quantum mechanics: new experiments, new applications, and new formulations of old questions

17
Quantum mechanics: new experiments, new applications, and new formulations of old questions This article has been downloaded from IOPscience. Please scroll down to see the full text article. 2000 Phys.-Usp. 43 585 (http://iopscience.iop.org/1063-7869/43/6/R03) Download details: IP Address: 141.225.218.75 The article was downloaded on 04/07/2012 at 12:57 Please note that terms and conditions apply. View the table of contents for this issue, or go to the journal homepage for more Home Search Collections Journals About Contact us My IOPscience

Upload: mikhail-b

Post on 09-Aug-2016

214 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • Quantum mechanics: new experiments, new applications, and new formulations of old

    questions

    This article has been downloaded from IOPscience. Please scroll down to see the full text article.

    2000 Phys.-Usp. 43 585

    (http://iopscience.iop.org/1063-7869/43/6/R03)

    Download details:IP Address: 141.225.218.75The article was downloaded on 04/07/2012 at 12:57

    Please note that terms and conditions apply.

    View the table of contents for this issue, or go to the journal homepage for more

    Home Search Collections Journals About Contact us My IOPscience

  • Abstract. Some of the quantum mechanical conceptual pro-blems, their current status, and related theoretical develop-ments are reviewed. The characteristics of the entangledquantum states are analyzed, and new experiments and quan-tum information applications involving such states are dis-cussed. The well-known paradox of Schrodingers cat (theimpossibility of observing superpositions of macroscopicallydistinct states that are predicted by quantum mechanics) isdiscussed. It is shown that decoherence (arising when a quan-tum system is measured in such a way that some informationabout its state is recorded in its environment) prevents thedistinguishing of a superposition and the corresponding mix-ture. This overcomes the difficulties associated with the para-doxical nature of quantum measurement provided we remainwithin the framework of the theory of open systems. Otherconceptual difficulties, while actually lying outside physics,are now the subject of much research and have already led tonew interesting interpretations of quantum mechanics. Thesuggestion of Wigner and others that the observers conscious-ness be included in the theory of quantum measurement isdiscussed in this context. A hypothesis is put forward whichmight enable the functioning of consciousness to be describedin quantum measurement terms.

    From the Editor. The advent of the theories of relativity andquantum mechanics has had a great impact on physics, andhas naturally touched fundamental philosophical (epistemo-logical, gnoseological) issues. As regards relativity (leavingaside the closely related cosmology and, to some extent, blackholes), its foundations are practically no longer debated. Bycontrast, quantum mechanics, its methodological basis, thetheory of measurements and other aspects are still activelydiscussed in world literature. And indeed, the advances inexperimental techniques have made it possible to perform anumber of most exquisite experiments (quantum teleporta-tion being just one example).

    In the past in the USSR the foundations of the newphysics were also much discussed, but, unfortunately, subjectto considerable ideological restrictions. To wit, one had topay genuine or at least formal homage to a philosophicaldoctrine known as dialectical materialism. This made freediscussion impossible, and the issues of methodology ofphysics of the present-day level practically disappeared fromRussian publications. This is felt even now, in spite of the factthat anyone today in Russia is completely free to engage inscientific discussion of methodological and, in particular,gnoseological matters. This paper by M B Menski| is a goodexample of the scientific treatment of the foundations ofquantummechanics not restricted by dogmas of any kind.Wehope that this will stimulate other authors to openly expresstheir opinions in presentations and letters to the Editor,without any ideological proscriptions. Of course, we are notreferring to speculations that ignore the recognized content ofmodern physics, and in particular, quantum mechanics.

    1. Introduction

    Quantum mechanics has long become an everyday workingtool for researchers in many different fields of physics. At the

    MBMenski| PNLebedev Physics Institute, RussianAcademy of SciencesLeninski| prosp. 53, 117924 Moscow, Russian FederationE-mail: [email protected]

    Received 12 April 2000, revised 19 April 2000

    Uspekhi Fizicheskikh Nauk 170 (6) 631 648 (2000)

    Translated by A S Dobroslavski|; edited by M S Aksenteva

    REVIEWS OF TOPICAL PROBLEMS PACS number: 03.65.Bz

    Quantum mechanics: new experiments, new applications,

    and new formulations of old questions

    M B Menski|}

    DOI: 10.1070/PU2000v043n06ABEH000771

    Contents

    1. Introduction 5852. Entangled states 586

    2.1 Nonclassicality of the EPR pair; 2.2 Applications: quantum information; 2.3 Quantum mechanics at a new stage

    3. Schrodingers cat 5903.1 Superposition of an alive and dead cat; 3.2 Amplification of quantum superposition; 3.3 Decoherence by the

    environment

    4. Extension of the theory of measurement 5934.1 Does decoherence solve the problem of measurement? 4.2 Attempts to advance the theory; 4.3 Quantummechanics

    and consciousness; 4.4 Selection of an alternative is this the work of the consciousness? 4.5 Quantum world and

    classical world

    5. Conclusions 598References 599

    Physics Uspekhi 43 (6) 585 600 (2000) # 2000 Uspekhi Fizicheskikh Nauk, Russian Academy of Sciences

    }The author is also known by the nameMBMensky. The name used hereis a transliteration under the BSI/ANSI scheme adopted by this journal.

  • same time, certain conceptual points that were at issue fromthe early days of quantum mechanics have not been resolvedeven to this day. The well known examples are the Einstein Podolsky Rosen (EPR) paradox and the paradox ofSchrodingers cat. The not solved yet conceptual problem ofquantum mechanics are often jointly referred to as problemof measurement. Unlike other physical problems, they lack astraightforward and clear formulation, and are often pre-sented in different ways by different authors. Moreover,many established scientists claim that there are no concep-tual problems in quantum mechanics whatsoever. Attemptsto raise these questions are oftenmet with admonishment andreproof. A typical comment is that this is philosophy notphysics, and the word philosophy clearly rings withcondescension.

    In recent years, however, this attitude to the conceptualproblems of quantum mechanics has been changing rapidly.In spite of the fact that they were discussed extensively in thepubertal years of quantum mechanics (see, for example,reprints of classic papers in Ref. [1]), and at all times weresystematically highlighted in textbooks (see, for example,Refs [2 5]), today there is a vast body of literature dedicatedto these problems. They are discussed today in much greaterdetail than before, and this discussion is gradually becoming afairly respectable occupation (see, for example, Refs [6 15]).Moreover, the old issues known from the times of thefounding fathers receive new formulations, special experi-ments are carried out to get answers, and discussionsgerminate new applications of quantum mechanics. In thispaper we try to illustrate the current state of affairs, withoutattempting to give a full coverage and admitting a certainsubjectivity of views expressed.

    We observe from the outset that the new applicationsgenerically referred to as quantum information emerged notso much from the studies of conceptual problems of quantummechanics as from the comparative analysis of quantumtheory versus classical. Of course, the analysis of the specificquantum aspects is a necessary preliminary stage in the studyof conceptual problems. However, new applications begin toarise at a level of analysis when it is too early yet to speak ofconceptual problems or paradoxes. One may well say that thework on new experiments and new applications is realphysics, and very interesting at that, while the paradoxes ofquantum mechanics are just a philosophical (conceptual,metaphysical) superstructure.

    One of the aims of this paper is to show that this is indeedthe case. More precisely, we are going to demonstrate that aformulation of quantummechanics is possible where there areno paradoxes, and which supplies answers to all the questionsusually asked by physicists. Paradoxes only arise when theinquirer is not content with the physical level of the theory,when he poses such questions that are not customarily askedin physics in other words, when he takes the liberty of goingbeyond the frontiers of physics. It is quite reasonable tobelieve that such attempts on the part of the physicist havelittle sense.

    Those who think that way must not be blamed. They mayeven be right, because constructive work in physics requireswell posed purely physical problems. Some researchers,however, find it necessary to go beyond the limits of theproper physical methodology, and to define a broader scopeof questions. It is then that the quantum paradoxes come tolight. As it turns out, attempts to resolve these paradoxesoften lead to remarkable new conceptions, which are at least

    very interesting. Admittedly, not much progress has beenmade in this direction. Nevertheless, the charm and boldnessof the emerging picture of the quantum world allow one tobelieve that this avenue will eventually lead the theory up to anew level. A possible concretization of this hope, which we aregoing to defend, consists in that the new theory may include(and possibly explain) the phenomenon of consciousness which still remains a mystery.

    So, in the forthcoming sections we shall analyze two basicspecifically quantum concepts: entangled states, and Schro-dingers cat. Most space (Sections 2 and 3) will be given to theanalysis of specific features of quantum mechanics (ascompared to the classical theory) related to these concepts,and to the new physical situations that follow. We shalldiscuss the schemes of quantum information based onentangled states, and the phenomenon of decoherence 1 thatprevents the observability of the macroscopic Schrodingerscat (superpositions of macroscopically distinct states).

