatthese causes are to be sought mainly in the manneraccording to which the associated individuals aregrouped. Only in this way, it seems, can history

Page 41: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

24 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

become a science, and sociology itself exist. [SeeDurkheim’s review of A.Labriola: ‘Essais sur laconception materialiste de l’histoire’ in RevuePhilosophique, December, 1897.]

It conflicts too with von Wiese’s conception of the taskof sociology as being to give an account of social life‘disregarding the cultural aims of individuals in societyin order to study the influences which they exert oneach other as a result of community life’. (See 2: p. 8.)

The crucial question here, of course, is how far anysense can be given to Durkheim’s idea of ‘the manneraccording to which associated individuals are grouped’apart from the ‘notions’ of such individuals; or howfar it makes sense to speak of individuals exertinginfluence on each other (in von Wiese’s conception) inabstraction from such individuals’ ‘cultural aims’. Ishall try to deal explicitly with these central questionsat a later stage in the argument. At present I simplywish to point out that positions like these do in factcome into conflict with philosophy, conceived as anenquiry into the nature of man’s knowledge of realityand into the difference which the possibility of suchknowledge makes to human life.

8. Rules: Wittgenstein’s Analysis

I must now attempt a more detailed picture of the wayin which the epistemological discussion of man’sunderstanding of reality throws light on the nature ofhuman society and of social relations between men. Tothat end I propose to give some account of the lightwhich has been shed on the epistemological issue by

Page 42: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

25PHILOSOPHICAL BEARINGS

Wittgenstein’s discussion of the concept of following arule in the Philosophical Investigations.

Burnet spoke of the mind’s ‘contact’ with reality.Let us take an obvious prima facie case of such contactand consider what is involved in it. Suppose that I amwondering in what year Everest was first climbed; Ithink to myself: ‘Mount Everest was climbed in 1953’.What I want to ask here is what is meant by saying thatI am ‘thinking about Mount Everest?’ How is mythought related to the thing, namely Mount Everest,about which I am thinking? Let us make the issuesomewhat sharper yet. In order to removecomplications about the function of mental images insuch situations I will suppose that I express my thoughtexplicitly in words. The appropriate question thenbecomes: what is it about my utterance of the words‘Mount Everest’ which makes it possible to say I meanby those words a certain peak in the Himalayas. I haveintroduced the subject in this somewhat roundaboutway in order to bring out the connection between thequestion about the nature of the ‘contact’ which themind has with reality and the question about the natureof meaning. I have chosen as an example of a wordbeing used to mean something a case where the wordin question is being used to refer to something, notbecause I assign any special logical or metaphysicalpriority to this type of meaning, but solely because inthis case the connection between the question about thenature of meaning and that about the relation betweenthought and reality is particularly striking.

A natural first answer to give is that I am able tomean what I do by the words ‘Mount Everest’ becausethey have been defined to me. There are all sorts of

Page 43: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

26 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

ways in which this may have been done: I may havebeen shown Mount Everest on a map, I may have beentold that it is the highest peak in the world; or I mayhave been flown over the Himalayas in an aeroplaneand had the actual Everest pointed out to me. Toeliminate further complications let us make the lastsupposition; that is, to use the technical terminology oflogic, let us concentrate on the case of ostensivedefinition.

The position then is this. I have had Everest pointedout to me; I have been told that its name is ‘Everest’;and in virtue of those actions in the past I am now ableto mean by the words ‘Mount Everest’ that peak in theHimalayas. So far so good. But now we have to ask afurther question: What is the connection between thoseacts in the past and my utterance of the words ‘MountEverest’ now which now gives this utterance of mine themeaning it has? How, in general, is a definitionconnected with the subsequent use of the expressiondefined? What is it to ‘follow’ a definition? Again thereis a superficially obvious answer to this: the definitionlays down the meaning and to use a word in its correctmeaning is to use it in the same way as that laid down inthe definition. And in a sense, of course, that answer isperfectly correct and unexceptionable; its only defect isthat it does not remove the philosophical puzzlement.For what is it to use the word in the same way as thatlaid down in the definition? How do I decide whether agiven proposed use is the same as or different from thatlaid down in the definition?

That is not a merely idle question, as can be seenfrom the following consideration. As far as immediateexternal appearances go, the ostensive definition

Page 44: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

27PHILOSOPHICAL BEARINGS

simply consisted in a gesture and a sound uttered as wewere flying over the Himalayas. But suppose that, withthat gesture, my teacher had been defining the word‘mountain’ for me, rather than ‘Everest’, as might havebeen the case, say, had I been in the process of learningEnglish? In that case too my grasp of the correctmeaning of the word ‘mountain’ would be manifestedin my continuing to use it in the same way as that laiddown in the definition. Yet the correct use of the word‘mountain’ is certainly not the same as the correct useof the word ‘Everest’! So apparently the word ‘same’presents us with another example of systematicambiguity: we do not know whether two things are tobe regarded as the same or not unless we are told thecontext in which the question arises. However much wemay be tempted to think otherwise, there is no absoluteunchanging sense to the words ‘the same’.

But isn’t the same at least the same?We seem to have an infallible paradigm of identity

in the identity of a thing with itself. I feel like saying:‘Here at any rate there can’t be any variety ofinterpretations. If you are seeing a thing you are seeingidentity too’.

Then are two things the same when they are whatone thing is? And how am I to apply what the one thingshows me to the case of two things? (37: I, 215.)

I said that the particular interpretation which is to beput upon the words ‘the same’ depends on the contextin which the question arises. That may be expressedmore precisely. It is only in terms of a given rule thatwe can attach a specific sense to the words the same’.In terms of the rule governing the use of the word

Page 45: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

28 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

‘mountain’, a man who uses it to refer to MountEverest on one occasion and to Mont Blanc on anotheroccasion is using it in the same way each time; butsomeone who refers to Mont Blanc as ‘Everest’ wouldnot be said to be using this word in the same way assomeone who used it to refer to Mount Everest. So thequestion: What is it for a word to have a meaning?leads on to the question: What is it for someone tofollow a rule?

Let us once again start by considering the obviousanswer. We should like to say: someone is following arule if he always acts in the same way on the same kindof occasion. But this again, though correct, does notadvance matters since, as we have seen, it is only interms of a given rule that the word ‘same’ acquires adefinite sense. ‘The use of the word “rule” and the useof the word “same” are interwoven. (As are the use of“proposition” and the use of “true”.)’ (37: I, 225.) Sothe problem becomes: How is the word ‘same’ to begiven a sense?; or: In what circumstances does it makesense to say of somebody that he is following a rule inwhat he does?

Suppose that the word ‘Everest’ has just beenostensively defined to me. It might be thought that Icould settle at the outset what is to count as the correctuse of this word in the future by making a consciousdecision to the effect: ‘I will use this word only to referto this mountain’. And that of course, in the context ofthe language which we all speak and understand, isperfectly intelligible. But, just because it presupposesthe settled institution of the language we all speak andunderstand, this does not throw any light on thephilosophical difficulty. Obviously we are not

Page 46: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

29PHILOSOPHICAL BEARINGS

permitted to presuppose that whose very possibility weare investigating. It is just as difficult to give anyaccount of what is meant by ‘acting in accordance withmy decision’ as it is to give an account of what it wasto ‘act in accordance with the ostensive definition’ inthe first place. However emphatically I point at thismountain here before me and however emphatically Iutter the words ‘this mountain’, my decision still has tobe applied in the future, and it is precisely what isinvolved in such an application that is here in question.Hence no formula will help to solve this problem; wemust always come to a point at which we have to givean account of the application of the formula.

What is the difference between someone who isreally applying a rule in what he does and someonewho is not? A difficulty here is that any series ofactions which a man may perform can be broughtwithin the scope of some formula or other if we areprepared to make it sufficiently complicated. Yet, that aman’s actions might be interpreted as an application ofa given formula, is in itself no guarantee that he is infact applying that formula. What is the differencebetween those cases?

Imagine a man—let us call him A—writing downthe following figures on a blackboard: 1 3 5 7. A nowasks his friend, B, how the series is to be continued.Almost everybody in this situation, short of havingspecial reasons to be suspicious, would answer: 9 1113 15. Let us suppose that A refuses to accept this asa continuation of his series, saying it runs as follows:1 3 5 7 1 3 5 7 9 11 13 15 9 11 13 15. He then asksB to continue from there. At this point B has a varietyof alternatives to choose from. Let us suppose that he

Page 47: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

30 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

makes a choice and that A again refuses to accept it,but substitutes another continuation of his own. Andlet us suppose that this continues for some time.There would undoubtedly come a point at which B,with perfect justification, would say that A was notreally following a mathematical rule at all, eventhough all the continuations he had made to datecould be brought within the scope of some formula.Certainly A was following a rule; but his rule was:Always to substitute a continuation different from theone suggested by B at every stage. And though this isa perfectly good rule of its kind, it does not belong toarithmetic.

Now B’s eventual reaction, and the fact that it wouldbe quite justified, particularly if several otherindividuals were brought into the game and if A alwaysrefused to allow their suggested continuations ascorrect—all this suggests a very important feature ofthe concept of following a rule. It suggests that one hasto take account not only of the actions of the personwhose behaviour is in question as a candidate for thecategory of rule-following, but also the reactions ofother people to what he does. More specifically, it isonly in a situation in which it makes sense to supposethat somebody else could in principle discover the rulewhich I am following that I can intelligibly be said tofollow a rule at all.

Let us consider this more closely. It is important toremember that when A wrote down: 1 3 5 7, B(representing anyone who has learnt elementaryarithmetic) continued the series by writing: 9 11 1315, etc., as a matter of course. The very fact that Ihave been able to write ‘etc.’ after those figures and

Page 48: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

31PHILOSOPHICAL BEARINGS

that I can be confident of being taken in one wayrather than another by virtually all my readers, isitself a demonstration of the same point. ‘The rule canonly seem to me to produce all its consequences inadvance if I draw them as a matter of course. Asmuch as it is a matter of course for me to call thiscolour “blue”.’ (37:I, 238.) It should be understoodthat these remarks are not confined to the case ofmathematical formulae but apply to all cases of rule-following. They apply, for instance, to the use ofwords like ‘Everest’ and ‘mountain’: given a certainsort of training everybody does, as a matter of course,continue to use these words in the same way as wouldeverybody else.

It is this that makes it possible for us to attach asense to the expression ‘the same’ in a given context. Itis extremely important to notice here that going on inone way rather than another as a matter of course mustnot be just a peculiarity of the person whose behaviourclaims to be a case of rule-following. His behaviourbelongs to that category only if it is possible forsomeone else to grasp what he is doing, by beingbrought to the pitch of himself going on in that way asa matter of course.

Imagine someone using a line as a rule in the followingway: he holds a pair of compasses, and carries one ofits points along the line that is the ‘rule’, while theother one draws the line that follows the rule. Andwhile he moves along the ruling line he alters theopening of the compasses, apparently with greatprecision, looking at the rule the whole time as if itdetermined what he did. And watching him we see nokind of regularity in this opening and shutting of the

Page 49: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

32 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

compasses. We cannot learn his way of following theline from it. Here perhaps one really would say: ‘Theoriginal seems to intimate to him which way he is togo. But it is not a rule’. (37: I, 237.)

Why is it not a rule? Because the notion of following arule is logically inseparable from the notion of makinga mistake. If it is possible to say of someone that he isfollowing a rule that means that one can ask whetherhe is doing what he does correctly or not. Otherwisethere is no foothold in his behaviour in which thenotion of a rule can take a grip; there is then no sensein describing his behaviour in that way, sinceeverything he does is as good as anything else he mightdo, whereas the point of the concept of a rule is that itshould enable us to evaluate what is being done.

Let us consider what is involved in making amistake (which includes, of course, a consideration ofwhat is involved in doing something correctly) Amistake is a contravention of what is established ascorrect; as such, it must be recognisable as such acontravention. That is, if I make a mistake in, say, myuse of a word, other people must be able to point it outto me. If this is not so, I can do what I like and there isno external check on what I do; that is, nothing isestablished. Establishing a standard is not an activitywhich it makes sense to ascribe to any individual incomplete isolation from other individuals. For it iscontact with other individuals which alone makespossible the external check on one’s actions which isinseparable from an established standard.

A qualification must be made here to avert apossible misunderstanding. It is, of course, possible,within a human society as we-know it, with its

Page 50: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

33PHILOSOPHICAL BEARINGS

established language and institutions, for an individualto adhere to a private rule of conduct. WhatWittgenstein insists on, however, is, first, that it mustbe in principle possible for other people to grasp thatrule and judge when it is being correctly followed;secondly, that it makes no sense to suppose anyonecapable of establishing a purely personal standard ofbehaviour if he had never had any experience of humansociety with its socially established rules. In this partof philosophy one is concerned with the generalconcept of following a rule; that being so, one is not atliberty, in explaining what is involved in that concept,to take for granted a situation in which that concept isalready presupposed.

9. Some Misunderstandings of Wittgenstein

The necessity for rules to have a social setting isparticularly important in connection with thephilosophical problem about the nature of sensations.For it implies that the language in which we speakabout our sensations must be governed by criteriawhich are publicly accessible; those criteria cannot restin something essentially private to a given individual,as many philosophers have supposed. Wittgenstein’sdiscussion in the Philosophical Investigations isintimately bound up with this special problem. But, asP.F.Strawson points out, Wittgenstein’s argumentsapply equally against the idea of any language which isnot, at some point, based on a common life in whichmany individuals participate. Strawson regards this factas an objection to Wittgenstein’s position for, healleges, it rules out as inconceivable something we can

Page 51: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

34 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

in fact perfectly well conceive. He argues that we canquite well imagine, as a logical possibility, a desert-islander who has never been brought up in a humansociety devising a language for his own use. We canalso, he says, imagine the introduction of an observer(B) of the user of this language who

observes a correlation between the use of its wordsand sentences and the speaker’s actions andenvironment. …Observer B is thus able to formhypotheses about the meanings (the regular use) of thewords of his subject’s language. He might in timecome to be able to speak it: then the practice of eachserves as a check on the practice of the other. Butshall we say that, before this fortunate result wasachieved (before the use of the language becomes ashared ‘form of life’), the words of the language hadno meaning, no use? (32: p. 85.)

To Strawson it seems self-evidently absurd to say sucha thing. The persuasiveness of his position lies in thefact that he appears to have succeeded in giving acoherent description of a situation which, onWittgenstein’s principles, ought to be indescribablebecause inconceivable. But this is only appearance; infact Strawson has begged the whole question. Hisdescription is vitiated at the outset as a contribution tothe problem under discussion by containing terms theapplicability of which is precisely what is in question:terms like ‘language’, ‘use’, ‘words’, ‘sentences’,‘meaning’—and all without benefit of quotation marks.To say that observer B may ‘form hypotheses about themeanings (the regular use) of the words in his subject’slanguage’ is senseless unless one can speak of what hissubject is doing in terms of the concepts of meaning,

Page 52: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

35PHILOSOPHICAL BEARINGS

language, use, etc. From the fact that we can observehim going through certain motions and making certainsounds—which, were they to be performed bysomebody else in another context, that of a humansociety, it would be quite legitimate to describe inthose terms, it by no means follows that his activitiesare legitimately so describable. And the fact that Bmight correlate his subject’s practices with his owndoes not establish Strawson’s point; for the wholesubstance of Wittgenstein’s argument is that it is notthose practices considered on their own which justifythe application of categories like language andmeaning, but the social context in which thosepractices are performed. Strawson says nothing tocontrovert those arguments.

This is well brought out by Norman Malcolm. As hesays, Strawson’s ‘language-user’ might utter a soundeach time a cow appeared; but what we need to ask iswhat makes that sound a word and what makes it theword for a cow. A parrot might go through just thesame motions and we should still not say he wastalking (with understanding). ‘It is as if Strawsonthought: There is no difficulty about it; the man justmakes the mark refer to a sensation’ (or, in thisinstance, just makes the sound refer to a cow). (16: p.554). But this at once raises all the difficultiesdiscussed in the last section; it is precisely the natureof the connection between an initial definition and thesubsequent use of a sound that is in question.

A.J.Ayer makes very similar objections toWittgenstein’s position. Like Strawson he is prone todescribe the activities of his hypothetical‘unsocialized’ Crusoe in terms which derive their sense

Page 53: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

36 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

from a social context. Consider, for instance, thefollowing passage:

He (that is, ‘Crusoe’) may think that a bird which hesees flying past is a bird of the same type as one whichhe has previously named, when in fact it is of a verydifferent type, sufficiently different for him to havegiven it a different name if he had observed it moreclosely. (4).

This of course presupposes that it makes sense to speakof ‘naming’ in such a context; and all the difficultiesabout the sense we are to attach to the notion ofsameness are raised in a particularly acute form bythe phrase ‘sufficiently different for him to have givenit a different name’. For a ‘sufficient difference’ iscertainly not something that is given for oneabsolutely in the object one is observing; it gets itssense only from the particular rule one happens to befollowing. But it is essential for Ayer’s argument thatthis should have a sense independent of any particularrule, for he is trying to use it as a foundation onwhich to build the possibility of a rule independent ofany social context.

Ayer also argues that ‘some human being must havebeen the first to use a symbol’. He wishes to imply bythis that socially established rules clearly cannot havebeen presupposed by this use; and if that were so, ofcourse, established rules cannot be a logicallynecessary prerequisite of the use of symbols in general.The argument is attractive, but fallacious. From the factthat there must have been a transition from a state ofaffairs where there was no language to a state of affairsin which there was language, it by no means follows

Page 54: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

37PHILOSOPHICAL BEARINGS

that there must have been some individual who was thefirst to use language. This is just as absurd as theargument that there must have been some individualwho was the first to take part in a tug-of-war; more so,in fact. The supposition that language was invented byany individual is quite nonsensical, as is well shown byRush Rhees in his reply to Ayer. (28: p. 85–87.) Wecan imagine practices gradually growing up amongstearly men none of which could count as the inventionof language; and yet once these practices had reached acertain degree of sophistication—it would be amisunderstanding to ask what degree precisely—onecan say of such people that they have a language. Thiswhole issue involves an application of something likethe Hegelian principle of a change in quantity leadingto a difference in quality, which I will discuss morefully at a later stage.

There is one counter-argument to Wittgenstein’sposition to which Ayer seems to attach peculiarimportance, since he uses it not only in the paper towhich I have been referring but also in his later book,The Problem of Knowledge. One of Wittgenstein’smost important arguments runs as follows:

Let us imagine a table (something like a dictionary)that exists only in our imagination. A dictionary can beused to justify the translation of a word X into a wordY. But are we also to call it a justification if such atable is to be looked up only in the imagination?—‘Well, yes; then it is a subjective justification.’—Butjustification consists in appealing to somethingindependent.—‘But surely I can appeal from onememory to another. For example, I don’t know if I haveremembered the time of departure of a train right andto check it I call to mind how a page of the time-table

Page 55: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

38 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

looked. Isn’t it the same here?’—No; for this processhas got to produce a memory which is actually correct.If the mental image of the time-table could not itself betested for correctness, how could it confirm thecorrectness of the first memory? (As if someone wereto buy several copies of the morning paper to assurehimself that what it said was true.)

Looking up a table in the imagination is no morelooking up a table than the image of the result of animagined experiment is the result of an experiment.(37:I, 265.)

Ayer’s counter-argument is that any use of language,no matter how publicly established, is open to the samedifficulty; for, he says, even if one’s use of a word ona particular occasion is ratified by other language-users, one still has to identify what they say. ‘No doubtmistakes can always occur; but if one never acceptedany identification without a further check, one wouldnever identify anything at all. And then no descriptiveuse of language would be possible.’ (3: Chapter 2,Section V.) Strawson also seems to think thatWittgenstein is open to such an objection for he asks,pointedly, in connection with Wittgenstein’sarguments: ‘Do we ever in fact find ourselvesmisremembering the use of very simple words of ourcommon language, and having to correct ourselves byattention to others’ use?’ (32: p. 85.)

