juristic origins of social contract theory

Upload: baris-basaran

Post on 05-Apr-2018

219 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/31/2019 Juristic Origins of Social Contract Theory

    1/4

    THE JURISTIC ORIGINS OF SOCIAL CONTRACT THEORY Antony Black This article seeks to

    explain the rise ofsocial contract as a way of thinking about government.

    1 By social contract I mean the view that human authorities are established by agreement with their

    subjects for specific tasks, that their legitimacy depends upon fulfilment of these tasks, and that such

    agreements may be enforced by clear, defined procedures, as one would enforce a contract in private

    law. Contracts, it may be noted, are a specific type of oath or promise in that by their naturethey are conditional: the performance of A by x is made conditional upon the performance of B

    by y. Contract became a characteristic way of justifying political actions, in particular resistance to

    superior authority, in later sixteenth-century Netherlands and France.

    From the seventeenth cen- tury onwards it played an important part in the way political authorities in

    general were defined and justified, and their powers in many cases delimited. It has proved to be one

    of the ideas from that time whose vitality is still evident today. We need to consider here both the

    development of elaborate argument by theorists, and the diffusion of a general contractarian ideology

    amongst the political classes of the time. Both this popular diffusion and the philosophical elaboration

    coincided with the further and decisive secularization of political argument in the early modern

    period; they were one of the principal means by which this took place.

    It is important, therefore, to identify as clearly as possible the way these ideas developed, including

    their origins.

    At present several causal explanations for the rise of contractarianism are on offer:

    first, that the political contract was implicit in feudal relationships between the king as lord and

    the barons as vassals. 2 It must be conceded that feudal arrangements provided a mental milieu

    and set of precedents by which conditional contracts between rulers and subjects could be

    justified. But, if this can form part of an explanation, it cannot stand on its own. Coronation oaths and

    feudal homage constituted specific acts between specific individuals, and were practised for centuries

    without ever being elaborated into a general theory about the role and scope of government. If feudal

    relationships themselves HISTORY OF POLITICAL THOUGHT. Vol. XIV. No. 1. Spring 1993 1 I

    would like to thank Martin van Gelderen for his numerous suggestions on passages relating to the

    Netherlands, and two readers for History of Political Thought for their patient comments. 2 As Marc

    Bloch said ofvassal homage, ?transferred, as was inevitable, to the political sphere . . . this idea was

    to have far-reaching influence?, Feudal Society, trans. L. Manyon (London, 1961), p. 451. Cf. L.

    Buisson, Potestas und Caritas (Cologne, 1958), Ch. 6. Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2010 For

    personal use only -- not for reproduction alone ? and they were anyway far less systematic than used

    to be thought ? were the origin, one would have expected contractarianism to have arisen much

    earlier, and in other places as well as north-western Europe.

    Secondly, it is true that Calvinism did to a considerable extent coincide with the diffusion of

    contractarian ideas of government among wider sections of the population. Aspects of Calvinist

    theology breathed new life into the language of ?coven- ant?. Yet there were significant

    differences between the type of covenant envisaged by theologians and believers as existing

    between God and the Christian, or again amongst congregations of believers, and the type ? or

    rather the various types ? of agreement envisaged by those developing political contractarianism in

    that same cultural milieu.

    Thus Calvinism too must be seen as part of the explanation, but not, even if we supplement it with ?

    feudalism?, the whole of it.

  • 7/31/2019 Juristic Origins of Social Contract Theory

    2/4

    Thirdly, there were specific passages in authorita- tive moralists, notably Cicero, discussing

    contractual relations between a peo- ple and their ruler. 3 These, however, had been current in

    literary society for many centuries without giving rise to either a worked-out philosophy of political

    contract or a general belief in contractual agreements as defining the ruler?ruled relationship.

    Nevertheless, it may be conceded that such texts provided, when people wished for it, further

    legitimation for a contractual view of government.

    Lastly, C.B. Macpherson and others have suggested that developments in English political

    theory during the seventeenth century, which included the use of a social covenant, owed their

    inspiration to the ethos of a nascent capitalist bourgeoisie. 4

    One might suspect a predilection for contract because this played such a prominent part in business

    life. Mercantile capitalism was indeed, it will be argued, extremely important, but one needs to be

    much more precise about the role it played. For there is no a priori reason why relationships or ideas

    prevalent in a certain domain of social life, whether these be patron?client relationships (?

    feudalism?), religious thought, or again economic transactions, should automatically ? ?sooner orlater?, as people tend to say ? be applied to government as well. We need to rid ourselves more

    thoroughly of the implications of holistic social theory, notably of the Marxist variety. Contrac- tual

    relationships, especially among those engaged in commercial activity, seem to have been at least as

    much a part of Islamic society, without affecting 3 For example, Cicero, De Officiis, II.12. See Mario

    d?Addio, L?idea del contratto sociale dai Sofisti alla Riforma (Milan, 1954); J.W. Gough, The Social

    Contract (Oxford, 2nd edn., 1957), Ch. 3; M. Grignaschi, ?Le probl me du contrat sociale et de l?

    origine de la ??Civitas?? dans la scolastique?, in Commission Internationale pour l?Histoire des

    Assembl es d? tats, Anciens Pays et Assembl es d? tats, 22 (1961), pp. 65?85; Cary Nederman, ?

