when science gets personal: an analysis of scientific ... · edmund kwok-fai lo master of theology...

83
When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific Practices According to Michael Polanyi and Thomas Kuhn by Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo A Thesis submitted to the Faculty of Regis College and the Graduate Centre for Theological Studies of the Toronto School of Theology. In partial fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Theology awarded by Regis College and the University of Toronto. © Copyright by Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo 2019

Upload: others

Post on 18-Aug-2020

0 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific Practices

According to Michael Polanyi and Thomas Kuhn

by

Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo

A Thesis submitted to the Faculty of Regis College and the Graduate Centre for Theological Studies of the Toronto School of Theology.

In partial fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Theology awarded by Regis College and the University of Toronto.

© Copyright by Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo 2019

Page 2: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

ii

When Science Gets Personal:

An Analysis of Scientific Practices According to Michael Polanyi and Thomas Kuhn

Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo

Master of Theology

Regis College and the University of Toronto

2019

Abstract An examination of scientific practices according to Michael Polanyi and Thomas Kuhn

reveals a unique involvement of scientists on a personal level. Such a personal

involvement reveals the teleology behind scientific practices through the intentions of the

scientists. According to Polanyi, scientists are in search of truth in reality; for Kuhn,

scientists strive to solve scientific problems as puzzles. Such differences are reflected in a

potential science-religion dialogue: A Polanyian approach can find common ground with

religion, while a Kuhnian approach either leads to a confrontation or a parting of ways

with religion due to unresolvable conflicts. By using Polanyi’s interpretive framework

that is personal knowledge, the personal nature of scientific practices overlaps with the

personal nature of religious practices, with the common ground being the truth-seeking

person.

Page 3: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

iii

Contents Introduction .................................................................................................................... 1 Chapter One: Michael Polanyi ....................................................................................... 5

The Structure of Skills .................................................................. 5

The Awareness in the Performance of a Skill: Polanyi on Focal and

Subsidiary Awareness ................................................................... 6

Subsidiary Awareness and the Beginning of “Personal” ................ 7

Beliefs and Rules in Scientific Practices ........................................ 9

Neither Subjective Nor Objective ................................................ 10

Intellectual Passion ..................................................................... 12

Heuristic Passion ........................................................................ 14

Persuasive Passion ...................................................................... 15

Summary of Motivations............................................................. 16

Master-Apprentice ...................................................................... 18

Scientist-Scientist ....................................................................... 19

Tradition ..................................................................................... 20

Chapter Two: Thomas Kuhn ......................................................................................... 23

Paradigms Versus Rules .............................................................. 24

Anomaly ..................................................................................... 26

Crisis and Emergence of Scientific Discoveries........................... 26

Response to Crisis ....................................................................... 27

Personal Knowledge ................................................................................. 5

Human Passions as Motivations ............................................................. 12

Scientific Community............................................................................. 18

Summary ................................................................................................ 22

Normal Science and Paradigms .............................................................. 23

Anomaly and Crisis ................................................................................ 26

Page 4: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

iv

Why “Revolution”? ..................................................................... 29

The Necessity of Revolutions ...................................................... 30

Paradigm Shift as a Change of Worldview .................................. 32

Resolutions of Scientific Revolutions .......................................... 32

Puzzles and Parameters ............................................................... 36

Chapter Three: Critical Engagement of Polanyi and Kuhn............................................. 41

Motivations and Passions ............................................................ 41

The Authority of the Scientific Community ................................ 42

Scientific Progress ...................................................................... 44

Continuity or Rupture?................................................................ 46

An Evolutionary Kind of Progress .............................................. 47

Teleology of Scientific Practices ................................................. 48

Suitable Analogy to Describe Scientists? .................................... 53

Chapter Four: Science and Religion, Matters of Faith ................................................... 57

Scientific Revolution .............................................................................. 29

Aim of Normal Science .......................................................................... 34 Motivation: To Solve Puzzles ................................................................. 35

Scientific Practices and Community ....................................................... 38 Summary ................................................................................................ 39

On Scientific Practices: Similarities Between Polanyi and Kuhn ................. 41

On Scientific Practices: Differences Between Polanyi and Kuhn ............ 44

Summary ................................................................................................ 55

The Silos of Kuhn .................................................................................. 57 Kuhn in Theology .................................................................................. 59 Polanyi: Truth, Reality and Theology ..................................................... 62 Vocation................................................................................................. 64 Personal Knowledge and Theology ........................................................ 66 From Scientific to Religious Practices .................................................... 68 Summary ................................................................................................ 72

Page 5: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

v

Conclusion .................................................................................................................... 73 Bibliography ................................................................................................................. 76

Page 6: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

1

Introduction Given the influence of scientific progress on human lives and society, exploring the

prospect of a dialogue between science and religion becomes ever more pertinent from

the perspective of theologians. Such prospect is especially important in the face of

popular portrayals that do injustice to both science and religion. A lack of understanding

fosters over-simplification1: Just as it is unhelpful to consider “religion” as a monolithic

entity in which everyone believes in the same way, it is equally unhelpful to consider

“science” in general terms that turns out to be far removed from the ways in which

science is actually practiced.

The Late-Nineteenth and Early-Twentieth Century proves to be an important period in

which scholars begin to understand science in different ways. For instance, scholars from

the German and British scientific circles begin to focus on methodological issues in

science, an effort that eventually gives rise to logical positivism, with an emphasis on the

roles of logic and mathematics along with the abandonment of metaphysics2. Within the

same period, other scholars begin to explore the role of history in how we consider

science: The historical context does not merely function as background information but

rather as an integral part in which scientific discoveries are to be understood. The shift

can also be seen as a turn away from a matter-of-fact presentation of scientific

discoveries: Such a presentation is akin to one that is typically seen in an encyclopedia,

1 Admittedly, popular works of prominent anti-religion scientists (such as Richard Dawkins, Sam Harris and Jerry A. Coyne) and controversial topics such as arguing for a young earth tend to attract more public attention; nevertheless, such opinions highlight only a small percentage of views and cannot be considered as representative of a consensus amongst scientists. 2 The philosophical positions taken by scholars from the German scientific circles are diverse, with some taking inspirations from the philosophy of Immanuel Kant and adopting a view that scientific knowledge is not relativistic but rather absolute; others side more with Ernst Mach and adopt a position that rejects any kind of a priori elements in how knowledge is gained in general, and particularly in scientific knowledge. The Kantian and Machian schools of thought – especially the Machian – are influential in laying the groundwork for the development of logical positivism from the Vienna Circle. Frederick Suppe, ‘The Search for Philosophic Understanding of Scientific Theories’, in The Structure of Scientific Theories, ed. Frederick Suppe, Second edition (Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1977), 6-15; Richard Creath, ‘Logical Empiricism’, in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Edward N. Zalta, Fall 2017 (Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, 2017), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2017/entries/logical-empiricism/.

Page 7: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

2

with the focus being on the success of a few influential scientists while neglecting or

discarding the scientific problems of that time, or that which has gone before and after the

said major discoveries, as well as the errors made by scientists3. Rather than simply

considering what works, the shift to the historical pays close attention to the scientific

achievements that lay the groundwork for major scientific breakthroughs4.

An example of the turn to the historical is the scholarly work by Paul Tannery on the

history of mathematics. Tannery opines that the significance of a branch of science can

only be properly appreciated when situated within a larger context of the general history

of science5, which can be seen as the mutual enrichment between synthesis and research6.

Other notable contributions include Antonio Favaro’s twenty-volume edition of the

works of Galileo and Pierre Duhem’s study of Leonardo da Vinci. Favaro compares

Galileo’s work with the latter’s friends and foes, while Duhem compares da Vinci’s work

with both da Vinci’s predecessors and successors, as well as the minor figures who have

since been long forgotten7. Tannery, Favaro and Duhem are pioneers who pave the way

for subsequent scholars to pursue a more holistic understanding of science through the

consideration of the historical context of scientific discoveries8.

3 For instance, scholars of the Enlightenment period commonly consider the Middle Ages as a dark age. Voltaire deems the discussion of the works of Ptolemy and Tycho Brahe as unnecessary since both the systems of Ptolemy and Tycho are false. While such a sentiment is not universal, the disregard for the historical context can be seen as a desire to distance oneself from an age that offers very little to the scientific understanding of the time. Herbert Butterfield, Herbert Butterfield: Essays on the History of Science (Lewiston, NY: Edwin Mellen Press, 1998), 42–43. 4 The study of the history of science both better situate scientific discoveries within the context of scientific progress and serves to better understand the role of science in shaping history of societies in general; indeed, some scholars believe that the construction of a history of modern Europe is impossible without considering the impact of science. Butterfield, 32–35. 5 Butterfield, 44. 6 Butterfield, 46. The founding of scholarly journals devoting to the study of the history of the sciences is an example of such a turn towards the historical. Tannery is influential in the founding of the journal Revue de Synthèse Historique, and George Sarton in the journal Isis, both of which are founded in the earl 1900s and remain in publication to this present day. Another example is Aldo Mieli’s founding of the journal Archeion. Butterfield, 47. 7 Butterfield, 47–50. 8 A key contributor who has picked up the mantle of the aforementioned scholars is the British historian Herbert Butterfield, whose essays from which I have referred extensively in the introduction. Herbert’s seminal work describes the origin of modern science within the context of the medieval period. Herbert also summarizes the historical approach towards a better understanding of science as scientists’ needing help from historians, and historians needing help from scientists. Herbert Butterfield, The Origins of Modern Science, 1300-1800 (London, UK: G. Bell, 1957).

Page 8: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

3

The historical approach towards science is a contextualization through the consideration

of successes and failures, or predecessors and successors. A snapshot of the progress in

the historical consideration of science can be seen from the symposium titled The

Structure of Scientific Change at Oxford in 1961, attended by distinguished scholars such

as Joseph Needham, Georges Canguilhem and Imre Lakatos, among others. The wide

scope of the symposium is reflected from the discussion topics: The historical

reconstruction of science; the lives and motivations of those who take part in scientific

activity; the essential changes in scientific thought and the ways through which the

changes have been brought about; the social context of scientific and technical changes;

the historiography of science9.

Approaches that examine scientific discoveries through the ways in which scientific

expertise is practiced are considered in the sociological portion of the symposium10. Here,

the contributions from the two scholars of interest in this thesis can be found: Thomas

Kuhn and Michael Polanyi11. Such an approach is a contextualization of scientific

discoveries by examining what actually takes place in scientists’ attempts at noteworthy

discoveries, as supposed to a conceptual speculation of scientists’ work as following

certain scientific precepts by rote12. Polanyi argues that scientific practices show a

9 Alistair Cameron Crombie, ‘Introduction’, in Scientific Change: Historical Studies in the Intellectual, Social, and Technical Conditions for Scientific Discovery and Technical Invention, from Antiquity to the Present (Symposium on the History of Science (1961: Oxford, England)), ed. Alistair Cameron Crombie (New York, NY: Basic Books, 1963), 10. 10 The link between the sociological and the historical approach to understanding science can be perceived: The ways in which the trade of scientists is practiced can be discussed with greater depth by examining what happens when such practices take place. The historical approach is a consideration of what has happened, and such an approach remains useful despite the inevitable picking and choosing of what is being documented. 11 The attention paid to scientific practices can at least be partly explained by the background of Polanyi and Kuhn, as both Polanyi and Kuhn begin as scientists: Kuhn a physicist, and Polanyi a physical chemist. Both are intimately familiar with the journey of scientific discovery by having gone through the thick of scientific research in a hands-on manner. 12 Andrew Pickering observes that very little attention has been directed to understanding scientific practices until the Twentieth Century, with Polanyi and Kuhn being the two forerunners, along with Ludwik Fleck whose work highlights how medicine is practiced. Rather than scientific practices, the focus is casted upon scientific knowledge as a product of science. For example, Anglo-American philosophy of science has focused on the relationship between scientific theory and facts; the focus can be seen both from those who ascribe to the “logical-empiricist mainstream” thoughts, and those – such as Paul Feyerabend – who do not ascribe to the aforementioned mainstream opinions. Andrew Pickering, ‘From Science as Knowledge to Science as Practice’, in Science as Practice and Culture, ed. Andrew Pickering (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1992), 3.

Page 9: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

4

personal – and even passionate – involvement of the scientist which directly goes against

the stereotype of scientific activities as a search for the objective without the involvement

of the person13. On the other hand, Kuhn argues that scientific practices reveal the

process of scientific progress.

The focus of the following essay is the understanding of scientific practices according to

Polanyi and Kuhn. My main thesis is that the ways in which scientific practices are

understood change the ways in which science-religion dialogue take place. My work is

divided into four chapters. The first chapter is devoted to how Polanyi understands

scientific practices through an interpretative framework termed “personal knowledge”;

the second chapter focus on how Kuhn understands scientific practices through the ways

in which scientific progress takes place. I argue that an examination of what happens in

scientific practices reveals a tight link between scientific practices and the intentions of

scientists as well as the epistemological roots of scientific knowledge. The third chapter

is an examination of the similarities and differences of how Polanyi and Kuhn envision

scientific practices. I argue that Polanyi’s notion of scientists’ pursuit of a reality beyond

the self provides a better description to the ways in which scientific practices actually

take place; consequently, Polanyi’s notion of the personal is a more useful framework in

understanding scientific practices than that of Kuhn’s. The fourth chapter engages the

thoughts of Polanyi and Kuhn within the context of a science-religion dialogue. I argue

that the understanding of the intentions of scientists and the epistemological roots of

scientific knowledge better set the stage for a dialogue with religion due to the

recognition of common grounds. I also argue that science-religion dialogue is possible

within a Polanyian framework due to a common epistemological foundation, whereas a

confrontation between science and religion is all but inevitable within a Kuhnian

framework. Finally, I argue that – when understood in a Polanyian manner – scientific

practices and religious practices are comparable because of a shared cognitive

framework, and that understanding scientific practices allows for a better understanding

of religious practices.

13 Michael Polanyi, Personal Knowledge: Towards a Post-Critical Philosophy (Chicago, Ill.: The University of Chicago Press, 1958), 134.

Page 10: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

5

Chapter One: Michael Polanyi

In Michael Polanyi’s interpretative framework termed personal knowledge, practices play

a determinant role in the acquisition of knowledge by the ways in which practical skills

are performed. I argue that personal knowledge lays bare both the personal motivations of

scientists and the necessary involvement on the level of the person in the acquisition of

scientific knowledge, and that both personal motivations and the nature of practices in

personal knowledge can serve as a potential bridge for a science-religion dialogue. The

significance of Polanyi’s interpretative framework lies in the emphasis of practices as

supposed to procedural rules in knowledge acquisition, as well as the insistence of

preserving two positions that may seem irreconcilable at first glance: Objectivity in truth

and personal involvement.

Personal Knowledge

The Structure of Skills

In order to better understand the link between scientific practices and scientific

knowledge, Polanyi insists that “the structure of skills” in general must be understood,

with skills being goal-oriented actions that need to be learned: “The aim of a skillful

performance is achieved by the observance of a set of rules which are not known as such

to the person following them”14. Polanyi highlights the importance of an aspect of skills

of which the person remains unaware in a certain way when the skill is being performed.

For example, swimming is a skill that needs to be taught in order to perform properly.

Polanyi does not mean that explicit instructions such as “extend yourself at the end of the

front crawl stroke by rotating your torso” are unnecessary; rather, Polanyi focuses on the

ways in which swimmers keep afloat, refraining from emptying the lungs while breathing

out and over-inflating the lungs while breathing in with the aim of maintaining an

14 Polanyi, 49.

Page 11: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

6

increased level of buoyancy in the water15. While the theory behind buoyancy during

swimming can be understood on an intellectual level, such a theory does not teach the

hows of moving through water. The explanatory powers of the underlying scientific

theories do not shed any light upon the ways in which swimming is performed in

practice; the rules do not explain the hows of the practicing of a skill16.

While the example of swimming is indicative of muscular skills, the same

aforementioned principle can be seen in more specialized skills such as that of a

physician, and Polanyi calls the learning of such specialized skills “connoisseurship”17.

Polanyi cites a physician’s recognizing the accentuation of the second sound of the

pulmonary artery to illustrate that a specified diagnostic ability must be learned through

practice. Physicians learn about diagnostic criteria from medical textbooks, but a proper

diagnosis in practice can only be learned through a repeated exposure to symptom-

manifesting cases; physicians fully realize the difference between the presence and

absence of the symptoms through practice18. The importance of connoisseurship is

reflected in the large amounts of time that the students of medicine spend in more

practical courses19. Similar to the swimming example, rules for medical diagnosis do not

show the hows of a diagnostic practice. The practitioners remain unware of the hows of

the practicing of a skill, and the awareness of the performance of a skill will be discussed

in detail in the next section.

The Awareness in the Performance of a Skill:

Polanyi on Focal and Subsidiary Awareness

According to Polanyi, the structure of skills also illustrates different aspects of the

awareness of the person who performs the skill, whom will be henceforth called the

performer. Take a more general example of hammer and nail: The performer attends to

15 Polanyi, 49. 16 Polanyi, 50. 17 Polanyi, 54. 18 Polanyi, 54–55. 19 Polanyi, 55.

Page 12: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

7

the hammer and nail in different ways during the act of hammering a nail: When the

hammer is being brought down onto the nail, the performer focuses on how the head of

the hammer strikes the nail and not how the handle of the hammer hits the palm. At the

same time, the performer is not oblivious to the feeling of the latter, as the handling of the

hammer remains important in the effective guiding of the hammer onto the nail. Polanyi

calls the awareness of the hammer striking the nail a focal awareness, and the awareness

of the feeling of the hammer in the palm a subsidiary awareness20. The usage of a

dentist’s probe also illustrates the two different kinds of awareness in a more specialized

manner21. When a dentist handles the probe to examine a cavity, the dentist’s focal

awareness is the interaction between the probe and the cavity, while the subsidiary

awareness is the dentist’s manipulation of the probe. Focal awareness and subsidiary

awareness are mutually exclusive22; the performer focally attends to one specific action

while everything else falls into the subsidiary. Another example is the playing of a piano:

The performer is focally aware of the piece of music while being subsidiarily aware of

the movement of the fingers. When the attention is switched onto the action of the

fingers, confusion ensues and the performer may have to stop the playing23. The piano

example illustrates that a subsidiary awareness is not the same as ignorance but rather

being aware in an unspecifiable manner24. While mutually exclusive, focal and subsidiary

awareness are not fixed entities; the latter switches to the former – and vice versa – when

attention is diverted to what the performer is doing subsidiarily.

Subsidiary Awareness and the Beginning of “Personal”

Polanyi’s examples involve objects that are not a part of – and in this sense external to –

the human body. When external objects are being attended to, the performer relies on

subsidiary awareness through the performer’s body; by extension, Polanyi argues that

20 Polanyi, 55. 21 Polanyi, 55. 22 Polanyi, 56. 23 Polanyi, 56. 24 Polanyi, 56. Polanyi also calls such an involvement of the subsidiary awareness “tacit”, as evident from the title of Polanyi’s book The Tacit Dimension.

Page 13: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

8

subsidiary awareness can also be seen as an act of making the external object into a part

of the performer’s own body25. For example, an external object such as the medical probe

is “incorporated” into the dentist’s body:

While we rely on a tool or a probe, these are not handled as external objects. We may test the tool for its effectiveness or the probe for its suitability […] but the tool and the probe can never lie in the field of these operations; they remain necessarily on our side of it, forming part of ourselves, the operating persons. We pour ourselves out into them and assimilate them as parts of our own existence. We accept them existentially by dwelling in them.26

Such an act of incorporation of something external signals a turn to the “personal”: The

“personal” goes beyond the performer’s engagement through focal and subsidiary

awareness. Through the assimilation, the external tool is treated as simply a part of the

performer. The act of assimilation is also “personal” because the object is being

incorporated, and the performer – as Polanyi says – “pours” oneself into the object. The

external object becomes a tool only when the performer intends the object for the

performer’s own purposes; the performer is confident in the intention regardless of

whether the intended result – be it the probing of a cavity or the hammering of a nail – is

successfully achieved or not27.