But this objection is misconceived; Wittgensteindoes not say that every act of identification in factneeds a further check in the sense that we can neverrest contented with our judgments. That so obviouslyleads to an infinite regress that it is difficult to imagineanyone maintaining it who did not want to establish a

Page 56: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

39PHILOSOPHICAL BEARINGS

system of complete Pyrrhonean scepticism such as isvery far indeed from Wittgenstein’s intention. In factWittgenstein himself is very insistent that‘Justifications have to come to an end somewhere’; andthis is a foundation stone of many of his mostcharacteristic doctrines: as for instance his treatment ofthe ‘matter of course’ way in which rules are, ingeneral, followed. Ayer and Strawson havemisunderstood Wittgenstein’s insistence that it must bepossible for the judgment of a single individual to bechecked by independent criteria (criteria that areestablished independently of that individual’s will); itis only in special circumstances that such a checkactually has to be made. But the fact that it can bedone if necessary makes a difference to what can besaid about those cases in which it needs not to be done.A single use of language does not stand alone; it isintelligible only within the general context in whichlanguage is used; and an important part of that contextis the procedure of correcting mistakes when theyoccur and checking when a mistake is suspected.

Page 57: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

40

CHAPTER TWO

THE NATURE OF MEANINGFUL

BEHAVIOUR

1. Philosophy and Sociology

IN Section 7 of the last chapter I tried to indicate ina general way how philosophy, conceived as the

study of the nature of man’s understanding of reality,may be expected to illuminate the nature of humaninterrelations in society. The discussion ofWittgenstein in Sections 8 and 9 has borne out thatpresumption. For it has shown that the philosophicalelucidation of human intelligence, and the notionsassociated with this, requires that these notions beplaced in the context of the relations between men insociety. In so far as there has been a genuinerevolution in philosophy in recent years, perhaps itlies in the emphasis on that fact and in the profoundworking out of its consequences, which we find inWittgenstein’s work. ‘What has to be accepted, thegiven, is—so one could say—forms of life.’ (37:II, xi,p. 226e.)

I said earlier that the relation betweenepistemology and the peripheral branches ofphilosophy was that the former concerned the generalconditions under which it is possible to speak ofunderstanding while the latter concerned the peculiar

Page 58: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

41NATURE OF MEANINGFUL BEHAVIOUR

forms which understanding takes in particular kindsof context. Wittgenstein’s remark suggests apossibility of rephrasing this: whereas thephilosophies of science, of art, of history, etc., willhave the task of elucidating the peculiar natures ofthose forms of life called ‘science’, ‘art’, etc.,epistemology will try to elucidate what is involved inthe notion of a form of life as such. Wittgenstein’sanalysis of the concept of following a rule and hisaccount of the peculiar kind of interpersonalagreement which this involves is a contribution to thatepistemological elucidation.

This conclusion has important consequences forour conception of the social studies; particularly thetheoretical part of general sociology and thefoundations of social psychology. As is well known,there has always been some dispute about the rolewhich sociology ought to play vis-à-vis the othersocial studies. Some have thought that sociologyshould be the social science par excellence,synthesising the results of special social studies, likeeconomic and political theory, into a unified theory ofsociety in general. Others, however, have wanted toregard sociology simply as one social science on thesame level as all the others, confined to a restrictedsubject-matter of its own. However, whichever ofthese views one adopts, one can in the end hardlyavoid including in sociology a discussion of thenature of social phenomena in general; and this isbound to occupy a special place amongst the variousdisciplines devoted to the study of society. For allthese disciplines are in one way or another concernedwith social phenomena and require, therefore, a clear

Page 59: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

42 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

grasp of what is involved in the concept of a socialphenomenon. Moreover,

all the subjects of investigation which are attributed tosociology, urbanism, race contacts, social stratification,or the relations between social conditions and mentalconstructions (Wissenssoziologie), are in fact difficultto isolate, and have the character of total phenomenawhich are connected with society as a whole and withthe nature of society. (2: p. 119.)

But to understand the nature of social phenomena ingeneral, to elucidate, that is, the concept of a ‘form oflife’, has been shown to be precisely the aim ofepistemology. It is true that the epistemologist’sstarting point is rather different from that of thesociologist but, if Wittgenstein’s arguments are sound,that is what he must sooner or later concern himselfwith. That means that the relations between sociologyand epistemology must be different from, and verymuch closer than, what is usually imagined to be thecase. The accepted view runs, I think, roughly asfollows. Any intellectual discipline may, at one timeor another, run into philosophical difficulties, whichoften herald a revolution in the fundamental theoriesand which form temporary obstacles in the path ofadvancing scientific enquiry. The difficulties in theconception of simultaneity which Einstein had to faceand which presaged the formulation of therevolutionary Special Theory of Relativity, provide anexample. Those difficulties bore many of thecharacteristics which one associates withphilosophical puzzlement and they were notablydifferent from the technical theoretical problems

Page 60: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

43NATURE OF MEANINGFUL BEHAVIOUR

which are solved in the normal process of advancingscientific enquiry. Now it is often supposed that newlydeveloping disciplines, with no settled basis of theoryon which to build further research, are particularlyprone to throw up philosophical puzzles; but that thisis a temporary stage which should be lived throughand then shaken off as soon as possible. But, in myview, it would be wrong to say this of sociology; forthe philosophical problems which arise there are nottiresome foreign bodies which must be removedbefore sociology can advance on its own independentscientific lines. On the contrary, the central problemof sociology, that of giving an account of the natureof social phenomena in general, itself belongs tophilosophy. In fact, not to put too fine a point on it,this part of sociology is really misbegottenepistemology. I say ‘misbegotten’ because itsproblems have been largely misconstrued, andtherefore mishandled, as a species of scientificproblem.

The usual treatment of language in textbooks ofsocial psychology shows the inadequacies to whichthis may lead. The problem of what language is isclearly of vital importance for sociology in that, withit, one is face to face with the whole question of thecharacteristic way in which human beings interactwith each other in society. Yet the important questionsare usually left untouched. One finds examples of theways in which analogous concepts may differ in thelanguages of different societies with, perhaps, someindication of the ways in which these differencescorrespond to differences in the main interests whichare characteristic of the life carried on in those

Page 61: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

44 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

societies. All this can be interesting and evenilluminating if brought forward by way of illustrationin discussing what it is, after all, for people to have alanguage at all. But this one hardly ever meets.Instead, the notion of having a language, and thenotions that go along with that: such as meaning,intelligibility, and so on—these are taken for granted.The impression given is that first there is language(with words having a meaning, statements capable ofbeing true or false) and then, this being given, itcomes to enter into human relationships and to bemodified by the particular human relationships intowhich it does so enter. What is missed is that thosevery categories of meaning, etc., are logicallydependent for their sense on social interactionbetween men. Social psychologists sometimes pay lip-service to this. We are told, for instance, that‘Concepts are products of interaction of many peoplecarrying on the important business of living togetherin groups’ (30: p. 456). But the authors go no furtherwith this than to remark on the way in whichparticular concepts may reflect the peculiar life of thesociety in which they are current. There is nodiscussion of how the very existence of conceptsdepends on group-life. And they show that they do notunderstand the force of this question when they speakof concepts ‘embodying generalizations’; for onecannot explain what concepts are in terms of thenotion of a generalization. People do not first makegeneralizations and then embody them in concepts: itis only by virtue of their possession of concepts thatthey are able to make generalizations at all.

Page 62: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

45NATURE OF MEANINGFUL BEHAVIOUR

2. Meaningful Behaviour

Wittgenstein’s account of what it is to follow a ruleis, for obvious reasons, given principally with an eyeto elucidating the nature of language. I have now toshow how this treatment may shed light on otherforms of human interaction besides speech. The formsof activity in question are, naturally, those to whichanalogous categories are applicable: those, that is, ofwhich we can sensibly say that they have a meaning, asymbolic character. In the words of Max Weber, weare concerned with human behaviour ‘if and in so faras the agent or agents associate a subjective sense.(Sinn) with it’. (33: Chapter I.) I want now toconsider what is involved in this idea of meaningfulbehaviour.

Weber says that the ‘sense’ of which he speaks issomething which is ‘subjectively intended’; and hesays that the notion of meaningful behaviour is closelyassociated with notions like motive and reason.‘“Motive” means a meaningful configuration ofcircumstances which, to the agent or observer, appearsas a meaningful “reason” (Grund) of the behaviour inquestion.’ (Ibid.)

Let us consider some examples of actions which areperformed for a reason. Suppose that it is said of acertain person, N, that he voted Labour at the lastGeneral Election because he thought that a Labourgovernment would be the most likely to preserveindustrial peace. What kind of explanation is this? Theclearest case is that in which N, prior to voting, hasdiscussed the pros and cons of voting Labour and hasexplicitly come to the conclusion: ‘I will vote Labour

Page 63: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

46 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

because that is the best way to preserve industrialpeace’. That is a paradigm case of someone performingan action for a reason. To say this is not to deny that insome cases, even where N has gone through such anexplicit process of reasoning, it may be possible todispute whether the reason he has given is in fact thereal reason for his behaviour. But there is very often noroom for doubt; and if this were not so, the idea of areason for an action would be in danger of completelylosing its sense. (This point will assume greaterimportance subsequently, when I come to discuss thework of Pareto.)

The type of case which I have taken as a paradigm isnot the only one covered by Weber’s concept. But theparadigm exhibits clearly one feature which I believeto have a more general importance. Suppose that anobserver, O, is offering the above explanation for N’shaving voted Labour: then it should be noted that theforce of O’s explanation rests on the fact that theconcepts which appear in it must be grasped not merelyby O and his hearers, but also by N himself. N musthave some idea of what it is to ‘preserve industrialpeace’ and of a connection between this and the kindof government which he expects to be in power ifLabour is elected. (For my present purposes it isunnecessary to raise the question whether N’s beliefs ina particular instance are true or not.)

Not all cases of meaningful behaviour are as clear-cut as this. Here are some intermediate examples. Nmay not, prior to casting his vote, have formulated anyreason for voting as he does. But this does notnecessarily preclude the possibility of saying that hehas a reason for voting Labour and of specifying that

Page 64: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

47NATURE OF MEANINGFUL BEHAVIOUR

reason. And in this case, just as much as in theparadigm, the acceptability of such an explanation iscontingent on N’s grasp of the concepts contained in it.If N does not grasp the concept of industrial peace itmust be senseless to say that his reason for doinganything is a desire to see industrial peace promoted,

A type of case even farther removed from myparadigm is that discussed by Freud in ThePsychopathology of Everyday Life. N forgets to post aletter and insists, even after reflection, that this was‘just an oversight’ and had no reason. A Freudianobserver might insist that N ‘must have had a reason’even though it was not apparent to N: suggestingperhaps that N unconsciously connected the posting ofthe letter with something in his life which is painfuland which he wants to suppress. In Weberian terms,Freud classifies as ‘meaningfully directed’ (sinnhaftorientiert) actions which have no sense at all to thecasual observer. Weber seems to refer to cases of thissort when, in his discussion of borderline cases, hespeaks of actions the sense of which is apparent only‘to the expert’. This means that his characterization ofSinn as something ‘subjectively intended’ must beapproached warily: more warily, for instance than it isapproached by Morris Ginsberg, who appears toassume that Weber is saying that the sociologist’sunderstanding of the behaviour of other people mustrest on an analogy with his own introspectiveexperience. (See 11: pp. 153 ff.)This misunderstandingof Weber is very common both among his critics andamong his vulgarizing followers; I will say more aboutit at a later stage. But Weber’s insistence on theimportance of the subjective point of view can be

Page 65: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

48 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

interpreted in a way which is not open to Ginsberg’sobjections: he can be taken as meaning that evenexplanations of the Freudian type, if they are to beacceptable, must be in terms of concepts which arefamiliar to the agent as well as to the observer. Itwould make no sense to say that N’s omission to post aletter to X (in settlement, say, of a debt) was anexpression of N’s unconscious resentment against X forhaving been promoted over his head, if N did nothimself understand what was meant by ‘obtainingpromotion over somebody’s head’. It is worthmentioning here too that, in seeking explanations ofthis sort in the course of psychotherapy, Freudians tryto get the patient himself to recognize the validity ofthe proffered explanation; that this indeed is almost acondition of its being accepted as the ‘right’explanation.

The category of meaningful behaviour extends alsoto actions for which the agent has no ‘reason’ or‘motive’ at all in any of the senses so far discussed. Inthe first chapter of Wirtschaft und Gesellschaft Webercontrasts meaningful action with action which is‘purely reactive’ (bloss reaktiv) and says that purelytraditional behaviour is on the borderline betweenthese two categories. But, as Talcott Parsons pointsout, Weber is not consistent in what he says aboutthis. Sometimes he seems to regard traditionalbehaviour as simply a species of habit, whereas atother times he sees it as ‘a type of social action, itstraditionalism consisting in the fixity of certainessentials, their immunity from rational or othercriticism’. (24: Chapter XVI.) Economic behaviourrelated to a fixed standard of living is cited as an

Page 66: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

49NATURE OF MEANINGFUL BEHAVIOUR

example: behaviour, that is, where a man does notexploit an increase in the productive capacities of hislabour in order to raise his standard of living but doesless work instead. Parsons remarks that tradition inthis sense is not to be equated with mere habit, buthas a normative character. That is, the tradition isregarded as a standard which directs choices betweenalternative actions. As such it clearly falls within thecategory of the sinnhaft.

Suppose that N votes Labour without deliberatingand without subsequently being able to offer anyreasons, however hard he is pressed. Suppose that he issimply following without question the example of hisfather and his friends, who have always voted Labour.(This case must be distinguished from that in whichN’s reason for voting Labour is that his father andfriends have always done so.) Now although N does notact here for any reason, his act still has a definitesense. What he does is not simply to make a mark on apiece of paper; he is casting a vote. And what I want toask is, what gives his action this sense, rather than, say,that of being a move in a game or part of a religiousritual. More generally, by what criteria do wedistinguish acts which have a sense from those whichdo not?

In the paper entitled R.Stammlers ‘Ueberwindung’der materialistischen Geschichtsauffassung, Weberconsiders the hypothetical case of two ‘non-social’beings meeting and, in a purely physical sense,‘exchanging’ objects. (See 34.) This occurrence, hesays, is conceivable as an act of economic exchangeonly if it has a sense. He expands this by saying thatthe present actions of the two men must carry with

Page 67: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

50 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

them, or represent, a regulation of their futurebehaviour. Action with a sense is symbolic: it goestogether with certain other actions in the sense that itcommits the agent to behaving in one way rather thananother in the future. This notion of ‘being committed’is most obviously appropriate where we are dealingwith actions which have an immediate socialsignificance, like economic exchange or promise-keeping. But it applies also to meaningful behaviour ofa more ‘private’ nature. Thus, to stay with examplesused by Weber, if N places a slip of paper between theleaves of a book he can be said to be ‘using abookmark’ only if he acts with the idea of using theslip to determine where he shall start re-reading. Thisdoes not mean that he must necessarily actually so useit in the future (though that is the paradigm case); thepoint is that if he does not, some special explanationwill be called for, such as that he forgot, changed hismind, or got tired of the book.

The notion of being committed by what I do now todoing something else in the future is identical in formwith the connection between a definition and thesubsequent use of the word defined, which I discussedin the last chapter. It follows that I can only becommitted in the future by what I do now if my presentact is the application of a rule. Now according to theargument of the last chapter, this is possible onlywhere the act in question has a relation to a socialcontext: this must be true even of the most private acts,if, that is, they are meaningful.

Let us return to N’s exercise of his vote: itspossibility rests on two presuppositions. In the firstplace, N must live in a society which has certain

Page 68: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

51NATURE OF MEANINGFUL BEHAVIOUR

specific political institutions—a parliament which isconstituted in a certain way and a government whichis related in a certain way to the parliament. If helives in a society whose political structure ispatriarchal, it will clearly make no sense to speak ofhim as ‘voting’ for a particular government, howevermuch his action may resemble in appearance that ofa voter in a country with an elected government.Secondly, N must himself have a certain familiaritywith those institutions. His act must be aparticipation in the political life of the country,which presupposes that he must be aware of thesymbolic relation between what he is doing now andthe government which comes into power after theelection. The force of this condition becomes moreapparent in relation to cases where ‘democraticinstitutions’ have been imposed by alienadministrators on societies to which such ways ofconducting political life are foreign. The inhabitantsof such a country may perhaps be cajoled into goingthrough the motions of marking slips of paper anddropping them into boxes, but, if words are to retainany meaning, they cannot be said to be ‘voting’unless they have some conception of the significanceof what they are doing. This remains true even if thegovernment which comes into power does so in factas a result of the ‘votes’ cast.

3. Activities and Precepts

I have claimed that the analysis of meaningfulbehaviour must allot a central role to the notion of arule; that all behaviour which is meaningful (therefore

Page 69: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

52 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

all specifically human behaviour) is ipso facto rule-governed. It may now be objected that this way ofspeaking blurs a necessary distinction: that some kindsof activity involve the participant in the observance ofrules, whilst others do not. The free-thinking anarchist,for example, certainly does not live a life which iscircumscribed by rules in the same sense as does themonk or the soldier; is it not wrong to subsume thesevery different modes of life under one fundamentalcategory?

This objection certainly shows that we must exercisecare in the use we make of the notion of a rule; but itdoes not show that the way of speaking which I haveadopted is improper or unilluminating. It is importantto notice that, in the sense in which I am speaking ofrules, it is just as true to speak of the anarchistfollowing rules in what he does as it is to say the samething of the monk. The difference between these twokinds of men is not that the one follows rules and theother does not; it lies in the diverse kinds of rule whicheach respectively follows. The monk’s life iscircumscribed by rules of behaviour which are bothexplicit and tightly drawn: they leave as little room aspossible for individual choice in situations which callfor action. The anarchist, on the other hand, eschewsexplicit norms as far as possible and prides himself onconsidering all claims for action ‘on their merits’: thatis, his choice is not determined in advance for him bythe rule he is following. But that does not mean that wecan eliminate altogether the idea of a rule from thedescription of his behaviour. We cannot do thisbecause, if I may be permitted a significant pleonasm,the anarchist’s way of life is a way of life. It is to be

Page 70: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

53NATURE OF MEANINGFUL BEHAVIOUR

distinguished, for instance, from the pointlessbehaviour of a berserk lunatic. The anarchist hasreasons for acting as he does; he makes a point of notbeing governed by explicit, rigid norms. Although heretains his freedom of choice, yet they are stillsignificant choices that he makes: they are guided byconsiderations, and he may have good reasons forchoosing one course rather than another. And thesenotions, which are essential in describing theanarchist’s mode of behaviour, presuppose the notionof a rule.

An analogy may help here. In learning to writeEnglish there are a number of fairly cut-and-driedgrammatical rules which one acquires, such as that itis wrong to follow a plural subject with a singularverb. These correspond roughly to the explicit normsgoverning monastic life. In terms of correct grammarone does not have a choice between writing ‘theywere’ and ‘they was’: if one can write grammaticallythe question of which of these expressions one shoulduse just does not arise. But this is not the only kind ofthing one learns; one also learns to follow certainstylistic canons, and these, while they guide the wayin which one writes, do not dictate that one shouldwrite in one way rather than another. Hence peoplecan have individual literary styles but, within certainlimits, can write only correct grammar or incorrectgrammar. But it would plainly be mistaken toconclude from this that literary style is not governedby any rules at all: it is something that can be learned,something that can be discussed, and the fact that itcan be so learned and discussed is essential to ourconception of it.

Page 71: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

54 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

Perhaps the best way to support this point will beto consider a persuasive presentation of the caseagainst it. Such a presentation is offered by MichaelOakeshott in a series of articles in the CambridgeJournal1. Much of Oakeshott’s argument coincideswith the view of human behaviour which has beenpresented here, and I will begin by considering thispart of what he says before venturing some criticismsof the rest.