    In Section 4 we briefly discuss the paradoxes andconceptual issues of quantum mechanics that cannot beresolved within the framework of decoherence. The ques-tions we try to answer are:

    Is it necessary to ask these eternal questions? Can they be answered within the realm of physics? Are there answers to these questions beyond the limits

    of physical theory?We shall arrive at conclusions that are not new, but have

    not yet been universally accepted: From a practical standpoint these questions are not

    necessary. They cannot be resolved (and should not be posed)

    within the framework of physics. If a solution does exist, its formulation will in someway

    or other include such a nonphysical element as the mind ofthe observer.

    Finally, we formulate and try to substantiate the hypoth-esis that may explain the phenomenon of consciousness interms of the quantum theory of measurements.

    2. Entangled states

    Quantum correlation, or the entangled states (also known asEPR states) may arise in a system that consists of two ormoreinteracting subsystems. There is no entanglement arise whenthe system occurs in the state of the form jCi jcijji, wherejci and jji are the states of respective subsystems. Such astate is referred to as factorized. However, even if in thebeginning the state is factorized, it may become entangledafter the subsystems interact with one another. The simplestentangled state has the form 2

    jCi 12p jc1ijj1i jc2ijj2i : 1

    Obviously, if the entire system occurs in state (1), the state ofeach subsystem is not determined. There is only a correlation

    1The modern description of decoherence derives from the work of a range

    of physicists includingMurray Gell-Mann, JimHartle, Stephen Hawking,

    Erich Joos, Dieter Zeh, Wojciech Zurek, and others. Selective description

    of decoherence by restricted path integrals was proposed by Menskii|, seebelow). (Authors note to the English edition.)2 In the general case the entangled state includes more than two compo-

    nents, jCi 1= np Pi jciijii. The set of components of the super-position can even be continuous.

    586 M BMenski| Physics Uspekhi 43 (6)

  • which may be described as follows: if one subsystem occurs instate jcii (i 1; 2), then the other occurs in state jjii.

    2.1 Nonclassicality of the EPR pairThe feasibility of entangled states leads to certain features ofquantum systems that have no analogs in classical physics andtherefore seem very strange to the intuition developed in theanalysis of classical systems. Situations of this kind wereanalyzed in the work of Einstein, Podolsky and Rosen [16]. Itturned out that the concept of the element of reality in theclassical sense is not applicable to the quantum theory. Thiscontradiction between quantum mechanical predictions andclassical intuition became known as the Einstein Podolsky Rosen (EPR) paradox.

    This paradox was at the center of the famous debatebetween Einstein and Bohr (see Ref. [17]), and was later muchdiscussed in literature. In 1964 John Bell proposed a simpleand clear formulation of this paradox in terms of the so-calledBell inequalities (see Ref. [6]), which we shall discuss here ingeneral terms.

    The simplest way to carry out such an analysis is to use theexample of the decay of a particle with spin 0 into twoparticles with spin 1=2. The state of the two particles aftersuch decay is 3

    jCi 12p j "i1j#i2 j#i1j"i2 ; 2

    where j"ii denotes the state of ith particle with its spindirected upwards with respect to the selected axis (say, z),and j#ii denotes the state of ith particle with downward spin.Evidently, state (2) is an entangled state of the two particles;the direction of spin of each particle is not determined, butthere is quantum correlation between the directions of thespins of the two particles.

    As a result of this correlation, measurements of theprojections of the spins of the two particles are correlatedeven when the particles have traveled far away from eachother. If the measurement of spin projection of the firstparticle shows that the spin is directed upwards, then thespin of the other particle is directed downwards no matterhow far away that particle is, and vice versa.

    There is nothing peculiar or specifically quantum in thissituation. A similar correlation between the results ofmeasurements of two objects may well exist in classicalphysics as well. Assume, for example, that there are twoballs in a black box, one white and the other black. Let then awall be placed in the box that separates the balls, and twohalves of the box, each containing one ball, are moved faraway from each other. Obviously, when these half-boxes areopened, the results are correlated: if one contains the whiteball, the other has the black one, and vice versa.

    The specifically quantum features arise when we measurethe projections of the spins of two particles onto differentaxes. For example, we measure the projection of the spin ofthe first particle onto the z axis, and the projection of spin ofthe other particle onto an axis inclined with respect to z. If wefind that the spin of the first particle is directed upwards (inthe positive sense of the z axis), it is not possible to predict forcertain the result of the other measurement. However, the

    conventional quantum mechanical rules can be used todetermine the probabilities of the two alternative results ofmeasurement. And it turns out that the results of quantummechanical calculations are incompatible with the assump-tion that the observed properties had existed before themeasurement.

    Bell introduced the concept of the objective local theory,in which the properties of the system (in our case the particle)objectively exist irrespective of the measurement, and whichincludes some other principles characteristic of the classicaltheory. Namely, in the objective local theory

    each particle is characterized by a number of variables(which may correspond, for instance, to the wave function),which are possibly correlated for the two particles;

    the results of measurement of one particle do notdepend on whether the other particle is measured or not,and if it is, they do not depend on the result of such ameasurement;

    the characteristics of statistical ensembles (and there-fore the statistics of measurement) depend only on theconditions that existed at earlier times: retrospective caus-ality is not possible.

    Bells theorem [6] proved in 1964 states that the objectivelocal theory and quantum mechanics give different predic-tions as to the statistics of the results of measurements. Moreprecisely, the axioms of the objective local theory lead tocertain inequalities (Bells inequalities) for the probabilities ofdifferent results of measurements, and quantum mechanicspredicts that these inequalities are violated when the projec-tions of spin onto different axes are measured for the twoparticles.

    After the formulation of Bells theorem, attempts weremade to experimentally verify Bells inequalities, and in 1980Aspect experimentally demonstrated that Bells inequality isviolated (see Ref. [18]) 4. This result agrees with quantummechanics and disagrees with the objective local theory. Thiswas experimental proof of the fact that it is not (or at least notalways) possible to treat the states of microscopic systems asobjective reality independent of the measurements per-formed. Later there were many more correlation experimentsof the type that Aspect carried out.

    Aspects experiments, like any experiments with EPRpairs, are also interesting because they demonstrate so-calledquantum nonlocality: themeasurement applied to one of theparticles predetermines the outcome of a measurementcarried out on the other particle at the same time and at adifferent location. Two events (measurement of the firstparticle and measurement of the second particle) may beseparated by a spacelike interval, and still one measurementpredetermines the result of the other. To make this circum-stance even more convincing, experiments similar to thoseperformed by Aspect have been carried out with an everincreasing distance between the particles. Recently the groupled by N Gisin in Geneva set up a correlation experiment [19]with a distance of 10 km between the two particles of the EPRpair. The outcome of the experiment was the same.

    At first glance it may seem that causality is violated inthese experiments. This is not the case, however, because therelationship between the two events (measurement of the first

    3 The minus sign in this expression ensures that the state of the two

    particles is singlet rather than being a component of triplet state

    corresponding to total spin 0 rather than 1.

    4 These experiments used polarized photons rather than particles with spin

    1=2, and it was the polarization of the photon that was measured, not theprojection of the spin. However, the calculation for such a measurement is

    essentially the same as that used for spin projection.

    June, 2000 Quantum mechanics: new experiments, new applications, and new formulations of old questions 587

  • particle and measurement of the second particle) is acorrelation rather than the relationship of cause and effect.Even though there is a correlation between the results ofmeasurements of the two particles, the statistics of measure-ment of a single particle bears no trace of such a correlation:the projection of the spin (onto any axis) at eachmeasurementis positive with probability 1=2 or negative with the sameprobability. The experimenter has no control over the resultsof measurements, and hence cannot send a signal to the pointwhere the other particle is located. Faster-than-light trans-mission of a signal is not feasible.

    The impossibility of faster-than-light communicationimplies that quantum nonlocality has a special correlationnature. The nonlocality of the results of measurements ariseswhen we have an EPR pair (two particles in an entangledstate). However, the creation of such a pair is a local process.The fact that preparation of quantum nonlocality is by itself alocal process will become clear in Section 2.2.1 where wediscuss quantum teleportation. Another illustration is theconsideration [20] of an EPR pair of spin particles in thegravitational field that rotates the spin of the particles. In thiscase there is no global direction in space onto which the spincould be projected. The correct description of the correlationrequires defining spacial directions at the point where one ofthe particles is found, and defining the directions at thelocation of the other particle by parallel transport along theworld lines of the particles 5.

    In experiments like those carried out by Aspect, theobjective local theory is ruled out by observations in whichthe statistics of outcomes of measurements performed on theEPR pair are measured. Greenberger, Horn and Zeilingerproposed a more sophisticated correlation experiment withthree photons (see Ref. [21]), in which the results ofmeasurements as predicted by the objective local theorydiffer more radically from the predictions of quantumtheory: for a certain measurement the objective local theorypredicts a positive result, whereas quantum mechanicspredicts a negative result (and the latter is confirmedexperimentally).