More importantly, Polanyi proposes that the skillful aspects behind the using a physical

tool continues to apply when the physical tool is replaced with an intellectual tool28.

Through the subsidiary awareness, intellectual tools such as interpretative frameworks in

the sciences are being incorporated29. The performer of such an “intellectual practice”

takes in the intellectual tool and pours oneself into the tool as if the tool is a part of the

25 Polanyi, Personal Knowledge, 59. 26 Polanyi, 59. 27 Polanyi, 60. 28 Polanyi, 59. 29 Polanyi explains the interpretive frameworks in the sciences as such: “I am not speaking of the specific assertions which fill the textbooks, but of the suppositions which underlie the method by which these assertions are arrived at. We assimilate most of these pre-suppositions by learning to speak of things in a certain language, in which there are names for various kinds of objects, names by which objects can be classified, making such distinctions as between past and present, living and dead, healthy and sick, and thousands of others. Our language includes the numerals and the elements of geometry, and it refers in these terms to laws of nature whence we can pass on to the roots of these laws in scientific observations and experiments”. Polanyi, 59.

Page 14: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

9

performer. The performer implicitly accepts the interpretative framework, and the

framework is intended to be used for the purposes of the performer30. The performer has

confidence in such an intention, just as the performer has confidence in using a hammer

on a nail whether the attempt is successful or not. Therefore, what makes knowledge

personal is the incorporation of intellectual tools, as well as the performer’s implicit

belief and confidence in such tools.

Beliefs and Rules in Scientific Practices

Since interpretive frameworks found in science are implicitly accepted and believed

through the subsidiary awareness of scientists, belief plays an important role in scientific

practices. What is the relationship between such a belief and rules that are found in

scientific practices? Polanyi thinks that expectations and methods in scientific practices

are mutually determined, as expectations and methods adjust to each other according to

the success or failure in scientific practices31. Such a mutual relationship is founded upon

practices. Beliefs are embedded subsidiarily within practices and the former is only

realized in a focal manner upon the performer’s own reflection of the process of

establishing facts32. A similar situation can be seen with rules in Polanyi’s earlier

examples of the practicing of skills: The premises and rules of buoyancy cannot be

focally discovered prior to the act of swimming until the performance of swimming has

been experienced and reflected upon; indeed, the performer practices a skill while being

focally ignorant but subsidiarily aware of the rules33. Once focally known through

reflection and analysis, the rules and methods can be used to guide and improve the

performance of the skill of interest34. Polanyi’s understanding of scientific practices

explicitly rejects the view that scientific practices are governed by presuppositions that

come before and are independent from scientific practices.

30 Polanyi, 61. 31 Polanyi, 161. 32 Polanyi, 162. 33 Polanyi, 162. 34 Polanyi, 163.

Page 15: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

10

Neither Subjective Nor Objective

Polanyi’s great emphasis on the personal aspect of scientific knowledge aims to do away

with the notion that there exists a complete, detached objectivity in the sciences, which

Polanyi describes as “a delusion and is in fact a false ideal”35. Meanwhile, neither does

Polanyi endorse any kind of subjectivist approach where everyone’s scientific standards

and results are equally valid. Polanyi rejects both the traditional accounts of objectivity

and subjectivity in scientific knowledge:

We may distinguish between the personal in us, which actively enters into our commitments, and our subjective states, in which we merely endure our feelings. This distinction establishes the conception of the personal, which is neither subjective nor objective in so far as the personal submits to requirements acknowledged by itself as independent of itself, it is not subjective; but in so far as it is an action guided by individual passions, it is not objective either. It transcends the disjunction between subjective and objective.36

That which Polanyi proposes as personal transcends the objective because what guides

scientists’ scientific practices is the individual passions of scientists (a topic which will

be discussed in detail in the next section); the personal also transcends the subjective

because of the scientists’ acknowledgement and commitment to a universal standard that

is independent of the scientists37. Scientists’ fiduciary passion triggers a confident

utterance about scientific facts is personal when scientists submit to such facts as

universally valid; on the other hand, such passion is reduced to subjectivity when

scientists reflect on the act of utterance of scientific facts in a manner that is non-

35 Polanyi, 18. Polanyi thinks that the view of a completely detached and impersonal view of the sciences is exemplified by the French scientist Pierre Simon de Laplace: “An intelligence which knew at one moment of time – wrote Laplace – ‘all the forces by which nature is animated and the respective positions of the entities which compose it, […] would embrace in the same formula the movements of the largest bodies in the universe and those of the lightest atom: nothing would be uncertain for it, and the future, like the past, would be present to its eyes.’ Such a mind would possess a complete scientific knowledge of the universe.” Polanyi argues that a Leplacean worldview is akin to a set of equations and data which tell the scientist nothing about the scientist’ object of interest. More importantly, Polanyi argues that this Leplacean view promotes a kind of “strictly objective knowledge…continues to sustain a universal tendency to enhance the observational accuracy and systematic precision of science, at the expense of its bearing on its subject matter”. Polanyi, 139–141. 36 Polanyi, 300. 37 Polanyi, 303.

Page 16: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

11

committal to any independent and universal standards38. With an independent standard

comes a sense of obligation: “The freedom of the subjective person to do as he pleases is

overruled by the freedom of the responsible person to act as he must”39. The “personal”

perspective bestows a sense of responsibility upon scientists that goes beyond the mere

fulfilment of a task. In fact, Polanyi describes the obligation as a scientist’s vocation40,

and there cannot be any sense of self-indulgence in such a pursuit41. Ultimately, the

standard that is independent from scientists serves to guide the scientists to a much bigger

goal: “We can assimilate an object as a tool if we believe it to be actually useful to our

purposes […] The act of personal knowing can sustain these relations only because the

acting person believes that they are apposite: that he has not made them but discovered

them. The effort of knowing is thus guided by a sense of obligation towards the truth: by

an effort to submit to reality” (Italics original)42. Personal knowledge demands the giving

of the lives of scientists over to a pursuit of truth and reality that provides the ground for

scientists’ personal commitment43. The commitment of scientists does not guarantee any

success and can be misguided, yet such uncertainties are implicit in great scientific

inquiries and discoveries44. How can such a commitment from scientists be better

understood? What more can be said about the motivations behind scientists’ pursuit of

truth and reality?

38 Polanyi, 303. Polanyi does not see a personal desire for an universal – and hence “impersonal” – truth as contradictory because the personal and the universal need each other within the framework of commitment: “Here the personal comes into existence by asserting universal intent, and the universal is constituted by being accepted as the impersonal term of this personal commitment”. Polanyi, 308. 39 Polanyi, 309. 40 Polanyi, 322–323. 41 Michael Polanyi, The Tacit Dimension (Garden City, N.Y.: Doubleday, 1967), 25. 42 Polanyi, Personal Knowledge, 63. 43 Polanyi, 311. Polanyi sees no difference in saying “I believe ‘p’” and “‘p’ is true”. Both sayings indicate a confident asserting of ‘p’ as a fact. Beliefs – through personal commitment – inherently indicate a directionality towards truth. Polanyi, 317. 44 Polanyi, 310.

Page 17: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

12

Human Passions as Motivations

According to Polanyi, human passions both serve as motivations behind scientific

practices and are indispensable aspects of what makes knowledge personal45. Polanyi

further differentiates passions into intellectual, heuristic, and persuasive passion.

Intellectual Passion

Intellectual passion can be understood as a kind of felt appreciation of ingenuity,

scientific value and scientific beauty46; “the excitement of the scientist making a

discovery […] telling that something is intellectually precious and, more particularly, that

it is precious to science”47. Scientists judge and appreciate that something is worthwhile

in scientific practices. Three different factors constitute that which Polanyi considers as

scientific value: 1. Certainty (or accuracy); 2. Systematic relevance (or profundity); and

3. Intrinsic interest. The first two criteria are considered “inherently scientific” while the

last criterion that is intrinsic interest is considered “extra-scientific”48, which highlights

the personal component that allows scientists to give directionality to scientific research.

An intellectual appreciation is not simply scientists’ reflex towards the products of

scientific practices; scientists do not simply find every piece of gathered data to be

interesting49. In fact, evidence that do not agree with the scientists’ preferred approach is

45 Polanyi, 134. According to Polanyi, passions for knowledge acquisition are already reflected in animal behaviours. An “active principle” underlies tacit intelligence, and such an active principle is apparent even in the general alertness of primitive creatures such as worms, which seek to explore and exert some kind of control over the situations that the worms encounter. The development of such tacit intellectual powers in more advanced creatures is also evident. For instance, upon discovering a novel manipulation of a tool, chimpanzees repeatedly enact the same manipulation for the action’s own sake but not for any practical purposes. Such behaviour exhibited in animals is a prefiguration of the intellectual passions and satisfaction that can be observed from human beings; that being said, Polanyi thinks that the intellectual passions of a scientific pursuit transcend that which animals are capable of, and animals are unable to appreciate the intellectual beauty that scientists can identify through scientific practices. Polanyi, 132–133. 46 Polanyi, 133. 47 Polanyi, 134. 48 Polanyi, 135–136. 49 Polanyi cites the discovery of T. W. Richards to illustrate that accuracy in observations does not equate to scientifically valuable: Richards was awarded the Nobel prize in 1914 for discovering a method to accurately determine the atomic weights of chemicals. Yet less than twenty years later, Frederick Soddy – also a Nobel laureate in chemistry – declared that the kind of measurement pioneered by Richard was of as

Page 18: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

13

often ignored, in hoping that such evidence can eventually be either accommodated or

found to be irrelevant to the particular investigation at hand50. Polanyi does not consider

scientists’ ignoring certain evidence to be problematic because such an approach prevents

scientists from being drawn into futile projects51.

Scientific values – certainty, systematic relevance and intrinsic interest – are appreciated

by scientists’ sense of intellectual or scientific beauty on a personal level, and is

intimately related to scientists’ vision of reality; the sense of intellectual beauty is guided

by the scientists’ “vision of the general nature of things”:

Our vision of reality, to which our sense of scientific beauty responds, must suggest to us the kind of questions that it should be reasonable and interesting to explore. It should recommend the kind of conceptions and empirical relations that are intrinsically plausible and which should therefore be upheld, even when some evidence seems to contradict them, and tell us also, on the other hand, what empirical connections to reject as specious, even though there is evidence for them – evidence that we may as yet be unable to account for on any other assumptions. In fact, without a scale of interest and plausibility based on a vision of reality, nothing can be discovered that is of value to science; and only our grasp of scientific beauty, responding to the evidence of our senses, can evoke this vision.52

Intellectual beauty that is found in science is characterized by the former’s contact with

reality53. Such an understanding resonates with that which makes knowledge personal:

little interest as “the determination of the average weight of a collection of bottles, some of them full and some of them more or less empty”: “It had been realized meanwhile that the value of atomic weights results from the accidental proportion in which the constituent isotopes happen to be present in the elements as found in nature. A magnitude that had seemed to characterize a deep-seated feature of the universe, had turned out to have no such bearing. Though factually correct, it had proved deceptive because – contrary to expectation – it did not correspond to anything substantial in nature. When the exact atomic weight of an element ceased to be of interest to science, what had seemed important turned out to be trivial”. The example of determination of atomic weights also shows the importance of historical context, in that scientific discoveries can be considered valuable during one period but are considered of little use in another. Polanyi, 136. 50 Polanyi, 138. 51 According to Polanyi, there is a caveat in scientists’ deliberate ignorance of certain pieces of evidence: There isn’t any rules by which scientists can guarantee that the ignored evidence is not true. In other words, there is no safeguard to prevent the scientists’ decision to discard valuable scientific results that conflict with the scientists’ scientific worldview. Polanyi, 138. 52 Polanyi, 135. 53 The link between beauty and reality is not restricted to the scientific realm, as such a link is present in other realms such as art and mathematics; indeed, Polanyi speaks of an “artistic beauty” that is a token of “artistic reality”, and a “mathematical beauty” that is reflective of a “mathematical reality”. Such an

Page 19: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

14

The intellectual passion of scientists is stirred by the intellectual beauty of truth in reality.

Indeed, Polanyi describes intellectual beauty as “a guide to discovery and as a mark of

truth”54. When understood in such a manner, scientists – through intellectual passion –

are motivated by a beauty that is both external to the scientists and reflects that which is

real; the pursuit of a reality that is independent of oneself is the difference between the

fulfilment of a universal obligation and a private satisfaction55. Unsurprisingly, Polanyi

thinks that scientists can have a misguided intellectual passion which results from a false

vision of reality; namely, that “a misguided intellectual passion, a passion for achieving

absolutely impersonal knowledge which, being unable to recognize any persons, presents

us with a picture of the universe in which we ourselves are absent. In such a universe

there is no one capable of creating and upholding scientific values; hence there is no

science”56. Truth in reality is not determined by scientists, but intellectual passion for

scientific values gives the scientists motivation to proceed with scientific research.

Heuristic Passion

Through intellectual passion, scientists are attracted to a beauty that reflects reality57.

Along with intellectual passion comes a motivation that leads scientists to persist in

scientific pursuits, a motivation that is directly linked to another passion that renders

scientists capable of scientific discoveries, and Polanyi calls the latter passion the

heuristic passion58. While the type of motivation provided by intellectual passion is more

appreciation has universal intent, and bears witness beyond that to the presence of an inexhaustible fount of meaning which may be exhibited in the future. Polanyi, 201. 54 Polanyi, 300. 55 Polanyi, 174. Polanyi distinguishes the difference between scientific knowledge and the operational principle of technology; namely, that the former yields a discovery that “makes an addition to our knowledge of nature”, while the latter results in an invention, whose new and established operational principle offers some kind of practical advantage. Polanyi sees beauty – albeit in different terms – in both scientific discovery and technological invention: The former allows scientists to probe more deeply into the nature of things, while the latter turns known facts into a technological advantage. The key implication between theoretical and practical interest is that scientists’ pure intellectual passions may be ostracized by a view of scientific progress that is only measured by practical interests. Polanyi, 177–180. 56 Polanyi, 142. 57 Polanyi never explicitly states that intellectual passion is a prerequisite for scientific pursuits, but intellectual passion guided by a sense of intellectual beauty does provide a kind of foundational motivation, and is an indispensable part of scientific pursuits. 58 Polanyi, Personal Knowledge, 143.

Page 20: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

15

inspirational, heuristic passion provides the motivation in the operational aspect of a

discovery process. The heuristic passion of scientists provides the motivation to seek a

resolution to whatever scientific problem in a resourceful manner. Scientists are not

driven by a heuristic passion that follows a pre-established list of scientific procedures

through which the generation of novel scientific knowledge is guaranteed. Indeed,

Polanyi believes that creative scientists “spend their lives in trying to guess right”59.

Scientists’ decisions are informed by experience in scientific practices, and Polanyi calls

such educated guesses – in paraphrasing Albert Einstein – “a groping for the meaning of

the facts”60. When heuristic passion is engaged, the type of scientific work that is being

engaged is creative, both in the sense that scientists seek different – and at times

surprising – venues in an attempt to discover novel scientific knowledge, and that

scientists undergo an irrevocable change in a perception of the world through a deepening

of understanding, hence creating a new worldview61. Polanyi describes heuristic passion

in two contrasting ways: “Heuristic passion seeks no personal possession. It sets out not

to conquer, but to enrich the world. Yet such a move is also an attack. It raises a claim

and makes a tremendous demand on other men”62. The enriching aspect comes from a

desire to pursue new insights that contribute to a better understanding of the world, yet

there also exists an aggressive aspect whose underlying passion Polanyi calls persuasive.

Persuasive Passion

To persuade is to convince another to change a previously-held opinion. Polanyi sees the

objective of the persuasion as changing the vision of reality of another63. Convinced of

59 Polanyi, 143. The guesses of scientists are not matters of chance. Such a guessing process can be distinguished between scientific and unscientific guesses: The former, if erroneous, can be called mistaken; whereas the latter, if erroneous, can be considered as incompetent; Polanyi, 144. 60 Polanyi, 150. 61 Polanyi, 143. 62 Polanyi, 150. While Polanyi’s description of heuristic passion as not to conquer the world but as an attack can seem contradictory, such a description can be interpreted in the following manner: Driven by heuristic passion, scientists strive to enrich the world by discovering, but not exerting control and dominance over truth in reality through a kind of conquest. The “attack” component takes place on a more personal level, as the ways in which scientists try to convince others of new discoveries can be aggressive because of the belief that such discoveries do reflect a part of reality. 63 Polanyi, Personal Knowledge, 150.

Page 21: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

16

the validity and value of a new discovery, scientists try to convert others to see reality

through a different lens; such a conversion is a crossing of a gap that is similar to the

“heuristic gap” that one has crossed upon a new discovery64. A worldview is irrevocably

changed through scientific discovery, and scientists try to convince others to go through a

similar irrevocable change. The case of Galileo illustrates that persuasive passion is much

more than just demanding a change in scientific opinions:

The real ground of Galileo’s conviction lay in his passionate appreciation of the greater scientific value of the heliocentric view: a feeling which was accentuated by his angry rebellion against Aristotle’s authority over science. His opponents had on their side the common-sense view which sees the earth at rest, and, above all, a vivid consciousness of man’s uniqueness as the only particle of the universe that feels responsible to God. Their craving to retain for man a location which corresponds to his importance in the universe was the emotional force opposed to the intellectual appeal of Copernicanism.65

Galileo engages in a battle that is waged not only over scientific facts, but more

importantly over a difference in worldview: Heliocentrism threatens the unique position

of the human person in the universe for which an Aristotelian system allows.

Summary of Motivations

The three kinds of passions that fuel scientists’ motivations in scientific practices can be

summarized as such: Intellectual passion affirms both the interest and value in scientific

facts that scientists encounter; heuristic passion is the wellspring of originality,

discovering new horizons through the scientific pursuit and linking such novelty with

intellectual passion; heuristic passion then turns into a persuasive one in trying to

convince others of the new vision that resulted from a new scientific discovery66. The

passions which motivate scientists can undergo a kind of transformation into what

Polanyi calls a “public” passion:

Personal participation changes from an impetuous pouring out of oneself into channels of untried assumptions, into a confident holding of certain

64 Polanyi, 150. 65 Polanyi, 152. 66 Polanyi, 159.

Page 22: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

17

conclusions as part of one’s interpretative framework. The driving power of originality is reduced to a static personal polarization of knowledge; the intellectual effort which led to discovery and guided its verification is transformed into the force of a conviction which holds it to be true – in exactly the same way as the effort of acquiring a skill is transformed into a sense of its mastery.67

The three types of passions that have previous been discussed are more “fluid”: Scientists

who are driven by a vision of intellectual beauty to pursue novel discoveries face many

uncertainties; as well, creativity and fluidity are necessary in scientists’ approach towards

experimentation. Once the scientific knowledge becomes more certain and trustworthy,

the underlying passions transform into a more solidified state: A confidence in certain

conclusions with a force of conviction. The latter scenario of solidification also serves as

a signal that such scientific knowledge can be confidently presented to a more general

audience for a dissemination of knowledge, as the passions of scientists go from private

to public. When scientific discoveries are learned through textbooks, that which takes

place in the private still happens on the public stage to a certain extent:

A theory like that of relativity continues to attract the interest of ever new students and laymen by intimations of its beauty yet hidden to their understanding: a beauty which is rediscovered every time a new mind apprehends the theory […] All true appreciation of science by the public continues to depend on the appreciation of such beauty even though sensed only at second hand; it offers an indirect tribute to the values that the multitude have been taught to entrust to a group of men whose cultural guidance they have accepted.68

Similar passions arouse when scientific discoveries are being taught to students; the

students are indirectly experiencing the fruition of scientific pursuits, as intellectual

beauty has been rediscovered and appreciated. The switch of scientists’ passions from

private to public points to the role of the scientific community and the relationship

between the persons who are a part of such a community.