Very much in accordance with the view I have beenadvocating is Oakeshott’s rejection of what he callsthe ‘rationalistic’ misconception of the nature ofhuman intelligence and rationality. (See 21.)According to this misconception the rationality ofhuman behaviour comes to it from without: fromintellectual functions which operate according to lawsof their own and are, in principle, quite independentof the particular forms of activity to which they maynevertheless be applied.

A good example (not discussed by Oakeshotthimself) of the sort of view to which he objects isHume’s famous assertion that ‘Reason is, and oughtonly to be the slave of the passions, and can neverpretend to any other office than to serve and obeythem’. On this view the ends of human conduct areset by the natural constitution of men’s emotions;those ends being given, the office of reason is mainlyto determine the appropriate means of achievingthem. The characteristic activities carried on in humansocieties spring then, presumably, from this interplayof reason and passion. Against this picture Oakeshott 1Reprinted in Rationalism in Politics, London, Methuen, 1962.

Page 72: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

55NATURE OF MEANINGFUL BEHAVIOUR

is quite correct to point out that: ‘A cook is not a manwho first has a vision of a pie and then tries to make it;he is a man skilled in cookery, and both his projectsand his achievements spring from that skill’. (21.)Generally, both the ends sought and the meansemployed in human life, so far from generating formsof social activity, depend for their very being on thoseforms. A religious mystic, for instance, who says thathis aim is union with God, can be understood only bysomeone who is acquainted with the religious traditionin the context of which this end is sought; a scientistwho says that his aim is to split the atom can beunderstood only by someone who is familiar withmodern physics.

This leads Oakeshott to say, again quite correctly,that a form of human activity can never be summed upin a set of explicit precepts. The activity ‘goes beyond’the precepts. For instance, the precepts have to beapplied in practice and, although we may formulateanother, higher-order, set of precepts prescribing howthe first set is to be applied, we cannot go further alongthis road without finding ourselves on the slipperyslope pointed out by Lewis Carroll in his paper, justlycelebrated amongst logicians, What the Tortoise Said toAchilles (5).

Achilles and the Tortoise are discussing threepropositions, A, B, and Z, which are so related that Zfollows logically from A and B. The Tortoise asksAchilles to treat him as if he accepted A and B as truebut did not yet accept the truth of the hypotheticalproposition (C) ‘If A and B be true, Z must be true’,and to force him, logically, to accept Z as true.Achilles begins by asking the Tortoise to accept C,

Page 73: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

56 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

which the Tortoise does; Achilles then writes in hisnotebook:

“ABC (If A and B are true, Z must be true)Z.”

He now says to the Tortoise: ‘If you accept A and Band C, you must accept Z’. When the Tortoise askswhy he must, Achilles replies: ‘Because it followslogically from them. If A and B and C are true, Z mustbe true (D). You don’t dispute that, I imagine?’ TheTortoise agrees to accept D if Achilles will write itdown. The following dialogue then ensues. Achillessays:

‘Now that you accept A and B and C and D, of courseyou accept Z.’

‘Do I?’ said the Tortoise innocently. ‘Let’s makethat quite clear. I accept A and B and C and D. SupposeI still refuse to accept Z?’

‘Then Logic would take you by the throat, and forceyou to do it!’ Achilles triumphantly replied. ‘Logicwould tell you “You can’t help yourself. Now thatyou’ve accepted A and B and C and D, you must acceptZ”. So you’ve no choice, you see.’

‘Whatever Logic is good enough to tell me is worthwriting down,’ said the Tortoise. ‘So enter it in yourbook, please. We will call it

(E) If A and B and C and D are true, Z must be true.Until I’ve granted that, of course, I needn’t grant Z. Soit’s quite a necessary step, you see?’

‘I see,’ said Achilles; and there was a touch ofsadness in his tone.

The story ends some months later with the narrator

Page 74: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

57NATURE OF MEANINGFUL BEHAVIOUR

returning to the spot and finding the pair still sittingthere. The notebook is nearly full.

The moral of this, if I may be boring enough topoint it, is that the actual process of drawing aninference, which is after all at the heart of logic, issomething which cannot be represented as a logicalformula; that, moreover, a sufficient justification forinferring a conclusion from a set of premisses is to seethat the conclusion does in fact follow. To insist on anyfurther justification is not to be extra cautious; it is todisplay a misunderstanding of what inference is.Learning to infer is not just a matter of being taughtabout explicit logical relations between propositions; itis learning to do something. Now the point whichOakeshott is making is really a generalization of this;where Carroll spoke only of logical inference,Oakeshott is making a similar point about humanactivities generally.

4. Rules and Habits

All the above fits in very well with the positionoutlined in Chapter I. Principles, precepts,definitions, formulae—all derive their sense from thecontext of human social activity in which they areapplied. But Oakeshott wishes to take a further step.He thinks it follows from this that most humanbehaviour can be adequately described in terms ofthe notion of habit or custom and that neither thenotion of a rule nor that of reflectiveness is essentialto it. This seems to me a mistake for reasons which Ishall now try to give.

In The Tower of Babel Oakeshott distinguishes

Page 75: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

58 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

between two forms of morality: that which is ‘a habitof affection and behaviour’ and that which is ‘thereflective application of a moral criterion’ (20). Heseems to think that that ‘habitual’ morality could existin abstraction from ‘reflective’ morality. In habitualmorality, he says, situations are met ‘not byconsciously applying to ourselves a rule of behaviour,nor by conduct recognized as the expression of amoral ideal, but by acting in accordance with acertain habit of behaviour’. These habits are notlearned by precept but by ‘living with people whohabitually behave in a certain manner’. Oakeshottappears to think that the dividing line betweenbehaviour which is habitual and that which is rule-governed depends on whether or not a rule isconsciously applied.

In opposition to this I want to say that the test ofwhether a man’s actions are the application of a rule isnot whether he can formulate it but whether it makessense to distinguish between a right and a wrong wayof doing things in connection with what he does.Where that makes sense, then it must also make senseto say that he is applying a criterion in what he doeseven though he does not, and perhaps cannot,formulate that criterion.

Learning how to do something is not just copyingwhat someone else does; it may start that way, but ateacher’s estimate of his pupil’s prowess will lie in thelatter’s ability to do things which he could preciselynot simply have copied. Wittgenstein has described thissituation very well. He asks us to consider someonebeing taught the series of natural numbers. Perhaps hehas first to copy what his teacher has written with his

Page 76: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

59NATURE OF MEANINGFUL BEHAVIOUR

hand being guided. He will then be asked to do the‘same’ thing by himself.

And here already there is a normal and an abnormalhearer’s reaction…We can imagine, e.g. that he doescopy the figures independently, but not in the rightorder: he writes sometimes one sometimes another atrandom. And then communication stops at that point.Or again he makes ‘mistakes’ in the order.—Thedifference between this and the first case will ofcourse be one of frequency.—Or he makes asystematic mistake; for example he copies every othernumber, or he copies the series 0, 1, 2, 3, 4, 5 …likethis: 1, 0, 3, 2, 5, 4… Here we shall almost betempted to say he has understood wrong. (37:I, 143.)

The point here is that it matters that the pupil shouldreact to his teacher’s example in one way rather thananother. He has to acquire not merely the habit offollowing his teacher’s example but also the realizationthat some ways of following that example arepermissible and others are not. That is to say, he has toacquire the ability to apply a criterion; he has to learnnot merely to do things in the same way as his teacher,but also what counts as the same way.

The importance of this distinction may be broughtout by taking Wittgenstein’s example a stage further.Learning the series of natural numbers is not justlearning to copy down a finite series of figures in theorder which one has been shown. It involves being ableto go on writing down figures that have not been shownone. In one sense, that is, it involves doing somethingdifferent from what one was originally shown; but inrelation to the rule that is being followed, this countsas ‘going on in the same way’ as one was shown.

Page 77: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

60 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

There is a sense in which to acquire a habit is toacquire a propensity to go on doing the same kind ofthing; there is another sense in which this is true oflearning a rule. These senses are different and a greatdeal hangs on the difference. Let us consider the case ofan animal forming a habit: here there can be no questionof ‘the reflective application of a criterion’. Supposethat N teaches his dog to balance a lump of sugar on itsnose and to refrain from eating it until N utters a wordof command. The dog acquires a propensity to respondin a certain way to N’s actions; we have here a type ofcase which fits reasonably well into the behaviourist’scherished category of stimulus and response. N,however, being a simple dog-lover rather than ascientist, no doubt speaks differently: he says the doghas learned a trick. This way of speaking is worthlooking at, for it opens the door to the possibility ofassessing the dog’s performance in terms which do notbelong to the stimulus-response set of concepts at all.He can now say that the dog has done the trick‘correctly’ or ‘incorrectly’. But it is important to noticethat this is an anthropomorphic way of speaking; itrequires a reference to human activities, and normswhich are here applied analogically to animals. It is onlythe dog’s relation to human beings which makes itintelligible to speak of his having mastered a trick; whatthis way of speaking amounts to could not be elucidatedby any description, however detailed, of caninebehaviour in complete isolation from human beings.

The same point is involved in pointing out that whatcounts as ‘always doing the same kind of thing whenthe word of command is uttered’ is decided by N ratherthan by the dog. Indeed it would be nonsensical to

Page 78: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

61NATURE OF MEANINGFUL BEHAVIOUR

speak of the dog’s doing this. It is only in relation toN’s purposes, involving as they do the notion of atrick, that the statement that the dog ‘always does thesame kind of thing’ has any sense.

But whereas a dog’s acquisition of a habit does notinvolve it in any understanding of what is meant by‘doing the same thing on the same kind of occasion’,this is precisely what a human being has to understandbefore he can be said to have acquired a rule; and thistoo is involved in the acquisition of those forms ofactivity which Oakeshott wants to describe in terms ofthe notion of habit. A legal analogy may help here.Oakeshott’s distinction between the two forms ofmorality is in many ways like the distinction betweenstatute law and case law; and Roscoe Pound is taking upan attitude to this distinction somewhat analogous toOakeshott’s when he refers to statute law as ‘themechanical application of rules’ and distinguishes itfrom case law which involves ‘intuitions’ (reminiscentof Oakeshott’s discussion of politics in terms of‘intimations’: see 22). This may sometimes be a helpfulway of speaking, but it should not blind us to the factthat the interpretation of precedents, just as much as theapplication of statutes, involves following rules in thesense in which I have been using the expression here. AsOtto Kahn-Freund puts it: ‘One cannot dispense with aprinciple which links one decision with another, whichraises the judicial act beyond the realm of sheerexpediency’. (27; the reference to Pound is hisIntroduction to the Philosophy of Law, Chapter III. E.H.Levi gives an excellent concise account, with examples,of the way in which the interpretation of judicialprecedents involves the application of rules: 14.)

Page 79: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

62 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

It is only when a past precedent has to be applied toa new kind of case that the importance and nature ofthe rule become apparent. The court has to ask whatwas involved in the precedent decision and that is aquestion which makes no sense except in a contextwhere the decision could sensibly be regarded as theapplication, however unselfconscious, of a rule. Thesame is true of other forms of human activity besideslaw, though elsewhere the rules may perhaps never bemade so explicit. It is only because human actionsexemplify rules that we can speak of past experience asrelevant to our current behaviour. If it were merely aquestion of habits, then our current behaviour mightcertainly be influenced by the way in which we hadacted in the past: but that would be just a causalinfluence. The dog responds to N’s commands now in acertain way because of what has happened to him inthe past; if I am told to continue the series of naturalnumbers beyond 100, I continue in a certain waybecause of my past training. The phrase ‘because of’,however, is used differently of these two situations: thedog has been conditioned to respond in a certain way,whereas I know the right way to go on on the basis ofwhat I have been taught.

5. Reflectiveness

Many of the statements Oakeshott makes abouthabitual modes of behaviour sound like the things Ihave been saying about rule-governed behaviour.

Custom is always adaptable and susceptible to thenuance of the situation. This may appear a paradoxical

Page 80: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

63NATURE OF MEANINGFUL BEHAVIOUR

assertion; custom, we have been taught, is blind. It is,however, an insidious piece of misobservation; customis not blind, it is only ‘blind as a bat’. And anyone whohas studied a tradition of customary behaviour (or atradition of any other sort) knows that both rigidity andinstability are foreign to its character. And secondly,this form of the moral life is capable of change as wellas of local variation. Indeed, no traditional way ofbehaviour, no traditional skill, ever remains fixed; itshistory is one of continuous change. (20.)

Nevertheless, the issue between us is not a merelyverbal one. Whereas Oakeshott maintains that the sortof change and adaptability of which he here speaksoccurs independently of any reflective principles, Iwant to say that the possibility of reflection isessential to that kind of adaptability. Without thispossibility we are dealing not with meaningfulbehaviour but with something which is either mereresponse to stimuli or the manifestation of a habitwhich is really blind. I do not mean by this thatmeaningful behaviour is simply a putting into effectof pre-existing reflective principles; such principlesarise in the course of conduct and are only intelligiblein relation to the conduct out of which they arise. Butequally, the nature of the conduct out of which theyarise can only be grasped as an embodiment of thoseprinciples. The notion of a principle (or maxim) ofconduct and the notion of meaningful action areinterwoven, in much the same way as Wittgensteinspoke of the notion of a rule and the notion of ‘thesame’ being interwoven.

To see this, let us look at one of the thingsOakeshott says about the contrast between his allegedtwo forms of morality. He says that dilemmas of the

Page 81: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

64 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

form ‘What ought I to do here?’ are likely to arise onlyfor someone who is self-consciously trying to followexplicitly formulated rules, not for someone who isunreflectively following an habitual mode ofbehaviour. Now it may well be true that, as Oakeshottalleges, the necessity for such heartsearchings is likelyto be more frequent and pressing for someone who istrying to follow an explicit rule without a foundation ofeveryday experience in its application. But questions ofinterpretation and consistency, that is, matters forreflection, are bound to arise for anyone who has todeal with a situation foreign to his previous experience.In a rapidly changing social environment suchproblems will arise frequently, not just becausetraditional customary modes of behaviour have brokendown, but because of the novelty of the situations inwhich those modes of behaviour have to be carried on.Of course, the resulting strain may lead to a breakdownin the traditions.

Oakeshott says that the predicament of Westernmorals is that ‘our moral life has come to be dominatedby the pursuit of ideals, a dominance ruinous to asettled mode of behaviour’. (20.) But what is ruinousto a settled mode of behaviour, of whatever kind, is anunstable environment. The only mode of life which canundergo a meaningful development in response toenvironmental changes is one which contains withinitself the means of assessing the significance of thebehaviour which it prescribes. Habits too may ofcourse change in response to changing conditions. Buthuman history is not just an account of changinghabits: it is the story of how men have tried to carryover what they regard as important in their modes of

Page 82: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

65NATURE OF MEANINGFUL BEHAVIOUR

behaviour into the new situations which they have hadto face.

Oakeshott’s attitude to reflectiveness is, as a matterof fact, incompatible with a very important point whichhe makes early on in the discussion. He says that themoral life is ‘conduct to which there is an alternative’.Now though it is true that this ‘alternative’ need not beconsciously before the agent’s mind it must besomething which could be brought before his mind.This condition is fulfilled only if the agent coulddefend what he has done against the allegation that heought to have done something different. Or at least hemust be able to understand what it would have beenlike to act differently. The dog who balances sugar onits nose in response to its master’s command has noconception of what it would be to respond differently(because it has no conception of what it is doing at all).Hence it has no alternative to what it does; it justresponds to the appropriate stimulus. An honest manmay refrain from stealing money, though he could doso easily and needs it badly; the thought of actingotherwise need never occur to him. Nevertheless, hehas the alternative of acting differently because heunderstands the situation he is in and the nature ofwhat he is doing (or refraining from doing).Understanding something involves understanding thecontradictory too: I understand what it is to acthonestly just so far as and no farther than I understandwhat it is not to act honestly. That is why conductwhich is the product of understanding, and only that, isconduct to which there is an alternative.

Page 83: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

66

CHAPTER THREE

THE SOCIAL STUDIES AS SCIENCE

1. J.S.Mill’s ‘Logic of the Moral Sciences’

I TRIED to show in the last chapter how the view ofphilosophy presented in Chapter I leads to the

discussion of the nature of human activities in society.I want next to consider some of the difficulties whicharise if we try to base our understanding of societieson the methods of natural science. I start with JohnStuart Mill for two reasons: first, because Mill statesnaively a position which underlies thepronouncements of a large proportion ofcontemporary social scientists, even if they do notalways make it explicit; second, because some rathermore sophisticated interpretations of the socialstudies as science, which I shall examinesubsequently, can be best understood as attempts toremedy some of the more obvious defects in Mill’sposition. (Though I do not want to suggest that thisrepresents the actual historical genesis of such ideas.)

Mill, like many of our own contemporaries,regarded the state of the ‘moral sciences’ as a ‘blot onthe face of science’. The way to remove this was togeneralize the methods used in those subjects ‘onwhich the results obtained have finally received theunanimous assent of all who have attended the proof.

Page 84: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

67SOCIAL STUDIES AS SCIENCE

(18: Book VI, Chapter I.) For this reason he regardedthe philosophy of the social studies as just a branch ofthe philosophy of science. ‘The methods ofinvestigation applicable to moral and social sciencemust have been already described, if I have succeededin enumerating and characterizing those of science ingeneral.’ (Ibid.) This implies that, despite the title ofBook VI of the System of Logic, Mill does not reallybelieve that there is a ‘logic of the moral sciences’. Thelogic is the same as that of any other science and allthat has to be done is to elucidate certain difficultiesarising in its application to the peculiar subject-matterstudied in the moral sciences.

That is the task to which the main part of Mill’sdiscussion is addressed. I want here to examine ratherthe validity of the thesis which his discussion takesfor granted. To understand it we need to refer toMill’s conception of scientific investigation generally,which is based on Hume’s ideas about the nature ofcausation. (See 12: Sections IV to VII; and 18: BookII.) To say that A is the cause of B is not to assert theexistence of any intelligible (or mysterious) nexusbetween A and B, but to say that the temporalsuccession of A and B is an instance of ageneralization to the effect that events like A arealways found in our experience to be followed byevents like B.

If scientific investigation consists in establishingcausal sequences, then it seems to follow that we mayhave a scientific investigation of any subject-matterabout which it is possible to establish generalizations.Indeed, Mill goes further: ‘Any facts are fitted, inthemselves, to be a subject of science, which follow

Page 85: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

68 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

one another according to constant laws; although theselaws may not have been discovered, nor even bediscoverable by our existing resources’. (18: Book VI,Chapter III.) That is, there may be science whereverthere are uniformities; and there may be uniformitieseven where we have not yet discovered them and arenot in a position to discover them and formulate themin generalizations.

Mill cites the contemporary state of meteorology asan example: everybody knows that changes inatmospheric conditions are subject to regularities; theyare therefore a proper subject for scientific study. Thishas not got very far owing to ‘the difficulty ofobserving the facts on which the phenomena depend’.The theory of the tides (‘Tidology’) is in somewhatbetter shape in that scientists have discovered thephenomena on which the movements of the tidesdepend in general; but they are unable to predictexactly what will happen in particular circumstancesowing to the complexity of local conditions in thecontext of which the gravitational effects of the moonoperate. (Ibid.)

Mill supposes that the ‘science of human nature’could at least be developed to the level of Tidology.Owing to the complexity of the variables we may beunable to do more than make statistical generalizationsabout the probable outcome of social situations. ‘Theagencies which determine human character are sonumerous and diversified…that in the aggregate theyare never in two cases exactly similar.’ Nevertheless,

an approximate generalization is, in social inquiries,for most practical purposes equivalent to an exact one;

Page 86: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

69SOCIAL STUDIES AS SCIENCE

that which is only probable when asserted ofindividual human beings indiscriminately selected,being certain when affirmed of the character andcollective conduct of masses.