    2.2 Applications: quantum informationThe properties of entangled states and some other character-istic features of quantummechanics have found their way intonew practical applications of quantum mechanics known asquantum information [22 25]. These applications are beingdeveloped in three major categories:

    quantum teleportation, quantum cryptography, quantum computers.

    The main results in the field of quantum information areexpressed in terms of qubits (from quantum bit), a qubitbeing a system that may occur in either of two states, forexample, j0i and j1i, or in a superpositions of these states 6.Two or more qubits may occur in an entangled state.

    2.2.1 Quantum teleportation. The purpose of quantumteleportation is to transfer a certain quantum state from one

    point to another. This is accomplished with the aid of an EPRpair or, in other words, by means of quantum correlation.So far (both theoretically and experimentally) the problem ofteleportation of just one qubit has been considered.

    Let observer A (Alice) have a qubit in the state

    jciA aj0iA bj1iA ;

    where the parameters a and b are not known to the observer.Now the task is to transfer another qubit of the remoteobserver B (Bob) into the same state

    jciB aj0iB bj1iB :

    To do this, qubit B has to be in a certain way correlated that is, included into the EPR pair. For example, at point Bone may create an EPR pair of two qubits, C and B, and thenmove qubit C to the location of observer A (alternatively, anEPR pair of two qubits can be created at an arbitrary point inspace, and thenmove one qubit of the pair to A, and the otherto B). Now observer B has qubit B, and we only need to bringit into the required state. This is accomplished in three steps:

    (1) A certain specially designedmeasurement is performedon the system consisting of qubits A and C. Such ameasurement may give 4 different results.

    (2) The result of measurement is transmitted (through aconventional that is, classical communication channel)to point B.

    (3) The state of qubit B (that arises after the measurementperformed at point A) is subjected to one of four transformsdepending on the outcome of the measurement.

    It is easy to show that teleportation according to thisscheme is possible. For this, it will suffice to take the state ofEPR pair of the form

    jFiCB 12p j01iCB j10iCB 1

    2p j0iCj1iB j1iCj0iB

    and at the first step perform a measurement on qubits A andC that is described by the projectors 7

    P1 12

    j01iAC j10iACACh01j AC h10j ;P2 1

    2

    j01iAC j10iACACh01j AC h10j ;P3 1

    2

    j00iAC j11iACACh00j AC h11j ;P4 1

    2

    j00iAC j11iACACh00j AC h11j :With this selection of EPR pair and measurement, theadjusting transforms Ui to be performed at the third stepmust have the form

    U1 1 ; U2 j0ih0j j1ih1j ;U3 j0ih1j j1ih0j ; U4 ij0ih1j j1ih0j :

    If the measurement gives the ith result, the state that arisesafter the measurement is (up to a normalization coefficient)

    5Moreover, the correlation is somewhat blurred because the world lines

    of quantum particles are defined only approximately.6 Examples are the states of a particle with spin 1=2 with a definiteprojection onto a selected axis, the state of a photon with one of the two

    possible orthogonal polarizations, or the states of a two-level system with

    a definite energy.

    7 The change of state of the measured system at ith result of measurement

    is described by the action of projector Pi. The squared modulus of the

    resulting vector is the probability of ith result of measurement.

    588 M BMenski| Physics Uspekhi 43 (6)

  • PijciAjFiCB. Then it is easy to show that qubit B assumes adefinite state jciiB determined by coefficients a and b andnumber i. This state is identical to the initial state jciA only ifi 1. However, we know how to get the required state ofqubit B for arbitrary i: the state jciiB after the measurementmust be subjected to transformation Ui. Then qubit Bassumes the required state

    Ui jciiB jciB :

    Observe that qubit A after these operations does not occur inany definite state. Instead we have an entangled state ofqubits A and C.

    Thus, in the case of quantum teleportation the arbitrary(and not known in advance) state of qubit A is destroyed, butat another point qubit B assumes an identical state. Theinstrument of teleportation is the EPR pair with thecomponents at points A and B, which essentially forms aquantum correlation line. In addition to this correlation lineprepared in advance, we also need a conventional commu-nication channel between points A and B to transmitinformation about the result of measurement of qubits Aand C.

    Teleportation is carried out in three steps. At the first(preparatory) step the correlation line (EPR pair) is created.At the second step, the qubits A and C are measured. Thequantum part of information about the state jci isinstantaneously transmitted from point A to point B bymeans of quantum correlation. Reconstruction of this stateat point B, however, also requires classical information thatcan be transmitted not faster than the speed of light.

    It is true that when the result of measurement is i 1, thestate jci is teleported instantaneously, at the time ofmeasurement, and no additional adjustment is required. Butthe experimenter at point B does not know which of the fourpossible results was obtained at point A, and so at everymeasurement it is not known whether any deformation ofstate has occurred during teleportation that has to becorrected. This leads us to conclusion that faster than lightteleportation is not possible even when the correlation line isprepared in advance.

    Quantum teleportation was experimentally realized atInnsbruck University [26] with polarized photons as qubits.For more details see review [25] 8.

    2.2.2 Quantum cryptography. We saw that in the case ofteleportation of a quantum state from one point to anotherthe state of qubit at the initial point is destroyed. This is one ofthe implications of the general theorem stating the impossi-bility of cloning a quantum state. This theorem follows fromthe linear nature of quantum mechanics. Any process inquantum mechanics is described by a unitary linear opera-tor. Cloning had it been possible would have been

    described by the transform

    Ujc 0ijAi jc 0i1jc 0i2jA0i ;

    where jAi, jA0i denote the states of the apparatus before andafter cloning, respectively. Writing such equations for twodifferent states of the system jc 0i, jc 00i, and taking advantageof the linearity of operatorU, we get for the superpositions ofthese states

    Uajc 0i bjc 00ijAi

    ajc 0i1jc 0i2jA 0i bjc 00i1jc 00i2jA 00i :

    Obviously, a superposition of two (nonidentical) states jc 0i,jc 00i cannot be cloned: even when jA0i jA00i, then stateajc 0i bjc 00i becomes ajc 0i1jc 0i2 bjc 00i1jc 00i2, which isnot the same as

    ajc 0i1 bjc 00i1ajc 0i2 bjc 00i2

    :

    The impossibility of cloning a quantum state is theprinciple of quantum cryptography. A quantum crypto-graphic device sends a sequence of photons down thewaveguide, useful information being encoded in the polariza-tions of photons in the stream.Had cloning been possible, onecould penetrate into the waveguide and copy the information(create, for example, an identical sequence of photons)without altering the states of photons that fly down thewaveguide. Since cloning is impossible, however, anyattempt to get the information (intercept the message) leadsto distortion of the state of photons moving in the waveguide.Special data processing protocols use this distortion to detecteavesdropping with any desired probability.

    In this way, the specific features of quantum mechanicsallow the construction of communication channels with anydesired degree of protection against eavesdropping (for moredetails see Ref. [25]).

    2.2.3 Quantum computing. The idea of the quantum computer[22, 24] is based on the feasibility of superpositions ofquantum mechanical states. A quantum system with twobasic states (a qubit) allows the numbers 0 and 1 to beencoded in these states j0i, j1i. Accordingly, a chain of nqubits, each of which occurs in one of the two possible states,represents an n-digit binary number. Now if each qubit in thechain occurs in a superposition of basic states j0i j1i= 2p ,then the state of the entire chain of qubits may be described asa superposition of 2 n binary numbers of length n. A sequenceof unitary transforms applied to such a chain realizes a certainprocedure of processing of information (represented asbinary words), and all 2 n sets of inputs will be processed inparallel.

    This is the realization of quantum parallelism, whichallows certain calculation processes to be made much moreefficient than is possible with a classical computer. Problemsthat take an exponentially long (which means practicallyinfinite) time with a classical computer may be solved byquantum computer over a polynomially long time, which forsome practically important tasks is quite feasible 9.

    8 B B Kadomtsev and M B Kadomtsev (see, for example, Refs [27, 11])

    suggested that the Sokolov effect, as yet not explained (the polarization of

    a hydrogen atom flying along a metallic surface [28]) may be due to

    quantum correlation between the atom and the immense number of

    electrons in the surface layer of metal. This could have been another very

    interesting manifestation of entangled states; in our opinion, however, the

    authors fail to give convincing proof that the effects of EPR pairs formed

    by the atom with different electrons add up in a coherent fashion (which is

    necessary for the effect to be reasonably strong). So this matter calls for

    additional consideration. We also doubt the conclusion made in Ref. [11]

    that the Sokolov effect can be used for communication faster than light.

    9 Exponential or polynomial with respect to the length n of binary numbers

    processed.

    June, 2000 Quantum mechanics: new experiments, new applications, and new formulations of old questions 589

  • According to the above, the state of a quantum computeris a sum of an immense number of terms, each of which is aproduct of states of the form j0i or j1i (the terms in thisproduct describe the possible states of individual qubits in thelong chain). Accordingly, the state of a quantum computer isnothing else but a very complicated entangled state. After aseries of unitary transforms that rearrange this state inaccordance with the set task, the resulting state is measured,and the result of this measurement is actually the goal of thecalculation. We see that the work of a quantum computer isbased on operations with complex entangled states of a chainof qubits.