67 Polanyi, 172. 68 Polanyi, 172.

Page 23: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

18

Scientific Community

According to Polanyi, the ways in which scientists interact with one another within the

scientific community are emblematic of personal knowledge. Three key aspects shall be

discussed: The relationship between the master and the apprentice; the relationship

between fellow scientists, and the role of tradition within a scientific community.

Master-Apprentice

Polanyi believes that the essentials of scientific practices can be learned by junior

scientists only “through close personal association with the intimate view and practice of

a distinguished master”69. Polanyi describes such a relationship as one between a master

and an apprentice. The relationship between J. J. Thomson and Ernest Rutherford with

the work on the atomic model, as well as the four future Nobel laureates under the

tutelage of Rutherford serve as good examples70. The relationship is characterized by the

apprentice’s learning of the master’s “personal intuitions” through the latter’s work. Such

intuitions include the ways through which scientific problems and corresponding

techniques are chosen; the ways scientists react to novel clues or unforeseen difficulties,

as well as the ways in which scientists discuss the works of colleagues or the manners in

which possibilities are speculated71.

By evoking the image of a master and an apprentice, Polanyi is also comparing scientific

practices to practices of other disciplines such as art; in fact, Polanyi considers scientific

practices as a kind of art. Some aspects of art cannot be specified in detail, and such

aspects are not passed on through explicit precepts but rather from the personal

interaction between the master and the apprentice72; similarly, “while the articulate

contents of science are successfully taught all over the world in hundreds of new

69 Michael Polanyi, Science, Faith and Society (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1964), 43. 70 Polanyi, 44. 71 Polanyi, 43–44. 72 Polanyi, Personal Knowledge, 53.

Page 24: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

19

universities, the unspecifiable art of scientific research has not yet penetrated to many of

these”73. Herein lies the connection between the master-apprentice relationship and

Polanyi’s personal knowledge: The unspecifiable aspects of scientific practices can only

be tacitly learned by the apprentice from the master. The apprentice must first believe the

master before the former can learn and know, and such a role of belief is similar to the

self-confident scientists who embark on a journey of discovery; the difference is that

while scientists are confident in themselves, the confidence of the apprentice lies in

another person that is the master74. The confidence of the apprentice in another also

informs Polanyi’s perspective that the apprentice is submitting to authority when learning

from the master75. A good master does not try to brainwash the apprentice, but rather

encourages the development of the latter’s originality76. A relationship of mentorship

exists between the master and the apprentice amidst tensions of dependence and

independence.

Scientist-Scientist

It is impossible for a scientist to have complete knowledge of the entire scientific

discipline. Regardless of the breadth and depth of the scientist’s knowledge, only a first-

hand knowledge of a fragment of the scientist’s own discipline can be realistically

expected. The rest must come from a second-hand knowledge that originated from others.

In what way does such an acceptance take place?

For each member of the (scientific) community can judge at first hand only a small number of his fellow members, and yet eventually each is accredited by all. What happens is that each recognizes as scientists a number of other by whom he is recognized as such in return, and these relations form chains which transmit these mutual recognitions at second hand through the whole community. This is how each member becomes directly or indirectly accredited by all. The system extends into the past. Its members recognize the same set of persons as their masters and derive from this allegiance a

73 Polanyi, 53. 74 Polanyi, 208. 75 Polanyi, 53. The apprentice’s submission to the master is not absolute. As the apprentice matures and gains experience, the reliance on the master also decreases. Polanyi, Science, Faith and Society, 45. 76 Polanyi, 46.

Page 25: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

20

common tradition, of which each carries on a particular strand.77

For Polanyi, what matters is the first-hand judgement of a scientist of a fellow colleague.

Realistically, a scientist can only make informed judgements about a handful of fellow

scientists. In acknowledging the work of a few scientists, a scientist acknowledges and

accredits fellow scientists as experts who are intimately involved in the pursuit and

discovery of novel scientific knowledge. When everyone is able to recognize a few others

as fellow experts, then everyone is indirectly but mutually accredited by all, and such

accreditations bind all scientists together into a scientific community. Such a process of

scrutiny and accreditation is a kind of checks and balances that maintain the integrity of a

scientist’s work and reputation. Polanyi likens such a process to a marching column

where the marchers keep and are kept in step with adjacent marchers78. The image of a

marching column illustrates a dynamic component of the scientific community: The

scientific beliefs and values of scientists can change according to novel and fundamental

discoveries. Such changes do not occur in a coordinated change of formation as if

scientists are simply taking marching orders from an authority figure; the scientific

community never marches onwards with perfect uniformity, and conflicting views always

exist within a body that marches onwards in general79.

Tradition

The mutual scrutiny and accreditation between scientists extends to the past. Scientists

acknowledge several common scientists as masters, and a mutual recognition extending

into the past indicates an allegiance to a shared tradition. Such a tradition consists of a

kind of consensus, but not one in which everyone agrees upon everything through a vote;

rather, the consensus is a trust in a body of scientific knowledge on which scientists can

rely. The relationship between the scientist and an existing consensus does not remain

static: “whenever I submit to a current consensus, I inevitably modify its teaching; for I

submit to what I myself think it teaches and by joining the consensus on these terms I

77 Polanyi, Personal Knowledge, 163. 78 Polanyi, 217. 79 Polanyi, 164.

Page 26: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

21

affect its content. On the other hand, even the sharpest dissent still operates by partial

submission to an existing consensus: for the revolutionary must speak in terms that

people can understand”80. The personal aspect of knowledge acquisition once again

comes to the fore. Scientists submit to and adopt a scientific consensus by involving the

scientists’ own interpretation of the consensus and believing that the consensus truly

reflects that which is indeed the case in reality. Even the most unconventional and daring

scientists necessarily affirm scientific discoveries from scientists of generations past81.

Such an affirmation remains so even if a new discovery posts a challenge to traditional

grounds of the existing body of scientific knowledge; the trailblazing scientists must

nevertheless appeal to the said tradition as a common ground with others who hold a

different opinion. Ground-breaking scientific discoveries cannot happen under groundless

conditions.

As the apprentice submits to the master, so the scientist submits to the scientific tradition;

authority functions on the level of the individual82. Scientists submit to the yet-to-be-

discovered knowledge which have been deemed as valuable; scientists recognize “the

authority of that which he is going to learn and of those from whom he is going to learn

it”83. Those who dissent from the consensus can also be considered through the lens of

authority: “Every dissenter is a teacher. The figures of Antigone and of the Socrates of

the Apology are monuments of the dissenter as lawgiver. So are also the prophets of the

Old Testament, and so is a Luther, or Calvin. All modern revolutionaries since the

Jacobins demonstrate likewise that dissent does not seek to abolish public authority, but

to claim it for itself”84. Dissenters are not simply rebelling against the existing authority,

but are trying to claim the authority in order to establish a new consensus according to the

dissenters’ own perspective.

80 Polanyi, 208–209. 81 Polanyi, 171. 82 Polanyi, Science, Faith and Society, 48. 83 Polanyi, 45. 84 Polanyi, 209.

Page 27: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

22

Summary

I have argued that when Polanyi’s notion of personal knowledge is being employed to

better understand scientific practices, scientists’ desire to pursue truth in reality – which

serves as motivation behind scientific practices – can be revealed. Polanyi’s

understanding of scientific practices requires that scientists commit to the truth that is

being sought, and acknowledge that there exists a truth that is not of the scientists’ own

design. The essential role of commitment and belief in Polanyi’s interpretive framework

not only provide an alternative to, but also presents a challenge to the understanding that

scientific knowledge is impersonal. Personal knowledge advocates for the role of

personal belief, which has often been associated with religious but not scientific matters.

Polanyi’s efforts can hence be seen as a redemption of the role of belief in the acquisition

of scientific knowledge and knowledge in general. The role of belief also extends to the

ways in which non-scientists assent to scientific knowledge.

As aforementioned, Polanyi does not have any monopoly on the study in scientific

practices. Thomas Kuhn also values the contribution of scientific practices and veers

away from a theory-centric understanding of science. Despite the common interest, Kuhn

understands scientific practices through a different interpretive framework, which Kuhn

terms “scientific revolutions”. The thoughts of Kuhn are the main topics for the next

chapter. Kuhn addresses similar topics such as the scientific authority and the motivation

of scientists, which serve as a good comparison to that of Polanyi.

Page 28: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

23

Chapter Two: Thomas Kuhn A deeper dive into Kuhn’s interpretive framework allows for an understanding of

scientific practices from another angle; namely, that scientific practices must be

understood through the lens of what Kuhn calls normal science and scientific revolutions.

I argue that scientists’ desire to resolve scientific problems as puzzles in scientific

practices reveals the inner motivations of scientists, and such motivations can act as

potential common grounds for a science-religion dialogue.

Normal Science and Paradigms

The majority of scientific practices take place in what Kuhn calls “normal science”,

which refers to the “research firmly based upon one or more past scientific achievements,

achievements that some particular scientific community acknowledges for a time as

supplying the foundation for its further practice”85. Scientists’ acknowledgement of the

normal science-establishing foundational research can either be implicit or explicit.

Normal science sets the boundaries for scientific practices by dictating both the kind of

problems to be pursued as well as the methods to be used in such pursuits. Some

examples of agenda-setting normal science include Aristotle’s Physica, Ptolemy’s

Almagest, or Newton’s Principia and Opticks86. Scientific practices within normal

science are determined by what Kuhn calls “scientific achievements”: “Their

achievement was sufficiently unprecedented to attract an enduring group of adherents

away from competing modes of scientific activity”, and that “it was sufficiently open-

ended to leave all sorts of problems for the redefined group of practitioners to resolve”87.

The parameters that are established by past scientific achievements ensure that further

scientific development be possible, and that scientists’ efforts and resources be

consolidated to further such development. Kuhn calls scientific achievements with the

aforementioned characteristics “paradigms”. Putting the two definitions together, normal

85 Thomas S. Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2nd ed., enlarged, International Encyclopedia of Unified Science (Chicago: University of Chicago, 1970), 10. 86 Kuhn, 10. 87 Kuhn, 10.

Page 29: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

24

science consists of scientific practices that are established upon paradigms, which are

scientific achievements that both attract the interest of a significant number of scientists

and display enough potential for further development. Scientific practices do not take

place within paradigms that guarantee success; the success of paradigms – such as

Aristotle’s analysis of motion or Ptolemy’s computations of planetary position – need not

be fully realized before being considered as such88. Paradigms can represent a promise of

further success, and normal science provides scientists the venue for the actualization of

the promise89.

Paradigms Versus Rules

Kuhn argues that neither normal science nor paradigms influence scientific practices by

preparing a detailed list of instructions and conditions that scientists must seek to fulfil,

as scientists can follow a certain paradigm without agreeing with every details90. Kuhn

does not suggest that scientific practices are irrational and undetermined; rather, scientific

practices – when operating within paradigms – are not entirely determined by rules:

“Rules, I suggest, derive from paradigms, but paradigms can guide research even in the

absence of rules”91. The rules for scientific practices are not the prerequisites of

paradigms; rather, paradigms – as a focus of scientists’ commitment – precede the rules

and concepts92.

Kuhn lists four reasons for the priority of paradigms over explicit rules in scientific

practices. Firstly, unearthing the scientific rules that have guided traditions of normal

science is a “severe difficulty”93. When scientists seek to find the common ground for

certain research problems of interest in normal science, the commonality is found in

88 Kuhn, 23. 89 Kuhn, 23–24. Kuhn does not consider the scientific practices within normal science to be a source for new discoveries even if the products of normal science turn out to be useful on many fronts. According to Kuhn, scientific practices within normal science represent more of a filling in the blanks – or what Kuhn calls “mopping up operations” – in fulfilling the predictions of a paradigm. Kuhn, 24. 90 Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 44. 91 Kuhn, 42. 92 Kuhn, 11. 93 Kuhn, 46.

Page 30: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

25

scientific achievements that have been acknowledged and passed on, but not in any sets

of rules94. Secondly, concepts and laws are never learned in an isolated manner, but

through applications. The students of Newtonian physics learn better the meaning of

terms such as “force”, “mass” and “time” when the terms are being applied in problem-

solving situations than from incomplete yet somewhat helpful textbook definitions95.

Thirdly, if a scientific community wholeheartedly accepts a certain paradigm, normal

science can proceed even without rules. Conversely, discussions and debates over rules

and theories often ensue when a paradigm is insecure. The transition from Newtonian to

quantum mechanics is marked by such debates over the general nature and standards of

physics96. Fourthly, the application of scientific rules or laws is dependent upon the

professional subspecialties. The laws of quantum mechanics can be taught to physical

physicists, but how the physicists apply the laws depends on the degree to which the

respective specialties are influenced by the laws. While quantum mechanics can be a

paradigm for many groups, some groups are more influenced by the paradigm than

others97.

The four aforementioned reasons share one key commonality: Scientific practices are not

predicated by rules, and that the rules are better understood from being applied to

scientific practices. Scientists do not form any task forces to determine what goes into

paradigms; on the other hand, paradigms do not impose upon scientists as if the latter are

automatons. In scientific practices, scientists notice both conceptual and practical tools

that help to further widen and deepen the scientific discipline. Such practices are further

elucidated as instructions and rules which serve to provide formation for future scientists.

94 Kuhn, 45–46. 95 Kuhn, 46–47. 96 Kuhn, 47–48. 97 Kuhn, 49–50.

Page 31: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

26

Anomaly and Crisis

Anomaly

As aforementioned, normal science is the terrain where scientific practices take place, as

scientists explore and articulate that which is expected to occur within the parameters of,

and hence the full implication of paradigms. What happens when the outcome of

scientists’ research does not match what is expected within the paradigms of interest,

especially after the possibility of observational, experimental or calculation errors have

been ruled out? Kuhn calls such an occurrence in scientific practices an “anomaly”98.

Wilhelm Röntgen’s discovery of X-rays serves as an example: Röntgen discovers an

unexpected glow on a barium platinocyanide screen when the discharging of cathode rays

is in process. Subsequent investigations indicate that the effect results from something

else aside from the cathode rays, and that the “something else” bears some similarity to

light99. New discoveries that emerge from anomalies bear several common

characteristics: Scientists’ awareness of an anomaly; an emergence of observational and

conceptual recognition; and a potential categorical and procedural change of paradigm

that is met with resistance100. Such resistance can be explained by the nature of

paradigms: Scientific practices that take place in normal science operates within

paradigm-dependent parameters, which include specialized usage and development of

vocabularies, concepts, skills and equipment; such a process of professionalization leads

to both a restricting of scientists’ vision and a resistance to paradigm change101. An

anomaly only appears against the backdrop of established paradigms.

Crisis and Emergence of Scientific Discoveries

An anomaly threatens the status of the existing paradigm and the normal science, both of

which help to guide scientific practices. Kuhn argues that any emergence of new theories

98 Kuhn, 53. 99 Kuhn, 57. 100 Kuhn, 62. 101 Kuhn, 64.

Page 32: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

27

is generally preceded by a period of professional insecurity as the result of a persistent

failure of the existing paradigm to provide a satisfactory answer to the anomaly102.

Examples include the unsettling of an Aristotelian worldview by Galileo’s study of

motion, as well as the birth of quantum mechanics from the difficulties surrounding

phenomena such as back-body radiation and photoelectric effect103. Such unresolved

tensions often persist for a long time within an existing paradigm, and the scientific field

of interest are said to be in a state of crisis104. A crisis is a time of uncertainty, a blurring

of the existing paradigm and a loosening of rules for scientific practices within normal

science105. In other words, scientific practices can take place both within and out of the

boundaries of the existing normal science during a crisis.

Response to Crisis

Scientists can respond to a crisis with a persistent examination of the anomaly, which

creates a competition between paradigms. Comparisons are made between the scientific

practices which take place within the existing paradigm and those which take place

within the developing paradigm; the rejection of one is the acceptance of another106. A

crisis can be resolved in three ways. Firstly, normal science prevails, as the scientific

practices of normal science are able to resolve the crisis-provoking problem. Secondly,

the crisis-provoking problem comes out on top, as the scientific practices within neither

the existing nor the developing paradigm are able to provide a satisfactory solution.

Thirdly, the new paradigm emerges victorious, as such a paradigm is able to generate

solutions to the crisis in out-competing the existing paradigm, thus winning over the

acceptance of practicing scientists107. Kuhn casts the most attention on the third option

and argues that the transitioning from the existing paradigm to the novel paradigm is a

non-cumulative process; the new paradigm neither builds upon, nor is such a paradigm a

102 Kuhn, 67–68. 103 Kuhn, 67. 104 Kuhn, 67. 105 Kuhn, 84. 106 Kuhn, 77. Scientists always lend allegiance to and operate within a paradigm. The rejection of a paradigm without taking up another is akin to the rejection of science itself. Kuhn, 79. 107 Kuhn, 84.

Page 33: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

28

better and improved version of the old paradigm: “It is a reconstruction of the field from

new fundamentals, a reconstruction that changes some of the field’s most elementary

theoretical generalizations as well as many of its paradigm methods and applications”108.

The image of a foundational reconstruction is a key point that will be revisited.

Where do scientists stand in the midst of a crisis, with the blurring and emerging of

paradigms? Kuhn cites the example of the Nobel laureate Wolfgang Pauli, a theoretical

physicist. Pauli’s general disposition – and a personal shift in mood and outlook – can be

discerned from correspondences written before and after the publication of Werner

Heisenberg’s paper on matrix mechanics that paves the way for a new quantum theory.

Pauli feels hopeless and dejected before the publication: “At the moment physics is again

terribly confused. In any case, it is too difficult for me, and I wish I had been a movie

comedian or something of the sort and had never heard of physics.” The pre-publication

response stands in stark contrast to Pauli’s rejuvenated stance five months after the

publication: “Heisenberg’s type of mechanics has again given me hope and joy in life. To

be sure it does not supply the solution to the riddle, but I believe it is again possible to

march forward”109. This example of Pauli also supports the understanding that a

paradigm offers a promising way forward for scientific practices.

Not all scientists undergo the same change of mind as Pauli in encountering and

identifying the emerging paradigm. In many cases, the attitudes of scientists fluctuate

regarding the existing paradigms and the corresponding practices110. Scientists’ search for

a new paradigm may seem random at times, as if different experiments are performed in a

directionless trial-and-error manner. Scientists generate speculative theories, hoping for a

successful landing that will lead to a new paradigm; if the attempt is unsuccessful, the

theories can be discarded111. During the period of transition, Kuhn refers to the ongoing

scientific practices as transitioning from normal – that is, belong to the realm of normal

science – to extraordinary, and the transition can be detected from signs such as the

108 Kuhn, 85. 109 Kuhn, 83–84. 110 Kuhn, 90. 111 Kuhn, 87.

Page 34: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

29

proliferation of competing articulations, the willingness to try anything, the expression of

explicit discontent, the recourse to philosophy and to debate over fundamentals112. Such a

transition to a new paradigm is what Kuhn calls “scientific revolution”113.