    Nature, Sin and the Origins of Society: the Ciceronian Tradition in Medieval Political Thought?, in

    Journal of the History of Ideas, 49 (1988), pp. 3?26. 4 C.B. Macpherson, The Political Theory of

    Possessive Individualism (Oxford, 1962). 58 A. BLACK Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2010 For

    personal use only -- not for reproduction relations between political rulers and ruled, or people?s

    attitude towards these. They certainly never became a way, let alone ? as in parts of Europe ? the way

    of conceptualizing political relations.

    Again, contractual political relation- ships had existed prior to Islam (and perhaps even afterwards) in

    parts of the Nile to Oxus region (as Hodgson calls it), in the relation of ?emperor? to cities, without

    being translated into a dominant political norm. 5

    The argument of this essay is that the missing link, which Europe had, was the law as this affected,

    and was developed for, certain political relationships and certain social organizations; that is, publicor constitutional law. We may find in law and jurisprudence the link between feudal, or again

    capitalist ? the two were not always distinct ? social arrangements, on the one hand, and political

    ideology on the other. (The perception of Maine, that the theory ofsocial contract ?though nursed

    into importance by political passions, derived all its sap from the speculations of the lawyers?, 6

    seems to have been lost to sight.) I We may note, first, that fidelity, promise, oath and contract

    were strongly represented as moral ideas in pre-modern European culture. 7 They were

    embedded not only in feudal relationships but also in the culture of cities, guilds and even some

    villages, in which members commonly swore an oath to all fellow-members and/or to the

    authorities, as a condition of membership. 8 The sanctity of the promise, and therefore of all

    contracts, was inspired and strongly legitimated both by Stoic ethics as transmitted by the

    Roman world in Cicero and the Ancient Roman jurists, and by Christian teaching.

  • 7/31/2019 Juristic Origins of Social Contract Theory

    3/4

    In medieval Chris- tian language the concept of fides (faith), fidelis (the individual believer) and

    fidelitas (faithfulness) was exceptionally strong; one of the commonest terms for the Christian

    community was universitas fidelium (the society of the 5 See Marshall G.S. Hodgson, The Venture of

    Islam: Conscience and History in a World Civilization, Vol. 1: The Classical Age of Islam (Chicago,

    1974); Ann K.S. Lambton, State and Government in Medieval Islam (Oxford, 1981); Patricia

    Springborg, ?The Contractual State: Orientalism and Despotism?, in History of Political Thought,

    VIII (1987), pp. 395?433. 6 Sir Henry Maine, Ancient Law (London, 1861), Ch. 9 (this may havebeen a disparaging philosophical assessment rather than a historical statement). 7 See Paolo Prodi, Il

    Sacramento del Potere: il giuramento politico nella storia constituz- ionale dell? Occidente (Bologna,

    1992). 8 See especially O.G. Oexle, ?Conjuratio und Gilde im fr hen Mittelalter?, in Gilden und Z

    nfte, ed. B. Schwinek per (Sigmaringen, 1985), pp. 151?213; Max Weber, The City, ed. and trans. D.

    Martindale and G. Neuwirth (New York, 1958), pp. 104?10 on the medieval European city as ?oath-

    bound confederation?, Eidgenossenschaft, conjuratio (first published in Archiv f r Sozialwissenschaft

    und Sozialpolitik, 47 (1921), pp. 621ff.); P. Michaud-Quantin, Universitas (Paris, 1970), pp. 129?31.

    THE JURISTIC ORIGINS OF SOCIAL CONTRACT THEORY 59 Copyright (c) Imprint Academic

    2010 For personal use only -- not for reproduction faithful/of believers). I

    ndeed the concepts of theological belief and of personal fidelity tended to become merged. All of this

    hugely enhanced loyalty in human relationships in general, as a social value. To the many well-known

    testimonies of this, one may add a passage from the Secreta Secretorum (a thirteenth- century

    compilation falsely attributed to Aristotle), which draws an explicit political conclusion:

    You know, then, that faith (or trust: fides) brings about the association of human beings, the dwelling-

    places of cities, the community of men and the government of kings; faith enables strong places to be

    occupied, cities to be preserved, kings to rule. If you remove faith, all men will revert to their pristine

    condition, they will be like brutes and beasts. Beware, most faithful king, of breaking faith; keep

    firmly to your oaths and treaties, even if they are burdensome. 9 A much less recognized potential

    origin ofsocial contractthinking was the civil (Roman) and canon jurists? writings on pacts,

    agreements and contracts (pacta, conventus, contractus). From the twelfth to the sixteenth century and

    beyond, there was an immense juristic literature on these subjects, with a flood of monographs De

    Pactis in the fifteenth century. 10 Contracts were clearly an area ripe for adjudication. In general, it is

    to be noted that jurists frequently lumped together contractual arrangements between a lord and

    a vassal (whether an individual or an incorporated town) and those between merchants, share-

    holders, labourers and so on, as being essentially of the same type from a legal and moral viewpoint.