    Operations of this kind can be used, for example, forfinding the period of a periodic function, or for factorizingvery large numbers. The latter possibility is especiallyvaluable, because it would allow the easy breaking of cipherscurrently used. In principle, this can also be accomplishedwith classical computers, but takes such a long time as to betotally impractical.

    Of course, there are immense difficulties in the way ofconstructing quantum computers which operate with num-bers that are long enough. First of all, one has to ensurequantum coherence of a very large number of qubits (whichcan be represented by different physical systems forexample, atoms). This requires preventing (or makingextremely small) any uncontrollable interactions of qubitswith one another and with the environment. In Section 3.3 weshall demonstrate how interactions lead to decoherence (theloss of coherence).

    The difficulties here are so formidable that they may eventurn out to be insurmountable. For example, it may turn outthat the realization of quantum computation requires makingthe uncontrollable interactions exponentially small, which ishardly possible. So far, however, quantum computers areregarded to be feasible in principle, and considerableresources are being allocated to the solution of this task. Theidea of a quantum computer is discussed at greater length inpaper [25].

    2.3 Quantum mechanics at a new stageTo conclude the section of entangled states, let us make a fewmore remarks. The specific features of quantum mechanicsrelated to entangled states were first formulated in connectionwith the EPR paradox; today, however, they are no longerregarded as paradoxical. For the people who work profes-sionally with the quantum mechanical formalism (that is, formost physicists), there is nothing paradoxical either in EPRpairs, or in the most complicated entangled states with a largenumber of terms and a large number of factors in each term.The results of any experiments with such states, in principle,are readily interpretable (although technical difficulties in thecalculation of complex entangled states are of coursepossible).

    The disappearance of the feeling of paradoxicality isexplained by the fact that the specifics of the entangledstates, known from the early days of quantum mechanics,have been studied over the years in considerable detail. Inparticular, some features were formulated as straightforwardand clear statements or theorems, such as the impossibility ofcloning of states. Going into detail also gave rise to newapplications of quantummechanicsquantum information.

    The process of active and detailed study of the specificfeatures of quantum mechanical states and quantum mea-surements over the past two decades was obviously fostered

    by the development of new experimental capabilities, with thegreat sensitivity of todays instruments. The increasedsensitivity of measurements has brought about a situation inwhich many more experimenters have to use quantummechanics in their daily work (see, for example, Ref. [29]).This gave rise to new branches of science such as quantumoptics, for example. People working in these new fields havedeveloped useful analogies and straightforward definitions,which allow students or beginners quickly to get the hang ofquantum mechanics, to learn to find the correct approachesto the tasks typical of their particular field. The availability ofplain language facilitated the development of physicalintuition.

    Concurrently and in close connection with the process ofassimilation of quantum mechanics by a much greaternumber of physicists and engineers than ever, its oldapplications (such as superconductivity) and entirely newones (quantum information) were being developed. Day-to-day experience with quantum mechanics stripped many of itsfeatures (like the superposition of states, the entangled states)of the aura of paradoxicality.

    However, quantum mechanics still has certain aspectswhich possess some weirdness and paradoxicality, and whichfor this very reason may be the new point of growth inquantum theory. Let us discuss these aspects.

    3. Schrodingers cat

    As is known, the space of states of a quantum mechanicalsystem is linear. This means that, along with any two of itsstates jc1i, jc2i, the linear combination (superposition)c1jc1i c2jc2i with arbitrary (complex) coefficients c1, c2 isalso possible. For example, if a point particle may occur ateither of two points, it may also occur at both points at thesame time. There is nothing like that in classical mechanics.The space of states of a classical system is not a linear space. Aclassical system may occur in one of the possible states, butthere is no meaning in the sum of its states. For example, astone may occur either at one point, or at another, but not atboth points at the same time. Of course, here the points arefinite regions whose dimensions are small compared with thedistance between them.

    As applied to microscopic objects (particles or atoms), thefeasibility of superpositions of states has long ceased tosurprise anyone. Moreover, the existence of superpositionhas long been proved experimentally. A classic example is thefamous two-slit experiment the interference pattern from abeam of particles passing through two slits in an opaquescreen. On the other hand, it is hard to conceive a super-position of macroscopically distinct states of a macroscopicbody (for example, two possible locations of a stone).

    As a matter of fact, however, these two statements comeinto contradiction which arises from the possible amplifica-tion which converts a superposition of twomicrostates into asuperposition of two macrostates. Such amplification takesplace in the case of quantum measurement that is, anymeasurement applied to a quantum system.

    This contradiction or paradox was clearly expressed bySchrodinger in his mental (thought) experiment known asSchrodingers cat.

    3.1 Superposition of an alive and dead catThe decay of an unstable quantum system (for example,radioactive atom) is governed by an exponential probability

    590 M BMenski| Physics Uspekhi 43 (6)

  • law. Over a time much longer than the half-life of the isotope,the decay will occur with certainty. This means that over thistime the state jc1i, corresponding to the nondecayed atom,will go over into the state jc2i, which describes the decayedatom and the products of its decay. At any intermediate time,however, the state of unstable atom is described as asuperposition c1jc1i c2jc2i of states of the nondecayedand decayed atom (the coefficient c1 decreases with time,and c2 increases).

    This is not surprising since we are talking about amicroscopic system (atom), and superpositions of states formicroscopic systems are possible. Assume now that theproducts of decay are registered, for example, by a Geigercounter, which activates a relay that switches a macroscopicdevice. In order to dramatize the situation and add spice to hisreasoning, Schrodinger suggested placing the atom togetherwith Geiger counter into a box where there is a cat, an ampulewith cyanide, and a device that breaks this ampule. When theatom decays and the counter clicks, the device is activated andbreaks the ampule the poor cat dies. All is clear for timesmuch longer than the atoms half-life: the cat is dead. Whenthe time is close to the atoms half-life, however, the atom is ina superposition of the decayed and nondecayed state. But thismeans that the cat is a superposition of an alive and dead cat!

    So there is a contradiction between the conclusion (thenecessity of superposition) to which we arrived by logicalreasoning, and the observation that can hardly be doubted:the cat can be either alive or dead, but nobody has ever seenanything like a superposition of these two states.

    This conclusion can be reformulated or refined.Wheneverwe open the box, we see either an alive cat (and thismeans thatthe atom has not decayed) or a dead cat (whichmeans that thedecay has occurred). Before we open the box, however, thelogic of quantum mechanics makes us believe that the system(atom cat) occurs in a superposition of two states (non-decayed atom alive cat) and (decayed atom dead cat).The paradox consists in that the description of the situationdepends on whether we have opened the box to see what isinside, or not.

    3.2 Amplification of quantum superpositionAll that is placed in the box apart from the atom itself servesthe purpose of amplification that converts the superpositionof states of the microscopic system into a superposition ofstates of the macroscopic system. Such amplification occursin any quantum measurement. The mechanism of amplifica-tion consists in the formation of an entangled state whichincludes a macroscopic number of subsystems (or degrees offreedom). Let us explain this.

    Amplification involves the interaction of the quantumsystem (which occurs in the state of superposition) with othersystems (or degrees of freedom), which causes entanglement(quantum correlation) with the latter. Then the initial systemand the newly entangled systems all interact with a greaternumber of systems, bringing them into the entangled state.This goes on until there is an entangled state that involves agreat number of systems, or at least a great number of degreesof freedom. If such processes involve a sufficient number ofdegrees of freedom, then the resulting state can only beinterpreted as a superposition of macroscopically distinctstates of the macroscopic system. Let us now describe this inthe language of mathematical equations. Assume that themicroscopic (and therefore by all means quantum) system coccurs in the state of superposition c1jc1i c2jc2i. Now

    assume that this system has interacted with some othersystem a. For the given initial state ja0i of system a, theresult of interaction depends on the state of system c. We aregoing to consider only such an interaction which leads to thedistinguishing between the states jc1i and jc2i, withoutchanging these states. It is this kind of interaction that istypical of processes which may be referred to as measure-ments (in this particular case it is the measurement character-ized by projectors jc1ihc1j and jc2ihc2j). Distinguishingmeans that the final states of the system a, corresponding tothe initial states jc1i and jc2i of system c, are different. Thetransition described by this interaction may be described as

    jc1ija0i ! jc1ija1i ; jc2ija0i ! jc2ija2i :

    Here the arrow replaces the action of unitary operation thatdescribes the evolution. Then, however, by virtue of thelinearity of this operator, the initial state c1jc1i c2jc2i ofsystem c causes the transition

    c1jc1i c2jc2ija0i ! c1jc1ija1i c2jc2ija2i :

    In this way, the interaction gives rise to the entangled state ofsystems c and a.