Scientific Revolution

Why “Revolution”?

Why is the word “revolution” used to describe a change of paradigms in scientific

practices, instead of simply “change”, “shift”, “modification”, or other similar words?

Does the word “revolution” capture something that the other words do not? Kuhn argues

that “revolution” evokes a sense of the political, and parallels can be drawn between the

radical changes found in both the political and the scientific. Firstly, revolution can be

understood as a growing sense of discontent regarding the inability of the existing

institution to provide adequate solutions for problems114. Secondly, the proposed changes

of scientific practices involve demand an overhaul of the existing establishment which is

met with great resistance, coupled with a kind of lawless middle period that lacks

governance115. Kuhn compares the competition between paradigms as similar to a

competition between political institutions in “a choice between incompatible modes of

community life”116. Due to such an incompatibility, progress through scientific

revolutions cannot be cumulative, even if the achievements of scientific practices in

normal science are cumulative117.

112 Kuhn, 91. 113 Kuhn, 90. 114 This sense of revolution applies to both major paradigm changes such as that of Copernicus, or more minor ones such as the discovery of oxygen or X-rays. What may be a revolution for some may not seem to be so for others; the discovery of X-rays is a major shift of paradigm for those whose research focuses on radiation theory, but not so for astronomers whose paradigms are untouched by the said discovery. Kuhn, 92–93. 115 Kuhn, 93. 116 Kuhn, 94. 117 Kuhn, 96.

Page 35: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

30

The Necessity of Revolutions

More importantly, Kuhn does not think that such a mode of competition and

incompatibility is one of the ways through which discoveries are made by scientists;

revolution is the only way:

Unanticipated novelty, the new discovery, can emerge only to the extent that his anticipations about nature and his instruments prove wrong. Often the importance of the resulting discovery will itself be proportional to the extent and stubbornness of the anomaly that foreshadowed it. Obviously, then, there must be a conflict between the paradigm that discloses anomaly and the one that later renders the anomaly law-like. […] There is no other effective way in which discoveries might be generated.118

The stark contrast between the unanticipated discovery and the anticipated result of the

existing paradigm is akin to the difference between right and wrong; the new discovery

proves the old paradigm wrong. Given the incompatibility between right and wrong,

Kuhn argues that a satisfactory explanation of an anomaly that defies the existing

paradigm implies a fundamental and necessary incompatibility. The same argument

applies to the discovery of new scientific theories:

Paradigms provide all phenomena except anomalies with a theory-determined place in the scientist’s field of vision. But if new theories are called forth to resolve anomalies in the relation of an existing theory to nature, then the successful new theory must somewhere permit predictions that are different from those derived from its predecessor. That difference could not occur if the two were logically compatible. In the process of being assimilated, the second must displace the first.119

A prominent example is the shift from Newtonian and Einsteinian physics, that Einstein’s

theory can only be accepted as right if the falsity of Newton’s theory is accepted120, and

any attempt to reconcile the two involves a fundamental change in scientists’ worldview

118 Kuhn, 96–97. 119 Kuhn, 97. 120 Kuhn, 98.

Page 36: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

31

that will destroy the distinctive character of the new theory121. Kuhn goes even further to

argue for the stark difference between two competing paradigms: “And as the problems

change, so, often, does the standard that distinguishes a real scientific solution from a

mere metaphysical speculation, word game, or mathematical play. The normal-scientific

tradition that emerges from a scientific revolution is not only incompatible but often

actually incommensurable with that which has gone before”122. When two things are

incommensurable, neither a common basis, measure nor standard are available as tools

for comparison. There are no common standards because the standards are neither raised

nor lowered, but rather changed with the changing of a paradigm123. Such a view of

incommensurability contributes to the often-futile debates between scientists who

embrace different paradigms as scientists “talk through” each other124, and Kuhn

describes scientists’ changing of allegiance from one paradigm to another as a conversion

that goes beyond proof or error125. The incommensurability between two competing

paradigms highlights a comprehensive change in scientific practices: The development of

the newer paradigm influences scientific practices by introducing a new way of

understanding and tackling a scientific problem.

121 Kuhn admits that the either-Einstein-or-Newton position does not represent the majority of the views, and Kuhn summarizes the opposition of such a position: Newtonian dynamics is still being successfully applied by engineers and physicists. Furthermore, Einstein’s theory can be used to prove Newton’s ideas in some restrictive conditions. Kuhn disagrees, as such a restriction prevents scientists from relying on the scientists’ own research and theories when entering uncharted territories, hence halting scientific development. Kuhn also doubts whether Newtonian physics can really be derived from relativistic physics. Such a view of continuity can only be achieved with a drastic change in the definition of variables in Newtonian equations: “Simultaneously we have had to alter the fundamental structural elements of which the universe to which they apply is composed.” This kind of change renders Newtonian physics un-Newtonian. Kuhn, 98–102. 122 Kuhn, 103. 123 Kuhn, 108. 124 Kuhn, 109. 125 Kuhn, 151. Kuhn has often been criticized for proposing the legitimacy of irrationality through the usage of the word “conversion”. Kuhn tries to debunk the criticism in the postscript of The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, whereby the usage of the word “incommensurability” is clarified: “Two men who perceive the same situation differently but nevertheless employ the same vocabulary in its discussion must be using words differently. They speak, that is, from what I have called incommensurable viewpoints. How can they even hope to talk together much less to be persuasive.” The kind of talking through each other that I mention in the main text is what Kuhn calls a “communication breakdown”. Kuhn argues that the two scientists who operate within competing paradigms belong to “different language communities” and that the scientists need to become “translators” in order to communicate with the other. The other’s “language” – that is, the other’s paradigm – needs to be comprehended, and the scientists’ own theories need to be communicated in the other’s “language”: “Since translation, if pursued, allows the participants in a communication breakdown to experience vicariously something of the merits and defects of each other’s point of view, it is a potent tool both for persuasion and for conversion”. Kuhn, 200–203.

Page 37: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

32

Paradigm Shift as a Change of Worldview

The comprehensiveness of the change in scientific practices during a scientific revolution

is akin to a change in how scientists see the world – or, the world that pertains to the

scientists – as a whole. Kuhn likens such a change to learning to see a new gestalt: The

seeing of the new gestalt signals the abandonment of the old gestalt. Since not every

scientist actively participates in a scientific revolution, the worldview of scientists must

be re-educated as scientists learn to see a new gestalt126. Kuhn cites the discovery of the

planet Uranus as an example. Between the Seventeenth and Eighteenth Centuries,

Astronomers note the presence of a star in the position that Uranus occupies, but further

descriptions are impossible due to technological limitations. With the aid of an improved

telescope in observing the motion of Uranus among the stars, Sir William Hershel

concludes that Uranus is in fact a comet in 1781. The conclusion is disputed by Anders

Johan Lexell only a few months later, as the latter endures through fruitless attempts of

fitting the observed motion of Uranus into a cometary orbit. Lexell suggests that the

observed orbit of Uranus is probably planetary in character, and the acceptance of such a

suggestion by fellow astronomers signals a paradigm shift127. Once the planetary

character of Uranus is understood, Uranus can never be seen as a comet again.

Resolutions of Scientific Revolutions

While both competitions between paradigms and scientific revolutions may take many

years to manifest, neither competition nor revolution continues for perpetuity. How are

scientific revolutions resolved? Kuhn thinks that the changing of the minds of scientists

are very difficult even in the presence of proof, while citing similar sentiments expressed

by both Charles Darwin and Max Planck128. Kuhn does not consider such a resistance to

126 Kuhn, 112. 127 Kuhn, 115–116. 128 Kuhn is hardly alone in thinking that the minds of scientists are difficult to change. Neither Darwin nor Planck seem particularly optimistic about the prospect of scientists’ changing of minds. Towards the end of Origin of Species, Darwin writes: “Although I am fully convinced of the truth of the views given in this volume […] I by no means expect to convince experienced naturalists whose minds are stocked with a

Page 38: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

33

change as antithetic to scientific progress; in fact, resistance is an integral part of that

which is scientific practice:

The source of resistance is the assurance that the older paradigm will ultimately solve all its problems, that nature can be shoved into the box that the paradigm provides. Inevitably, at times of revolution, that assurance seems stubborn and pigheaded as indeed it sometimes becomes. […] That same assurance is what makes normal or puzzle-solving science possible. And it is only through normal science that the professional community of scientists succeeds, first, in exploiting the potential scope and precision of the older paradigm and, then, in isolating the difficulty through the study of which a new paradigm may emerge.129

Resistance is part of the fabric of normal science, the necessary tenacity required of

scientists to pursue scientific interests. The same kind of attitude can be found in

scientists’ pursuits that result in scientific revolutions. Both normal science and scientific

revolutions are driven by scientists’ belief that the paradigm of choice is able to provide

satisfactory answers through the respective scientific practices. Given the personal

involvement of scientists, scientific proofs alone cannot sway scientists in a change of

opinions and minds. In addition to the superiority of the emerging paradigm in solving

scientific problems that evade the old paradigm, there also exists other factors: For

instance, there is an aesthetic component which appeals to scientists, that the theory

provided by the new paradigm is “neater”, “more suitable” or “simpler” when comparing

to that of the old paradigm130. There is also the forward-looking aspect: The favoured

paradigm is more promising in guiding and directing further research regarding problems

that remain unresolved131. Ultimately, scientists take a long time to be convinced; the

conversion of an entire group of scientists is rare, and a slow shift in the distribution of

professional allegiances to a certain paradigm is more common132. The increase of

multitude of facts all viewed, during a long course of years, from a point of view directly opposite to mine. […] [B]ut I look with confidence to the future, to young and rising naturalists, who will be able to view both sides of the question with impartiality.” In Planck’s scientific autobiography, Planck similarly remarks that “a new scientific truth does not triumph by convincing its opponents and making them see the light, but rather because its opponents eventually die, and a new generation grows up that is familiar with it”. Kuhn, 151. 129 Kuhn, 151–152. 130 Kuhn, 155. 131 Kuhn, 157. 132 Kuhn, 158.

Page 39: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

34

membership in a certain paradigm leads to more research and a subsequent improvement

of the paradigm, which in turn increases the paradigm’s competitiveness until the

paradigm begins to adopt the mode of a normal science by out-competing the rival

paradigm133. Scientists’ switching of paradigms and the subsequent increase in

membership signal a change in the dominant mode of scientific practices.

While the ways in which scientific practices are conducted may change according to the

dominant theory of the day, such a change is possible only when scientists decide to trust

the new theory and subsequently modify the practices. How do scientists decide upon

which scientific problems to pursue? What motivates scientists in pursuing scientific

practices in the first place? The context of normal science needs to be examined in order

to properly understand the motivation of scientists.

Aim of Normal Science

Kuhn lists three major foci for scientific investigations within the context of the dominant

paradigm, and the three foci are never entirely distinct from each other134. The first type

of experiment focuses on scientific facts that – through the paradigm – “have shown to be

particularly revealing of the nature of things”135. Examples of the revelation of “the

nature of things” include wavelengths and spectral intensities in physics, as well as

boiling point and acidity of solutions in chemistry136. The second type strives to

demonstrate an agreement between theoretical prediction and observable fact, and the

scintillation counter that is designed to demonstrate the existence of the neutrino serves

as an example137. The third type of experiment strives to exhaust the implications of a

paradigm, an effort which involves the thorough articulation of a paradigm theory and the

resolution of ambiguities138. Examples include the determination of a universal constant

133 Kuhn, 159. 134 Kuhn, 25. 135 Kuhn, 25. 136 Kuhn, 25. 137 Kuhn, 26–27. 138 Kuhn, 27.

Page 40: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

35

such as Joule’s co-efficient139, and the articulation of quantitative laws such as Joule’s

formula relating generated heat to electrical resistance and current140. The three foci of

scientific experiments describe the objects of interest in scientific practices; however,

Kuhn thinks that the success in better articulating a paradigm through addressing the

whats does not, and cannot, account for the “enthusiasm and devotion” that scientists

show141; the motivations of scientists are to be understood through a different lens.

Motivation: To Solve Puzzles

Kuhn argues that there can be many reasons behind scientists’ being engaged in scientific

practices in the first place: A desire to be useful; an excitement to explore new territories;

a hope to find order; a drive to put established knowledge to test, and so on142. The

aforementioned reasons, however, do not adequately reflect what actually takes place

within scientists:

The scientific enterprise as a whole does from time to time prove useful, open up new territory, display order, and test long-accepted belief. Nevertheless, the individual engaged on a normal research problem is almost never doing any one of these things. Once engaged, his motivation is of a rather different sort. What then challenges him is the conviction that, if only he is skillful enough, he will succeed in solving a puzzle that no one before has solved or solved so well.143

In scientific practices, scientists consider the research question of interest to be like a

puzzle, and scientists are motivated to solve the puzzle with creativity, skillfulness and

determination144; however, Kuhn is adamant about the value of scientific problems that

are viewed as puzzles: “It is no criterion of goodness in a puzzle that its outcome be

intrinsically interesting or important”145. The objects of scientific research need not

139 Kuhn, 28. 140 Kuhn, 28. 141 Kuhn, 36. 142 Kuhn, 37. 143 Kuhn, 38. 144 Kuhn, 36–37. 145 Kuhn, 36.

Page 41: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

36

possess any intrinsic value which serves as an attraction for scientists. One major

criterion of puzzles is that an attainable outcome be necessary146; with such a criterion in

mind, problems such as a cure for cancer cannot be considered a puzzle because there is

not, and may not be any foreseeable solution147. The attainable outcome also highlights

the necessary focus in scientific practices: While scientists may sincerely desire to cure

cancer, the project at hand may only entail an analysis of how the modification of a

certain protein’s amino acid sequence affects tumour growth in mice, and the scientists’

involvement may simply be the creation of the transgenic mice at one point, and the

analysis of protein-protein interaction under an in vitro setting at another. The puzzle of

interest, then, is not a cure for cancer per se but rather “how does the alteration of the

amino acid sequence affect the interaction between protein A and proteins B, C, D along

with E”. While the outcome of a puzzle needs to be attainable, how the puzzle is solved

needs not be predictable. Hence such a pursuit is a challenge to the scientists’ ingenuity

and skill.

Puzzles and Parameters

While scientists are free to choose which puzzles to tackle, such a selection takes place

within certain parameters: “One of the things a scientific community acquires with a

paradigm is a criterion for choosing problems that, while the paradigm is taken for

granted, can be assumed to have solutions. To a great extent these are the only problems

that the community will admit as scientific or encourage its members to undertake”148.

The parameters of the puzzles are determined by the boundaries which are set by the

paradigm-dependent scientific community. Paradigms provide the necessary conceptual

and instrumental tools that are needed for scientific practices149. For instance, an issue

such as “the design of a lasting peace” cannot be reduced to a puzzle form150, and

scientists have neither the vocabulary nor the tools to tackle such an issue as a puzzle.

146 Kuhn, 37. 147 Kuhn, 37. 148 Kuhn, 37. 149 Kuhn, 37. 150 Kuhn, 37.

Page 42: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

37

Moreover, the parameters provided by paradigms must also include rules which set limits

to both the kind of solutions that are deemed acceptable and the practical procedures that

are performed in striving towards the solutions151. There are necessarily limiting factors

to solving a jigsaw puzzle: There is a predetermined image of interest; the project is

limited by the very nature of the puzzle, as the jigsaw puzzle pieces must go together in

an interlocking manner until everything fits in one piece and the intended image can be

seen. While the puzzle pieces can be alternatively arranged in a non-interlocking manner

to form a contemporary piece of art, such a completed piece will not be considered a

solution152. Kuhn proposes that “rule” be more widely understood as “established

viewpoint” or “preconception”. As an example, scientists who want to measure optical

wave lengths will not build an instrument that simply correlate certain numbers to certain

spectral lines. Rather, scientists already have an “established viewpoint” in mind; that is,

the established optical theory and numbers that represent wave lengths153. Scientists’

motivation to solve puzzles requires a commitment to certain established rules that are

provided by existing paradigms. In addition to methodological commitments, there exists

a higher level of commitment involving the scientists’ worldview which Kuhn describes

as “quasi-metaphysical”. René Descartes’ influential writings give shape to the

worldview of many scientists in Descartes’ time, in that natural phenomena – and

ultimately, the universe – can be explained through the lens of corpuscularism. Scientists’

commitment to such a Cartesian worldview helps to determine the methodological

approaches taken in the scientific practices of the time154. The commitment to a particular

worldview also provides a standard for scrutinizing the scientific practices of others155.

151 Kuhn, 38. 152 Kuhn, 38. 153 Kuhn, 39. 154 Kuhn, 41. 155 Kuhn, 42. Kuhn’s discussion of scientists’ motivation in scientific practices as a desire to solve puzzles takes place within the context of paradigms during the time of normal science. What about scientists’ motivation during a crisis? Recall that the scientific experiments that lead to a crisis stem from normal science; in other words, motivations that apply during a period of normal science remain valid during a crisis. If the crisis leads to a scientific revolution, there is necessarily a period of flux in which the boundaries of the old paradigm disintegrate, while that of a new paradigm begins to take shape. How are puzzles selected during this period? Kuhn doesn’t address such a point in The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, but an educated guess can be taken: Since puzzles are chosen within the boundaries of a paradigm, the new puzzle is probably chosen within the still-forming parameters of the new paradigm.

Page 43: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

38

Both the motivation to solve scientific problems as puzzles and the commitment to a

certain worldview reflect a personal involvement of scientists. Scientists must decide the

kind of puzzles to tackle and the kind of worldview to embrace. Such decisions are made

whether scientific practices take place in normal science or an emerging paradigm. Such

personal involvement of scientists can become more valuable if scholars from other

disciplines – such as religion – also value personal worldviews and personal motivations

as a compass for scholarly research.

Scientific Practices and Community

The link between scientific practices on an individual and communal level is found in

scientists’ subscription to paradigms. In order that a paradigm become prominent in the

scientific community, a sufficient number of scientists must subscribe to the paradigm,

directly leading to the prevalence of certain scientific practices. Once the influence of the

paradigm reaches a critical level in the scientific community, the paradigm becomes the

standard that is followed by other scientists th1rough educational means. Students who

aspire to become scientists must study the paradigms of interest by learning the accepted

rules and standards of the current scientific practices, in order that the students both

become engaged in scientific practices and be considered members of the scientific

community156. The students are learning the fundamentals that are shared by fellow

scientists which include the specialized vocabularies, the specific theories and formulae,

the scientific instruments, the procedures of specific experiments, the acceptable

standards of results, and so on. As discussed in an earlier section, paradigms give rise to

rules, not vice versa. Similarly, scientists in training learn about scientific practices

within the context of paradigms without much explicit outlines on the characteristics of

the paradigms157. Kuhn argues that such learning is reflected in the nature of scientific

education: “Scientists, it should already be clear, never learn concepts, laws, and theories

in the abstract and by themselves. Instead, intellectual tools are from the start

156 Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 11. 157 Kuhn, 46.

Page 44: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

39

encountered in a historically and pedagogically prior unit that displays them with and

through their applications”158. Scientists are educated primarily through concrete

applications but not abstract concepts.

In addition to learning through applications, Kuhn also stresses the importance of books –

such as scientific textbooks, books that popularize science and philosophical works about

science – in educating others about scientific practices159. Books, along with teachers, are

the two sources of authority from which students learn scientific theories and discoveries

that are part and parcel of scientific practices. The outcome of past scientific revolutions

are recorded in textbooks to illustrate the foundation of the current normal science160; in

other words, textbooks do not illustrate the revolutionary process through which the

current normal science comes about. When scientific revolutions take place and the

normal science is overthrown, normal science-embracing textbooks need to be rewritten.