(Ibid.) Just as the irregularity of the tides as between differentplaces on the globe does not mean that there are noregular laws governing them, so in the case of humanbehaviour. Individual divergences are to be explainedby the operation of laws on highly diversifiedindividual situations. So broad statisticalgeneralizations are not ultimately enough: they must be‘connected deductively with the laws of nature fromwhich they result’. These ultimate laws of nature arethe ‘Laws of Mind’ discussed in Chapter IV of theLogic; they differ from ‘empirical laws’ not in kind butin their much greater degree of generality andexactitude. Like all scientific laws they are statementsof uniformities, namely ‘uniformities of successionamong states of mind’. Mill raises the question whetherthese should be resolved into uniformities ofsuccession between physiological states and states ofmind and concludes that, though this may one day bepossible to a significant degree, it does not vitiate thepossibility of establishing autonomous psychologicallaws which do not depend on physiology.

‘Ethology, or the Science of the Development ofCharacter’ can be based on our knowledge of the Lawsof Mind. (18: Book VI, Chapter IV.) This comprises thestudy of human mental development, which Millconceives as resulting from the operation of the generalLaws of Mind on the individual circumstances of

Page 87: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

70 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

particular human beings. Hence he regards Ethology as‘altogether deductive’, as opposed to Psychologywhich is observational and experimental.

The laws of the formation of character are…derivativelaws, resulting from the general laws of mind, and areto be obtained by deducing them from those generallaws by supposing any given set of circumstances, andthen considering what, according to the laws of mind,will be the influence of those circumstances on theformation of character. (Ibid.)

Ethology is related to Psychology as is mechanics totheoretical physics; its principles are ‘axiomata media’,on the one hand derived from the general Laws ofMind and on the other hand leading to the ‘empiricallaws resulting from simple observation’.

The discovery of these lowest-level empirical laws isthe task of the historian. The social scientist aims toexplain the empirical laws of history by showing howthey follow, first from the axiomata media of Ethology,and ultimately from the general laws of Psychology.This leads Mill to his conception of the ‘InverseDeductive Method’. Historical circumstances are soexceedingly complex, owing to the cumulative effect of‘the influence exercised over each generation by thegenerations which preceded it’ (18: Book VI, ChapterX), that nobody could hope to achieve a sufficientlydetailed knowledge of any particular historicalsituation to predict its outcome. So, in dealing withlarge-scale historical developments, the social scientistmust, for the most part, wait and see what happens,formulate the results of his observations in ‘EmpiricalLaws of Society’, and finally ‘connect them with the

Page 88: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

71SOCIAL STUDIES AS SCIENCE

laws of human nature, by deductions showing that suchwere the derivative laws naturally to be expected as theconsequences of those ultimate ones’. (Ibid.)

Karl Popper has indicated some of themisconceptions in this account of the social sciences.In particular he has criticized what he calls Mill’s‘Psychologism’: the doctrine that the development ofone social situation out of another can ultimately beexplained in terms of individual psychology. He hasalso shown the confusions involved in describing thefindings of history as ‘empirical laws of society’,rather than as statements of trends. (See 25: Chapter14; and 26: Section 27.) Here I want to concentrate onsome of the other elements in Mill’s view; I hope thusto be able to show that Mill’s conception of the socialstudies is open to much more radical objections eventhan those which Popper has brought forward.

2. Differences in Degree and Differences in Kind

Mill regards all explanations as fundamentally of thesame logical structure; and this view is the foundationof his belief that there can be no fundamental logicaldifference between the principles according to whichwe explain natural changes and those according towhich we explain social changes. It is a necessaryconsequence of this that the methodological issuesconcerning the moral sciences should be seen asempirical: an attitude involving a wait-and-see attitudeto the question of what can be achieved by the socialsciences and, incidentally, ruling the philosopher out ofthe picture.

But the issue is not an empirical one at all: it is

Page 89: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

72 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

conceptual. It is not a question of what empiricalresearch may show to be the case, but of whatphilosophical analysis reveals about what it makessense to say. I want to show that the notion of a humansociety involves a scheme of concepts which islogically incompatible with the kinds of explanationoffered in the natural sciences.

Both the rhetorical strength and the logicalweakness of Mill’s position revolve round the phrase‘just very much more complicated’. It is true, so theline of thought runs, that human beings reactdifferently to their environment from other creatures;but the difference is just one of complexity. So theuniformities, though more difficult to discover in thecase of humans, certainly exist; and the generalizationswhich express them are on precisely the same logicalfooting as any other generalizations.

Now though human reactions are very much morecomplex than those of other beings, they are not justvery much more complex. For what is, from one pointof view, a change in the degree of complexity is, fromanother point of view, a difference in kind: theconcepts which we apply to the more complexbehaviour are logically different from those we applyto the less complex. This is an instance of somethinglike the Hegelian ‘Law of the Transformation ofQuantity into Quality’ which I mentioned inconnection with Ayer in the first Chapter.Unfortunately, Hegel’s account of this, as well asEngels’s gloss on Hegel, commits a mistake closelyanalogous to Mill’s, in failing to distinguish physicalchanges from conceptual changes. They include, asinstances of one and the same principle, the sudden

Page 90: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

73SOCIAL STUDIES AS SCIENCE

qualitative change of water into ice following on aseries of uniform quantitative changes of temperature,and on the other hand the qualitative change fromhirsuteness to baldness following on a series ofuniform quantitative changes in the number of hairs.(See 1: Chapter II, Section 7. For a detailed applicationof the principle to a particular sociological problem see27, passim.)

By how many degrees does one need to reduce thetemperature of a bucket of water for it to freeze?—Theanswer to that has to be settled experimentally. Howmany grains of wheat does one have to add togetherbefore one has a heap?—This cannot be settled byexperiment because the criteria by which we distinguisha heap from a non-heap are vague in comparison withthose by which we distinguish water from ice: there isno sharp dividing line. Neither, as Acton mentions, isthere any sharp dividing line between what is and whatis not alive: but that does not make the differencebetween life and non-life ‘merely one of degree’. Actonsays that ‘the point at which we draw the line is one thatwe have to choose, not one that the facts press upon usin unmistakable fashion’. But though there may be achoice in borderline cases, there is not in others: it is notfor me or anyone else to decide whether I, as I writethese words, am alive or not.

The reaction of a cat which is seriously hurt is ‘verymuch more complex’ than that of a tree which is beingchopped down. But is it really intelligible to say it isonly a difference in degree? We say the cat ‘writhes’about. Suppose I describe his very complex movementsin purely mechanical terms, using a set of space-timeco-ordinates. This is, in a sense, a description of what

Page 91: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

74 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

is going on as much as is the statement that the cat iswrithing in pain. But the one statement could not besubstituted for the other. The statement which includesthe concept of writhing says something which nostatement of the other sort, however detailed, couldapproximate to. The concept of writhing belongs to aquite different framework from that of the concept ofmovement in terms of space-time co-ordinates; and it isthe former rather than the latter which is appropriate tothe conception of the cat as an animate creature.Anyone who thought that a study of the mechanics ofthe movement of animate creatures would throw lighton the concept of animate life would be the victim of aconceptual misunderstanding.

Similar considerations apply to my earliercomparison between the reactions of a dog who istaught a trick and those of a man who is taught a ruleof language. Certainly the latter are very much morecomplex, but what is more important is the logicaldifference between the concepts which are applicable.Whereas the man learns to understand the rule the dogjust learns to react in a certain way. The differencebetween these concepts follows but cannot beexplained in terms of the difference in the complexityof the reactions. As indicated in the earlier discussion,the concept of understanding is rooted in a socialcontext in which the dog does not participate as doesthe man.

Some social scientists have acknowledged thedifference in concept between our currently accepteddescriptions and explanations of natural and of socialprocesses respectively, but have argued that the socialscientist need not adhere to this non-scientific

Page 92: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

75SOCIAL STUDIES AS SCIENCE

conceptual framework; that he is at liberty to framesuch concepts as are useful for the kind ofinvestigation he is conducting. I shall consider some ofthe fallacies in this line of thought in the next chapter;but Mill does not follow it. He takes for granted thescientific legitimacy of describing human behaviour interms which are current in everyday discourse. TheLaws of Mind are high-level causal generalizationssetting out invariable sequences between ‘Thoughts,Emotions, Volitions, and Sensations’. (18: Book VI,Chapter IV.) And his argument against Libertarianismin Chapter II is couched in terms of such conventionalcategories as ‘character and disposition’, ‘motives’,‘purposes’, ‘efforts’, and so on. I have next then todiscuss the attempt to interpret explanations ofbehaviour in such terms as based on generalizations ofthe causal type.

3. Motives and Causes

It will not do simply to dismiss Mill as antediluvian, forhis approach flourishes still at the present time, as canbe seen by studying the discussion of motives inT.M.Newcomb’s prominent textbook of socialpsychology. (19: Chapter II). Newcomb agrees with Millin regarding explanations of actions in terms of theagent’s motives as a species of causal explanation; butdiffers from him in regarding motives as physiological,rather than psychological, states. A motive is ‘a state ofthe organism in which bodily energy is mobilized andselectively directed towards part of the environment’.Newcomb also speaks of ‘drives’: ‘bodily states felt asrestlessness, which initiate tendencies to activity’.

Page 93: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

76 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

Clearly a mechanical model is at work here: it is as ifthe actions of a man were like the behaviour of a watch,where the energy contained in the tensed spring istransmitted via the mechanism in such a way as to bringabout the regular revolution of the hands.

Why does Newcomb abandon Mill’s caution aboutadmitting Comte’s claim that explanation in terms ofmotives should be reducible to physiologicalexplanations? Is it that the once problematicphysiological states have now been identified? Not atall for, as Newcomb says, ‘nothing akin to a motive hasever been seen by a psychologist’. No, theidentification of motives with ‘states of the organism’is the action of a drowning man clutching at a straw.Newcomb thinks himself forced to this conclusion bythe unacceptability of the only alternatives he canenvisage: viz. that ‘motives are merely figments of thepsychologist’s imagination’ or else that the motiveascribed to a sequence of behaviour is simply asynonym for that behaviour itself.

He also imagines that there is compelling, thoughnecessarily circumstantial, positive evidence. ‘First, abehaviour sequence may show varying degrees ofstrength, or intensity, while its direction remains more orless constant.’ ‘The only way to account for such facts isto assume that a motive corresponds to an actual state ofthe organism.’ Newcomb weights the scales heavily inhis own favour by relying largely on examples whichinvolve obviously physiological drives like hunger, thirstand sex; and by appealing mainly to experiments withanimals (to whose behaviour the concept of a motive isnot obviously appropriate), he ensures that only thephysiological aspects of those drives shall be taken into

Page 94: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

77SOCIAL STUDIES AS SCIENCE

account. But would it be intelligent to try to explain howRomeo’s love for Juliet enters into his behaviour in thesame terms as we might want to apply to the rat whosesexual excitement makes him run across an electricallycharged grid to reach his mate? Does not Shakespearedo this much better?

Moreover, unless and until the ‘actual state of theorganism’ is actually identified and correlated with theappropriate mode of behaviour, this type of explanationis as vacuous as those which Newcomb rejects. And thefacts which he adduces certainly do not constituteevidence for the desired conclusion; the most one cansay is that if there were good independent reasons forregarding motives as bodily states, those facts wouldnot be incompatible with such a view. This isparticularly obvious in connection with the‘experimental evidence’, to which Newcomb appeals,provided by Zeigarnik in 1927. In these experiments aset of people were each given a series of twenty tasksand were told that there was a strict (thoughunspecified) time-limit for each task. But each subjectwas in fact allowed to complete only half his allottedtasks, irrespective of the time he had taken, and wasgiven to understand that his permitted time hadexpired. Subsequently it was found that the subjectswere inclined to remember the nature of theuncompleted tasks more readily than the others and tomanifest a desire to be allowed to finish them.Newcomb comments:

Such evidence suggests that motivation involves amobilization of energy earmarked, as it were, forachieving a specified goal. The experimental data do

Page 95: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

78 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

not provide final ‘proof’ for such a theory, but they areconsistent with it and are difficult to explain in anyother way. (19: p. 117.)

Now this evidence only ‘suggests’ such a conclusion tosomeone who is already predisposed to believe it; andthe necessity for any special explanation is not in factobvious. The behaviour noted by Zeigarnik is perfectlyintelligible in such terms as the following: that thesubjects’ interest had been aroused and they wereirritated at not being allowed to finish something whichthey had started. If that sounds insufficiently scientificto anyone, he should ask himself just how much isadded to our understanding by Newcomb’s way oftalking. There is in fact a very simple, but nonethelesscogent, argument against the physiological interpretationof motives. To discover the motives of a puzzling actionis to increase our understanding of that action; that iswhat ‘understanding’ means as applied to humanbehaviour. But this is something we in fact discoverwithout any significant knowledge about people’sphysiological states; therefore our accounts of theirmotives can have nothing to do with their physiologicalstates. It does not follow, as Newcomb fears, that motiveexplanations are either mere tautologies or are an appealto figments of the imagination. But before I try to give apositive account of what they do involve, there are somefurther misconceptions to be removed.

Mill, as we have seen, rejects the physiologicalaccount of motives, but he still wants to make motiveexplanations a species of causal explanation. Theconception he wishes to advocate, though he is notvery explicit, seems to be something like this.—A

Page 96: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

79SOCIAL STUDIES AS SCIENCE

motive is a specific mental occurrence in a Cartesiansense of ‘mental’ implying that it belongs wholly to therealm of consciousness). A toothache, for instance, ismental in this sense, whereas the hole in the toothwhich gives rise to the ache is physical. It makes senseto say that someone has a hole in his tooth, of which heis unaware, but not that that he has a toothache ofwhich he is unaware: ‘unfelt ache’ is a self-contradictory expression. The issue between Mill andNewcomb can now be phrased as follows: whereasNewcomb wants to assimilate motives (toothaches) tostates of the organism (holes in the teeth), Mill insiststhat these are different and argues that it has yet to beshown whether to every motive (toothache) therecorresponds a specific kind of organic state (dentaldecay). But what we can do, Mill argues, is to studythe causal relation between motives, considered aspurely conscious events, and the actions to which theygive rise. This involves careful observation of whatspecific mental occurrences are associated with whatactions—just as we might discover that certain kinds ofstoppage in a motor engine are associated with ablocked carburettor and certain others with a defectivesparking plug.

Mill’s account does fit moderately well certain kindsof fact which we can discover about ourselves. Forinstance, I might come to associate a certain kind ofheadache with an incipient attack of migraine; everytime I experience that kind of headache I can thenpredict that, within an hour, I shall be lying in bed ingreat discomfort. But nobody would want to call myheadache the motive for the migraine.—Neither, ofcourse, should we as a matter of fact be justified in

Page 97: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

80 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

calling the headache the cause of the migraine: but thisraises general difficulties about the validity of Mill’saccount of scientific method which it would be out ofplace to discuss here.

4. Motives, Dispositions and Reasons

Gilbert Ryle argues, against the kind of accountadvocated by Mill, that to speak of a person’s motivesis not to speak of any events at all, either mental orphysical, but is to refer to his general dispositions toact in the ways in question. ‘To explain an act as donefrom a certain motive is not analogous to saying thatthe glass broke, because a stone hit it, but to the quitedifferent type of statement that the glass broke, whenthe stone hit it, because the glass was brittle.’ (29: p.87.) There are a number of objections to this. For onething, there seems to be a danger of reducing motiveexplanations to the sort of vacuity feared by Newcomb.(An analogous point is made by Peter Geach; See 10:p. 5.) Again, Ryle’s account runs into difficultieswhere we assign a motive to an act which is quite atvariance with the agent’s previously experiencedbehaviour. There is no contradiction in saying thatsomeone who never before manifested any signs of ajealous disposition has, on a given occasion, actedfrom jealousy; indeed, it is precisely when someoneacts unexpectedly that the need for a motiveexplanation is particularly apparent.

But for my present purposes it is more important tonotice that though Ryle’s account is different fromMill’s in many respects, it is not nearly differentenough. A dispositional, just as much as a causal,

Page 98: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

81SOCIAL STUDIES AS SCIENCE

statement, is based on generalizations from what hasbeen observed to happen. But a statement about anagent’s motives is not like that: it is better understoodas analogous to a setting out of the agent’s reasons foracting thus. Suppose that N, a university lecturer, saysthat he is going to cancel his next week’s lecturesbecause he intends to travel to London: here we have astatement of intention for which a reason is given. NowN does not infer his intention of cancelling his lecturesfrom his desire to go to London, as the imminentshattering of the glass might be inferred, either fromthe fact that someone had thrown a stone or from thebrittleness of the glass. N does not offer his reason asevidence for the soundness of his prediction about hisfuture behaviour. (Cf. Wittgenstein; 37: I, 629 ff.)Rather, he is justifying his intention. His statement isnot of the form: ‘Such and such causal factors arepresent, therefore this will result’; nor yet of the form:‘I have such and such a disposition, which will resultin my doing this’; it is of the form: ‘In view of suchand such considerations this will be a reasonable thingto do’.

This takes me back to the argument of Chapter II,Section 2, which provides a way of correcting Ryle’saccount of motives. Ryle says that a statement aboutsomeone’s motives is to be understood as a ‘law-likeproposition’ describing the agent’s propensity to act incertain kinds of way on certain kinds of occasion. (29:p. 89.) But the ‘law-like proposition’ in terms of whichN’s reasons must be understood concerns not N’sdispositions but the accepted standards of reasonablebehaviour current in his society.

Page 99: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

82 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

The terms ‘reason’ and ‘motive’ are notsynonymous. It would, for instance, be absurd todescribe most imputations of motives as‘justifications’: to impute a motive is more often tocondemn than it is to justify. To say, for example, thatN murdered his wife from jealousy is certainly not tosay that he acted reasonably. But it is to say that his actwas intelligible in terms of the modes of behaviourwhich are familiar in our society, and that it wasgoverned by considerations appropriate to its context.These two aspects of the matter are interwoven: onecan act ‘from considerations’ only where there areaccepted standards of what is appropriate to appeal to.The behaviour of Chaucer’s Troilus towards Cressida isintelligible only in the context of the conventions ofcourtly love. Understanding Troilus presupposesunderstanding those conventions, for it is from themthat his acts derive their meaning.

I have noted how the relation between N’s intentionand his reason for it differs from the relation between aprediction and the evidence offered in its support. Butsomebody who knows N and his circumstances welland who is familiar with the type of considerationwhich he is prone to regard as important, may on thebasis of this knowledge predict how he is likely tobehave. ‘N has a jealous temperament; if his emotionsin that direction are aroused he is likely to becomeviolent. I must be careful not to provoke him further.’Here I adduce N’s motives as part of the evidence formy prediction of his behaviour. But though this ispossible, given that I already possess the concept of amotive, that concept is not in the first place learned aspart of a technique for making predictions (unlike the

Page 100: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

83SOCIAL STUDIES AS SCIENCE

concept of a cause). Learning what a motive is belongsto learning the standards governing life in the societyin which one lives; and that again belongs to theprocess of learning to live as a social being.

5. The Investigation of Regularities

A follower of Mill might concede that explanations ofhuman behaviour must appeal not to causalgeneralizations about the individual’s reaction to hisenvironment but to our knowledge of the institutionsand ways of life which give his acts their meaning. Buthe might argue that this does not damage thefundamentals of Mill’s thesis, since understandingsocial institutions is still a matter of grasping empiricalgeneralizations which are logically on a footing withthose of natural science. For an institution is, after all,a certain kind of uniformity, and a uniformity can onlybe grasped in a generalization. I shall now examine thisargument.