    Assume now that the interaction involves a large numberof systems (or degrees of freedom) a; b; g; . . . ;o. The initial(measured) systemc does not necessarily interact with each ofthese systems. It may interact with just some of these systems,and the systems that have interacted with system c willsubsequently interact with the rest (and with one another).What is important is that in some way or other theinformation about the system c will be recorded in the statesof all the other systems involved. As before, we assume thatthe state of system c does not change, and the states of allother systems depend on this state in such a way that theymake a distinction between the states jc1i and jc2i. Thismeans that the interaction causes the transition

    jc1i ja0ijb0ijg0i . . . jo0i ! jc1i ja1ijb1ijg1i . . . jo1i ;

    jc2i ja0ijb0ijg0i . . . jo0i ! jc2i ja2ijb2ijg2i . . . jo2i :

    Then, owing to the linearity of the operator of evolution, thesuperposition of states jc1i and jc2i of system c causes thetransitionc1jc1i c2jc2i

    ja0ijb0ijg0i . . . jo0i! c1jc1i ja1ijb1ijg1i . . . jo1i c2jc2i ja2ijb2ijg2i . . . jo2i c1jc1i jA1i c2jc2i jA2i : 3

    If the number of systems that take part in the interaction ismacroscopically large, then there is entanglement of system cwith the macroscopic system A, and we have a superpositionof two distinct states of the macroscopic system. The statesthat make up the superposition are macroscopically distinctin the sense that the great number of degrees of freedom inthem are described by different wave functions. Thus arisesthe superposition of macroscopically distinct states of themacroscopic system. Such is the mechanism of amplificationreferred to above.

    In this way, following the conventional guidelines ofquantum mechanics, we come to the conclusion that super-positions should exist for arbitrarily large systems (which

    June, 2000 Quantum mechanics: new experiments, new applications, and new formulations of old questions 591

  • have arbitrarily many degrees of freedom). Naturally, thequestion arises whether it might be possible to create andobserve superpositions of distinct states of macroscopicsystems. Sometimes this task is formulated as the creationand observation of Schrodinger cats.

    Obviously, what precisely is a macroscopic system is notan easy question, nor what is classical behavior [9, 30 32]. Inany case, however, one can try creating superpositions forsystems consisting of an increasing number of particles. Thedifficulty in the experimental realization of this program isthat the system must be very carefully insulated otherwisethe superposition will be quickly transformed into a mixturebecause of decoherence (see below). For mesoscopic systemscontaining several particles this task has been solved [33, 34].It has been proved experimentally that quantum mechanicsapplies not only to microscopic systems but also to meso-scopic systems.

    It is possible to create superpositions in systems with amuch greater number of particles. For example, the Joseph-son effect is used for setting up conditions in a superconduct-ing ring that (according to the laws of quantum mechanics)create superposition of two currents flowing in oppositedirections, each carrying about 1015 electrons. Such experi-ments agree with the predictions of quantum mechanics, butas yet none of them has given a direct proof of the existence ofsuperposition: the results can be interpreted in terms of themacrorealistic theory, in which there is no superposition butonly one current, and it is not known precisely which of them.It is quite possible that direct proof will soon be obtained inmore accurate experiments.

    3.3 Decoherence by the environmentWe saw that the amplification of quantum superpositionleads to a paradox: quantum mechanics logically brings usto the conclusion that superpositions of macroscopicallydistinct states ought to exist, but nobody has ever observedsuch states. Let us once again bring up the example ofSchrodingers cat: as long as the box is closed, we can onlyguess what is in there; if we trust quantum mechanics, wecome to the conclusion that there is a superposition of an aliveand dead cat. When we open the box, however, the cat iseither dead or alive and nothing else.

    This situation is seen as a paradox that calls forexplanation (resolution). An attempt at explanation, datingback to Heisenberg and gaining recognition in the scientificcommunity today, is based on the concept of decoherence.

    Decoherence of a quantum system occurs every time itsstate gets entangled with the state of its environment, so thatthe information about the state of the system is recorded inthe state of its environment. Let us consider, for example,process (3) which transfers the initial factorized state of thesystem and its environment into the entangled state

    jCi c1jc1ijA1i c2jc2ijA2i :

    This is a pure state, and therefore it can be described by thevector of state (wave function). However, we can also expressit in terms of the density matrix:

    R jCihCj :

    If we are only interested in the state of the system c (and notits environment A), we can describe this state by the so-calledreduced density matrix, which equals the trace of matrix R

    with respect to the degrees of freedom of the environment:

    r trAR jc1j2jc1ihc1j jc2j2jc2ihc2j c1c2hA2jA1ijc1ihc2j c2c1hA1jA2ijc2ihc1j : 4

    States jA1i and jA2i are macroscopically distinct theydiffer from one another in the immense number of degrees offreedom. In the notation of Eqn (3), ja1i differs from ja2i, jb1idiffers from jb2i, etc. Because of this, the scalar productsha1ja2i; hb1jb2i; . . . are each less than one inmagnitude. So theproduct of all these numbers hA1jA2i is practically zero, andthe cross terms in Eqn (4) vanish.

    The state of system c, therefore, is described by thedensity matrix

    r jc1j2jc1ihc1j jc2j2jc2ihc2j : 5This is a mixed state that can be interpreted as follows: thesystem occurs with probability jc1j2 in the state jc1i, and withprobability jc2j2 in the state jc2i. This is exactly what ought tobe expected after the measurement (at least for the simplesttype of measurement described by von Neumanns reductionpostulate). Emergence of the mixed state (5) is calleddecoherence. Decoherence is associated with the loss ofinformation about the relative phase of coefficients c1, c2.There is extensive literature on decoherence. Importantworksin this field are Refs [30, 35 41]. The physical nature ofdecoherence is discussed in great detail and from differentstandpoints in the books [9, 11], where the readerwill also finda comprehensive bibliography. A review of various phenom-enological approaches to the description of the process ofdecoherence can be found in Refs [42, 43].

    Two types of mixed states sometimes are distinguishedthat have similar density matrices: (1) propermixed states of aclosed system that arise when it is not known exactly in whichof the pure states the system occurs, and (2) improper mixedstates that are, like in our present case, associated withreduction that is, arising upon transition from a closedsystem to its subsystem. If such a distinction is made, then it isoften maintained that it is not correct to interpret impropermixtures in terms of incomplete knowledge, as is done forproper mixtures. Such a distinction, however, only makessense when it is possible to control experimentally not onlythe system itself, but also its environment (or, in case of aclosed system, to make sure that the system is closed). Onecannot think of an experiment confined to the limits of asystem occurring in a mixed state that would be capable ofverifying whether the system is closed (so mixture thencorresponds to incomplete knowledge) or open (so themixture is a consequence of the entanglement of the systemwith the environment). The impossibility of experimentaldistinction between these two cases follows directly from thefact that the predictions of all experiments feasible in a givensystem are expressed in terms of the density matrix of thissystem.

    It is important for us now that because of entanglementwith the environment the system goes from the pure initialstate into a mixed state. The superposition of states of thesystem vanishes (or at least cannot be observed) if we confineourselves to experiments on the system alone, withouttouching its environment A. Another thing is also true: if thestates jc1i and jc2i are orthogonal, then after entanglementof the system with its environment not only the system butalso the environment are not in the state of superposition, butrather in a mixed state.

    592 M BMenski| Physics Uspekhi 43 (6)

  • Applying this to the case of Schrodingers cat, we can nowdescribe the situation somewhat more accurately. Quantummechanics predicts that the composite system (atom cat)occurs in the superposition of two factorized states: (non-decayed atom alive cat) and (decayed atom dead cat). Ifwe are only interested in the atom, we can only say that itoccurs in a mixed state that is, it has not yet decayed withprobability jc1j2, and already has decayed with probabilityjc2j2. Similarly, with regard to the cat alone (forgetting theatom) we can say that it occurs in a mixed state: alive withprobability jc1j2, and dead with probability jc2j2. In any case,there are no experiments which could be performed on the catwithout touching the atom that could demonstrate that theactual underlying cause of the probability distributionjc1j2; jc2j2 is the superposition, and not just incompleteknowledge about the actual state of the cat (alive or dead).

    If the experiments are performed on the complete system(which in our case would include both the atom and the cat),then it is in principle possible to distinguish superpositionfrom mixture: superposition produces certain interferencepatterns that are absent in the case of mixture. This is ofcourse true, but one has to bear in mind that these effects willbe observed only when all the degrees of freedom of themacroscopic system (the cat) are taken into account. In anycase, only a small fraction of the degrees of freedom can be leftbeyond the control of the measuring system, otherwise it willbe not possible to distinguish between superposition andmixture.

    This can be seen from model (3). If the states of some ofthe degrees of freedom c; a; b; g; . . . ;o are left out, then todescribe the state of the remaining degrees of freedom onemust calculate the reduced densitymatrix for them, taking thetrace for all degrees of freedom that are not observed. Thenthe cross (interference) terms in this density matrix willcontain scalar products related to the degrees of freedomexcluded from observation. Each of these scalar products isless than one by modulus, and if they are numerous enough,the interference terms disappear and superposition cannot bedistinguished frommixture.Moreover, even if just one degreeof freedom (say, o) is left out, and the scalar product ho1jo2ifor it is zero, superposition cannot be distinguished frommixture. When the number of degrees of freedom is macro-scopic, it is of course impossible in the experiment to controlall the degrees of freedom without exception. Accordingly,decoherence in macroscopic systems seems inevitable for allpractical purposes.