The rewriting of textbooks continues the trend of only mentioning that which pertains to

the normal science of the day, as the content of the textbooks “inevitably disguise not

only the role but the very existence of the revolutions that produced them”161. While the

outcome of a scientific revolution is documented, taught and propagated, the process

which leads to the outcome is not, thus rendering the nature of scientific revolutions

invisible162.

Summary

I have argued that scientific practices change according to the ebbs and flows of scientific

revolution. I have also argued that scientific problems are chosen and solved like puzzles

as scientists see fit, and such a choice reveals both the inner motivation and the

worldview of scientists that can potentially act as a common ground for science-religion

dialogue. Other scholars have already taken Kuhn’s insights on revolutions to consider

158 Kuhn, 46. 159 Kuhn, 136. 160 Kuhn, 137. 161 Kuhn, 137. 162 Kuhn, 136.

Page 45: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

40

other academic disciplines in a different light, so there is potential to the appropriation of

other Kuhnian insights in an attempt to speak a common language across disciplines.

Kuhn’s insights regarding the dynamics of a scientific revolution controversially deviate

from a more conventional understanding of the formation of scientific knowledge, as

scientific practices before and after the revolution can be seen as incommensurable with

each other, and that the key pursuit in scientists’ practices comes from a desire that is

personally-driven but not knowledge-driven.

Both interpretive frameworks of Polanyi and Kuhn are grounded in scientific practices

and show promises in providing a common language in a science-religion dialogue. In

what ways are the two approaches similar and different? How do such similarities and

differences affect the ability to engage in a science-religion dialogue? Is one interpretive

framework preferable over another, and if so, for what reasons? The aforementioned

questions provide the framework of the following chapter.

Page 46: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

41

Chapter Three: Critical Engagement of Polanyi and Kuhn

In the following comparison of the thoughts of Polanyi and Kuhn on scientific practices, I

argue that despite significant similarities, a philosophical difference exists beneath the

divergence of thought between Polanyi and Kuhn with regards to knowledge, truth, and

the personal involvement of scientists. The discovery of the philosophical underpinnings

of Polanyi and Kuhn is important in setting the stage for a critical assessment of the ways

in which science can potentially interact with religion.

On Scientific Practices: Similarities Between Polanyi

and Kuhn

Motivations and Passions

Both Polanyi and Kuhn consider the personal involvement of scientists in scientific

practices to be important. Such importance is most evident in the discussion of the

passions behind the motivations of scientists.

Whereas Polanyi explicitly names the passions (intellectual, heuristic, and persuasive),

Kuhn does not; nevertheless, Kuhn speaks of “desire”, “excitement”, “hope”, and “drive”

when describing that which attracts scientists to pursue scientific practices163. According

to Kuhn, the aforementioned desires are not what ultimately motivate scientists in

scientific practices; the most fundamental desires is to solve puzzles in a competent

manner164. The solving of puzzles requires that scientists be creative, skillful and

determined165. Such descriptions compare favourably to a part of what Polanyi calls

intellectual and heuristic passion166: The intellectual passion of scientists provides the

163 Kuhn, 37. 164 Kuhn, 38. 165 Kuhn, 36–37. 166 A complete parallel between Kuhn’s ideas and Polanyi’s intellectual and heuristic passion is not being endorsed here. In fact, there are some stark differences between the two authors regarding another aspect of intellectual passion of scientists; that is, the kind of vision that ultimately attracts scientists in scientific

Page 47: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

42

necessary persistence in the scientists’ pursuit of a discovery, whereas heuristic passion

provides scientists with the drive to engage in scientific practices in a resourceful and

creative manner167. Moreover, Kuhn’s insistence that scientists must persuade others to

convert to the scientists’ own paradigm resonates with what Polanyi describes as

persuasive passion, as both authors stress that proof and evidence alone cannot change

the mind of scientists168. Both argue that the purpose of such persuasion is to convert a

scientist’s personal worldview, with Kuhn adding that such conversion is necessitated by

the incommensurability of paradigms. Intimately linked to the conversion of scientists is

the scientists’ commitment: According to Polanyi, scientists are committed to both an

independent standard – and ultimately, an obligation towards truth – that is beyond the

scientists169, and a belief that the results of the scientists’ research do indeed reflect reality

even at the risk of being wrong170. For Kuhn, scientists commit to both a personal

worldview that influences the decisions made in scientific practices, and the adoption of

paradigms either in normal science or during a crisis171. The commitment to a certain

paradigm results in the slow rate of conversion from one paradigm to another, and also

the resistance to the suggestion of a new paradigm172.

The Authority of the Scientific Community

In addition to similarities on the individual level, there are also similarities between the

views of Polanyi and Kuhn regarding scientific practices on the level of the scientific

community, with the key similarity being the authority of the community. For Polanyi,

the scientific community is made up of scientists who inherit scientific practices from

practices. The issue of scientists’ visions will be addressed in the next section when the differences between Polanyi and Kuhn are examined. 167 Polanyi, Personal Knowledge, 143. 168 Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 151; Polanyi, Personal Knowledge, 150. 169 Polanyi, Personal Knowledge, 63. 170 Polanyi, 310. 171 Thomas S. Kuhn, ‘The Function of Dogma in Scientific Research’, in Scientific Change: Historical Studies in the Intellectual, Social, and Technical Conditions for Scientific Discovery and Technical Invention, from Antiquity to the Present (Symposium on the History of Science (1961: Oxford, England)), ed. Alistair Cameron Crombie (New York, NY: Basic Books, 1963), 375; Martin X. Moleski, ‘Polanyi Vs. Kuhn: Worldviews Apart’, Tradition and Discovery 33, no. 2 (2006): 8–9. 172 Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 151–152.

Page 48: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

43

mentor scientists and in turn the latter’s mentors from the past:

Science exists as a body of wide-ranging authoritative knowledge only so long as the consensus of scientists continues. It lives and grows only so long as this consensus can resolve the perpetual tension between discipline and originality. Every succeeding generation is sovereign in reinterpreting the tradition of science. With it rests the fatal responsibility of the self-renewal of scientific convictions and methods. To speak of science and its continued progress is to profess faith in its fundamental principles: and in the integrity of scientists in applying and amending these principles.173

The consensus between scientists is not a unanimous decision on everything pertaining to

scientific practices; rather, the consensus is dynamic with room for tensions and

reinterpretations. While the traditions that are passed on through the scientific community

are authoritative, traditions can only remain authoritative through the practicing scientists

who continue to assent to such traditions; such an understanding of authority points to the

intimate link between the individual and the communal. For Kuhn, the scientific

community is authoritative in determining the kind of scientific practices and knowledge

that are performed and propagated. Authority is shaped by the dominant paradigm that is

adopted by the scientific community. While individual scientists certainly participate in

the scientific community through scientific practices, Kuhn argues that the scientific

community is not an entity that is simply a collection of the voice of individual scientists:

When important decisions need to be made regarding the general direction of scientific

practices, the responsibility lies not on the shoulders of individual scientists but rather of

the scientific community, as if the latter takes on a role that is greater than the sum of the

parts174. The similarities between the thoughts of Polanyi and Kuhn have been well-

documented, and the two scholars clearly have an admiration for each other’s work175.

Despite the similarities, major differences ultimately set Polanyi and Kuhn apart,

revealing the underlying philosophical differences. In the next section, I discuss two key

differences: The ways in which scientific practices contribute to scientific progress, and

the teleology behind scientific practices.

173 Polanyi, Science, Faith and Society, 16. 174 Kuhn, ‘The Function of Dogma in Scientific Research’, 394–395. 175 Kuhn, 375–393.

Page 49: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

44

On Scientific Practices: Differences Between Polanyi

and Kuhn

Scientific Progress

Polanyi: Cumulative

For Polanyi, scientific community is where scientific progress takes place. Polanyi sees

scientific progress as cumulative in several ways. Firstly, tradition is the foundation of the

scientific community. Scientists are trained by mentors, who in turn are mentored by

earlier scientists. The scientific knowledge that are embedded in scientific practices are

passed on through tradition. Scientific progress can be traced through such a line of

tradition. The inheritance of a scientific tradition also includes a necessity to reinterpret

such a tradition, as well as a renewing of scientific convictions and methods176. The

constant need for renewal must be distinguished from a complete overhaul in which the

new product bears no resemblance to the inherited scientific practices. Major renewals

take place within the tradition that has been passed on. The discoveries of tomorrow are

built upon the achievements of the past.

Secondly, the scientific community has enough room to house more than just one

perspective. The consensus amongst scientists is not rigid, and the consensus is able to

handle the constant tension between discipline and originality177. Polanyi does not

elucidate how the balancing act occurs, but an educated guess can be taken based on how

Polanyi considers the interactions between fellow scientists. Scientists often disagree

with each other, and the persuasive passion of scientists can lead to a resolution of such

disagreements. Persuasive passion is necessary because scientific practices and the

generated knowledge fundamentally personal, according to Polanyi’s understanding of

personal knowledge. Persuasion takes place between two scientists who are connected in

a network of accreditation between other scientists, but not between two strangers

176 Polanyi, Science, Faith and Society, 16. 177 Polanyi, 16.

Page 50: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

45

without any previous ties. Disagreements may persist beyond the current generation of

scientists, and a resolution may only surface later. Such a delay of resolution does not

eliminate the fact that both scientists are working within a shared accreditation; the

shared commonality is the foundation of the cumulative nature of scientific progress.

Kuhn: Paradigm-Dependent Progress and Regress

Kuhn argues that scientific progress can be better understood by looking at how progress

is understood in other disciplines. In disciplines such as history, philosophy, arts and

literature, students have direct access to the works of the pivotal players of the respective

fields from past to present178, which gives the students a broader historical appreciation of

the fields of interest, and especially an appreciation for the competing ideas: “ (The

student) has constantly before him a number of competing and incommensurable

solutions to these problems, solutions that he must ultimately evaluate for himself”179.

Such a perspective is congruent with Kuhn’s conception of paradigms and scientific

revolutions: In the face of competing paradigms, scientists must judge the evidence at

hand and make a personal decision to pledge allegiance to one paradigm.

Scientific progress is defined by the dominant paradigm of the time. Insofar as the

paradigm of normal science is successful in providing scientists with the tools to solve

scientific problems, the resolution to such problems can be considered as progress within

normal science180. When a crisis happens and a new paradigm begins to emerge, the

ensuing success can also be considered as progress181. In other words, there is scientific

progress in both normal science and the aftermath of a scientific revolution. More

importantly, such a progress is determined by the group of scientists who are behind the

scientific achievements, as Kuhn argues that the definition of scientific progress partly

“lies simply in the eye of the beholder”182. The beholders are the scientists who subscribe

178 Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 165. 179 Kuhn, 165. 180 Kuhn, 166. 181 Kuhn, 166. 182 Kuhn, 163.

Page 51: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

46

to the problem-solving potential of certain paradigms, and the scientists inevitably

consider the success in the scientists’ own practices as progress. Scientists determine

what defines scientific progress according to the success or failure of the scientists’ own

subscribed paradigms. When a group of scientists out-competes another with a new

paradigm, a new normal science is established and the victor considers such advancement

as progress. When the group of victorious scientists are subsequently defeated by another

group of scientists because the latter’s paradigm proves to be even more successful, then

the former will consider such a happening as regress. Given the competitive nature

between opposing paradigms, Kuhn’s view of scientific progress is non-cumulative. The

present does not build upon the past; rather, the present is the victor over the past. A

scientific revolution overthrows the previous paradigm, just as a revolution overthrows a

past regime.

Continuity or Rupture?

Scientific practices play different roles in various stages of scientific progress for Polanyi

and Kuhn: While both think that scientists try to change the minds of other scientists,

Polanyi considers such confrontation as an integral part of scientific practices, whereas

Kuhn sees such an act of conversion – and ultimately the success of the conversion – as a

break from the past. Scientists either participate in a continual construction of the corpus

of scientific knowledge or a winner-take-all competition which may result in a

revolution183. The differences between the two scholars can be visualized as such:

Polanyi’s idea of scientific progress is like a system of roads that has sufficient room to

encompass disagreements and tensions between scientists; Kuhn’s idea of scientific

progress sees the paths traveled by scientists as disconnected segments that are isolated at

both ends, first by the revolution that opened the new path and then by the next

revolution that closed it. For Kuhn, the progress made by normal science in exploring the

path created by a revolution is incommensurable with what came before and what comes

after; each normal science – through the respective paradigms – has different standards

183 Granted, crisis and scientific revolutions seldom take place, and not all scientists are participants.

Page 52: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

47

and is not contingent upon the previous paradigm184.

An Evolutionary Kind of Progress

Kuhn also argues that scientific progress resembles development of a certain kind: “The

developmental process described in this essay has been a process of evolution from

primitive beginnings – a process whose successive stages are characterized by an

increasingly detailed and refined understanding of nature. But nothing that has been or

will be said makes it a progress of evolution toward anything”185. The success of a certain

paradigm – and, by extension, the success of scientists’ puzzle-solving – is illustrated by

an increasingly improved understanding of nature. More importantly, the competition

between two paradigms can be compared to the competition between two species as is

seen in evolution: The one who is more successful in solving key puzzles of interest is the

“fitter” of the two, and the former propagates the problem-solving method by setting the

standard for future generations. There may come a time of crisis in which the dominating

paradigm must be readjusted, just as a species needs to evolve to better adapt to

environmental stress. The paradigm continues until such a paradigm fails to provide

solutions to certain problems, and is rendered extinct by another paradigm that provides

solutions to solving the said problems186.

184 Kuhn’s idea of scientific progress drastically differs from the more traditional concept that progress is characterized by the accumulation of scientific knowledge, that such an accumulation depends on an independent standard that can serve as a kind of arbiter. Martin Moleski criticizes Kuhn’s idea regarding progress as such: If there is no universal criterion to evaluate scientific knowledge across different paradigms due to their incommensurability, then how can there be any progress? Moleski also rejects Kuhn’s idea of a progress that is determined by the scientific community. Moleski, ‘Polanyi Vs. Kuhn’, 16. 185 Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 170–171. 186 Analogies are never completely waterproof, and at times can raise more questions than provide answers. For example, while the comparison between scientific progress with evolution does well to highlight the aspect of competition between paradigms, such a comparison also seems to assume that there is always a better-adapted paradigm on the horizon, and no paradigms dominate forever. Certainly, the more adapted of the two species wins out in the evolutionary process often enough. A species can also adapt to the environment through hundreds and thousands of generations. For instance, the homo sapiens from more than 100,000 years ago would be quite different from that of today. Can such an adaptation be compared to a paradigm? If a paradigm continues to adapt to the pertinent problem of the times to the extent that the current paradigm looks drastically different from the original version, what criteria are employed to ensure that the evolved paradigm has remained the same paradigm, or has the adapting paradigm evolved or mutated into another paradigm altogether? Can a successful paradigm reach the pinnacle of evolution and be invincible against others?

Page 53: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

48

Such a comparison to evolution highlights the importance of directionality, or a lack

thereof: “A sort of progress will inevitably characterize the scientific enterprise so long as

such an enterprise survives. In the sciences there need not be progress of another sort. We

may, to be more precise, have to relinquish the notion, explicit or implicit, that changes of

paradigm carry scientists and those who learn from them closer and closer to the

truth”187. The implicit goal of a scientific enterprise is that such scientific enterprise and

the operating paradigm “survive”, that the scientific enterprise not be rendered obsolete

by others who operate with another paradigm; in other words, survival per se can be

considered as progress in the eyes of the followers of a paradigm. Such a mode of

survival harkens to the process of evolution, in that the survival of a species is considered

through the success or failure of the species’ propagation of progenies. Kuhn links the

evolutionary process to the lack of a telos: Just as there needs not be a goal in evolution

other than survival, scientific progress needs not be associated with a pursuit of truth188.

Polanyi and Kuhn differs greatly on whether any teleos in scientific practices is

necessary, and such a difference is the topic of discussion in the next section.

Teleology of Scientific Practices

Different Motivations

The difference between Polanyi and Kuhn regarding the teleology of scientific practices

can be clearly seen in the motivations of scientists. Kuhn argues that the motivation

which underlies all other motivations is a desire to solve puzzles in a competent manner.

Puzzles do not appear out of the blue, and scientists must decide to see puzzles as

puzzles. In other words, the motivation comes from a desire to solve scientific problems

that scientists have chosen to consider as such. Polanyi argues that the motivations of

scientists have everything to do with the scientists’ goal in scientific practices. Scientists

187 Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 171. 188 In The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, Kuhn does not address the issue regarding truth until the last few pages. Kuhn’s move seems to be intentional, as Kuhn does not think that truth – or, the ways in which truth has been understood in scientific practices – contributes much in the Kuhnian vision of scientific practices. Kuhn, 170–173.

Page 54: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

49

are attracted by an intellectual beauty that is characterized by a contact with reality189.

Heuristic passion stems from scientists’ intellectual passion as a desire to discover such

intellectual beauty190. Equipped with a new discovery, scientists are driven by persuasive

passion to convince others of the new findings which are believed to be reflective of a

part of reality191. In the eyes of Kuhn, scientists are attracted by what stems from within;

that is, the satisfaction of solving a puzzle. For Polanyi, scientists are attracted by

something from without, a glimpse of reality which subsequently becomes the object of

scientific pursuits.

Kuhn: A Context-Dependent Scientific Practice

Are teleologically self-directed scientific practices problematic? Kuhn doesn’t think so;

in fact, Kuhn has serious doubts about the need for any kind of telos in scientific

practices, especially in how the goal of scientific practices has been traditionally

understood:

We are all deeply accustomed to seeing science as the one enterprise that draws constantly nearer to some goal set by nature in advance. But need there be such a goal? Can we not account for both science’s existence and its success in terms of evolution from the community’s state of knowledge at any given time? Does it really help to imagine that there is some one full, objective, true account of nature and that the proper measure of scientific achievement is the extent to which it brings us closer to that ultimate goal?192

Kuhn rejects an objectivity that is simply “out there” around which scientists revolve;

nature per se cannot be the goal for scientists193. On the other hand, not having an

189 Polanyi, Personal Knowledge, 135. 190 Polanyi, 143. 191 Polanyi, 150. 192 Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 171. 193 Kuhn opposes the idea that nature is the objective standard by default after which scientists pursue, but Kuhn is not hostile towards the idea of understanding nature. For example, one of the characteristics of a paradigm is that a paradigm is “particularly revealing of the nature of things”; scientists try to bring nature and theory into closer agreement through scientific practices; scientists try to force nature to fit into a “preformed and inflexible box” that is the paradigm; an anomaly signifies some difficulties in the fit between paradigm and nature; scientific experiments seen as puzzle-solving involves a comparison between a paradigm and nature. In short, scientists explore and examine nature through scientific practices,

Page 55: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

50

objective, “out there” nature as an aim does not mean that scientific practices have no aim

at all. The aim goes from being dictated by nature to being dictated by the scientists, as

scientists decide on what problems to solve194. The success resulting from scientific

practices is not so much an explicit aim of scientists but rather a product of prevailing

against other competing paradigms. On a smaller scale in scientific practices, scientists

determine the goal; on a larger scale of paradigms and scientific community, there needs

not be any overarching goals at all.