A regularity or uniformity is the constant recurrenceof the same kind of event on the same kind of occasion;hence statements of uniformities presuppose judgementsof identity. But this takes us right back to the argumentof Chapter I, Section 8, according to which criteria ofidentity are necessarily relative to some rule: with thecorollary that two events which count as qualitativelysimilar from the point of view of one rule would countas different from the point of view of another. So toinvestigate the type of regularity studied in a given kindof enquiry is to examine the nature of the rule accordingto which judgements of identity are made in thatenquiry. Such judgements are intelligible only relatively

Page 101: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

84 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

to a given mode of human behaviour, governed by itsown rules.1 In a physical science the relevant rules arethose governing the procedures of investigators in thescience in question. For instance, someone with nounderstanding of the problems and procedures ofnuclear physics would gain nothing from being presentat an experiment like the Cockcroft-Waltonbombardment of lithium by hydrogen; indeed even thedescription of what he saw in those terms would beunintelligible to him, since the term ‘bombardment’does not carry the sense in the context of the nuclearphysicists’ activities that it carries elsewhere. Tounderstand what was going on in this experiment hewould have to learn the nature of what nuclearphysicists do; and this would include learning thecriteria according to which they make judgements ofidentity.

Those rules, like all others, rest on a social contextof common activity. So to understand the activities ofan individual scientific investigator we must takeaccount of two sets of relations: first, his relation tothe phenomena which he investigates; second, hisrelation to his fellow-scientists. Both of these areessential to the sense of saying that he is ‘detectingregularities’ or ‘discovering uniformities’; but writerson scientific ‘methodology’ too often concentrate on

1 Cf. Hume: A Treatise of Human Nature, Introduction—“’Tisevident, that all the sciences have a relation, greater or less, tohuman nature; and that however wide any of them may seem to runfrom it, they still return back by one passage or another.” Hume’sremark is a further reminder of the close relation between thesubject of this monograph and one of the most persistent anddominant motifs in the history of modern philosophy.

Page 102: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

85SOCIAL STUDIES AS SCIENCE

the first and overlook the importance of the second.That they must belong to different types is evidentfrom the following considerations.—The phenomenabeing investigated present themselves to the scientist asan object of study; he observes them and noticescertain facts about them. But to say of a man that hedoes this presupposes that he already has a mode ofcommunication in the use of which rules are alreadybeing observed. For to notice something is to identifyrelevant characteristics, which means that the noticermust have some concept of such characteristics; this ispossible only if he is able to use some symbolaccording to a rule which makes it refer to thosecharacteristics. So we come back to his relation to hisfellow-scientists, in which context alone he can bespoken of as following such a rule. Hence the relationbetween N and his fellows, in virtue of which we saythat N is following the same rule as they, cannot besimply a relation of observation: it cannot consist inthe fact that N has noticed how his fellows behave andhas decided to take that as a norm for his ownbehaviour. For this would presuppose that we couldgive some account of the notion of ‘noticing how hisfellows behave’ apart from the relation between N andhis fellows which we are trying to specify; and that, ashas been shown, is untrue. To quote Rush Rhees: ‘Wesee that we understand one another, without noticingwhether our reactions tally or not. Because we agree inour reactions, it is possible for me to tell yousomething, and it is possible for you to teach mesomething’. (28.)

In the course of his investigation the scientistapplies and develops the concepts germane to his

Page 103: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

86 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

particular field of study. This application andmodification are ‘influenced’ both by the phenomenato which they are applied and also by the fellow-workers in participation with whom they are applied.But the two kinds of ‘influence’ are different. Whereasit is on the basis of his observation of the phenomena(in the course of his experiments) that he develops hisconcepts as he does, he is able to do this only in virtueof his participation in an established form of activitywith his fellow-scientists. When I speak of‘participation’ here I do not necessarily imply anydirect physical conjunction or even any directcommunication between fellow-participants. What isimportant is that they are all taking part in the samegeneral kind of activity, which they have all learned insimilar ways; that they are, therefore, capable ofcommunicating with each other about what they aredoing; that what any one of them is doing is inprinciple intelligible to the others.

6. Understanding Social Institutions

Mill’s view is that understanding a social institutionconsists in observing regularities in the behaviour of itsparticipants and expressing these regularities in theform of generalizations. Now if the position of thesociological investigator (in a broad sense) can beregarded as comparable, in its main logical outlines,with that of the natural scientist, the following must bethe case. The concepts and criteria according to whichthe sociologist judges that, in two situations, the samething has happened, or the same action performed,must be understood in relation to the rules governing

Page 104: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

87SOCIAL STUDIES AS SCIENCE

sociological investigation. But here we run against adifficulty; for whereas in the case of the naturalscientist we have to deal with only one set of rules,namely those governing the scientist’s investigationitself, here what the sociologist is studying, as well ashis study of it, is a human activity and is thereforecarried on according to rules. And it is these rules,rather than those which govern the sociologist’sinvestigation, which specify what is to count as ‘doingthe same kind of thing’ in relation to that kind ofactivity.

An example may make this clearer. Consider theparable of the Pharisee and the Publican (Luke, 18, 9).Was the Pharisee who said ‘God, I thank Thee that Iam not as other men are’ doing the same kind of thingas the Publican who prayed ‘God be merciful unto mea sinner’? To answer this one would have to start byconsidering what is involved in the idea of prayer; andthat is a religious question. In other words, theappropriate criteria for deciding whether the actions ofthese two men were of the same kind or not belong toreligion itself. Thus the sociologist of religion will beconfronted with an answer to the question: Do thesetwo acts belong to the same kind of activity?; and thisanswer is given according to criteria which are nottaken from sociology, but from religion itself.

But if the judgements of identity—and hence thegeneralizations—of the sociologist of religion rest oncriteria taken from religion, then his relation to theperformers of religious activity cannot be just that ofobserver to observed. It must rather be analogous to theparticipation of the natural scientist with his fellow-workers in the activities of scientific investigation.

Page 105: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

88 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

Putting the point generally, even if it is legitimate tospeak of one’s understanding of a mode of socialactivity as consisting in a knowledge of regularities, thenature of this knowledge must be very different from thenature of knowledge of physical regularities. So it isquite mistaken in principle to compare the activity of astudent of a form of social behaviour with that of, say,an engineer studying the workings of a machine; andone does not advance matters by saying, with Mill, thatthe machine in question is of course immensely morecomplicated than any physical machine. If we are goingto compare the social student to an engineer, we shall dobetter to compare him to an apprentice engineer who isstudying what engineering—that is, the activity ofengineering—is all about. His understanding of socialphenomena is more like the engineer’s understanding ofhis colleagues’ activities than it is like the engineer’sunderstanding of the mechanical systems which hestudies.

This point is reflected in such common-senseconsiderations as the following: that a historian orsociologist of religion must himself have somereligious feeling if he is to make sense of the religiousmovement he is studying and understand theconsiderations which govern the lives of itsparticipants. A historian of art must have someaesthetic sense if he is to understand the problemsconfronting the artists of his period; and without thishe will have left out of his account precisely whatwould have made it a history of art, as opposed to arather puzzling external account of certain motionswhich certain people have been perceived to gothrough.

Page 106: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

89SOCIAL STUDIES AS SCIENCE

I do not wish to maintain that we must stop at theunreflective kind of understanding of which I gave asan instance the engineer’s understanding of theactivities of his colleagues. But I do want to say thatany more reflective understanding must necessarilypresuppose, if it is to count as genuine understandingat all, the participant’s unreflective understanding.And this in itself makes it misleading to compare itwith the natural scientist’s understanding of hisscientific data. Similarly, although the reflectivestudent of society, or of a particular mode of sociallife, may find it necessary to use concepts which arenot taken from the forms of activity which he isinvestigating, but which are taken rather from thecontext of his own investigation, still these technicalconcepts of his will imply a previous understandingof those other concepts which belong to the activitiesunder investigation.

For example, liquidity preference is a technicalconcept of economics: it is not generally used bybusiness men in the conduct of their affairs but by theeconomist who wishes to explain the nature andconsequences of certain kinds of business behaviour.But it is logically tied to concepts which do enter intobusiness activity, for its use by the economistpresupposes his understanding of what it is to conducta business, which in turn involves an understanding ofsuch business concepts as money, profit, cost, risk, etc.It is only the relation between his account and theseconcepts which makes it an account of economicactivity as opposed, say, to a piece of theology.

Again, a psychoanalyst may explain a patient’sneurotic behaviour in terms of factors unknown to the

Page 107: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

90 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

patient and of concepts which would be unintelligibleto him. Let us suppose that the psychoanalyst’sexplanation refers to events in the patient’s earlychildhood. Well, the description of those events willpresuppose an understanding of the concepts in termsof which family life, for example, is carried on in oursociety; for these will have entered, howeverrudimentarily, into the relations between the child andhis family. A psychoanalyst who wished to give anaccount of the aetiology of neuroses amongst, say, theTrobriand Islanders, could not just apply withoutfurther reflection the concepts developed by Freud forsituations arising in our own society. He would havefirst to investigate such things as the idea of fatherhoodamongst the islanders and take into account anyrelevant aspects in which their idea differed from thatcurrent in his own society. And it is almost inevitablethat such an investigation would lead to somemodification in the psychological theory appropriatefor explaining neurotic behaviour in this new situation.

These considerations also provide somejustification for the sort of historical scepticism whichthat underestimated philosopher, R.G.Collingwood,expresses in The Idea of History . (6: passim.)Although they need not be brought to the foregroundwhere one is dealing with situations in one’s ownsociety or in societies with whose life one isreasonably-familiar, the practical implications becomepressing where the object of study is a society whichis culturally remote from that of the investigator. Thisaccounts for the weight which the Idealists attached toconcepts like ‘empathy’ and ‘historical imagination’(which is not to deny that these concepts give rise to

Page 108: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

91SOCIAL STUDIES AS SCIENCE

difficulties of their own). It is also connected withanother characteristic doctrine of theirs: that theunderstanding of a human society is closelyconnected with the activities of the philosopher. I ledup to that doctrine in the first two chapters and shallreturn to it in the last two.

7. Prediction in the Social Studies

In my discussion of Oakeshott in the last chapter Inoticed the importance of the fact that voluntarybehaviour is behaviour to which there is an alternative.Since understanding something involves understandingits contradictory, someone who, with understanding,performs X must be capable of envisaging thepossibility of doing not-X. This is not an empiricalstatement but a remark about what is involved in theconcept of doing something with understanding.Consider now an observer, O, of N’s behaviour. If Owants to predict how N is going to act he mustfamiliarize himself with the concepts in terms of whichN is viewing the situation; having done this he may,from his knowledge of N’s character, be able to predictwith great confidence what decision N is going to take.But the notions which O uses to make his predictionare nonetheless compatible with N’s taking a differentdecision from that predicted for him. If this happens itdoes not necessarily follow that O has made a mistakein his calculations; for the whole point about a decisionis that a given set of ‘calculations’ may lead to any oneof a set of different outcomes. This is quite differentfrom predictions in the natural sciences, where afalsified prediction always implies some sort of

Page 109: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

92 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

mistake on the part of the predictor: false or inadequatedata, faulty calculation, or defective theory.

The following may make that clearer. To understandthe nature of the decision confronting N, O must beaware of the rules which provide the criteria specifyingfor N the relevant features of his situation. If oneknows the rule which someone is following one can, ina large number of cases, predict what he will do ingiven circumstances. For instance, if O knows that N isfollowing the rule: ‘Start with 0 and add 2 till youreach 1,000’, he can predict that, having written down104, N will next write 106. But sometimes even if Oknows with certainty the rule which N is following, hecannot predict with any certainty what N will do:where, namely, the question arises of what is involvedin following that rule, e.g. in circumstances markedlydifferent from any in which it has previously beenapplied. The rule here does not specify any determinateoutcome to the situation, though it does limit the rangeof possible alternatives; it is made determinate for thefuture by the choice of one of these alternatives and therejection of the others—until such time as it againbecomes necessary to interpret the rule in the light ofyet new conditions.

This may throw some light on what is involved inthe idea of a developing historical tradition. As Iremarked earlier, Mill thought of historical trends asanalogous to scientific laws and Popper wished tomodify that conception by pointing out that thestatement of a trend, unlike that of a true law, involvesa reference to a set of specific initial conditions. I nowwant to make a further modification: even given aspecific set of initial conditions, one will still not be

Page 110: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

93SOCIAL STUDIES AS SCIENCE

able to predict any determinate outcome to a historicaltrend because the continuation or breaking off of thattrend involves human decisions which are notdetermined by their antecedent conditions in thecontext of which the sense of calling them ‘decisions’lies.

Two words of caution are necessary in connectionwith my last remark. I am not denying that it issometimes possible to predict decisions; only that theirrelation to the evidence on which they are based isunlike that characteristic of scientific predictions. AndI am not falling into the trap of saying that historicaltrends are consciously willed and intended by theirparticipants; the point is that such trends are in part theoutcome of intentions and decisions of theirparticipants.

The development of a historical tradition mayinvolve deliberation, argument, the canvassing of rivalinterpretations, followed perhaps by the adoption ofsome agreed compromise or the springing up of rivalschools. Consider, for instance, the relation betweenthe music of Haydn, Mozart and Beethoven; or therival schools of political thought which all claim, withsome show of reason, to be based on the Marxisttradition. Think of the interplay between orthodoxyand heresy in the development of religion; or of theway in which the game of football was revolutionizedby the Rugby boy who picked up the ball and ran. Itwould certainly not have been possible to predict thatrevolution from knowledge of the preceding state ofthe game any more than it would have been possible topredict the philosophy of Hume from the philosophiesof his predecessors. It may help here to recall

Page 111: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

94 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

Humphrey Lyttleton’s rejoinder to someone who askedhim where Jazz was going: ‘If I knew where Jazz wasgoing I’d be there already’.

Maurice Cranston makes essentially the same pointwhen he notices that to predict the writing of a piece ofpoetry or the making of a new invention would involvewriting the poem or making the invention oneself. Andif one has already done this oneself then it isimpossible to predict that someone else will make upthat poem or discover that invention. ‘He could notpredict it because he could not say it was going tohappen before it happened.’ (8: p. 166.)

It would be a mistake, though tempting, to regardthis as a piece of trivial logic-chopping. One appears tobe attempting an impossible task of a priori legislationagainst a purely empirical possibility. What in fact oneis showing, however, is that the central concepts whichbelong to our understanding of social life areincompatible with concepts central to the activity ofscientific prediction. When we speak of the possibilityof scientific prediction of social developments of thissort, we literally do not understand what we are saying.We cannot understand it, because it has no sense.

Page 112: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

95

CHAPTER FOUR

THE MIND AND SOCIETY

1. Pareto: Logical and Non-Logical Conduct

WHAT I tried to show in Chapter III was that theconceptions according to which we normally

think of social events are logically incompatible withthe concepts belonging to scientific explanation. Animportant part of the argument was that the formerconceptions enter into social life itself and not merelyinto the observer’s description of it. But there is apowerful stream of thought which maintains that theideas of participants must be discounted as more likelythan not to be misguided and confusing. To this streambelongs, for instance, the quotation from Durkheim atthe end of Chapter I. I propose now to examine theattempt made by Vilfredo Pareto, in The Mind andSociety, a title in which Pareto’s translator has mostadmirably caught his main preoccupation, to showempirically that the ideas which people have, inbehaving as they do, influence the nature and outcomeof their behaviour far less fundamentally than isusually thought; and that, therefore, the sociologistmust develop his own concepts de novo and pay aslittle attention as possible to the ideas of participants.My examination is designed to bring out two mainpoints: first that Pareto mistakes what is essentially a

Page 113: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

96 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

philosophical issue for an empirical, scientific, one;second, that the conclusion of his argument is in factfalse.

Pareto starts by considering what is involved in ascientific approach to sociology. His answer is,roughly, that it consists in using only concepts whichhave a strictly empirical reference, in subjecting one’stheories always rigorously to the control ofobservation and experiment, and in ensuring thatone’s inferences always follow strict logic. This hecalls the ‘logico-experimental’ approach. Thesociologist’s data are the actions of human beingsliving together, and from these Pareto singles out, asrequiring special attention, that behaviour whichexpresses an intellectual content.

Current in any given group of people are a number ofpropositions, descriptive, preceptive or otherwise…Such propositions, combined by logical or pseudological nexuses and amplified with factual narrations ofvarious sorts, constitute theories, theologies,cosmogonies, systems of metaphysics, and so on.Viewed from the outside without regard to any intrinsicmerit with which they may be credited by faith, allsuch propositions and theories are experimental facts,and as experimental facts we are here obliged toconsider and examine them. (23: Section 7.)

We are here concerned with Pareto’s views on how thepropositions and theories which people embrace arerelated to their other behaviour. How, for instance, arethe propositions of Christian theology related to thepractice of Christian rites? Now Pareto rightly pointsout that this question is ambiguous. It may mean: Dothese theories really constitute good reasons for the

Page 114: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

97THE MIND AND SOCIETY

actions they purport to justify? Or it may mean: Ispeople’s behaviour really governed by the ideas theyembrace in the way they would claim, or would they goon behaving like that even if they ceased to embracesuch ideas? Pareto conceives it to be the function of ascientific ‘logico-experimental’ sociology to answerboth these questions; for this purpose he introducestwo important distinctions: (i) that between logical andnon-logical action; (ii) that between residues andderivations.

(i) is designed to throw light on the question how farthe theories people embrace really constitute goodreasons for the actions they perform.

There are actions that use means appropriate to endsand which logically link means with ends. There areother actions in which those traits are missing. The twosorts of conduct are very different according as they areconsidered under their objective or their subjectiveaspect. From the subjective point of view nearly allhuman actions belong to the logical class. In the eyesof the Greek mariner sacrifices to Poseidon and rowingwith oars were equally logical means ofnavigation…Suppose we apply the term logical actionsto actions that logically conjoin means to ends not onlyfrom the standpoint of the subject performing them, butfrom the standpoint of other persons who have a moreextensive knowledge—in other words, to actions thatare logical both subjectively and objectively in thesense just explained. Other actions we shall call non-logical (by no means the same as ‘illogical’). (23:Section 150.)

A logical action then is one that fulfils the followingconditions: (a) it is thought of by the agent as havinga result and is performed by ‘him for the purpose of

Page 115: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

98 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

achieving that result; (b) it actually does tend to havethe result which the agent envisages; (c) the agent has(what Pareto would regard as) good (i.e. ‘logico-cxperimental’) grounds for his belief; (d) the endsought must be one that is empirically identifiable.The diversity of these criteria means that an actioncan also be non-logical in a variety of different ways,of which the following are among the most important.It may be non-logical because the agent does notthink to achieve any end by it at all; this seems tocorrespond to what Max Weber meant by actions thatare wertrational as opposed to zweckrational. ButPareto thinks these are few and far between because,he says, ‘human beings have a very conspicuoustendency to paint a varnish of logic over theirconduct’ (Section 154). (It is interesting andimportant that he is unable to conceive of any way inwhich an action may have even the appearance ofbeing logical except in terms of the category of meansand ends.) Again, an action may be non-logicalbecause, although the agent performs it for the sakeof an end, it either achieves some quite different endor none at all. This may be because, as Pareto puts it,the end envisaged is not in fact a real one at all but is‘imaginary’, because ‘located outside the field ofobservation and experience’ (Section 151): he severaltimes mentions the salvation of the soul as anexample of an ‘imaginary’ end of this sort. Or it maybe because, although the end envisaged is a perfectlyreal one, it is not gained in the way the agent thinks itis: to this class Pareto assigns both operations inmagic (Section 160) and also ‘certain measures (forexample, wage-cutting) of business men

Page 116: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

99THE MIND AND SOCIETY

(entrepreneurs) working under conditions of freecompetition’ (Section 159).