    So, the solution of the paradox of Schrodingers cat (theimpossibility of observing superpositions of macroscopicallydistinct states predicted by quantum mechanics) may run asfollows. Even if a certain system occurs in a state described bya superposition, and then this state becomes entangled withthe state of the environment in such a way that recorded in theenvironment is information that allows distinguishing thecomponents of superposition, the state of the system is subjectto decoherence. This means that the state becomes a mixture(not a superposition) of the same components, and there areno experiments on the system (not touching the environmentthat had brought about the decoherence) that can tell uswhether the mixture results from a superposition, or fromincomplete knowledge about which of the componentsactually exists. The consequence of decoherence is that thepredictions of quantum theory for macroscopic states cannotbe distinguished from the predictions of macrorealistictheory, unless literally all the degrees of freedom are

    controlled. Obviously, the number of components in super-position and in mixture is arbitrary the case of twocomponents has been considered here only for the sake ofsimplicity.

    We see that the phenomenon of decoherence is veryimportant from a conceptual standpoint. This phenomenonmust also be taken into account if the effects of theenvironment on the dynamics of the system under considera-tion are not negligibly small that is, if the system is open.because of this, much attention is paid to the study ofdecoherence. The role of decoherence in quantum measure-ments has been studied not only theoretically but alsoexperimentally. Especially interesting are the experimentsstaged at Ecole Normale Superieure in Paris [44]. Thecomponents of superposition were represented by the statesof the electromagnetic field in a superconducting resonator,close to the coherent states.

    The coherent state is a state ultimately close to a certainmode of classical electromagnetic field 10, and it involves alarge number of photons. The states close to two modes thatdiffered in phase were taken for the experiment. Since therewere only a few photons in the cavity, the states under studywere not precisely coherent, but had similar properties.Because the number of photons was not large, it was possibleto form a superposition of two modes with different phases (amesoscopic Schrodingers cat). Dissipation in the super-conducting cavity is small, and the superposition persistedfor a long timeduring this time there was no uncontrollabledecoherence. Instead, slow controlled decoherence wasintroduced into the system. For this end atoms were passedone after another through the cavity, where they interactedwith photons and caused decoherence. This gave rise to anentangled state of photons and atoms, and information aboutthe phase of electromagnetic field was written in the states ofatoms. As a result, the superposition of modes of theelectromagnetic field with two different phases graduallyturned into a mixture (the process of decoherence).

    In this way, the process of decoherence associated withquantum measurement has been realized and studied in amesoscopic system. In other words, decoherence has not onlybeen predicted theoretically, but has also been observed inexperiment. It goes without saying that decoherence lifts theveil of mystery from quantum measurement. But does itcompletely solve the problem of measurement in quantummechanics? Some physicists still have doubts. Attempts tosolve this problem in a more radical way lead to veryinteresting developments of quantum theory.

    4. Extension of the theory of measurement

    In this section we consider some variants of quantum theoryof measurement that go beyond the framework of the theoryof decoherence; we start, however, with a discussion of theadvantages and drawbacks of this theory.

    4.1 Does decoherence solve the problem of measurement?From a practical standpoint, decoherence completelyexplains the process of measurement, and how the measure-

    10 To avoid confusion, please note that the word coherent in coherent

    state refers to the existence of a definite phase of the classical wave

    process. In all previous cases this word had a different meaning, referring

    to the existence of a certain relative phase between different components in

    the quantum superposition.

    June, 2000 Quantum mechanics: new experiments, new applications, and new formulations of old questions 593

  • ment leads to a mixed state that is equivalent to theprobability distribution with respect to various pure statescorresponding to the alternative results of measurement.Interpretation is given in the framework of quantummechanics of the closed system; at the last stage, however,the treatment is limited to a certain subsystem, and averagingis carried out with respect to degrees of freedomwhich are leftout of this subsystem. It is this averaging that leads to amixedstate. If instead of a subsystem we consider the entire closedsystem, we have superposition in place ofmixturewhich, aswe have demonstrated, leads to the paradox of Schrodingerscat.

    Thus, the interpretation of quantum measurement interms of decoherence may be regarded as quite adequate aslong aswe agree to consider only open systems, and never dealwith closed systems. As a matter of fact, there is nothingunnatural in such a convention.What is more, it is quite in thespirit of physics: in physics we are taught to ask only thosequestions that can be answered by observation (measure-ment), and measurement is not capable of controlling each ofthe macroscopic number of degrees of freedom.

    If the measurement is described in terms of an opensystem, this system can be as broad as desired, but there stillhave to be some degrees of freedom outside in whichinformation about the result of measurement will berecorded in one way or another. This condition is character-istic of quantum measurement, and corresponds to the wellknown arbitrariness in dividing the entire Universe into themeasured system and themeasuring instrument. Onemay callthe instrument everything except the system that is beingmeasured; or onemay include some part of the apparatus intothe measured system, calling the measuring device only therecorder (needle); or else the needle can also be consideredpart of themeasured system, then themeasuring device beginswith the photons entering the eye of the observer, etc. Themeasured system can be made broader and broader, butsomething must always be left out that carries informationabout the state of themeasured system. Since the observer, hisbrain, the mechanisms of memory etc. are usually notincluded into consideration with the framework of physics,we come to the conclusion that all proper physical questionscan be formulated and solved within the framework of thetheory of open systems using the mechanism of decoherence.As we have found out, the conceptual issues of quantummechanics receive adequate treatment in the context of suchan approach.

    This approach is actively being developed in particular inthe direction of description of more and more complicatedmeasurements. Also considered are continuous (prolonged intime) quantum measurements. The problems associated withthis approach are more technical than conceptual. The effortsare aimed at the construction of a consistent theory of open(measured) systems (see, for example, the review [42] and thebook [43]). One may distinguish two essentially differentlevels of description of such systems: nonselective andselective. The nonselective description takes into account allpossible results of measurement, each of which is associatedwith a certain probability. The behavior of the measuredsystem is then described by a density matrix which containsboth the alternative pure states and the distribution ofprobabilities with respect to these states. In the case ofselective description the task is formulated differently: howdoes the system behave when the measurement yields oneoutcome out of all possible results? In this case the behavior of

    the system is described by the vector of state (the wavefunction) which depends on the result of measurement.Obviously, for a one-time measurement (which is the kind ofmeasurement considered so far) the difference between thesetwo descriptions is not large. If, however, the measurement isrepeated many times, and we want to follow the change in thestate of the system caused by this series of measurements,these two approaches are technically much different (whilethe physical content of the process naturally remains thesame). This is even more true in case of continuousmeasurement.

    So, the theory of open systems permits the description ofquantum measurements without running into conceptualdifficulties. For some people, however, this is not enough,and they want to go further and improve the quantum theory.Motives differ: some believe that of first importance is thetheory of closed systems, whereas open systems only ought tobe regarded as subsystems of the closed ones. Others areworried by the fact that improper mixtures cannot beinterpreted in terms of incomplete knowledge (as done inSection 3.3), and so they are not convinced by the argumentsupposed to prove the indistinguishability of superpositionsand mixtures in the case of decoherence. As a matter of fact,this reasoning implies that the researcher is not content withthe description of an open system, and wants the descriptionto include the environment (where the answer to the questionwhether the mixture is proper or improper lies). This alsoassumes a description in terms of a closed system.

    In our opinion, the most stimulating motive for goingfurther than the theory of decoherence is the following: thetheory of decoherence adequately explains the existence ofdifferent alternative results of measurement, each with itsown probability, but it is desirable to have a theory thatexplains how one of these alternatives is selected.

    4.2 Attempts to advance the theoryThe most straightforward attempt to advance the theory ofquantum measurements is the hypothesis of spontaneousdecoherence [45]. In this theory the Schrodinger equation ismodified by the inclusion of a stochastic term that accountsfor spontaneous decoherence. In other words, decoherenceaccording to this theory is not caused by interaction betweenthe system and its environment, but occurs spontaneouslyfrom time to time without any external influence. This raisesdecoherence to the rank of a fundamental law of nature. Theparameters of the modified Schrodinger equation areadjusted so that on the microscopic level its predictionscoincide with the predictions of quantum mechanics, butthere are no superpositions of macroscopically distinct stateson themacroscopic level.With fixed parameters such a theorycan always be experimentally verified, and the proposedvariants are most likely to be checked experimentally in thenext few years. On the other hand, if a checkwith the accuracyavailable today gives a negative result, one can still keep thetheory and readjust the parameters.