Kuhn’s rejection of nature that is “out there” as the aim of scientific practices has another

implication, on which Kuhn elaborates in the postscript of The Structure of Scientific

Revolutions:

One often hears that successive theories grow ever closer to, or approximate more and more closely to, the truth. Apparently generalizations like that refer not to the puzzle-solutions and the concrete predictions derived from a theory but rather to its ontology, to the match, that is, between the entities with which the theory populates nature and what is “really there”. Perhaps there is some other way of salvaging the notion of ‘truth’ for application to whole theories, but this one will not do. There is, I think, no theory-independent way to reconstruct phrases like ‘really there’; the notion of a match between the ontology of a theory and its “real” counterpart in nature now seems to me illusive in principle.195

Kuhn does not envision scientific practices as contributing to the exploration of a nature

that is “really there”, an approach which Kuhn terms “ontological”. Kuhn does not deny

that nature exists, or that the relationship between theory and nature is important in

scientific practices; rather, nature must not be considered in a theory-independent manner.

If there must be some context to the topic of discussion, then a theory-independent nature

– and, by extension, truth – is a non-starter. The notion of truth does not factor into

but such an improved understanding of nature is not the explicit goal that scientists pursue. Kuhn, 25; 27; 82; 135; 145. 194 Once again, the choices made by scientists are not free of constraints, as the former depend on the parameters which are established by the dominant paradigm that the scientific community has previously adopted. 195 Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 206–207.

Page 56: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

51

Kuhn’s analysis of scientific practices196. Kuhn’s understanding of truth – as either a

reluctance or indifference to engage truth – corresponds to a kind of scientific progress in

the mould of Darwin: “Science may not be moving towards greater truth; rather ‘one

damned thing after another’ as Darwin has taught us to understand organic evolution”197.

How is the context determined, then? Since the scientific community holds the authority

in establishing the criteria for scientific practices, such context may be determined by

“the collective aspirations of the community of scientists, or of its leading members”198.

Imre Lakatos makes a similar observation that truth, according to Kuhn, is determined via

a consensus from scientists in the scientific community199. If truth is context-dependent,

is Kuhn venturing into the territory of relativism? Kuhn foresees such a criticism and

responds as such: “Though the temptation to describe that position as relativistic is

understandable, the description seems to me wrong. Conversely, if the position be

relativism, I cannot see that the relativist loses anything needed to account for the nature

of and development of the sciences”200. Neither does Kuhn admit to being relativistic, nor

does Kuhn bother to explain away the criticism. If such a view is relativistic, so be it;

scientific progress continues forth. Moleski suggests that Kuhn’s denial of being

relativistic is more of a rhetorical move, as “Kuhn’s reluctance to affirm the role of truth

in the progress of science leaves him with a very stunted epistemology”201. The claim of

relativism harkens back to Kuhn’s view that whether scientific progress is taking place

lies in the eye of the beholder: Given that scientists operate under the dominant paradigm

of the scientific community, relativism takes place on the communal level: Both the

standards for scientific progress and the parameters for problem-solving are relative to

196 Struan Jacobs, ‘Michael Polanyi and Thomas Kuhn: Priority and Credit’, Tradition and Discovery 33, no. 2 (2006): 32. 197 Moleski, ‘Polanyi Vs. Kuhn’, 11. 198 Maben Walter Poirier, ‘A Comment on Polanyi and Kuhn’, The Thomist 53, no. 2 (1989): 261. 199 Lakatos also considers Polanyi as a subscriber of such a line of thought, that truth is determined by consensus. Maben Walter disagrees with Lakatos’ interpretation: For the former, while Kuhn does appear to hold the position of “truth by consensus”, Polanyi’s position – as I shall discuss in the next section – has more of an individual rather than a communal focus; or rather, the seemingly communal emphasis is grounded by the responsibility of individual scientists. Imre Lakatos, ‘Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes’, in Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, ed. Imre Lakatos and Alan Musgrave, Artech House ITS Series v. 4 (London: Cambridge University Press, 1970), 92; Poirier, ‘A Comment on Polanyi and Kuhn’, 261–264. 200 Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 207. 201 Moleski, ‘Polanyi Vs. Kuhn’, 19.

Page 57: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

52

the decisions of the scientific community that operates without any independent

standards. The meaning of scientific practices originates from the scientists themselves:

Scientists creatively develop a paradigm and determine what constitutes scientific

progress. Scientists are not in search of any meaning or truth that is “out there” but only

the success of the scientists’ own ideas.

Polanyi: Truth and Reality as Arbiters

The question that Kuhn tries to avoid is the most important one for Polanyi. Polanyi

argues for a clear telos in scientific practices: Scientists are in pursuit of a truth that is

independent of scientists; there is indeed a reality that is “out there”, and scientists strive

to gain an ever-improved understanding of reality through the interpretative framework

that is personal knowledge. The recurring theme in Polanyi’s thought is scientists’ pursuit

of truth in reality through scientific practices: Scientists’ motivations are driven by an

attraction to, and a desire to pursue the truth in reality; scientific progress is cumulative,

as an increase in scientific knowledge allows scientists to edge closer to the truth.

While Polanyi does see the scientific community and the more prominent members of the

community as authoritative, the scientific community per se does not wield such

authority; rather, the authority from the scientific community hinges upon the decisions

made by individual scientists through the latter’s personal knowledge. In addition to

feeling the desire to find out what is real, scientists also make a decision to pursue contact

with reality202. Pursuing reality also gives scientists a point of reference: “For Polanyi, it

is commitment to the real (to the universal criterion) that serves as the reference point,

that keeps scientists within the straight and narrow, and not arbitrary decision-making by

sanctioned authorities” (Italics original)203. Standards in scientific practices are

determined by scientists, and the scientists’ intentions make all the difference. A reference

point such as a pursuit of truth invites scientists to participate in something that is greater,

and the same dynamic of participation applies on the level of the scientific community.

202 Poirier, ‘A Comment on Polanyi and Kuhn’, 263. 203 Poirier, 263.

Page 58: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

53

Conversely, if standards are arbitrarily established by authoritative scientists, then the

reference point is the scientists, and the reference point can change according to who is in

charge. For Polanyi, the meaning behind scientific practices is sought by pursuing the

truth of reality that is “out there”, and scientists are personally invested in such a pursuit

because scientists are drawn to the prospect of coming into contact with truth in reality.

Suitable Analogy to Describe Scientists?

The difference in understanding scientific practices extends to an understanding of

scientists. Poirier offers two analogies to who scientists are in the eyes of Polanyi and

Kuhn, respectively: Polanyi’s scientists are like discoverers of truth and reality; scientific

practices are then acts of discovery since a previously-hidden reality is now

discovered204. On the contrary, scientists in the eyes of Kuhn are creators, as scientists are

people “who, through the sheer power of their creative imagination, bring forth a new

vision (i.e., a new paradigmatic order) around which they construct a world, proselytize

in its favour, and eventually succeed in imposing it on the scientific community, usually

by converting the more youthful members of the community to their way of seeing

things”205. How are the two analogies helpful in providing more insight into the role of

scientists and scientific practices? Discoverers venture into the unknown in search of

something that is already there; creators venture into the unknown to create something

that does not exist in the first place. Discoverers can be creative with the means of

discovery, but such a creativity does not change that which is about to be discovered.

Creators can also be creative, and such creativity affects both the means of creation and

the object that the creators intend to create206.

204 Poirier, ‘The Polanyi-Kuhn Issue’, 58–59. 205 Poirier, 57. 206 According to Poirier, there are two types of scientists in Kuhn’s conception of a scientific community. Firstly, there are those who fit into the category of “great scientists”, creative scientists who are able to both construct innovative paradigms and convince others to subscribe to the new perspective. Secondly, there are scientists who essentially function as “under-labourers” who – convinced of the correctness of a paradigm – perform the less exciting work of working out obscure aspects of the paradigm. Given the respective traits, “great scientists” can be associated with scientific revolutions and “under-labourers” with normal science. Poirier does not see the work of the “great scientists” in a favourable way, most probably because the “great scientists” in a Kuhnian sense do not pursue truth in reality. “Great scientists” have no foundation to ground any convictions. Hence such scientists share much in common with politicians in

Page 59: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

54

Self-made purpose or being attracted to truth in reality; self-made meaning or meaning

found in contact with reality. Are scientific practices about the scientists or something

other than the scientists? According to Kuhn, scientific practices are personal in that

scientists are both the beginning and the end: Scientists see certain situations as puzzles,

and the resolving of puzzles speaks to the scientists’ own creativity while providing

personal satisfaction to a job well done. According to Polanyi, scientific practices are

personal through the interpretive framework of personal knowledge: Scientific practices

are personal pursuits towards a reality that is beyond the scientists, and such pursuits

require that scientists incorporate the knowledge as one’s own.

While many of Kuhn’s ideas are insightful, I find Polanyi’s vision of the personal

involvement of scientists to be more convincing. Firstly, the personal aspect of Kuhn’s

view of scientific practices gets lost in the midst of scientific revolutions, as the collective

of scientists seems to diminish the involvement of individual scientists. The power of the

collective is to be expected when the analogy of choice is that of a revolution, in which

the collective has a stranglehold on the behavior of the individuals involved. Secondly,

Kuhn’s idea of a non-cumulative scientific progress which results in a fragmentation of

scientific knowledge is unrealistic. Even if scientists disagree over the extent of scientific

progress out of a difference in paradigms, such a disagreement does not inevitably lead to

an incommensurability, that the new-found knowledge cannot be considered as a part of a

greater corpus of knowledge. Polanyi’s portrayal of the scientific community is more

accommodating to different opinions: There is room for many because of shared

commonalities through the inherited scientific tradition.

When scientific practices are personal in a Polanyian sense, not only are scientists

attracted by and pursue reality; the commitment and belief that are inherent in personal

knowledge make a demand on scientists:

achieving goals through a campaign of charms; Poirier even calls associate “great scientists” with mesmerizers. While I sympathize with much of Poirier’s inputs regarding the Polanyi-Kuhn comparison, the great scientist/ under-labourer comparison is not something that I desire to bring into the conversation, as I think that the category of “creator” captures the point for the purpose of my thesis. Poirier, 56–58.

Page 60: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

55

It is the act of commitment in its full structure that saves personal knowledge from being merely subjective. Intellectual commitment is a responsible decision, in submission to the compelling claims of what in good conscience I conceive to be true. It is an act of hope, striving to fulfil an obligation within a personal situation for which I am not responsible and which therefore determines my calling. This hope and this obligation are expressed in the universal intent of personal knowledge.207

Through the framework of personal knowledge, scientific practices become a noble duty

that goes beyond the satisfaction derived from solving scientific problems as puzzles; the

corresponding responsibility provides a direction and meaning which are akin to that of a

personal calling. Such convictions are not uncommon from reputable scientists, as if there

is something attractive about the nature of the scientific work that draws such scientists to

conduct research with dedication and reverence: Such a “something” can be a greater

understanding about nature, or the truth that underlies nature. The “something” lies beyond

the scientists’ dictate. Such an attitude can be observed in many established scientists who

are authorities in the scholars’ respective disciplines208. In Kuhnian terms, the scientists

who are influential in shaping the paradigms do not go about scientific practices as Kuhn

envisions.

Summary

I have argued that the thoughts of Polanyi and Kuhn regarding scientific practices are

similar in both the emphasis on motivating passions as a driving force and the authority of

207 Polanyi, Personal Knowledge, 65. 208 The view that scientists are in pursuit of something greater can be expressed in a myriad of ways. Albert Einstein describes it as a religious attitude: “A knowledge of the existence of something we cannot penetrate, of the manifestations of the profoundest reason and the most radiant beauty – it is this knowledge and this emotion that constitute the truly religious attitude; in this sense, and in this alone, I am a deeply religious man”; John Polanyi (the son of Michael Polanyi), the recipient of the Nobel Prize in Chemistry in 1986, describes science as a search for truth; Satoshi Omura, the Nobel laureate in physiology or medicine in 2015 for the work on avermectins in treating tropical diseases, expresses a “profound respect for Nature”, and describes avermectins as “a splendid gift from the Earth”. Albert Einstein, The World as I See It (New York: Covici Friede, 1934), 5; ‘John C. Polanyi – On Being a Scientist: A Personal View’, accessed 26 April 2018, https://www.nobelprize.org/nobel_prizes/chemistry/laureates/1986/polanyi-article.html; Satoshi Omura, ‘Nobel Lecture: A Splendid Gift from the Earth: The Origins and Impact of Avermectin’ (7 December 2015), https://www.nobelprize.org/nobel_prizes/medicine/laureates/2015/omura-lecture.pdf.

Page 61: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

56

the scientific community. I have argued that the thoughts of Polanyi and Kuhn regarding

scientific practices differ in whether scientific progress is continuous and whether any kind

of teleology exists behind scientific practices. I have also argued that such differences

directly contribute to the contrasting ways in which scientific practices can be personal, and

the understanding of the meaning behind scientific practices. Not only do the philosophical

differences between the two scholars depict drastically different portrayals of scientists as

either creators of meaning or discoverers of truth; the said portrayals can also serve as a

bridge for or a barrier to a science-religion dialogue. How does such a dialogue look like if

scientists are creators of meaning, and how so if scientists are discoverers of truth? Are

there any similarities between the search for meaning in scientific practices and in religious

practices? The fittingness of the interpretive frameworks of Polanyi and Kuhn with regards

to facilitating a science-religion dialogue is put to test in the next chapter, with particular

foci on the philosophical underpinnings of scientific practices such as that of progress,

teleology, and the personal nature of practices.

Page 62: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

57

Chapter Four: Science and Religion, Matters of Faith How do the thoughts of Polanyi and Kuhn regarding scientific practices contribute to a

dialogue between science and religion, as well as matters of faith? I argue that the usage

of Kuhn’s interpretive framework leads to the creation of different silos of knowledge

that discourage dialogue between disciplines. I also argue that the usage of Polanyi’s

interpretive framework enables a better facilitation of a science-religion dialogue because

personal knowledge offers both a common language for both science and religion through

an understanding of practices, as well as a common interest in the pursuit of truth.

The Silos of Kuhn

As aforementioned, other scholars have described Kuhn as a relativist due to both Kuhn’s

insistence on scientific progress as being non-cumulative and the reluctance to attribute

any notions of truth into scientific practices. While Kuhn’s consistent objection to such

an accusation may signify that Kuhn never intends to appear as being relativistic, many

other scholars have taken Kuhn’s work to be as such209. David Bloor and Barry Barnes

advocate for the “Strong Programme” in the sociology of scientific knowledge, an

approach that is highly influential in the development of the field of science and

technology studies. Bloor and Barnes adopt Kuhn’s major insights regarding paradigms

and scientific revolutions while taking an explicitly relativistic stance210. Kuhn’s

understanding of incommensurability can be taken as an example of relativism: The

209 Kuhn spends much time to counter the claim of relativism, but to little effect. Jan Golinski describes Kuhn’s unwillingness to accept the power of Kuhn’s words as that of a “reluctant prophet”: “Toward the end of his life, he voiced his revulsion at prevailing relativistic attitudes that had appropriated and (in his view) misread his work. The image of Kuhn in his last years was of an unwitting pioneer of postmodernism, a reluctant prophet embarrassed by the honours paid to him by the unashamed relativists who followed in his wake”. Jan Golinski, ‘Thomas Kuhn and Interdisciplinary Conversation: Why Historians and Philosophers of Science Stopped Talking to One Another’, in Integrating History and Philosophy of Science, ed. Seymour Mauskopf and Tad Schmaltz, Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science (Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands, 2011), 18, https://link.springer.com/chapter/10.1007/978-94-007-1745-9_2. 210 Barry Barnes, ‘Realism, Relativism and Finitism’, in Cognitive Relativism and Social Science, ed. Diederick Raven, Jan de Wolf, and Lieteke van Vucht Tijssen (New Brunswick, N.J: Transaction Publishers, 1992), 131–47.

Page 63: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

58

views of scientists who subscribe to competing paradigms are incommensurable because

scientists cannot come to any kind of agreement with each other. Incommensurability

leads to either the abandonment of the losing paradigm or the creation of another

specialty in order that each paradigms continue to develop according to the respective

worldviews without conflicts211. When theories and knowledge are developed under non-

overlapping paradigms, different silos of discipline are established and continue to

develop in an independent manner. For instance, scholars distill significance from The

Structure of Scientific Revolutions in ways that are independent of Kuhn’s own intents:

Philosophers focus on the notion of incommensurability, whereas historians hone into the

question of historical causality of scientific changes. Ironically, Kuhn’s text does not

bring philosophers and historians of science together; the different foci of worldviews

actually drive philosophers and historians further apart, eliminating the possibility of any

conversations. Scholars are no longer interested in working towards a grand narrative, but

rather a narrower focus in specific situations212.

How does theology fit into such a picture? While Kuhn welcomes scholars from other

disciplines to apply Kuhnian insights into the scholars’ respective expertise, Kuhn never

ventures outside of the philosophy of science. If Kuhn were to treat theology as a

legitimate discipline, theology would be one of the many silos of academic disciplines,

and one that would have very little to do with anything that can be considered scientific.

Just as incommensurability exists between different scientific disciplines,

incommensurability also exists between different disciplines in general. Can any dialogue

take place in the midst of incommensurability? To put it another way: How would

Kuhnian scientists approach the prospect of a science-religion dialogue? In the postscript

of The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Kuhn describes scientists who subscribe to

competing paradigms as belonging to different language communities, and that scientists

must learn the other’s language in order to communicate213; however, the purpose behind

learning the language of the other is to convert the other to subscribe to the scientists’

211 K. Brad Wray, ‘Assessing the Influence of Kuhn’s Structure of Scientific Revolutions’, Metascience 21, no. 1 (1 March 2012): 7, https://doi.org/10.1007/s11016-011-9603-8. 212 Golinski, ‘Thomas Kuhn and Interdisciplinary Conversation’. 213 Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 200–202.

Page 64: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

59

own paradigm214. The spirit of scientific revolutions lives on: The goal of the dialogue is

neither to establish nor to build upon any common ground; anything that takes place

within the context of a dialogue is used with the ultimate goal of defeating the opponent.

When faced with the prospect of a science-religion dialogue, Kuhnian scientists would

either take the silo approach and treat theology as a discipline that is independent of

science, or the Kuhnian scientists would try to find a common language in order to

convert theologians to the scientists’ own paradigm. While the latter type of interaction

can still be considered as a kind of dialogue, such a dialogue is both competitive and

confrontational.

Kuhn in Theology

The previous section addresses the approach of a Kuhnian scientist towards theology;

how about a Kuhnian theologian? While theology has never been Kuhn’s

preoccupation215, some scholars have found Kuhn’s insights to be applicable in the realm

of religion.

Dirk-Martin Grube suggests that Christianity represents a paradigm shift from Judaism.

The resurrection of Christ is the anomaly that the existing paradigm – Judaism – fails to

214 Kuhn, 203. 215 In The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, Kuhn briefly mentions theology while describing scientific education; namely, that the narrow and rigid nature of scientific education are only comparable to the education of “orthodox theology”. Yet no explanation has been provided on what Kuhn means by orthodox theology. I mention only one other publication of Kuhn on such a topic: Kuhn’s presentation on the function of dogma in scientific research in the Symposium on the History of Science at Oxford in 1961. Kuhn describes the “dogmatism in mature science” as “a deep commitment to a particular way of viewing the world and of practicing science in it.” Through scientific education, such a commitment provides the rules of scientists to follow as puzzle-solvers. Dogmatism for Kuhn seems to equate to both a commitment on the individual level and a resistance to change on an institutional level. At no point does Kuhn try to make a direct comparison to religion or theology. Perhaps some may argue that the narrow and rigid pattern of education represents a similarity between the two disciplines. I provide two counter-arguments: Firstly, Kuhn never elaborates upon any understanding of the kind of education that takes place within “orthodox theology”, and whether Kuhn’s view actually reflects how theological education takes place is unclear. Even granting such a point to Kuhn does not diminish my second point: A comparison between methods of knowledge propagation is categorically different from saying that the contents of the respective knowledge have anything to do with each other. Kuhn, 166; Kuhn, ‘The Function of Dogma in Scientific Research’, 349.