Now the inclusion of all these different types ofaction (and many more besides) within a singlecategory is obviously going to give rise to seriousdifficulties. I should like here to concentrate on onesuch difficulty: that of making any clear distinctionbetween ‘non-logical’ and ‘illogical’ conduct. In theabove quotation from Section 150 of The Mind andSociety we saw that Pareto maintained that these are‘by no means the same’; and he is making the samepoint when he writes, much later, that ‘a mistake inengineering is not a non-logical action’ (Section 327).Nevertheless, Pareto holds that the mistake of anentrepreneur under free competition, who thinks thatby cutting his employees’ wages he will increase hisown profits is a non-logical action. How does a mistakein engineering differ relevantly from that of theentrepreneur (whose idea, Pareto says, may no longerbe a mistake in conditions of monopoly)? And is theentrepreneur’s mistake really comparable at all to theperformance of a magical rite? Surely it ought rather tobe compared to a mistake in a magical rite. Theentrepreneur’s mistake is a particular act (of whichthere may, nevertheless, be a great many similarexamples) within the category of business behaviour;but magical operations themselves constitute acategory of behaviour. Magic, in a society in which itoccurs, plays a peculiar role of its own and isconducted according to considerations of its own. Thesame is true of business activity; but it is not true ofthe kind of misguided business activity to which Paretorefers, for that can only be understood by reference to

Page 117: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

100 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

the aims and nature of business activity in general. Onthe other hand, to try to understand magic by referenceto the aims and nature of scientific activity, as Paretodoes, will necessarily be to misunderstand it.

The distinction between a general category ofaction—a mode of social life—and a particular sort ofact falling within such a category, is of centralimportance to the distinction between non-logical andillogical behaviour. An illogical act presumablyinvolves a mistake in logic; but to call something non-logical should be to deny that criteria of logic apply toit at all. That is, it does not make sense to say of non-logical conduct that it is either logical or illogical, justas it does not make sense to say of something non-spatial (such as virtue) that it is either big or small. ButPareto does not follow through the implications of this.For instance, he tries to use the term ‘non-logical’ in alogically pejorative sense, which is like concludingfrom the fact that virtue is not big that it must be small.A large part of the trouble here arises from the fact thathe has not seen the point around which the mainargument of this monograph revolves: that criteria oflogic are not a direct gift of God, but arise out of, andare only intelligible in the context of, ways of living ormodes of social life. It follows that one cannot applycriteria of logic to modes of social life as such. Forinstance, science is one such mode and religion isanother; and each has criteria of intelligibility peculiarto itself. So within science or religion actions can belogical or illogical: in science, for example, it would beillogical to refuse to be bound by the results of aproperly carried out experiment; in religion it would beillogical to suppose that one could pit one’s own

Page 118: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

101THE MIND AND SOCIETY

strength against God’s; and so on. But we cannotsensibly say that either the practice of science itself orthat of religion is either illogical or logical; both arenon-logical. (This is, of course, an over-simplification,in that it does not allow for the overlapping characterof different modes of social life. Somebody might, forinstance, have religious reasons for devoting his life toscience. But I do not think that this affects thesubstance of what I want to say, though it would makeits precise expression in detail more complicated.) Nowwhat Pareto tries to say is that science itself is a formof logical behaviour (in fact the form par excellence ofsuch behaviour), whereas religion is non-logical (in alogically pejorative sense). And this, as I have tried toshow, is not permissible.

There is a still deeper source for Pareto’s failure todistinguish adequately between ‘non-logical’ and‘illogical’; it is connected with his belief that theappropriate way to produce a completely impartial,uncommitted theory of the workings of humansocieties is to be governed solely by ‘logico-experimental’ criteria, which he conceives on theanalogy of what he takes to be the practice of thenatural sciences. From this point of view he is clearlyquite justified in evaluating rival theories about socialexistence (i.e. alternative sociological theories) byreference to those criteria. But he is constantly tryingto do more than this: to evaluate by reference to thesame criteria the ideas and theories which belong tothe subject-matter he is studying. But this involveshim in a fundamental confusion: that of taking sidesin just the sort of way which the application of thelogico-experimental technique was supposed to

Page 119: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

102 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

preclude. The embarrassment in which he is thusplaced illustrates what I wanted to emphasize inmaintaining that the type of problem with which he ishere concerned belongs more properly to philosophythan it does to science. This has to do with thepeculiar sense in which philosophy is uncommittedenquiry. I noted in the first chapter how philosophy isconcerned with elucidating and comparing the waysin which the world is made intelligible in differentintellectual disciplines; and how this leads on to theelucidation and comparison of different forms of life.The uncommittedness of philosophy comes out herein the fact that it is equally concerned to elucidate itsown account of things; the concern of philosophywith its own being is thus not an unhealthyNarcissistic aberration, but an essential part of what itis trying to do. In performing this task thephilosopher will in particular be alert to deflate thepretensions of any form of enquiry to enshrine theessence of intelligibility as such, to possess the key toreality. For connected with the realization thatintelligibility takes many and varied forms is therealization that reality has no key. But Pareto iscommitting just this mistake: his way of discussingthe distinction between logical and non-logicalconduct involves setting up scientific intelligibility(or rather, his own misconception of it) as the normfor intelligibility in general; he is claiming thatscience possesses the key to reality.

Science, unlike philosophy, is wrapped up in its ownway of making things intelligible to the exclusion of allothers. Or rather it applies its criteria unself-consciously; for to be self-conscious about such

Page 120: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

103THE MIND AND SOCIETY

matters is to be philosophical. This non-philosophicalunself-consciousness is for the most part right andproper in the investigation of nature (except at suchcritical times as that gone through by Einstein prior tothe formulation of the Special Theory of Relativity);but it is disastrous in the investigation of a humansociety, whose very nature is to consist in different andcompeting ways of life, each offering a differentaccount of the intelligibility of things. To take anuncommitted view of such competing conceptions ispeculiarly the task of philosophy; it is not its businessto award prizes to science, religion, or anything else. Itis not its business to advocate any Weltanschauung (inthe way Pareto offers, inconsistently, a pseudo-scientific Weltanschauung). In Wittgenstein’s words,‘Philosophy leaves everything as it was’.

In this connection it is worth while to recallCollingwood’s allegation that some accounts ofmagical practices in primitive societies offered by‘scientific’ anthropologists often mask ‘a half-conscious conspiracy to bring into ridicule andcontempt civilizations different from our own’. (7:Book I, Chapter IV.) A classic example of this corruptuse of ‘scientific objectivity’ is to be found inR.S.Lynd’s Knowledge for What? (15: p. 121, footnote7.) The philosophical confusions in Lynd’s argumentshould be evident to anyone who has followed theargument of this monograph.

2. Pareto: Residues and Derivations

To develop this point further I now turn to the secondof Pareto’s distinctions: between residues and

Page 121: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

104 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

derivations. This distinction is supposed to performtwo functions. In the first place it is supposed toprovide recurring features in our observation ofhuman societies, which will be a suitable subject forscientific generalization. Pareto argues that if onelooks at a wide variety of different societies atdifferent historical periods, one is struck by the factthat whereas certain kinds of conduct occur again andagain with very little variation, other kinds are veryunstable, changing constantly with time and differingconsiderably from one society to another. He calls theconstant, recurring element ‘residues’; they are whatremains when the changeable features are left out ofaccount. The variable elements are ‘derivations’, aterm which refers to a fact about such kinds ofconduct which Pareto claims to have discoveredempirically: namely, that the main occupants of thiscategory are the theories in terms of which people tryto explain why they behave as they do. The derivation‘represents the work of the mind in accounting for[the residue]. That is why [it] is much more variable,as reflecting the play of the imagination’. (23: Section850.) Because the derivations are so unstable andvariable in comparison with the residues, Paretourges, we must accept that the ideas and theorieswhich people embrace have little real influence on theway they otherwise behave; embracing the theoriescannot be a valid explanation of why people act in thegiven way, for that behaviour goes on even after thetheories have been abandoned. The concept of aderivation obviously offers many points ofcomparison with, for example, the Marxian concept ofan ‘ideology’ and the Freudian concept of a

Page 122: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

105THE MIND AND SOCIETY

‘rationalization’. The point I should like to emphasizehere, however, is that it is only by way of thisconceptual distinction that Pareto succeeds in findingcommon features of different societies of a sort whichappear suitable as a subject for scientificgeneralization. That is, the claim that there aresociological uniformities goes hand in hand with theclaim that human intelligence is much overrated as areal influence on social events.

I shall now quote an example of Pareto’s detailedapplication of the distinction.

Christians have the custom of baptism. If one knew theChristian procedure only one would not know whetherand how it could be analysed. Moreover, we have anexplanation of it: we are told that the rite of baptism iscelebrated in order to remove original sin. That still isnot enough. If we had no other facts of the same classto go by, we should find it difficult to isolate theelements in the complex phenomenon of baptism. Butwe do have other facts of that type. The pagans too hadlustral water, and they used it for purposes ofpurification. If we stopped at that we might associatethe idea of water with the fact of purification. But othercases of baptism show that the use of water is not aconstant element. Blood may be used for purification,and other substances as well. Nor is that all; there arenumbers of rites that effect the same result… The givencase, therefore, is made up of that constant element, a,and a variable element, b, the latter comprising themeans that are used for restoring the individual’sintegrity and the reasonings by which the efficacy ofthe means is presumably explained. The human beinghas a vague feeling that water somehow cleanses moralas well as material pollution. However, he does not, asa rule, justify his conduct in that manner. Theexplanation would be far too simple. So he goes

Page 123: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

106 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

looking for something more complicated, morepretentious, and readily finds what he is looking for.(23: Section 863.)

Now there are well-known philosophical difficultieswhich arise from the attempt to reject as nugatorywhole classes of reasonings as opposed to particularappeals to that kind of reasoning within an acceptedclass. Consider, for instance, the often discusseddifficulties involved in casting general doubt on thereliability of the senses, or of memory. But Paretowould no doubt maintain that his thesis is saved fromthis kind of vacuity by the mass of empirical evidenceon which it rests. However, his thesis concerning therelative variability of derivations and constancy ofresidues is not, as he thinks, a straightforward report ofthe results of observation; it involves a conceptualmisinterpretation of those results. The constantelement, a, and the variable element, b, are notdistinguished by observation but only as the result ofan (illegitimate) abstraction. In the example quoted ofthe purification residues, the unvarying element is notjust a straightforward set of physical movements for itmay take a multitude of different physical forms (asPareto himself is at pains to point out). The mere act ofwashing one’s hands would not be an instance of it; itwould become one only if performed with symbolicintent, as a sign of moral or religious purification. Thispoint is so important that I will illustrate it withanother example, the ‘sex residues’. Pareto does not, asmight be expected, mean to refer to the common factorof simple biological sexual intercourse which is foundamidst all the multifarious social customs and moral

Page 124: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

107THE MIND AND SOCIETY

ideas connected with sexual relations at different timesand in different societies. He explicitly rules this out.To qualify as a residue a form of behaviour must havea quasi-intellectual, or symbolic content. ‘Mere sexualappetite, though powerfully active in the human race,is no concern of ours here…We are interested in it onlyin so far as it influences theories, modes of thinking’.(23: Section 1,324.) For example, one dominantresidue which Pareto discusses is the ascetic attitude tosexual relations: the idea that they are to be avoided assomething evil or at least morally debilitating. But thisconstant factor, as in the previous example, is notsomething that Pareto has observed separately from thehighly various moral and theological systems of ideasin terms of which sexual ascetism is justified orexplained in different societies. It is something that hehas analysed out of those systems of ideas by means ofa conceptual analysis.

But ideas cannot be torn out of their context in thatway; the relation between idea and context is aninternal one. The idea gets its sense from the role itplays in the system. It is nonsensical to take severalsystems of ideas, find an element in each which can beexpressed in the same verbal form, and then claim tohave discovered an idea which is common to all thesystems. This would be like observing that both theAristotelian and Galilean systems of mechanics use anotion of force, and concluding that they thereforemake use of the same notion. One can imagine thehowl of rage which Pareto would send up at thephilistinism of such a proceeding; but he is guilty ofexactly the same kind of philistinism when, forinstance, he compares the social relation between ‘an

Page 125: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

108 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

American millionaire and a plain American’ to thatbetween an Indian of high caste and one of low caste.(See Section 1,044.) And this sort of comparison isessential to his whole method of procedure.

The same point may be expressed as follows. Twothings may be called ‘the same’ or ‘different’ onlywith reference to a set of criteria which lay downwhat is to be regarded as a relevant difference. Whenthe ‘things’ in question are purely physical thecriteria appealed to will of course be those of theobserver. But when one is dealing with intellectual(or, indeed, any kind of social) ‘things’, that is not so.For their being intellectual or social, as opposed tophysical, in character depends entirely on theirbelonging in a certain way to a system of ideas ormode of living. It is only by reference to the criteriagoverning that system of ideas or mode of life thatthey have any existence as intellectual or socialevents. It follows that if the sociological investigatorwants to regard them as social events (as, exhypothesi, he must), he has to take seriously thecriteria which are applied for distinguishing‘different’ kinds of actions and identifying the ‘same’kinds of actions within the way of life he is studying.It is not open to him arbitrarily to impose his ownstandards from without. In so far as he does so, theevents he is studying lose altogether their character associal events. A Christian would strenuously denythat the baptism rites of his faith were really the samein character as the acts of a pagan sprinkling lustralwater or letting sacrificial blood. Pareto, inmaintaining the contrary, is inadvertently removingfrom his subject-matter precisely that which gives

Page 126: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

109THE MIND AND SOCIETY

them sociological interest: namely their internalconnection with a way of living.

Miss G.E.M.Anscombe has remarked, in anunpublished paper, how there are certain activities—she mentions arithmetic as an example—which, unlikeother activities, such as acrobatics, cannot beunderstood by an observer unless he himself possessesthe ability to perform the activities in question. Shenotes that any description of activities like arithmeticwhich is not based on arithmetical (or whatever)capacities is bound to seem pointless and arbitrary, andalso compulsive in the sense that the steps no longerappear as meaningful choices. This is precisely theimpression of social activities which is given byPareto’s account of them as residues; but theimpression is not a well-founded one, it is an opticalillusion based on a conceptual misunderstanding.

This shows, I think, that the whole presupposition ofPareto’s procedure is absurd: namely that it is possibleto treat propositions and theories as ‘experimentalfacts’ on a par with any other kind of such fact. (See23: Section 7.) It is a presupposition which is certainlynot peculiar to him: it is contained, for instance, inEmile Durkheim’s first rule of sociological method: ‘toconsider social facts as things’. Pareto’s statement, andthe others like it, are absurd because they involve acontradiction: in so far as a set of phenomena is beinglooked at ‘from the outside’, ‘as experimental facts’, itcannot at the same time be described as constituting a‘theory’ or set of ‘propositions’. In a sense Pareto hasnot carried his empiricism far enough. For what thesociological observer has presented to his senses is notat all people holding certain theories, believing in

Page 127: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

110 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

certain propositions, but people making certainmovements and sounds. Indeed, even describing themas ‘people’ really goes too far, which may explain thepopularity of the sociological and social psychologicaljargon word ‘organism’: but organisms, as opposed topeople, do not believe propositions or embracetheories. To describe what is observed by thesociologist in terms of notions like ‘proposition’ and‘theory’ is already to have taken the decision to applya set of concepts incompatible with the ‘external’,‘experimental’ point of view. To refuse to describewhat is observed in such terms, on the other hand,involves not treating it as having social significance. Itfollows that the understanding of society cannot beobservational and experimental in one widely acceptedsense.

What I am saying needs qualification. I do notmean, of course, that it is impossible to take as a datumthat a certain person, or group of people, holds acertain belief—say that the earth is flat—withoutsubscribing to it oneself. And this is all Pareto thinkshe is doing; but actually he is doing more than this. Heis not just speaking of particular beliefs within a givenmode of discourse, but of whole modes of discourse.What he misses is that a mode of discourse has to beunderstood before anyone can speak of theories andpropositions within it which could constitute data forhim. He does not really consider the fundamentalproblem of what it is to understand a mode ofdiscourse. In so far as he thinks anything about it heregards it as simply a matter of establishinggeneralizations on the basis of observation; a viewwhich was disposed of in Chapter III.

Page 128: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

111THE MIND AND SOCIETY

There is, unfortunately, no space available to discussfurther examples of attempts, like Pareto’s, to eliminatehuman ideas and intelligence from the sociologist’saccount of social life. But readers may find itinstructive to re-read Durkheim’s Suicide in the light ofwhat I have been saying. It is particularly important tonotice the connection between Durkheim’sconclusion—that conscious deliberations may betreated as ‘purely formal, with no object butconfirmation of a resolve previously formed forreasons unknown to consciousness’, and his initialdecision to define the word ‘suicide’ for the purposesof his study in a sense different from that which it borewithin the societies which he was studying. (9.)

3. Max Weber: Verstehen and Causal Explanation

It is Max Weber who has said most about the peculiarsense which the word ‘understand’ bears when appliedto modes of social life. I have already referred to hisaccount of meaningful behaviour and propose in thenext two sections to say something about hisconception of sociological understanding (Verstehen).(See 33: Chapter 1.) The first issue on which I mean toconcentrate is Weber’s account of the relation betweenacquiring an ‘interpretative understanding’ (deutendverstehen) of the meaning (Sinn) of a piece ofbehaviour and providing a causal explanation (kausalerklären) of what brought the behaviour in questionabout and what its consequences are.

Now Weber never gives a clear account of thelogical character of interpretative understanding. Hespeaks of it much of the time as if it were simply a

Page 129: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

112 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

psychological technique: a matter of putting oneself inthe other fellow’s position. This has led many writersto allege that Weber confuses what is simply atechnique for framing hypotheses with the logicalcharacter of the evidence for such hypotheses. ThusPopper argues that although we may use ourknowledge of our own mental processes in order toframe hypotheses about the similar processes of otherpeople, ‘these hypotheses must be tested, they must besubmitted to the method of selection by elimination.(By their intuition, some people are prevented fromeven imagining that anybody can possibly dislikechocolate).’ (26: Section 29.)

Nevertheless, however applicable such criticismsmay be to Weber’s vulgarizers, they cannot justly beused against his own views, for he is very insistent thatmere ‘intuition’ is not enough and must be tested bycareful observation. However, what I think can be saidagainst Weber is that he gives a wrong account of theprocess of checking the validity of suggestedsociological interpretations. But the correction ofWeber takes us farther away from, rather than closer to,the account which Popper, Ginsberg, and the many whothink like them, would like to substitute.

Weber says:

Every interpretation aims at self-evidence or immediateplausibility (Evidenz). But an interpretation whichmakes the meaning of a piece of behaviour as self-evidently obvious as you like cannot claim just on thataccount to be the causally valid interpretation as well.In itself it is nothing more than a particularly plausiblehypothesis. (33: Chapter I.)

Page 130: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

113THE MIND AND SOCIETY

He goes on to say that the appropriate way to verifysuch an hypothesis is to establish statistical laws basedon observation of what happens. In this way he arrivesat the conception of a sociological law as ‘a statisticalregularity which corresponds to an intelligible intendedmeaning’.

Weber is clearly right in pointing out that theobvious interpretation need not be the right one.R.S.Lynd’s interpretation of West Indian voodoomagic as ‘a system of imputedly true and reliablecausal sequences’ is a case in point (15: p. 121); andthere is a plethora of similar examples in Frazer’s TheGolden Bough . But I want to question Weber’simplied suggestion that Verstehen is something whichis logically incomplete and needs supplementing by adifferent method altogether, namely the collection ofstatistics. Against this, I want to insist that if aproffered interpretation is wrong, statistics, thoughthey may suggest that that is so, are not the decisiveand ultimate court of appeal for the validity ofsociological interpretations in the way Webersuggests. What is then needed is a betterinterpretation, not something different in kind. Thecompatibility of an interpretation with the statisticsdoes not prove its validity. Someone who interprets atribe’s magical rites as a form of misplaced scientificactivity will not be corrected by statistics about whatmembers of that tribe are likely to do on variouskinds of occasion (though this might form part of theargument); what is ultimately required is aphilosophical argument like, e.g., Collingwood’s inThe Principles of Art. (6: Book 1, Chapter IV.) For amistaken interpretation of a form of social activity is

Page 131: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

114 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

closely akin to the type of mistake dealt with inphilosophy.