    They showed no great respect for the later fashionable distinction between feudal and capitalist

    relationships. 11 Indeed part of their 9 ?Scias itaque quod per fidem fit hominum congregatio,

    civitatum inhabitatio, virorum com- munio, regis dominatio; per fidem castra tenentur, civitates

    servantur, reges dominan- tur. Si quidem tollas fidem, cuncti homines ad statum pristinum revertentur,vid. ad instar brutorum et simili- tudinem bestiarum. Cave tibi, rex fidelissime, infringere datam

    fidem et serva firmiter juramenta tua et federa, etsi sint gravia?, Secreta Secretorum, ed. R. Steele

    (Oxford, 1920), p. 57. 10 Several of these are contained in Tractatus Universi Iuris (Lyon, 1549)

    (hereafter TUI), Vols. 3 and 16, and in Tractatus Illustrium Iurisconsultorum (Venice, 1584) (hereafter

    TII), Vol. 6, parts 1 and 2, and Vol. 7. Extensive discussion of pacts had, however, been going on for a

    long time in the standard lecture-commentaries, from Azo onwards. On the medieval jurists see

    Handbuch der Quellen und Literatur der neueren europ ischen Privat- rechtsgeschichte, Vol. 1:

    Mittelalter (1100?1500), ed. H. Coing (Munich, 1973); F. Ca- lasso, Medio Evo del Diritto, Vol. 1: Le

    Fonti (Milan, 1954). 11 See for example the following: ?Si princeps in concessione feudi reciperet

    pretium, licet uteretur verbis ??indulgemur??, tamen cum sit venditio . . . per consequens erit

    contractus irrevocabilis, et non habebit naturam feudi; immo non privabitur ex causis ex quibus aliasvasalli privari solent? (in other words, if money changes hands, investiture becomes an act of sale ?

    whatever ?concession theory? may be stated in the document): Jason de Maino (1435?1519), In

  • 7/31/2019 Juristic Origins of Social Contract Theory

    4/4

    secundum Digesti veteris commentaria (Lyon, 1540), fol. 136r, n.12?14. 60 A. BLACK Copyright (c)

    Imprint Academic 2010 For personal use only -- not for reproduction concern seems to have arisen

    from the changing character of feudal relation- ships, the conversion of service into money (?

    bastard feudalism?), and also from attempts by princes to treat fiefs as revocable governmental

    offices rather than hereditary possessions with jurisdictional rights (?centralization?). We may start

    with their conceptions of the relationship between a ruler, especially but not exclusively the emperor

    (princeps), and his vassals, espe- cially cities. A developed argument on this seems to date back to theend of the thirteenth century. Cino da Pistoia (1270?1336/7) tells us that Guido da Suzaria (died

    c.1290), in a question on ?Whether, if the emperor enters into certain pacts with a certain city

    (civitate) or baron, both he and his successors are bound to observe these (teneatur ea observare)?,

    replied that he was so bound, on the ground that ?the laws of nature tell us that pacts should be kept

    and that faith should be kept even with enemies?. 12 This was the view adopted by Bartolus of

    Sassoferrato (1313/14?1357), generally regarded as the greatest civil-law jurist of the Middle Ages,

    and certainly one of the most influential: ?If the emperor makes a pact with a certain city . . . it may

    seem that he is not (held to observe it), because he is ??released from the laws??. The contrary is the

    truth. For pacts come from the law of nations . . . The laws of nations are immutable.? 13 Bartolus?

    eminent pupil Baldus of Perugia (c.1327?1400), whose works like Bartolus? were used by law

    students well into the sixteenth century, similarly affirmed that, if the emperor or king of France hasinvested a duke with a fief, neither he nor his successors can divest him at will but only ?for a fault or

    felony of which (the duke) is convicted?. Baldus went on to make a significant statement which

    reconciled this evolving juristic consensus with Roman-law texts on imperial sovereignty: ?The

    emperor?s fullness of power does not stand in the way of this, because, while it is true that God has

    subjected laws to him, he has not subjected contracts to him, and he is bound by these.? 14 In the

    fifteenth century this was the commonly accepted legal opinion, expounded by one academic jurist

    after another in their commentaries, which were the staple Maino was the last major pre-humanist

    jurist, unspeakably long-winded though himself a spicy character. 12 In Codicem . . . Commentaria

    (Frankfurt, 1578), fol. 26r/a, n.7 (on Codex 1.14.4); cf. Cambridge History of Medieval Political

    Thought (hereafter CHMPT), ed. J.H. Burns (Cambridge, 1988), pp. 461?2. 13 On Codex 1.14.4. See

    also Albericus de Rosate in TII, Vol. 11, part 2, fol. 26v/a. 14 In usus feudorum commentaria (Pavia,

    1495), fol. 17v (Ad Feud. 1.7); see also In