    Other theories supposed to be more advanced thanconventional quantum mechanics include

    the quantum mechanics of David Bohm, the theory of consistent quantum histories, the many-worlds interpretation of quantum

    mechanics.In Bohms quantum mechanics, the wave function of the

    particle is supplemented with its path. By assumption, themotion of the particle may be regarded as a motion along a

    594 M BMenski| Physics Uspekhi 43 (6)

  • path, but the statistics of paths is derived from theSchrodinger equation. Thus, the predictions of the theorycoincide with the predictions of conventional quantummechanics. In a sense, Bohms theory differs from theprobabilistic formulation of quantum mechanics mostlyterminologically, but such distinctions are often importantin various interpretations and generalizations of quantummechanics.

    The theory of consistent histories [47 49] is based on thepicture of evolution of a quantum system resemblingFeynmans path integral. According to Feynman, theamplitude of propagation is represented as the sum (inte-gral) of amplitudes corresponding to different paths leadingfrom the starting point to the end point. In the theory ofconsistent histories, the total amplitude is represented as asum of amplitudes corresponding to different quantumhistories. Each history (simplifying a little) can be repre-sented as a bunch of Feynman paths. Then the question iswhat are the conditions under which this bunch of paths(quantum history) can be correctly associated not only withthe amplitude of probability, but with the probability itself. Itturns out that this can be done when the bunch of paths isbroad enough. In other words, the condition can beformulated for consistent introduction of probabilities. Suchsufficiently broad bunches of paths (histories) may beconsidered as describing classical motion.

    The theory of consistent histories therefore shows howthe classical evolution emerges from the purely quantumdescription of the system. In this case the quantum system isassumed to be closed. If we use this theory for describing themeasurement, then the treatment includes both the measuredsystem and the measuring device. The theory of consistenthistories allows the necessary condition of appearance ofclassical features to be formulated: it is the condition ofconsistency of histories (in Ref. [50] this condition is provedto be not sufficient). This theory, however, is also confined tothe listing of alternative classical options of evolution alongwith the associated probabilities. Such a theory does notdescribe the mechanism of selection of one of the availablealternatives. So the problem formulated at the end of Section4.1 is not solved in the theory of consistent histories.

    The most radical advancement of the theory is the many-worlds interpretation of quantum mechanics, proposed byEverett and developed by Wheeler [51, 52], and sometimesreferred to as the Everett Wheeler interpretation. Thisapproach considers the closed system that includes themeasured subsystem, the measuring device, the observer in short, all the Universe, the whole world. Accordingly, thereis no decoherence, and there is nothing to transform thesuperposition of alternative pure states into a mixture.According to Everett, each component of the superpositiondescribes the entire world, and none is privileged before therest. There are as many worlds as alternative results of themeasurement in question. Each of these worlds contains themeasured system, the measuring device, the observer. Thestate of the system, the state of the device, the state of mind ofthe observer in each of these worlds correspond to oneparticular result of measurement, but in different worlds theresults of measurement are different.

    Nowwhile in the theory of decoherence different results ofmeasurement are possible, but only one is realized (withappropriate probability), in Everetts interpretation allpossible results of measurement are real, but they are realizedin different worlds. Observe that in Everetts interpretation

    the problem of selection of the result still exists, but in adifferent formulation. The question which of the results isrealized is not pertinent, because all results are equally real.Instead, the question is in which of Everetts worlds theobserver finds himself.

    According to a metaphor proposed by Wheeler, at thetime of quantum measurement the observer faces a kind ofrailway switch, and his train may choose one of severaldirections. Depending on the direction selected by the train,the observer will see one or other result of measurement. Thepossible directions of the train correspond to the alternativeresults of measurements, or to different Everett worlds. Thetrain will go in one particular direction, but the rest areequally real, and the measurement yields there differentresults.

    4.3 Quantum mechanics and consciousnessSo, in the Everett Wheeler interpretation the difficult issueabout the selection of one from many alternative results ofmeasurement is at least treated from a different standpoint.Let us try to see whether it could be possible to go further inthe solution of this problem.

    Let us first recall the conclusion at which we arrivedearlier regarding the theory of open measured systems. Thetheory of open systems may be represented by the followingdiagram:

    This diagram means that the impact of environment on thesystem is taken into account, although a concretemodel of theenvironment is not included in the description. We saw thatsuch theory

    is complete from the standpoint of physics, because itmay include any part of the Universe with the possibleexception of certain structures deep inside the brain in whichinformation about the result of measurement is recorded;

    does not contain paradoxes (it leads to mixed states,not superpositions);

    can describe the selection of alternative result ofmeasurement only phenomenologically; the mechanism ofselection is left out of consideration.The phenomenological description of selection can beformalized in the case of instantaneous (infinitesimallyshort) measurement by von Neumanns reduction postulate,and in the case of continuous measurement by the restrictedpath integral or imaginary potential [42, 43].

    Such a description of selection is certainly good for allpractical purposes. From the conceptual standpoint, how-ever, the phenomenological description of selection is theweak point of the theory of open systems, which calls for thedevelopment of a more complete or more fundamentaltheory. Apparently this theory must be based on thetreatment of closed systems, as represented by the diagram

    (the model of the environment is explicitly included in theconsideration).

    As we have already had a chance to see, this theory leadsto superpositions of macroscopically distinct states (theparadox of Schrodingers cat), since it does not contain the

    System $

    System $ Environment

    June, 2000 Quantum mechanics: new experiments, new applications, and new formulations of old questions 595

  • mechanism of decoherence. In addition, seeking to describethe measurement in terms of a closed system, we spread thelimits of the system under consideration, so that eventually itwill include observers sense organs and those structures in hisbrain that are responsible for receiving information about theresult of measurement.

    If even one such structure is left out of what we considerthe measured system, then (1) decoherence arises, whichrelieves us from the paradoxical superposition of distinctstates, but (2) the selection of one of the alternatives isdescribed only phenomenologically, without referring to itsmechanism.

    If we include in the system under consideration all degreesof freedom that could carry information about the alter-natives (go over to the closed system), then there is nodecoherence, and thus (1) superpositions remains, and (2) asbefore, nothing is said about the mechanism of selection ofone of the alternatives (in this case, one component of thesuperposition).

    Can it be then that the selection does not occur anywhereat all? This is what is assumed in Everetts interpretation: allalternatives are equally real. There is, however, one circum-stance which tells us that the selection is actually made: everyexperimenter in a real experiment deals with just onealternative. Opening the box with Schrodingers cat, anyexperimenter will see the cat either alive or dead.

    Thus, trying to stay within the framework of physicalconventions, we always deal with the entire set of alternatives,but when the process is described from the standpoint ofconsciousness of one particular observer, we only deal withone alternative. It looks like we have to make a conclusionvery hard to accept for a physicist: a theory that would describenot only the set of alternative results of measurement and theassociated probability distribution, but also the mechanism ofselection of one particular result, ought to include the mind(consciousness) of the observer.

    In various forms the idea of including the observer andeven the mind into the theory was expressed from the earlydays of quantummechanics. For example, Pauli thought thatway [53]. Wigners paper [54] contains an even strongerstatement: not only the consciousness must be included intothe theory, but the mind can affect the reality. A similar ideawas expressed by Schrodinger in the conclusion to his bookWhat is life? [55]. Later we shall return to this bizarre idea ofthe mind affecting the reality. Here we just mention that therole of the mind in the interpretation of quantum mechanicshas been much discussed lately (see, for example, Refs [7, 8 10, 15].

    4.4 Selection of an alternative is this the work of theconsciousness?Is there anything to add to what has already been saidregarding the role of the mind in quantum measurement?We propose making one more step, seemingly small but, inour opinion, highly consequential.

    As already indicated, we cannot describe the mechanismof selection of one alternative if we remain within theframework of physical conventions. This is an unsolvedproblem. From the arguments developed above one mightconclude that the solution of this problem could be sought byincluding the mind of the observer in the consideration. Onthe other hand, although psychologists have long beenstudying the works of human mind, nobody has yet given asatisfactory definition of consciousness or its mechanism. The

    function of the consciousness remains mysterious andobscure. This also is an unsolved problem.

    Sowe have two unsolved problems: (1) the selection of onealternative in the case of quantum measurement, and (2) thefunctioning of the consciousness. We know cases in thehistory of science when two formidable problems were solvedsimultaneously, as though helping to solve one another. It isquite possible that currently we are also dealing with a pair ofdeeply interconnected problems.

    Based on this, we put forward the following hypothesis:The function of consciousness consists in selecting one of thealternative results of quantum measurement. In terms ofEveretts many-worlds interpretation, this statement willsound somewhat different: the function of consciousnessconsists in selecting one of the alternative Everett worlds 11.To the question what is consciousness{ we answer that it isthe selection of alternatives in the case of quantum measure-ment. Only after the selection has been made do we get adefinite picture of what is going on, described in the languageof classical physics (for example, only after the selection doesthe needle of the instrument assume definite position). Beforethe selection, there is only the quantum pattern with itsnumerous alternatives. One can say that only the selectionof an alternative determines what takes place in reality. Butafter all, this is what is understood by consciousness: it isconsciousness that tells us what takes place in reality. In thisway, the hypothesis that identifies consciousness withquantum selection is in agreement with our intuition.