Wittgenstein says somewhere that when we get intophilosophical difficulties over the use of some of theconcepts of our language, we are like savagesconfronted with something from an alien culture. I amsimply indicating a corollary of this: that sociologistswho misinterpret an alien culture are likephilosophers getting into difficulties over the use oftheir own concepts. There will be differences ofcourse. The philosopher’s difficulty is usually withsomething with which he is perfectly familiar butwhich he is for the moment failing to see in its properperspective. The sociologist’s difficulty will often beover something with which he is not at all familiar; hemay have no suitable perspective to apply. This maysometimes make his task more difficult than thephilosopher’s, and it may also sometimes make iteasier. But the analogy between their problems shouldbe plain.

Some of Wittgenstein’s procedures in hisphilosophical elucidations reinforce this point. He isprone to draw our attention to certain features of ourown concepts by comparing them with those of animaginary society, in which our own familiar ways ofthinking are subtly distorted. For instance, he asks usto suppose that such a society sold wood in thefollowing way: They ‘piled the timber in heaps ofarbitrary, varying height and then sold it at a priceproportionate to the area covered by the piles. Andwhat if they even justified this with the words: “Ofcourse, if you buy more timber, you must pay more”?’(38: Chapter I, p. 142–151.) The important question

Page 132: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

115THE MIND AND SOCIETY

for us is: in what circumstances could one say thatone had understood this sort of behaviour? As I haveindicated, Weber often speaks as if the ultimate testwere our ability to formulate statistical laws whichwould enable us to predict with fair accuracy whatpeople would be likely to do in given circumstances.In line with this is his attempt to define a ‘social role’in terms of the probability (Chance) of actions of acertain sort being performed in given circumstances.But with Wittgenstein’s example we might well beable to make predictions of great accuracy in this wayand still not be able to claim any real understandingof what those people were doing. The difference isprecisely analogous to that between being able toformulate statistical laws about the likely occurrencesof words in a language and being able to understandwhat was being said by someone who spoke thelanguage. The latter can never be reduced to theformer; a man who understands Chinese is not a manwho has a firm grasp of the statistical probabilities forthe occurrence of the various words in the Chineselanguage. Indeed, he could have that without knowingthat he was dealing with a language at all; andanyway, the knowledge that he was dealing with alanguage is not itself something that could beformulated statistically. ‘Understanding’, in situationslike this, is grasping the point or meaning of what isbeing done or said. This is a notion far removed fromthe world of statistics and causal laws: it is closer tothe realm of discourse and to the internal relationsthat link the parts of a realm of discourse. The notionof meaning should be carefully distinguished fromthat of function, in its quasi-causal sense, the use of

Page 133: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

116 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

which in social anthropology and sociology I shall notexplore further here.

4. Max Weber: Meaningful Action and Social Action

I can best bring out the implications of this byconsidering another aspect of Weber’s view: hisdistinction between behaviour which is merelymeaningful and that which is both meaningful andsocial. Now it is evident that any such distinction isincompatible with the argument of Chapter II of thisbook; all meaningful behaviour must be social, sinceit can be meaningful only if governed by rules, andrules presuppose a social setting. Weber clearlyrecognizes the importance of this issue for sociologyeven though he comes down on what I must regard asthe wrong side. What is interesting is that in so doinghe at the same time begins to write of social situationsin a way which is quite incompatible with what he hassaid about Verstehen; this is just what one wouldexpect in so far as Verstehen implies Sinn and Sinn, asI have argued, implies socially established rules. I amthinking here of the important paper: R.Stammlers“Ueberwindung” dermaterialistischenGeschichtsauffassung (34), where he connectstogether the following pair of assertions: first, thatthere is no logical difficulty in supposing a man to becapable of following rules of conduct in completeabstraction from any sort of social context; second,that there is no logical difference between thetechnique of manipulating natural objects (e.g.machinery) in order to achieve one’s ends and that of

Page 134: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

117THE MIND AND SOCIETY

‘manipulating’ human beings as, he suggests, does theowner of a factory his employees. He says: ‘that inthe one case “events of consciousness” enter into thecausal chain and in the other case not, makes“logically” not the slightest difference’; thuscommitting the mistake of supposing that ‘events ofconsciousness’ just happen to differ empirically fromother kinds of event. He does not realize that thewhole notion of an ‘event’ carries a different sensehere, implying as it does a context of humanlyfollowed rules which cannot be combined with acontext of causal laws in this way without creatinglogical difficulties. Weber thus fails in his attempt toinfer that the kind of ‘law’ which the sociologist mayformulate to account for the behaviour of humanbeings is logically no different from a ‘law’ in naturalscience.

In trying to describe the situation he is using as ‘anexample in such a way as to support his point of view,Weber ceases to use the notions that would beappropriate to an interpretative understanding of thesituation. Instead of speaking of the workers in hisfactory being paid and spending money, he speaks oftheir being handed pieces of metal, handing thosepieces of metal to other people and receiving otherobjects from them; he does not speak of policemenprotecting the workers’ property, but of ‘people withhelmets’ coming and giving back the workers thepieces of metal which other people have taken fromthem; and so on. In short, he adopts the external pointof view and forgets to take account of the ‘subjectivelyintended sense’ of the behaviour he is talking about:and this, I want to say, is a natural result of his attempt

Page 135: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

118 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

to divorce the social relations linking those workersfrom the ideas which their actions embody: ideas suchas those of ‘money’, ‘property’, ‘police’, ‘buying andselling’, and so on. Their relations to each other existonly through those ideas and similarly those ideas existonly in their relations to each other.

I am not denying that it may sometimes be useful toadopt devices like Weber’s ‘externalization’ of hisdescription of this situation. It may serve the purposeof drawing the reader’s attention to aspects of thesituation which are so obvious and familiar that hewould otherwise miss them, in which case it iscomparable to Wittgenstein’s use of imaginaryoutlandish examples, to which I have already referred.Again, it may be compared with the Verfremdungseffektwhich Berthold Brecht aimed at in his theatricalproductions, or to Caradog Evans’ use of outlandishlyliteral translations from the Welsh in his sinisterlysatirical stories about West Wales.1 The effect of allthese devices is to shake the reader or spectator out ofthe complacent myopia which over-familiarity mayinduce. What is dangerous is that the user of thesedevices should come to think of his way of looking atthings as somehow more real than the usual way. Onesuspects that Brecht may sometimes have adopted thisGod-like attitude (as would be consistent with hisMarxism); it is certainly involved in Pareto’s treatmentof ‘residues’; and although it is an attitude which is onthe whole very uncharacteristic of Weber, it neverthelessfollows very naturally from his methodological accountof the way in which social relations and 1 This last example was suggested to me by conversations with my

colleague, Mr. D.L.Sims.

Page 136: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

119THE MIND AND SOCIETY

human ideas are related and from any attempt tocompare sociological theories with those of naturalscience. The only legitimate use of such aVerfremdungseffekt is to draw attention to the familiarand obvious, not to show that it is dispensable fromour understanding.

Moreover, if this mistake in Weber’s account iscorrected, it becomes much easier to defend hisconception of Verstehen from a persistently reiteratedcriticism. Morris Ginsberg, for instance, writes:

It appears to be a basic assumption of verstehendeSoziologie and verstehende Psychologie that what weknow within our minds is somehow more intelligiblethan what is outwardly observed. But this is to confusethe familiar with the intelligible. There is no innersense establishing connexions between inner facts bydirect intuition. Such connexions are in fact empiricalgeneralizations, of no greater validity than the similargeneralizations relating to outward facts. (11: p. 155.)

It must be said very firmly here that the case for sayingthat the understanding of society is logically differentfrom the understanding of nature does not rest on thehypothesis of an ‘inner sense’ (a notion trenchantlycriticized by Peter Geach.—10: Section 24.) In fact itfollows from my argument in Chapter II that theconcepts in terms of which we understand our ownmental processes and behaviour have to be learned, andmust, therefore, be socially established, just as much asthe concepts in terms of which we come to understandthe behaviour of other people. Thus Ginsberg’s remarkthat the disgust induced by certain foods in someonewho is subject to a taboo ‘is not directly intelligible to

Page 137: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

120 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

anyone brought up in a different tradition’, so far frombeing a valid criticism of the sort of view which I havetried to present of Verstehen, follows immediately fromthat view. I have already dealt, in Chapter III, with theidea that the connections embodied in our concepts ofhuman behaviour are just the result of empiricalgeneralizations.

Page 138: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

121

CHAPTER FIVE

CONCEPTS AND ACTIONS

1. The Internality of Social Relations

TO illustrate what is meant by saying that the socialrelations between men and the ideas which men’s

actions embody are really the same thing consideredfrom different points of view, I want now to considerthe general nature of what happens when the ideascurrent in a society change: when new ideas come intothe language and old ideas go out of it. In speaking of‘new ideas’ I shall make a distinction. Imagine abiochemist making certain observations andexperiments as a result of which he discovers a newgerm which is responsible for a certain disease. In onesense we might say that the name he gives to this newgerm expresses a new idea, but I prefer to say in thiscontext that he has made a discovery within theexisting framework of ideas. I am assuming that thegerm theory of disease is already well established inthe scientific language he speaks. Now compare withthis discovery the impact made by the first formulationof that theory, the first introduction of the concept of agerm into the language of medicine. This was a muchmore radically new departure, involving not merely anew factual discovery within an existing way oflooking at things, but a completely new way of looking

Page 139: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

122 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

at the whole problem of the causation of diseases, theadoption of new diagnostic techniques, the asking ofnew kinds of question about illnesses, and so on. Inshort it involved the adoption of new ways of doingthings by people involved, in one way or another, inmedical practice. An account of the way in whichsocial relations in the medical profession had beeninfluenced by this new concept would include anaccount of what that concept was. Conversely, theconcept itself is unintelligible apart from its relation tomedical practice. A doctor who (i) claimed to acceptthe germ theory of disease, (ii) claimed to aim atreducing the incidence of disease, and (iii) completelyignored the necessity for isolating infectious patients,would be behaving in a self-contradictory andunintelligible manner.

Again, imagine a society which has no concept ofproper names, as we know them. People are known bygeneral descriptive phrases, say, or by numbers. Thiswould carry with it a great many other differences fromour own social life as well. The whole structure ofpersonal relationships would be affected. Consider theimportance of numbers in prison or military life.Imagine how different it would be to fall in love with agirl known only by a number rather than by a name;and what the effect of that might be, for instance, onthe poetry of love. The development of the use ofproper names in such a society would certainly countas the introduction of a new idea, whereas the mereintroduction of a particular new proper name, withinthe existing framework, would not.

I have wanted to show by these examples that a newway of talking sufficiently important to rank as a new

Page 140: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

123CONCEPTS AND ACTIONS

idea implies a new set of social relationships. Similarlywith the dying out of a way of speaking. Take thenotion of friendship: we read, in Penelope Hall’s book,The Social Services of Modern England (Routledge),that it is the duty of a social worker to establish arelationship of friendship with her clients; but that shemust never forget that her first duty is to the policy ofthe agency by which she is employed. Now that is adebasement of the notion of friendship as it has beenunderstood, which has excluded this sort of dividedloyalty, not to say double-dealing. To the extent towhich the old idea gives way to this new one socialrelationships are impoverished (or, if anyone objects tothe interpolation of personal moral attitudes, at leastthey are changed). It will not do, either, to say that themere change in the meaning of a word need not preventpeople from having the relations to each other theywant to have; for this is to overlook the fact that ourlanguage and our social relations are just two differentsides of the same coin. To give an account of themeaning of a word is to describe how it is used; and todescribe how it is used is to describe the socialintercourse into which it enters.

If social relations between men exist only in andthrough their ideas, then, since the relations betweenideas are internal relations, social relations must be aspecies of internal relation too. This brings me intoconflict with a widely accepted principle of Hume’s:‘There is no object, which implies the existence of anyother if we consider these objects in themselves, andnever look beyond the ideas which we form of them’.There is no doubt that Hume intended this to apply tohuman actions and social life as well as to the

Page 141: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

124 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

phenomena of nature. Now to start with, Hume’sprinciple is not unqualifiedly true even of ourknowledge of natural phenomena. If I hear a sound andrecognize it as a clap of thunder, I already commitmyself to believing in the occurrence of a number ofother events—e.g. electrical discharges in theatmosphere—even in calling what I have heard‘thunder’. That is, from ‘the idea which I have formed’of what I heard I can legitimately infer ‘the existenceof other objects’. If I subsequently find that there wasno electrical storm in the vicinity at the time I heardthe sound I shall have to retract my claim that what Iheard was thunder. To use a phrase of Gilbert Ryle’s,the word ‘thunder’ is theory-impregnated; statementsaffirming the occurrence of thunder have logicalconnections with statements affirming the occurrenceof other events. To say this, of course, is not toreintroduce any mysterious causal nexus in rebus, of asort to which Hume could legitimately object. It issimply to point out that Hume overlooked the fact that‘the idea we form of an object’ does not just consist ofelements drawn from our observation of that object inisolation, but includes the idea of connections betweenit and other objects. (And one could scarcely form aconception of a language in which this was not so.)

Consider now a very simple paradigm case of arelation between actions in a human society: thatbetween an act of command and an act of obedience tothat command. A sergeant calls ‘Eyes right!’ and hismen all turn their eyes to the right. Now, in describingthe men’s act in terms of the notion of obedience to acommand, one is of course committing oneself tosaying that a command has been issued. So far the

Page 142: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

125CONCEPTS AND ACTIONS

situation looks precisely parallel to the relationbetween thunder and electrical storms. But now oneneeds to draw a distinction. An event’s character as anact of obedience is intrinsic to it in a way which is nottrue of an event’s character as a clap of thunder; andthis is in general true of human acts as opposed tonatural events. In the case of the latter, although humanbeings can think of the occurrences in question only interms of the concepts they do in fact have of them, yetthe events themselves have an existence independent ofthose concepts. There existed electrical storms andthunder long before there were human beings to formconcepts of them or establish that there was anyconnection between them. But it does not make senseto suppose that human beings might have been issuingcommands and obeying them before they came to formthe concept of command and obedience. For theirperformance of such acts is itself the chiefmanifestation of their possession of those concepts. Anact of obedience itself contains, as an essentialelement, a recognition of what went before as an order.But it would of course be senseless to suppose that aclap of thunder contained any recognition of what wentbefore as an electrical storm; it is our recognition ofthe sound, rather than the sound itself, which containsthat recognition of what went before.

Part of the opposition one feels to the idea thatmen can be related to each other through their actionsin at all the same kind of way as propositions can berelated to each other is probably due to an inadequateconception of what logical relations betweenpropositions themselves are. One is inclined to thinkof the laws of logic as forming a given rigid structure

Page 143: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

126 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

to which men try, with greater or less (but nevercomplete) success, to make what they say in theiractual linguistic and social intercourse conform. Onethinks of propositions as something ethereal, whichjust because of their ethereal, non-physical nature,can fit together more tightly than can be conceived inthe case of anything so grossly material as flesh-and-blood men and their actions. In a sense one is right inthis; for to treat of logical relations in a formalsystematic way is to think at a very high level ofabstraction, at which all the anomalies, imperfectionsand crudities which characterize men’s actualintercourse with each other in society have beenremoved. But, like any abstraction not recognized assuch, this can be misleading. It may make one forgetthat it is only from their roots in this actual flesh-and-blood intercourse that those formal systems draw suchlife as they have; for the whole idea of a logicalrelation is only possible by virtue of the sort ofagreement between men and their actions which isdiscussed by Wittgenstein in the PhilosophicalInvestigations . Collingwood’s remark on formalgrammar is apposite: ‘I likened the grammarian to abutcher; but if so, he is a butcher of a curious kind.Travellers say that certain African peoples will cut asteak from a living animal and cook it for dinner, theanimal being not much the worse. This may serve toamend the original comparison’. (7: p. 259.) It willseem less strange that social relations should be likelogical relations between propositions once it is seenthat logical relations between propositions themselvesdepend on social relations between men.

What I have been saying conflicts, of course, with

Page 144: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

127CONCEPTS AND ACTIONS

Karl Popper’s ‘postulate of methodologicalindividualism’ and appears to commit the sin of whathe calls ‘methodological essentialism’. Poppermaintains that the theories of the social sciences applyto theoretical constructions or models which areformulated by the investigator in order to explaincertain experiences, a method which he explicitlycompares to the construction of theoretical models inthe natural sciences.

This use of models explains and at the same timedestroys the claims of methodological essentialism…Itexplains them, for the model is of an abstract ortheoretical character, and we are liable to believe thatwe see it, either within or behind the changingobservable events, as a kind of observable ghost oressence. And it destroys them because our task is toanalyze our sociological models carefully in descriptiveor nominalist terms, viz. in terms of individuals, theirattitudes, expectations, relations, etc.—a postulatewhich may be called ‘methodological individualism’.(26: Section 29.)

Popper’s statement that social institutions are justexplanatory models introduced by the social scientistfor his own purposes is palpably untrue. The ways ofthinking embodied in institutions govern the way themembers of the societies studied by the social scientistbehave. The idea of war, for instance, which is one ofPopper’s examples, was not simply invented by peoplewho wanted to explain what happens when societiescome into armed conflict. It is an idea which providesthe criteria of what is appropriate in the behaviour ofmembers of the conflicting societies. Because mycountry is at war there are certain things which I must

Page 145: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

128 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

and certain things which I must not do. My behaviouris governed, one could say, by my concept of myself asa member of a belligerent country. The concept of warbelongs essentially to my behaviour. But the concept ofgravity does not belong essentially to the behaviour ofa falling apple in the same way: it belongs rather to thephysicist’s explanation of the apple’s behaviour. Torecognize this has, pace Popper, nothing to do with abelief in ghosts behind the phenomena. Further, it isimpossible to go far in specifying the attitudes,expectations and relations of individuals withoutreferring to concepts which enter into those attitudes,etc., and the meaning of which certainly cannot beexplained in terms of the actions of any individualpersons. (Cf. Maurice Mandelbaum: 17.)

2. Discursive and Non-Discursive ‘Ideas’

In the course of this argument I have linked theassertion that social relations are internal with theassertion that men’s mutual interaction ‘embodiesideas’, suggesting that social interaction can moreprofitably be compared to the exchange of ideas in aconversation than to the interaction of forces in aphysical system. This may seem to put me in danger ofover-intellectualizing social life, especially since theexamples I have so far discussed have all beenexamples of behaviour which expresses discursiveideas, that is, ideas which also have a straightforwardlinguistic expression. It is because the use of languageis so intimately, so inseparably, bound up with theother, non-linguistic, activities which men perform,that it is possible to speak of their non-linguistic

Page 146: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

129CONCEPTS AND ACTIONS

behaviour also as expressing discursive ideas. Apartfrom the examples of this which I have already givenin other connections, one needs only to recall theenormous extent to which the learning of anycharacteristically human activity normally involvestalking as well: in connection, e.g., with discussions ofalternative ways of doing things, the inculcation ofstandards of good work, the giving of reasons, and soon. But there is no sharp break between behaviourwhich expresses discursive ideas and that which doesnot; and that which does not is sufficiently like thatwhich does to make it necessary to regard it asanalogous to the other. So, even where it would beunnatural to say that a given kind of social relationexpresses any ideas of a discursive nature, still it iscloser to that general category than it is to that of theinteraction of physical forces.