Page 65: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

60

come to terms with216; the belief that Jesus Christ is the Messiah also links the person of

the Messiah with the description of the Suffering Servant in the Book of the prophet

Isaiah, resulting in a drastic re-interpretation of what being the Messiah entails217. Just as

scientists who subscribe to competing paradigms seem to have different worldviews, so

different worldviews exist between Jews and Christians. On the other hand, Grube thinks

that Christians and Jews are entitled to each group’s respective beliefs, thus giving

legitimacy to both in the spirit of religious pluralism218. Grube does not speak of a

winning or losing paradigm, or even a competition between the two. Grube’s approach

contradicts how Kuhn describes scientific revolutions as akin to the evolutionary process:

Evolution doesn’t simply generate diversity through differentiation; evolution also

favours the species that can better adapt and survive. A more favourable interpretation is

that the difference between Judaism and Christianity is more comparable to the creation

of another specialty, with neither party gaining the upper hand; yet Grube plays down

such an aspect of competition.

Another example is work of the historian John O’Malley, who uses Kuhn’s notion of

paradigm shifts to evaluate some of the key developments in the history of Christianity:

The reformation under Pope Gregory VII in the midst of the Investiture Controversy in

the eleventh century; the Lutheran reformation in the sixteenth century and the Second

Vatican Council in the twentieth century. O’Malley distinguishes between “reform” and

“reformation”: “Reform” represents changes that take place within a given frame of

reference, whereas “reformation” involves significant changes in principles that also

replace the ones of old219. Kuhn’s idea of paradigm shifts applies to the latter case.

O’Malley is clear about what to adapt – or not to adapt –from Kuhn, as O’Malley is

mainly interested in Kuhn’s discussion of paradigms and paradigm shifts, but not in

216 Dirk-Martin Grube, ‘Christian Theology Emerged by Way of a Kuhnian Paradigm Shift’, International Journal of Philosophy and Theology 79, no. 1–2 (15 March 2018): 186–187, https://doi.org/10.1080/21692327.2017.1422988. 217 Grube, 190. 218 Grube, 189. 219 John W. O’Malley, ‘Developments, Reforms, and Two Great Reformations: Towards a Historical Assessment of Vatican II’, Theological Studies; Woodstock, Md., Etc. 44, no. 3 (1 September 1983): 376–377.

Page 66: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

61

Kuhn’s idea of puzzle-solving220. O’Malley argues that a paradigm shift is evident in all

three movements, with a particular focus on the Second Vatican Council. For instance,

the drastic changes in the perceived attitude and practice that result from the Council lead

O’Malley to conclude that something more than “reform” is taking place221. O’Malley

also refers to the key concept of the Second Vatican Council – aggiornamento, or

updating – as a rhetorical understatement, since a word such as “renewal” feels less

threatening than “reformation”222. O’Malley also subscribes to the idea that goes in

tandem with a paradigm shift: The adoption of a new paradigm signals a break from the

old. To be sure, O’Malley’s view is one of the two main interpretations of the Second

Vatican Council, one that Pope Emeritus Benedict XVI calls the “hermeneutic of

rupture”, with the other view being the “hermeneutic of continuity”223.

The two aforementioned examples show that some scholars do find Kuhn’s ideas to be

useful, especially in the realm of the history of Christianity and of the Church. Yet neither

are Kuhnian theologians in the strictest sense of the word: Neither Grube nor O’Malley

220 O’Malley, 377. 221 The following quote, albeit lengthy, illustrates how O’Malley sees the goal of the Second Vatican Council: “Put in the most generic terms, the aims of the Council were as follows: To end the stance of cultural isolation that the Church was now seen as having maintained; to initiate a new freedom of expression and action within the Church that certain Vatican institutions were now interpreted as having previously curtailed; to distribute more broadly the exercise of pastoral authority, especially by strengthening the role of the episcopacy and local churches vis-à-vis the Holy See; to modify in people’s consciousness and in the actual functioning of the Church the predominantly clerical, institutional, and hierarchical model that had prevailed; to affirm the dignity of the laity in the Church; to establish through a more conciliatory attitude, through some new theological insights, and through effective mechanisms a better relationship with other religious bodies, looking ultimately to the healing of the divisions in Christianity and fruitful ‘dialogue’ with non-Christian religions; to change the teaching of the Church on ‘religious liberty’ and give new support to the principle of ‘freedom of conscience’; to base theology and biblical studies more firmly on historical principles; to foster styles of piety based more obviously on Scripture and the public liturgy of the Church; to affirm clearly that the Church was and should be affected by the cultures in which it exercises its ministries; finally, to promote a more positive appreciation of ‘the world’ and the relationship of the Church to it, with a concomitant assumption of clearer responsibility for the fate of the world in ‘the new era’ that the Council saw opening up before its eyes”. O’Malley, 393–394. 222 O’Malley, 396. 223 Benedict XVI, Address of His Holiness Benedict XVI to the Roman Curia, Offering Them His Christmas Greetings (Vatican City: The Holy See, 2005), https://w2.vatican.va/content/benedict-xvi/en/speeches/2005/december/documents/hf_ben_xvi_spe_20051222_roman-curia.html. The positions of both the hermeneutic of rupture and continuity have been well-documented. For a further elucidation of the respective positions, please refer to O’Malley’s as well as Lamb and Levering’s book. John W. O’Malley, What Happened at Vatican II (Cambridge, Mass: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 2008); Matthew L. Lamb and Matthew Levering, Vatican II: Renewal Within Tradition (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008).

Page 67: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

62

adopts the entirety of Kuhn’s interpretative framework, as selected parts of Kuhn’s theory

are utilized: O’Malley takes a broad stroke approach and focuses on the general

characteristics of a paradigm shift without going into the issue of incommensurability,

whereas Grube softens Kuhn’s stance on the competition between two paradigms. Neither

adopts Kuhn’s reluctance to discuss matters of truth: While O’Malley does not explicitly

engage in a discussion on truth, O’Malley is also a Catholic priest and should be

sympathetic to Jesus’ claim that Jesus is “the way, the truth, and the life” (John 14:6). On

the other hand, Grube values the contribution of religion and favours religious pluralism.

Polanyi: Truth, Reality and Theology

A Polanyian scientist would readily be open to a science-religion dialogue. Indeed,

Polanyi’s approach already shares some common vocabularies with religion, given that

words such as “truth” and “reality” are used to describe scientists’ motivations behind

scientific practices. Polanyi describes the backbone of personal knowledge with an

example that carries a strong religious undertone, with the thoughts of St. Augustine of

Hippo: “We must now go back to St. Augustine to restore the balance of our cognitive

powers. […] He taught that all knowledge was a gift of grace, for which we must strive

under the guidance of antecedent belief: Nisi credideritis, non intelligitis”224. While the

phrase is taken from a discussion on faith-related matters, Étienne Gilson argues that the

accompanying attitude also reflects St. Augustine’s personal experience in the search for

224 Polanyi, Personal Knowledge, 266. The translation of the Latin phrase is: “Unless you believed, you understand not” (translation mine). I provide my own translation for the following reason: Polanyi is citing from St. Augustine’s De Libero Arbitrio, and the original is Nisi credideritis, non intellegetis (De Libero Arbitrio, Book 1, par. 4), while Polanyi has intelligitis appearing in lieu of intellegetis. The translation employed by Polanyi is “unless ye believe, ye shall not understand”; however, Credideritis is the perfect active form of crēdō (to believe), and intelligitis is the present active form of intelligō (to understand), which leads to my own translation. Moreover, non intelligitis can also be translated into “you do not understand”, but such a translation invites the question: “What do you not understand?” This is clearly not the point, as the meaning of St. Augustine’s saying points to understanding in general. Elsewhere, a quick search on Google Scholar reveals that the said phrase has intelligetis in place of intelligitis in the majority of the available literature. Intelligetis is the future active form of intelligō, and the latter part of the phrase is translated as “you shall not understand”, which corresponds to Polanyi’s translation. Perhaps there is a spelling error on the part of Polanyi, or that the word was mis-spelt in Polanyi’s source on St. Augustine. For the sake of consistency, I provide my own translation based on what appears in Polanyi’s book.

Page 68: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

63

truth225. Elsewhere, Polanyi references a similar theme that is widely attributed to St.

Anselm of Canterbury: “Unless he presumes that the substance and method of science are

fundamentally sound, he will never develop a sense of scientific value and acquire the

skill of scientific enquiry. This is the way of acquiring knowledge, which the Christian

Church Fathers described as fides quaerens intellectum, ‘to believe in order to know’”

(Translation original)226. Personal knowledge shares similar roots with the great

theologians of old: Belief is foundational in the search for knowledge. Therefore,

personal knowledge is inherently open to a dialogue between science and religion, as

Polanyi’s epistemology applies to how both scientific and theological knowledge are

attained227. For example, personal knowledge is on display in Polanyi’s friendship with

the author and journalist Arthur Koestler, with the topics of the correspondence between

the two ranging between science, religion and psychology. Polanyi and Koestler shared

both similarities and differences in thoughts, but the friendship continued out of a mutual

respect for the other’s convictions228.

225 According to Gilson, St. Augustine tries to search for truth through reason in vain, until “[…] he discovered that faith held possession in perpetuity of the very truth his reason had been unable to grasp. In theory, then, it seems quite logical to start from reason in order to come to faith; in practice, however, is not the opposite method the better? Is it not better to believe in order to know, rather than to know in order to believe, or even in order to know? At any rate, St. Augustine’s own experience taught him that it was better, and he in turn wants to persuade us that it is so.” Étienne Gilson, The Christian Philosophy of Saint Augustine, Random House Lifetime Library (New York: Random House, 1960), 27. 226 Michael Polanyi, Science, Faith, and Society, 15. Fides quaerens intellectum is more commonly translated as “faith seeking understanding”, which is consistent with quaerens being the present active participle of quaerō. 227 The consideration of Polanyi’s contribution to a dialogue between science and religion is founded upon overlaps in epistemologies. Such an epistemological perspective is not the only way to perceive the said dialogue. In fact, some scholars propose that the focus should not be cast upon issues of knowledge and truth, but rather a sociological or anthropological consideration of science and religion. According to such scholars, the key conflicts between science as religion lies not in epistemology but rather in sociology or anthropology. Such a perspective lies beyond the scope of the chapter, but Polanyi’s epistemology remains relevant at least through the sociological lens, as personal knowledge is grounded upon practices. John H. Evans and Michael S. Evans, ‘Religion and Science: Beyond the Epistemological Conflict Narrative’, Annual Review of Sociology 34, no. 1 (2008): 87–105, https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev.soc.34.040507.134702. 228 Lee Congdon, ‘Believing Unbelievers: Michael Polanyi and Arthur Koestler’, in Emotion, Reason and Tradition: Essays on the Social, Political and Economic Thought of Michael Polanyi, ed. Struan Jacobs and R. T. Allen (Aldershot, Hants, England: Ashgate, 2005), 21–40, http://www.loc.gov/catdir/toc/ecip0418/2004012170.html.

Page 69: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

64

Vocation

With conviction comes a responsibility towards the object of conviction. Polanyi’s argues

that the personal involvement and the responsibilities of scientists are akin to that of a

personal calling, or a vocation. Scientists are responsible for the pursuit of the truth and

to ensure the validity of the scientific work. The vocation of scientists can readily be

compared to the idea of a religious vocation. I hereby focus on simply one aspect of the

Christian vocation in Hans Urs von Balthasar’s The Christian State of Life. Von Balthasar

describes the calling of Christians as a call to love, and the criterion of such a love is not

determined by Christians, but rather by the love of the incarnate God: “This is my

commandment, that you love one another as I have loved you” (Jn 15:12)229. Such a call

to love makes a strong demand:

For this love to which we are called is not a circumscribed or limited love, not a love defined, as it were, by the measure of our human weakness. It does not allow us to submit just one part of our lives to its demands and leave the rest free for other pursuits; it does not allow us to dedicate just one period of our lives to it and the rest, if we will, to our own interests. The command to love is universal and unequivocal. It makes no allowances. It encompasses and makes demands upon everything in our nature: “with thy whole heart, with all thy soul, and with all thy mind.230

The demand of such a calling considered in a Christian manner is not compartmentalized,

because love cannot be compartmentalized; indeed, a calling to love affects the whole

person, as love “encompasses and makes demands upon everything in our nature”. When

considered through the lens of love, a Christian calling gives a person a definitive

orientation. Since love serves as the foundation, a Christian calling does not impose in an

oppressive way: “The more intimately one is involved in love, the more his love comes to

bear the inner form of a vow in which he exchanges his freedom from bonds for the bond

of love. Thus the bond that seemed to him, in the beginning, to be exactly the opposite of

the freedom of love, to be a burden and a duty, appears now to be ever more clearly

229 Hans Urs von Balthasar, The Christian State of Life (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1983), 26. 230 Von Balthasar, 27.

Page 70: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

65

identical with the freedom of love”231. The wish of the beloved is a command for the

lover: I want to do it; I must do it, and I shall freely do it because I love her. Love as a

gift of self may have the appearance of a loss of freedom, but love as such paradoxically

grants freedom. The command to love feels less and less like a duty, but more and more

like a second nature.

Points of convergence are already apparent despite a rough sketch of the nuanced

thoughts of von Balthasar on the Christian vocation. Firstly, there is the level of

engagement in a calling: The all-encompassing nature of a Christian vocation that is

characterized by a giving of self can be compared to the involvement of the person in

Polanyi’s framework of personal knowledge, as “we take in the object as a part of us and

we pour ourselves out into it”232. Both vocations call for an opening and giving of self.

Secondly, responsibility comes with being called. Both Polanyi and von Balthasar speak

of a kind of obligation that comes with a calling. While von Balthasar nuances the

explanation of such an obligation through the lens of love and freedom, Polanyi describes

the obligation of scientists through the lens of duty. While Polanyi does not describe

scientists’ relationship with the object of scientific practices in the language of love,

Polanyi does speak of the passionate nature of scientific practices: Scientists are attracted

to a kind of beauty that arouses the intellectual passion of scientists233. Similarly, both

beauty and truth – along with goodness – are the transcendentals that are found in

creatures and reflect the Creator God who is perfect beauty, truth, and goodness234.

While Polanyi’s corpus of work does include some musings on theology, the chosen

focus lies in the contribution of Polanyi’s epistemology to theology. The decision to not

directly tackle Polanyi’s opinions on religion is twofold: Firstly, Polanyi’s writings on

religion takes up a very small portion of Polanyi’s corpus, and the focus of my thesis lies

in Polanyi’s writings on scientific practices. Secondly, Polanyi’s exact stance on matters

231 Von Balthasar, 39. 232 Polanyi, Personal Knowledge, 60. 233 Polanyi, 135. 234 The Holy See, ‘Catechism of the Catholic Church’, 41, http://www.vatican.va/archive/ENG0015/__PC.HTM.

Page 71: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

66

of religion is difficult to pinpoint:

Because Polanyi was very reserved about his religious commitments, it is sometimes difficult to determine exactly where he stood on theological issues. There are ambiguities in his writings which allow strong theistic interpretations (Gelwick, Scott, Torrance, Apczynski, Bulles, and others) as well as atheistic interpretations (Grene, Prosch, Wetherick, Weightman, and others). Because of Polanyi’s lack of formal training in theology and because of his independence from any particular Christian tradition, it may be somewhat unfair to expect precision and clarity from him in his reflection on religious issues.235

Since Polanyi’s own theological opinions can be a moving target, I choose to focus on the

interpretation of Polanyi by trained theologians236. Indeed, the late Avery Cardinal Dulles

shares the same opinion: “Polanyi’s value for theology lies less in what he explicitly

stated about theological questions than in the transfer value of what he had to say about

science. It was in the field of science, not theology, that he spoke with special

authority”237. I thus turn to Dulles and Moleski in exploring what a Polanyian theologian

is like.

Personal Knowledge and Theology

While the key role of belief in Polanyi’s epistemology may present an obstacle to

scholars who are allergic to the word “belief” for one reason or another, Polanyi’s

interpretive framework is a natural ally to scholars who values the role of belief. With

Polanyi’s epistemology, both theology and science share a similar epistemological

grounding in virtue of a similar method in knowledge acquisition238. The shared

epistemological foundation can also partly explain the aforementioned pursuit of truth.

235 Martin X. Moleski, Personal Catholicism: The Theological Epistemologies of John Henry Newman and Michael Polanyi (Washington, D.C.: Catholic University of America Press, 2000), 142. 236 Moleski also notes that the employment of the same epistemology may yet result in different theologies; indeed, such is the case in Moleski’s comparing the epistemologies and theologies of John Henry Cardinal Newman and Polanyi, respectively. The theological nuances are mainly discussed in the fourth chapter and the conclusion of Moleski’s book, Personal Catholicism: The Theological Epistemologies of John Henry Newman and Michael Polanyi, Moleski, 139–169. 237 Avery Dulles, ‘Faith, Church, and God: Insights from Michael Polanyi’, Theological Studies 45, no. 3 (1 September 1984): 550, https://doi.org/10.1177/004056398404500306. 238 Moleski, Personal Catholicism, ix.

Page 72: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

67

Dulles remarks that Polanyi speaks “in almost the same terms” as John Henry

Newman239, and Moleski has compared in great detail Newman’s notion of the illative

sense with Polanyi’s personal knowledge240.

As the role of belief is influential in Polanyi’s conception of a scientific community, a

similar influence can also be seen in a religious community, namely the Church: The

members’ trust in the authority of the community’s leaders is essential in the transmission

of knowledge through practices. Dulles sees the content of such a transmission as more

than theological knowledge, but rather the transmission of the Christian revelation:

“Applied to the Church, Polanyi’s principles would indicate that adherence to Christian

revelation is inseparable from adherence to the Church and trust in her leadership to

uphold and transmit the revelation”241.

Similar to Maben Poirier’s analogy of an explorer to describe Polanyi’s vision of a

scientist’s identity, Dulles also takes up the same analogy in comparison to the Church:

“The Church is, to be sure, committed to preserving a precious patrimony handed down

in Scripture and tradition, but she must continually rethink and re-articulate her faith in

relation to new sociocultural situations and in relation to a growing body of human

knowledge. The theological community, as a kind of intelligentsia of the Church, could

perhaps be designated as a society of explorers”242. The image of the explorer serves as a

counterbalance to that of a community who is sustained by authority and assent:

Exploration implies a venturing into the unknown and a stretching of boundaries,

whereas authority implies guidelines and the maintenance of order. Dulles argues that the

Church has room for both exploration and authority, and such an image provides an

operating milieu for theologians. Moleski describes the tension between creativity and

stability as such: “As Polanyi showed, the way to make fresh, new discoveries that

transform the scientific tradition is first to dwell within the tradition, absorbing the tacit

vision by assimilating the articulate elements into one’s own interpretative framework.

239 Dulles, ‘Faith, Church, and God’, 538. 240 Moleski, Personal Catholicism. 241 Dulles, ‘Faith, Church, and God’, 540. 242 Dulles, 544.

Page 73: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

68

The only way to contribute to Christianity’s future is to embrace its past and present”243.