    This hypothesis is close to the ideas of Squires [7]. Hebelieved that consciousness is like a window opening into thequantumworld. It does not allow the entire quantumworld tobe seen, only a fragment of it (corresponding to one of thealternative results of quantum measurement or one ofEveretts worlds).

    Let us underline, nevertheless some distinctions of ourhypothesis from what has been discussed in the literature sofar. Many authors told that the explanation of quantummeasurement must in one way or another involve the mind ofthe observer. We believe that the function of mind (con-sciousness) by itself is one of the stages of quantummeasurement the selection of the alternative. Accord-ingly, there is no need to include consciousness in the theoryof measurement it is already included. We only need toidentify one of the elements of the theory ofmeasurement (theselection of the alternative) with something known in adifferent theory as consciousness (the work of consciousness).

    We anticipate one objection to this hypothesis. If thefunction of mind consists in the selection of one of the resultsof measurement, why then are the results selected withdifferent probabilities, precisely those predicted by quantummechanics? Everetts theory provides a simple and elegantanswer to this question. It is demonstrated that some amongthe multitude of parallel worlds are identical to each other(which means that their respective subsystems are in the same

    11 If we accept this hypothesis, the work of the mind is technically

    described by the restricted path integral or the imaginary potential, since

    these are the tools for describing a continuous measurement provided that

    one definite result of this measurement is selected [42, 43].

    {The Russian word osoznanie as used by the author seems not to have astraightforward equivalent in the English language. Generally, it means

    the result of the work of the consciousness, conscious knowledge or

    recognition acceptance of the validity or reality of something, aware-

    ness, understanding, comprehension. We translate it as conscious-

    ness, or sometime, in the loose context, as mind. (Translators note.)

    596 M BMenski| Physics Uspekhi 43 (6)

  • state), and a world of a certain type occurs more frequently,the higher the quantum mechanical probability of thecorresponding alternative. In other words, if N is the totalnumber of Everett worlds, and Ni is the number of worldscorresponding to the ith alternative, then pi Ni=N is thequantum mechanical probability of this alternative (for largeN).

    Thus, if the function of mind consists in the selection ofone of the alternative worlds, and this selection is made atrandom (that is, any of the worlds is selected with equalprobability), then the ith alternative result of measurementwill be selected with probability pi.

    This argument strengthens our hypothesis that identifiesthe function of mind with the selection of the Everett world.We can now respond to the famous remark of Einstein in hisdialogue with Bohr. Referring to the probabilistic interpreta-tion of quantummechanics, Einstein said, God does not playdice. Based on our hypothesis, we may answer that yes, Goddoes not play dice, He equally accepts all possibilities. It is themind of each observer that plays dice.

    Starting from our hypothesis, we note that there is just asmall step to the idea of Wigner [54] that the mind can affectreality. Indeed, if usually the mind selects one of Everettsworlds at random, by chance, then why cannot we assumethat there is a mind (so talented or specially trained) that canmake this selection with a purpose. In this case the selectioncan be predeterminedor at least the probability of selectinga particular option can be increased by effort of the will{. Inthe context of Wheelers metaphor, the observer endowedwith such an active mind can deliberately shift the switchand send the train along the desired track or at leastincrease the probability of the train taking the desired track.

    This of course is not a proof but pure speculation,although the conclusion seems to follow naturally fromarguments developed above. At the same time, it is not easyto agree with these conclusions. Let us try to refute twopossible objections. At first glance it seems that the hypoth-esis of the effect of consciousness on the selection of analternative (let us call it the hypothesis of the active mind)leads to (1) inconsistency between observations of differentobservers, and (2) possible violation of the laws of nature.However, this is not so, or not quite so.

    As it may seem, if the outcome of measurement to someextent depends on the observer, then two different observersof one and the same measurement may see different results.For example, the leader of an experimental group and hisassistant will look at the instrument and see different readingsbecause the leader wants them to be high, and the assistantwants them to be low (they probably stick to differenttheories, and each wants his theory to win). Of course, this isnever observed in practice, which casts a shadow over thetheory of active mind. More careful analysis shows, however,that the hypothesis of active mind does not imply any suchinconsistency.

    Let us turn to our model (3). Here the state of the leader(his mind ) and the state of assistant are described by differentfactors (or groups of factors) in each term. Assume that theyare factors a and b. It is obvious that these factors are either inthe state ja1ijb1i, or in the state ja2ijb2i. The readings of thedevice seen by both colleagues are always in agreement with

    each other. If one observer uses the power of his will toincrease the probability of getting into a certain Everettworld, in the same world he will find all other people whichhave access to information about the reading (or its implica-tions).

    In this example, assuming that both the leader and theassistant have active minds, the leader will most likely see thehigh reading (and will show this to his assistant, whowill haveto agree); conversely, the assistant will see a low reading andwill demonstrate this to his boss. The leader and the assistantwill shift the switch to different tracks, and each in his mindseye will see different Everetts worlds, but each of these worldswill be internally consistent. Of course, this arbitrariness withoperation of the switch shakes ones faith in the objectivity ofscience and we shall discuss this shortly.

    The second possible objection is the following. At firstglance it seems that if one can exercise ones will to get into apreferred Everetts world, then this feat will also change theprobabilities of different outcomes of measurement that is,the predictions of quantum mechanics are wrong, and thelaws of nature do not work. The first answer is that you canonly get into such an Everetts world that already exists andcan always be reached in the ordinary way, when theconsciousness selects one of the worlds at random. Accord-ingly, if a certain person has the ability to select a certainoutcome of measurement at his discretion, this can always beattributed to chance: such a likelihood always exists, howeversmall. On the other hand, such a person will be able toperform his feats over and over again. Each time his successcan be explained by mere chance, but if this happens toooften, the probability of chance occurrence may become quitesmall. Nevertheless, it will be impossible to prove withcertainty that this is not a mere coincidence.

    Moreover, the appearance that some person can repeat-edly produce an unlikely event (work amiracle) only occurs inthe mind of the miracle-worker himself (owing to the fact thathis mind can purposefully select an Everetts world). And it isonly in his mind that other observers are witnesses of hisrepeated success, and become convinced in his talent. If we tryto see how the same event looks in the eyes of anotherobserver with an ordinary mind, we find that in most caseshe will see that the event promised by themiracle-worker doesnot come true. After all, his mind selects an Everett world atrandom, and will most likely end up in such a world wheresuch an unlikely event does not happen. The conclusion isthat the laws of nature can be violated in the individualexperience of some people (endowedwith an activemind), butpeople with ordinary minds, using the techniques of statistics,will not confirm this.

    Let us look at this situation from a somewhat differentstandpoint. Assume that the man who is able to increase ordecrease at will the probability of getting into some Everettworld or other is an experimental scientist (like in the aboveexample). If this is possible, then the objectivity of scientificresearch is at stake. How can a result be objective if thescientist can affect it, and get eventually whatever he wants?The answer to this catch is already contained in our previousargument, but we shall repeat it in a slightly differentformulation. If our observer has an active mind, then he is akind ofmiracle-worker, and his results may run counter to thepredictions of quantum mechanics. As already indicated,however, the miracle (that is, the realization of the desiredresult) only occurs in his own mind. Even he himself canattribute this miracle to a fluke, because the result is admitted

    { This hypothesis is correct is the number of Everette worldsN is infinite.(Authors note to the English edition.)

    June, 2000 Quantum mechanics: new experiments, new applications, and new formulations of old questions 597

  • by quantum mechanics, even though with small probability.Finally, any other observer, who does not have an activemindand selects an Everett world at random, will as a rule end up insuch a world where the result of the experiment correspondsto themost probable of the alternatives predicted by quantummechanics (and in which themiracle-worker flunks). Personalexperience of any individual with a passive mind will alwaysconfirm the conventional probabilistic quantum mechanicalpredictions, and all miracle-workers will be dismayed.

    To make this last conclusion more clear, let us put it asfollows. While the miracle-worker is working alone in hislaboratory, with a high probability he gets the desired result,while the probability of the result which is most likely fromthe standpoint of quantum mechanics is low. Eventually theresult is published and becomes available for many readers.Consider any of these readers who does not have an activemind (or even has an active mind but is not keen on obtainingany particular result of this experiment). What is the resultthat he finds in the publication? The answer is obvious. Hismind will occur in one or other Everett world in accordancewith the conventional quantum mechanical distribution ofprobabilities. Accordingly, in the publication this person willmost likely see the result that is most probable according toquantum mechanics. So even if the miracle-worker favoredthe result associated with a low quantum mechanicalprobability, the audience of the journal, made up of ordinarypeople, will find in the publication the result that is mostprobable.

    The final conclusion may be formulated as follows. Evenif we accept the hypothesis of active mind, the objectivity ofscientific results is guaranteed by the fact that each finding ispublished and used by a large number of scientists that haveno active mind and no opportunity to affect the selection ofquantum mechanical alternative. This makes the