Collingwood provides a striking illustration of this inhis discussion of the analogy between language and dress.(7: p. 244.) Again, consider the following scene from thefilm Shane. A lone horseman arrives at the isolatedhomestead of a small farmer on the American prairieswho is suffering from the depredations of the rising classof big cattle-owners. Although they hardly exchange aword, a bond of sympathy springs up between thestranger and the homesteader. The stranger silently joinsthe other in uprooting, with great effort, the stump of atree in the yard; in pausing for breath, they happen tocatch each other’s eye and smile shyly at each other. Nowany explicit account that one tried to give of the kind ofunderstanding that had sprung up between these two, andwhich was expressed in that glance, would no doubt bevery complicated and inadequate. We understand it,

Page 147: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

130 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

however, as we may understand the meaning of apregnant pause (consider what it is that makes a pausepregnant), or as we may understand the meaning of agesture that completes a statement. ‘There is a story thatBuddha once, at the climax of a philosophicaldiscussion…took a flower in his hand, and looked at it;one of his disciples smiled, and the master said to him,“You have understood me”.’ (7: p. 243.) And what I wantto insist on is that, just as in a conversation the point of aremark (or of a pause) depends on its internal relation towhat has gone before, so in the scene from the film theinterchange of glances derives its full meaning from itsinternal relation to the situation in which it occurs: theloneliness, the threat of danger, the sharing of a commonlife in difficult circumstances, the satisfaction in physicaleffort, and so on.

It may be thought that there are certain kinds ofsocial relation, particularly important for sociology andhistory, of which the foregoing considerations are nottrue: as for instance wars in which the issue betweenthe combatants is not even remotely of an intellectualnature (as one might say, e.g., that the crusades were),but purely a struggle for physical survival as in a warbetween hunger migrants and the possessors of theland on which they are encroaching.1 But even here,although the issue is in a sense a purely materialone, the form which the struggle takes will stillinvolve internal relations in a sense which will notapply to, say, a fight between two wild animals overa piece of meat. For the belligerents are societies 1 This example was suggested to me by a discussion with mycolleague. Professor J.C.Rees as indeed was the realization for thenecessity for this whole section.

Page 148: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

131CONCEPTS AND ACTIONS

in which much goes on besides eating, seeking shelterand reproducing; in which life is carried on in termsof symbolic ideas which express certain attitudes asbetween man and man. These symbolic relationships,incidentally, will affect the character even of thosebasic ‘biological’ activities: one does not throw muchlight on the particular form which the latter may takein a given society by speaking of them inMalinowski’s neo-Marxist terminology as performingthe ‘function’ of providing for the satisfaction of thebasic biological needs. Now of course, ‘out-groupattitudes’ between the members of my hypotheticalwarring societies will not be the same as ‘in-groupattitudes’ (if I may be forgiven the momentary lapseinto the jargon of social psychology). Nevertheless,the fact that the enemies are men, with their own ideasand institutions, and with whom it would be possibleto communicate, will affect the attitudes of membersof the other society to them—even if its only effect isto make them the more ferocious. Human war, like allother human activities, is governed by conventions;and where one is dealing with conventions, one isdealing with internal relations.

3. The Social Sciences and History

This view of the matter may make possible a newappreciation of Collingwood’s conception of all humanhistory as the history of thought. That is no doubt anexaggeration and the notion that the task of thehistorian is to re-think the thoughts of the historicalparticipants is to some extent an intellectualisticdistortion. But Collingwood is right if he is taken to

Page 149: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

132 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

mean that the way to understand events in humanhistory, even those which cannot naturally berepresented as conflicts between or developments ofdiscursive ideas, is more closely analogous to the wayin which we understand expressions of ideas than it isto the way we understand physical processes.

There is a certain respect, indeed, in whichCollingwood pays insufficient attention to the mannerin which a way of thinking and the historical situationto which it belongs form one indivisible whole. Hesays that the aim of the historian is to think the verysame thoughts as were once thought, just as they werethought at the historical moment in question. (6: PartV.) But though extinct ways of thinking may, in asense, be recaptured by the historian, the way in whichthe historian thinks them will be coloured by the factthat he has had to employ historiographical methods torecapture them. The medieval knight did not have touse those methods in order to view his lady in terms ofthe notions of courtly love: he just thought of her inthose terms. Historical research may enable me toachieve some understanding of what was involved inthis way of thinking, but that will not make it open tome to think of my lady in those terms. I should alwaysbe conscious that this was an anachronism, whichmeans, of course, that I should not be thinking of herin just the same terms as did the knight of his lady.And naturally, it is even more impossible for me tothink of his lady as he did.

Nevertheless, Collingwood’s view is nearer the truththan is that most favoured in empiricist methodologiesof the social sciences, which runs somewhat asfollows—on the one side we have human history which

Page 150: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

133CONCEPTS AND ACTIONS

is a kind of repository of data. The historian unearthsthese data and presents them to his more theoreticallyminded colleagues who then produce scientificgeneralizations and theories establishing connectionsbetween one kind of social situation and another. Thesetheories can then be applied to history itself in order toenhance our understanding of the ways in which itsepisodes are mutually connected. I have tried to show,particularly in connection with Pareto, how thisinvolves minimizing the importance of ideas in humanhistory, since ideas and theories are constantlydeveloping and changing, and since each system ofideas, its component elements being interrelatedinternally, has to be understood in and for itself; thecombined result of which is to make systems of ideas avery unsuitable subject for broad generalizations. Ihave also tried to show that social relations really existonly in and through the ideas which are current insociety; or alternatively; that social relations fall intothe same logical category as do relations betweenideas. It follows that social relations must be anequally unsuitable subject for generalizations andtheories of the scientific sort to be formulated aboutthem. Historical explanation is not the application ofgeneralizations and theories to particular instances: itis the tracing of internal relations. It is like applyingone’s knowledge of a language in order to understand aconversation rather than like applying one’s knowledgeof the laws of mechanics to understand the workings ofa watch. Non-linguistic behaviour, for example, has an‘idiom’ in the same kind of way as has a language. Inthe same kind of way as it can be difficult to recapturethe idiom of Greek thought in a translation into modern

Page 151: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

134 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

English of a Platonic dialogue, so it can be misleadingto think of the behaviour of people in remote societiesin terms of the demeanour to which we are accustomedin our own society. Think of the uneasy feeling oneoften has about the authenticity of ‘racy’ historicalevocations like those in some of Robert Graves’snovels: this has nothing to do with doubts about awriter’s accuracy in matters of external detail.

The relation between sociological theories andhistorical narrative is less like the relation betweenscientific laws and the reports of experiments orobservations than it is like that between theories oflogic and arguments in particular languages. Considerfor instance the explanation of a chemical reaction interms of a theory about molecular structure andvalency: here the theory establishes a connectionbetween what happened at one moment when the twochemicals were brought together and what happened ata subsequent moment. It is only in terms of the theorythat one can speak of the events being thus ‘connected’(as opposed to a simple spatio-temporal connection);the only way to grasp the connection is to learn thetheory. But the application of a logical theory to aparticular piece of reasoning is not like that. One doesnot have to know the theory in order to appreciate theconnection between the steps of the argument; on thecontrary, it is only in so far as one can already grasplogical connections between particular statements inparticular languages that one is even in a position tounderstand what the logical theory is all about. (This isimplied by the argument of Lewis Carroll, which Ireferred to earlier.) Whereas in natural science it isyour theoretical knowledge which enables you to

Page 152: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

135CONCEPTS AND ACTIONS

explain occurrences you have not previously met, aknowledge of logical theory on the other hand will notenable you to understand a piece of reasoning in anunknown language; you will have to learn thatlanguage, and that in itself may suffice to enable you tograsp the connections between the various parts ofarguments in that language.

Consider now an example from sociology. GeorgSimmel writes:

The degeneration of a difference in convictions intohatred and fight occurs only when there were essential,original similarities between the parties. The(sociologically very significant) ‘respect for the enemy’is usually absent where the hostility has arisen on thebasis of previous solidarity. And where enoughsimilarities continue to make confusions and blurredoutlines possible, points of difference need an emphasisnot justified by the issue but only by that danger ofconfusion. This was involved, for instance, in the caseof Catholicism in Berne… Roman Catholicism does nothave to fear any threat to its identity from externalcontact with a church so different as the ReformedChurch, but quite from something as closely akin asOld-Catholicism. (31: Chapter I.)

Here I want to say that it is not through Simmel’sgeneralization that one understands the relationship heis pointing to between Roman and Old Catholicism:one understands that only to the extent that oneunderstands the two religious systems themselves andtheir historical relations. The ‘sociological law’ may behelpful in calling one’s attention to features ofhistorical situations which one might otherwise haveoverlooked and in suggesting useful analogies. Here

Page 153: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

136 THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE

for instance one may be led to compare Simmel’sexample with the relations between the RussianCommunist Party and, on the one hand, the BritishLabour Party and, on the other, the BritishConservatives. But no historical situation can beunderstood simply by ‘applying’ such laws, as oneapplies laws to particular occurrences in naturalscience. Indeed, it is only in so far as one has anindependent historical grasp of situations like this onethat one is able to understand what the law amounts toat all. That is not like having to know the kind ofexperiment on which a scientific theory is based beforeone can understand the theory, for there it makes nosense to speak of understanding the connectionsbetween the parts of the experiment except in terms ofthe scientific theory. But one could understand verywell the nature of the relations between RomanCatholicism and Old Catholicism without ever havingheard of Simmel’s theory, or anything like it.

4. Concluding Remark

I have made no attempt, in this book, to consider theundoubted differences which exist between particularkinds of social study, such as sociology, politicaltheory, economics, and so on. I have wanted rather tobring out certain features of the notion of a socialstudy as such. I do not think that individualmethodological differences, important as they may bewithin their own context, can affect the broad outlinesof what I have tried to say. For this belongs tophilosophy rather than to what is commonlyunderstood by the term ‘methodology’.

Page 154: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

137

BIBLIOGRAPHY

(1) ACTON, H.B., The Illusion of the Epoch, Cohen &West, 1955.

(2) ARON, RAYMOND, German Sociology, Heinemann,1957.

(3) AYER, A.J., The Problem of Knowledge, Macmillanand Penguin Books, 1956.

(4) AYER, A.J., ‘Can There be a Private Language?’,Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society,Supplementary Volume XXVIII.

(5) CARROLL, LEWIS, ‘What the Tortoise Said toAchilles’, Complete Works, Nonesuch Press.

(6) COLLINGWOOD, R.G., The Idea of History, OUP,1946.

(7) COLLINGWOOD, R.G., The Principles of Art, OUP,1938.

(8) CRANSTON, MAURICE, Freedom: A New Analysis,Longmans, 1953.

(9) DURKHEIM, EMILE, Suicide, Routledge & KeganPaul, 1952.

(10) GEACH, PETER, Mental Acts, Routledge & KeganPaul, 1957.

(11) GINSBERG, MORRIS, On the Diversity of Morals,Heinemann, 1956.

(12) HUME, DAVID, Enquiry into Human Understanding.(13) LASLETT, PETER (Ed.), Philosophy, Politics and

Society, Blackwell, 1956.(14) LEVI, E.H., An Introduction to Legal Reasoning,

University of Chicago, Phoenix Books, 1961.(15) LYND, R.S., Knowledge for What?, Princeton, 1945.(16) MALCOLM, NORMAN, Article in the Philosophical

Review, Vol. LXIII, 1954, pp. 530–559.

Page 155: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

138 BIBLIOGRAPHY

(17) MANDELBAUM, MAURICE, ‘Societal Facts’,B.J.Sociol., VI, 4 (1955).

(18) MILL, J.S., A System of Logic.(19) NEWCOMB, T.M., Social Psychology, Tavistock

Publications, 1952.(20) OAKESHOTT, Michael, ‘The Tower of Babel’,

Cambridge Journal, Vol. 2.(21) OAKESHOTT, MICHAEL, ‘Rational Conduct’,

Cambridge Journal, Vol. 4.(22) OAKESHOTT, MICHAEL, Political Education,

Bowes and Bowes, 1951.(23) PARETO, VILFREDO, The Mind and Society, New

York, Harcourt Brace, 1935.(24) PARSONS, TALCOTT, The Structure of Social

Action, Allen & Unwin, 1949.(25) POPPER, KARL, The Open Society and Its Enemies,

Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1945.(26) POPPER, KARL, The Poverty of Historicism,

Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1957.(27) RENNER, KARL (with Introduction by O.KAHN-

FREUND), The Institutions of Private Law and theirSocial Function, Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1949.

(28) RHEES, RUSH, ‘Can There be a Private Language?’,Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society,Supplementary Volume XXVIII.

(29) RYLE, GILBERT, The Concept of Mind, Hutchinson,1949.

(30) SHERIF, M. & SHERIF, C., An Outline of SocialPsychology, New York, Harper, 1956.

(31) SIMMEL, GEORG, Conflict, Glencoe, Free Press,1955.

(32) STRAWSON, P.F., Critical Notice in Mind, Vol.LXIII, No. 249, pp. 84 ff.

(33) WEBER, MAX, Wirtschaft und Gesellschaft,Tübingen, Mohr, 1956.

(34) WEBER, MAX, Gesammelte Aufsätze zurWissenschaftslehre, Tübingen, Mohr, 1922.

(35) WELDON, T.D., The Vocabulary of Politics. PenguinBooks, 1953.

Page 156: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

139BIBLIOGRAPHY

(36) WITTGENSTEIN, LUDWIG, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, Kegan Paul, 1923.

(37) WITTGENSTEIN, LUDWIG, PhilosophicalInvestigations, Blackwell, 1953.

(38) WITTGENSTEIN, LUDWIG, Remarks on theFoundations of Mathematics, Blackwell, 1956.

Page 157: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

140

Page 158: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

141

ACTON, H.B., 73, 137alternative conduct, 65anarchist, 52fanimals, 60–2, 74, 76fAnscombe, G.E.M., 109a priori, see conceptual questionsAron, Raymond, 42, 137Ayer, A.J., 4, 35–9, 72, 137 BAPTISM, 105f, 108Beethoven, 93Brecht, Berthold, 118Buddha, 130business, 89, 98–100Burnet, J., 8f, 21 CARROL, Lewis, 55–7, 134, 137Catholicism, Roman and Old, 135fcausation, 7f, 16f, 67, 75–80, 111–

6, 124Chaucer, Geoffrey, 82Cockcroft-Walton experiments, 84Collingwood, R.G., 90, 103, 113,

126, 129, 131, 137command and obedience, 124fconcepts, 8–11, 14f, 15–8, 23f, 43f,

46–8, 65, 72–5, 85, 89f, 96f,111, 118, 121–36

conceptual questions, 9f, 15–8, 71fcourtly love, 82, 132Cranston, Maurice, 94, 137criteria, 20f, 33, 58, 60, 73, 86f,

108, 127f DECISION, 91–3definition, 25–9, 50derivation, 103–11Descartes, René, 79disposition, 80f

drive, 75fDurkheim, Émile, 23f, 95, 109, 111,

137 ECONOMICS, 89Einstein, Albert, 42, 103empathy, 90empirical questions, 9f, 15–8, 71fends and means, 55, 97fEngels, Friedrich, 72epistemology, 5–7, 18–24, 40–3established standards, 32f, 81, 119ethology, 69fEvans, Caradog, 118experimental methods, 7–10, 73, 77,

96, 109f FLEW, A.G.N., 4form of life, 34, 40–2, 52f, 100fFrazer, Sir James, 113Freud, Sigmund, 47f, 90, 104friendship, 123function, 116, 131 GEACH, Peter, 80, 119, 137generalization, 44, 67–71, 75, 81,

83–8, 104f, 107f, 110, 119f, 133germ theory of disease, 121Ginsberg, Morris, 47f, 112, 119,

137grammar and style, 53Graves, Robert, 134 HABIT, 57–65Hall, Penelope, 123Haydn, 93Hegel, G., 7, 72fhistory, 64f, 70f, 88, 131–6

INDEX

Page 159: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

142 INDEX

Hume, David, 7f, 16f, 54, 67, 84,93, 123f, 137

IBSEN, H., 22fidea, see conceptIdealism, 90inference, 55–7, 81intelligibility, 11f, 18–21, 82, 102intention, 81finternal relation, 107, 121–31, 133interwovenness, 28, 63fintuition, 61, 112, 119inverse deductive method, 70f JUSTIFICATION, 81f, 114 KAHN-FREUND, O., 61, 137Kant, Immanuel, 22 LABRIOLA, A., 24language, 5, 10–6, 24–39, 43f, 115,

121–3, 128–30, 133fLaslett, Peter, 6, 137laws of mind, 69f, 75learning, 58f, 86legal precedent, 61Levi, E.H., 61, 137libertarianism, 75liquidity preference, 89Locke, John, 3, 5logic, 55–7, 67, 71, 96, 100, 125f,

134flogical and non-logical conduct, 95–

103love, 122Lynd, R.S., 103, 113, 137Lyttleton, Humphrey, 93f MAGIC, 99, 113Malcolm, Norman, 35, 137Malinowski, B., 131Mandelbaum, Maurice, 128, 138Marxism, 72, 93, 104, 118, 131meaning, 25–39, 115meaningful behaviour, 45–53, 116–

20metaphysics, 5–7meteorology, 68methodological essentialism and

individualism, 127f

methodology, 84, 136Mill, J.S., 66–76, 78–80, 83, 86, 88,

92, 138mistake, 32, 59, 99monks, 23, 52fMoore, G.E., 9fmorality, 58, 63–5motive, 45, 75–83Mozart, 93 NEWCOMB, T.M., 75–80, 138Newton, Sir Isaac, 1noticing, 85notion, see concept OAKESHOTT, Michael, 54–65, 91,

138organism, 75f, 110 PARETO, Vilfredo, 46, 95–111, 118,

133, 138Parsons, Talcott, 48, 138participation, 51, 74, 86, 87fPharisee and Publican, 87philosophy, 1–24, 42f, 84, 96, 101–

3, 113fphysiological states, 69, 75–9Popper, Karl, 71, 92, 112, 127f, 138Poseidon, 97Pound, Roscoe, 61prediction, 81f, 91–4private language, 33–9proper names, 123psychoanalysis, 47f, 89fpsychology, 69–71 QUALITY and quantity, 37, 72–4 REALITY, 7–24, 40, 102reason, 45–8, 54, 81f, 97–101Rees, J.C., 130reflectiveness, 62–5, 89regularity, 67–71, 83–6religion, 87f, 100fRenner, Karl, 73, 138residue, 103–11Rhees, Rush, 11, 37, 85, 138Romeo and Juliet, 77Rugby football, 93

Page 160: The Idea of a Social Scienceinthespaceofreasons.pbworks.com/f/Winch+The-idea-of-a-social... · THE IDEA OF A SOCIAL SCIENCE and its Relation to Philosophy SECOND EDITION by PETER

143INDEX

rule, 25–39, 50, 57–65, 74, 83f, 92,116

Ryle, Gilbert, 4, 18, 80f, 124, 138 same, 26–31, 36, 59–61, 83f, 86f,

108science 1f, 7–10, 66–94, 96, 100–3,

113sexual relations, 76f, 106fShakespeare, William, 77Sherif, C. & M., 44, 138Simmel, Georg, 135, 138Sims, D.L., 118Sinn, see meaningful behavioursocial psychology, 41, 43f, 75–80,

131sociology, 23, 40–3, 86–90, 101,

108, 114, 116statute law, 61statistics, 68f, 113, 115stimulus and response, 60, 65Strawson, P.F., 33–5, 38–9, 138symbolic action, 50, 106f THOUGHT, 11, 25tidology, 68tradition, 48f, 63f, 92f

trend, 71, 92Troilus and Cressida, 82 ‘UNDERLABOURER’ conception

of philosophy, 2–7, 11f, 20understanding, 18–24, 41, 65, 86–

91, 110, 111–20, 132uniformity, see regularityusage, 11 Verfremdungseffekt, 118fVerstehen, 111–20voting, 51 WAR, 127f, 130fWeber, Max, 45–50, 98, 111–20,

138Weldon, T.D., 12–15, 138wertrational, 98Wiese, L. von, 24Wittgenstein, Ludwig, 13–5, 19, 24–

39, 58f, 63, 103, 114f, 118,126, 138

writhing, 73 ZEIGARNIK, 77fzweckrational, 98