In both the scientific community and the Church, transformation comes from within.

Such a view on change is unsurprisingly contrary to that of John O’Malley, the latter of

whom favours a more fundamental change of vision – and more importantly, a break with

the past – that is more akin to Kuhn’s conception of a revolution.

From Scientific to Religious Practices

One of the more unique contributions of Polanyi’s epistemology to religion and theology

can be seen through the lens of “practices”: Just as a better understanding of scientific

practices can debunk the myth that scientists simply follow certain precepts, a better

understanding of religious practices can debunk the myth that believers live their lives

through a rigid following of certain rules. Religious practices touch upon all aspects of the

life of faith such as the sacraments, matters of devotion, and the teachings of the Church.

Religious practices can be engaged on an impersonal and objective level, in which matters

of faith are treated in a detached manner, keeping a critical distance between matters of

faith and the believers. Conversely, religious practices can be engaged in a purely

subjective manner, in which believers become sole arbiters of values regarding matters of

faith without any consideration of other pre-established criteria. If religious practices are to

be considered through a Polanyian lens, the key issue is that of personal appropriation:

Christianity, even more than the scientific community, needs mature believers who have personally appropriated the patrimony and who can transmit it by example and formative influence. What Polanyi said about scientific apprenticeship applies a fortiori to Christian discipleship, which involves a far more comprehensive dependence of the novice upon the master. Although Polanyi did not specifically address the question of religious education, his statements about scientific education may be taken as an implicit warning against the tendency to transfer the matrix of religious education from the family and the home to the school, considered as an academic institution. If Polanyi was correct, religious faith cannot ordinarily be transmitted by formal instruction in the impersonal situation of the classroom, though such instruction may help one to understand and cherish the faith that one has.244

243 Moleski, Personal Catholicism, 186. 244 Dulles, ‘Faith, Church, and God’, 541.

Page 74: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

69

Christian apprenticeship is akin to scientific discipleship: A personal appropriation of

faith is of utmost importance, as believers become formator for others in ways that go

beyond formal instructions. Religious practices are based on such a personal

appropriation of faith. Dulles’ observation of the transfer of religious education from the

home to the school is thought-provoking: In a school, religious education takes the form

of a class. While the possibility of the teachers being good Christian examples cannot be

dismissed, matters of faith are both distilled and compartmentalized into one of many

school subjects. Religious education may still take the form of the parents or

grandparents instructing the children; such an education at home, however, does contain

an extra dimension: Children are in constant contact with the parents or grandparents.

Matters of faith are expressed through family devotions, customs, or simply through a

Christian approach to life that quietly but assuredly bears the joys and sorrows through a

trust in the Lord. Religious practices communicate, teach, and transmit aspects of the

faith on a personal level, from the ones whose faith are better appropriated to others

whose faith are not as well appropriated. The transmission of religious practices can take

place through an intentional teaching moment, an observation of a living example or a

personal encounter. Polanyi’s idea of incorporating something external – be it a tool or a

concept – into the person can be a helpful guide: Matters of faith are not simply external

matters that can be filed away in the back of the mind to be recalled and applied at the

right moment; matters of faith are incorporated and become a part of the person.

Religious matters are practiced without being noticed, just as the grip of a hammer is not

the focal awareness in an act of hammering a nail, and that the hammer is being used an

extension of the person.

A personal example helps to better illustrate the correlation of religious practices and

personal appropriation of faith. The relic of St. Francis Xavier went on a cross-Canada

tour in January of 2018, and the relic made an appearance at the parish where I served as

a deacon on Sundays. Thousands of pilgrims had to queue up outside of the church, and

the accumulated wait for venerating the relic being two hours in total. I spent the entire

afternoon talking to queued-up pilgrims. I noticed that the pilgrims were very conscious

about not being at the church to worship the relic as if an object took the place of God,

Page 75: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

70

and that the pilgrims treated the long wait in line as simply a part of the pilgrimage. The

pilgrims were aware that the purpose of the pilgrimage was to ask for intercessory

prayers from the saint through the veneration of the relic. The pilgrims understood what

“communion of saints” meant in practice. The pilgrims understood that the grace of God

operates through the physical reality. While some materials from catechism or high

school religion classes might have been retained, the pilgrims articulated a theological

understanding in personal and unique ways, indicating a personal appropriation of being

Catholic. I also consider such a personal appropriation of faith through practice as an

example of the sensus fidelium, the senses of the faithful.

Another example of the personal nature of religious practices can be seen from the

apostolic exhortation Amoris Laetitia by Pope Francis, particularly pertaining to the role

of the family in Chapter 7. Francis refers to the family as “the first school of human

values”245. More importantly, Francis highlights the importance of having good personal

examples in the passing on of values: “Values are best embodied in a few exemplary

persons, but also realized imperfectly and to different degrees in others”246. The image of

persons as embodied values bears a striking similarity to that of scientists as persons who

have embodied learning and technical training. The degrees to which each person

embodies values vary, just as the degrees to which each scientist embodies scientific

training. When matters of moral instructions are considered within the context of a

family, parents are the primarily responsible for being the embodiment of values. Such a

responsibility is carried out through the religious practices of parents:

Parents rely on schools to ensure the basic instruction of their children, but can never completely delegate the moral formation of their children to others. A person’s affective and ethical development is ultimately grounded in a particular experience, namely, that his or her parents can be trusted. This means that parents, as educators, are responsible, by their affection and example, for instilling in their children trust and loving respect.247

245 Francis, ‘Amoris Laetitia: Post-Synodal Apostolic Exhortation on Love and Family’, The Holy See, 19 March 2016, http://w2.vatican.va/content/dam/francesco/pdf/apost_exhortations/documents/papa-francesco_esortazione-ap_20160319_amoris-laetitia_en.pdf, 274. 246 Francis, 272. 247 Francis, 263.

Page 76: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

71

Formalized education cannot replace personal examples; the family remains the primary

venue of formation. Parents are the primary educators through living examples, and

parents need to take ownership of such a responsibility. By delegating such a

responsibility to schools or other education programs – and more importantly, a lack of

experiencing of values thereof at home – turns formalized education into a disembodied

experience that lacks conviction. Children must learn from parents both through words

and practice, with an emphasis on the latter: “It is essential that children actually see that,

for their parents, prayer is something truly important. Hence moments of family prayer

and acts of devotion can be more powerful for evangelization than any catechism class or

sermon.”248 The family is more than just a school of values but also a school of the heart

through the joys and struggles of life. Such a proposed way of formation is not an either-

or scenario; the transmission of faith through the family does not negate the role of

formal education and teaching. While a disposition to “put the teachings into practice” is

an important part of a personal appropriation of values, putting teachings into practice

remains only a part of a more holistic approach. There is more to faith than having strong

convictions towards a list of precepts:

The institutional dimension of the Church is not the enemy of the personal dimension; the structure springs forth from the Person of Jesus. It is all too easy for both Catholics and non-Catholics to focus on subsidiary elements of the Church (dogma, sacraments, discipline) at the expense of the whole, but that does not mean that we can discard the subsidiaries at will. Memorizing a physics textbook is not enough to produce a good scientist; memorizing the catechism of the Church is not enough to produce a personal relationship with Jesus. In each case, the data is insufficient without a personal reorganization, a flash of insight, the opening of the eyes of the mind and heart to a new vision of reality, a discovery that transforms the person from within.249

Polanyi’s insight on the personal nature of knowledge is particularly important not solely

because religious practices can be understood on an epistemological level with a

248 Francis, 288. 249 Moleski, Personal Catholicism, 186. Moleski is not referring to the focal-subsidiary difference in human awareness when the word “subsidiary” is used in this quote; rather, Moleski refers to the whole-subsidiary difference. When the whole is the focus, the parts fall into the subsidiary awareness. The focus can also be diverted onto the subsidiaries (that is, shifting subsidiary awareness into a focal awareness, with the object being the subsidiaries of the whole), and such a shift can be misleading to the extent that the whole is forgotten. Polanyi, Personal Knowledge, 57–58.

Page 77: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

72

Polanyian framework; the framework resonates with the life of faith because the

foundation of faith is a personal encounter with Jesus Christ, an encounter through which

the lives of believers are transformed.

Summary

I have argued that Kuhn’s approach does not foster a dialogue between science and

religion because of Kuhn’s compartmentalization of disciplines and the reluctance to

discuss matters with an eye towards truth. I have argued that Polanyi’s approach is more

conducive to a science-religion dialogue given the insistence of the value of truth in

Polanyi’s epistemology, as well as acknowledging the personal nature of the vocation of a

scientist. I have further argued that Polanyi’s interpretive framework can be applied to

understand religious practices as a personal appropriation of the faith, turning the

interpretive framework into a common ground between science and religion. The starting

point of a science-religion dialogue has often been the respective content of the

disciplines. The comparison between Polanyi and Kuhn illustrates that such a dialogue

can be re-imagined by beginning from the standpoint of practices. The great advantage of

adopting Polanyi’s understanding of personal knowledge is that such an adoption

bypasses the customarily perceived obstacles of a dialogue between science and religion

by providing both a common means and end: Scholars from both disciplines are in search

of a truth that are independent of the scholars’ own arbitration, and the ways in which

knowledge is learned and appropriated take place through practices in both a scientific

and a religious setting. The link between scientific and religious practices is found within

the person who engages in such practices.

Page 78: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

73

Conclusion

I have argued that different understandings towards scientific practices can either make a

science-religion dialogue to be more constructive or confrontational. I have argued that

Polanyi’s conception of personal knowledge provides a more helpful framework because

personal knowledge serves as a common cognitive framework for both scientific and

religious practices. The framework of personal knowledge acts not only as a bridge

between science and religion, but also as a useful tool to better understand religious

practices. Practices – both scientific and religious – are primary means to teach and

transmit knowledge, and practices reveal inner motivations of practitioners. When

scientific and religious practices are considered in real life through Polanyi’s personal

knowledge, the ideological differences that seem to prevent opportunities for dialogue are

nowhere to be found, eliminating the perceived incompatibility between science and

religion.

Moreover, the Polanyian framework contextualizes scientific practices among the general

field of knowledge. In the book Science as Salvation, Mary Midgley succinctly

underscores the importance of context: “We do not need to esteem science less. What we

need is to esteem it in the right way. Especially we need to stop isolating it artificially

from the rest of our mental life”250. The isolation of science disconnects science from

other disciplines of knowledge, with the former sometimes appearing as the most

superior form of knowledge. Like science, disciplines such as history and language are

attempts to both understand the world and to articulate such an understanding. Polanyi’s

theory of personal knowledge further develops Midgley’s thoughts by acting as a

common framework that unites the different ways of understanding the world. Such a

contextualization both retains the importance of science and avoids over-glorifying

science as the only meaningful mode of knowledge.

250 Mary Midgley, Science as Salvation: A Modern Myth and Its Meaning (London ; New York: Routledge, 1992), 37.

Page 79: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

74

The involvement of the person in scientific practices also reveals other ramifications.

Polanyi stresses a personal commitment within the framework of personal knowledge in

general, and in scientific knowledge in particular. How is such a personal commitment

applicable to a scientific technology that can be seen as an extension of scientific

knowledge? Polanyi understands technology as applicable knowledge251, and sees a sharp

divide between science and technology252; Polanyi is critical of technology because of the

utilitarian motive that underlies the latter253. While Polanyi neither sees technology and

science as reconcilable, nor does Polanyi provide any remedies to such a perception of

technology, can a responsible usage of technology be envisioned through Polanyi’s

theory of personal knowledge, just as religious practices have been re-imagined through

the lens of personal knowledge?

The personal commitment that is required of scientists in the journey to discovery can be

traced back to scientists’ desire to pursue what is true in reality254. The pursuit of truth

can be considered as being a part of a greater pursuit of the transcendentals that is truth,

goodness and beauty. Can technology possibly be re-imagined as being guided by

scientists’ desire of truth, goodness and beauty? Such an approach is drastically different

from one that is utilitarian. The Polanyian approach requires that scientists be bound by a

pursuit of something that is greater than the scientists. The same can be applied to such

an approach towards technology, that the scientists’ pursuit be one that is motivated by

something greater – that is, something that touches upon goodness, truth and beauty –

rather than gaining an advantage over others. With such a motive, scientists are also

called to be responsible in scientific pursuits. Responsibility necessarily carries an ethical

dimension, and such a dimension can be informed by a theological ethics that seriously

takes the transcendentals into account. While much has been written on the ethics of the

products of technology, much less has been done with examining the possible redemption

of the technological process from discovery to production, particularly through the

251 Polanyi, Personal Knowledge, 175. 252 Polanyi, 178. 253 Polanyi, 180–182. 254 Polanyi, 135.

Page 80: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

75

experience of the scientist. Polanyi’s understanding of personal knowledge can provide

the tool for such a possibility.

Page 81: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

76

Bibliography Primary Sources Kuhn, Thomas S. ‘The Function of Dogma in Scientific Research’. In Scientific Change: Historical Studies in the Intellectual, Social, and Technical Conditions for Scientific Discovery and Technical Invention, from Antiquity to the Present (Symposium on the History of Science (1961: Oxford, England)), edited by Alistair Cameron Crombie, 1–11. New York, NY: Basic Books, 1963. ———. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. 2nd ed., enlarged. International Encyclopedia of Unified Science. Chicago: University of Chicago, 1970. Polanyi, Michael. Personal Knowledge: Towards a Post-Critical Philosophy. Chicago, Ill.: The University of Chicago Press, 1958. ———. Science, Faith and Society. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1964. ———. The Tacit Dimension. Garden City, N.Y.: Doubleday, 1967. Secondary Sources Barnes, Barry. ‘Realism, Relativism and Finitism’. In Cognitive Relativism and Social Science, edited by Diederick Raven, Jan de Wolf, and Lieteke van Vucht Tijssen, 131–47. New Brunswick, N.J: Transaction Publishers, 1992. Benedict XVI. Address of His Holiness Benedict XVI to the Roman Curia, Offering Them His Christmas Greetings. Vatican City: The Holy See, 2005. https://w2.vatican.va/content/benedict-xvi/en/speeches/2005/december/documents/hf_ben_xvi_spe_20051222_roman-curia.html. Butterfield, Herbert. Herbert Butterfield: Essays on the History of Science. Lewiston, NY: Edwin Mellen Press, 1998. ———. The Origins of Modern Science, 1300-1800. London, UK: G. Bell, 1957. Congdon, Lee. ‘Believing Unbelievers: Michael Polanyi and Arthur Koestler’. In Emotion, Reason and Tradition: Essays on the Social, Political and Economic Thought of Michael Polanyi, edited by Struan Jacobs and R. T. Allen, 21–40. Aldershot, Hants, England: Ashgate, 2005. http://www.loc.gov/catdir/toc/ecip0418/2004012170.html. Creath, Richard. ‘Logical Empiricism’. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by Edward N. Zalta, Fall 2017. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, 2017. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2017/entries/logical-empiricism/.

Page 82: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

77

Crombie, Alistair Cameron. ‘Introduction’. In Scientific Change: Historical Studies in the Intellectual, Social, and Technical Conditions for Scientific Discovery and Technical Invention, from Antiquity to the Present (Symposium on the History of Science (1961: Oxford, England)), edited by Alistair Cameron Crombie, 1–11. New York, NY: Basic Books, 1963. Dulles, Avery. ‘Faith, Church, and God: Insights from Michael Polanyi’. Theological Studies 45, no. 3 (1 September 1984): 537–50. https://doi.org/10.1177/004056398404500306. Einstein, Albert. The World as I See It. New York: Covici Friede, 1934. Evans, John H., and Michael S. Evans. ‘Religion and Science: Beyond the Epistemological Conflict Narrative’. Annual Review of Sociology 34, no. 1 (2008): 87–105. https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev.soc.34.040507.134702. Francis. ‘Amoris Laetitia: Post-Synodal Apostolic Exhortation on Love and Family’. The Holy See, 19 March 2016. http://w2.vatican.va/content/dam/francesco/pdf/apost_exhortations/documents/papa-francesco_esortazione-ap_20160319_amoris-laetitia_en.pdf. Gilson, Étienne. The Christian Philosophy of Saint Augustine. Random House Lifetime Library. New York: Random House, 1960. Golinski, Jan. ‘Thomas Kuhn and Interdisciplinary Conversation: Why Historians and Philosophers of Science Stopped Talking to One Another’. In Integrating History and Philosophy of Science, edited by Seymour Mauskopf and Tad Schmaltz, 13–28. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands, 2011. https://link.springer.com/chapter/10.1007/978-94-007-1745-9_2. Grube, Dirk-Martin. ‘Christian Theology Emerged by Way of a Kuhnian Paradigm Shift’. International Journal of Philosophy and Theology 79, no. 1–2 (15 March 2018): 178–93. https://doi.org/10.1080/21692327.2017.1422988. Jacobs, Struan. ‘Michael Polanyi and Thomas Kuhn: Priority and Credit’. Tradition and Discovery 33, no. 2 (2006): 25–36. ‘John C. Polanyi - On Being a Scientist: A Personal View’. Accessed 26 April 2018. https://www.nobelprize.org/nobel_prizes/chemistry/laureates/1986/polanyi-article.html. Lakatos, Imre. ‘Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes’. In Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, edited by Imre Lakatos and Alan Musgrave, 91–196. Artech House ITS Series v. 4. London: Cambridge University Press, 1970. Lamb, Matthew L., and Matthew Levering. Vatican II: Renewal Within Tradition. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008.

Page 83: When Science Gets Personal: An Analysis of Scientific ... · Edmund Kwok-Fai Lo Master of Theology Regis College and the University of Toronto 2019 Abstract An examination of scientific

78

Midgley, Mary. Science as Salvation: A Modern Myth and Its Meaning. London ; New York: Routledge, 1992. Moleski, Martin X. Personal Catholicism: The Theological Epistemologies of John Henry Newman and Michael Polanyi. Washington, D.C.: Catholic University of America Press, 2000. ———. ‘Polanyi Vs. Kuhn: Worldviews Apart’. Tradition and Discovery 33, no. 2 (2006): 8–24. O’Malley, John W. ‘Developments, Reforms, and Two Great Reformations: Towards a Historical Assessment of Vatican II’. Theological Studies; Woodstock, Md., Etc 44, no. 3 (1 September 1983): 373–406. ———. What Happened at Vatican II. Cambridge, Mass: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 2008. Omura, Satoshi. ‘Nobel Lecture: A Splendid Gift from the Earth: The Origins and Impact of Avermectin’. Stockholm, 7 December 2015. https://www.nobelprize.org/nobel_prizes/medicine/laureates/2015/omura-lecture.pdf. Pickering, Andrew. ‘From Science as Knowledge to Science as Practice’. In Science as Practice and Culture, edited by Andrew Pickering, 1–26. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1992. Poirier, Maben Walter. ‘A Comment on Polanyi and Kuhn’. The Thomist 53, no. 2 (1989): 259–79. ———. ‘The Polanyi - Kuhn Issue’. Tradition and Discovery 33, no. 2 (2006): 56–65. Suppe, Frederick. ‘The Search for Philosophic Understanding of Scientific Theories’. In The Structure of Scientific Theories, edited by Frederick Suppe, Second edition., 1–241. Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1977. The Holy See. ‘Catechism of the Catholic Church’, n.d. http://www.vatican.va/archive/ENG0015/__PC.HTM. Von Balthasar, Hans Urs. The Christian State of Life. San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1983. Wray, K. Brad. ‘Assessing the Influence of Kuhn’s Structure of Scientific Revolutions’. Metascience 21, no. 1 (1 March 2012): 1–10. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11016-011-9603-8.