surin, subalternity

Upload: liaharo

Post on 03-Apr-2018

222 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/29/2019 Surin, subalternity

    1/17

  • 7/29/2019 Surin, subalternity

    2/17

    the sovereign individual

    even if they are unable to acknowledge that this

    owing of deference is precisely what constitutes

    the kind of subordination that defines subalter-

    nity.5 Hence it is this subalterns concepts that

    constitute the thinkability of the condition in

    which (s)he is inserted, even though (s)he may beunable to perform the requisite operation of

    transcoding that renders this or that piece of

    deferential behavior (say) into a marker or symp-

    tom (in something like the Lacanian sense) of

    subalternity.

    Another way of making this point would be to

    say that a particular subaltern condition, like

    each and every cultural condition, has to secrete

    its multitudinous expressivities precisely in orderto be what it is, and that its concepts in ways

    that are inescapably selective, confining, and

    even arbitrary are the thematizations or repre-

    sentations of these expressivities. Or, more

    briefly, that the concepts of a particular subaltern

    condition are its expressivities limned in the form

    of that subalternitys thinkability.

    Theories of subalternity, by contrast, are the

    outcome of a theoretical operation whose object

    is the natures, functions, and so forth, of these

    expressivities. Theories of subalternity operate

    on a particular subalternitys thinkability, and

    involve a kind of transcoding. It is possible to ask

    the question What is subalternity? but there is

    another kind of question, involving quite another

    kind of theoretical operation, that can be asked

    as well, in this case: What is (a) theory (of subal-

    ternity)? Subalternity, qua condition, is a prodi-

    giously varied and complex practice of signs and

    images with an accompanying orchestration of

    affectivity, whose theory scholars like Spivak and

    Dipesh Chakrabarty must produce, but produce

    precisely as conceptual practice (in this case a

    practice that generates, in a metalanguage,

    concepts that reflect upon the concepts and

    expressivities of subalterns, expressivities which

    therefore constitute what is in effect a basal or

    first-order language that comes subsequently tobe transcoded). No theoretical intervention, no

    matter how refined or thoroughgoing it may be,

    can on its own constitute the concepts of (this or

    that) subalternity: the concepts of the subaltern

    are expressed in advance and independently of

    the theoretical practice of the individual, invari-

    ably an academic, who reflects on the situation of

    the subaltern. Theorists, qua theorists, can only

    create or traffic in theories of subalternity (or

    culture or collective fantasy or whatever).

    The concepts that theorists produce can be

    operative in more than one field of thought, andeven in a single field it is always possible for a

    concept to fulfil more than one function. Each

    domain of thought is defined by its own internal

    variables, variables that have a complex relation

    to their external counterparts (such as historical

    epochs, political and social conditions and

    processes, and even the brute physical character

    of things).6 It is an implication of this account of

    conceptual practice that a concept comes intobeing or ceases to be operative only when there

    is a change of function and/or field. Functions for

    concepts must be created or invalidated for the

    concepts in question to be generated or abol-

    ished, and new fields must be brought into being

    in order for these concepts to be rendered inap-

    plicable or illegitimate. To see this, we have only

    to consider the ethnographic accounts of the

    practice of deference provided in such well-

    known works as Pierre Bourdieus Outline of a

    Theory of Practice or James C. Scotts Weapons

    of the Weak.

    It is clear from Bourdieus and Scotts

    accounts that the various culturally sanctioned

    forms of deference are structured by an appara-

    tus that determines the timing, execution, and

    perception of the various acts and sequences of

    acts that constitute deference as is demon-

    strated by the person who bows too low and in so

    doing ironizes and thereby ruins what seems like

    a deferential greeting, or by the low-status cousin

    who replies a little too slowly to the chief

    landowners invitation to a wedding feast and

    who thereby insults him, and so forth. This appa-

    ratus demarcates the deferential from the merely

    ostensibly deferential, and in this way brings into

    being whole ranges of actions with this or that

    mode of deference as their condition of possibil-ity. The apparatus does this by providing rules

    that specify the appropriate operating conditions

    for the various enactments of deference, and

    these conditions, as Bourdieu and Scott point

    out, are always political. (One recalls

    Bourdieus lapidary formulation, The conces-

    4 8

  • 7/29/2019 Surin, subalternity

    3/17

    surin

    sions of politeness always contain political

    concessions (95; emphasis in original).)

    At a more general level, the concepts that are

    expressive of subalternity likewise follow rules

    that constrain their appearance and perpetuation.

    It may be, however, that subalternity is moreplausibly to be viewed as an order of orders, that

    is, as an order that brings together and orches-

    trates the rules for an amalgam or network of

    practices practices having to do in more or less

    complex ways with economic, social and cultural

    deprivation, political subordination, as well as

    with the various dispositions betokening the indi-

    viduals willingness to submit and to defer (or at

    any rate, with the socially instituted expectationof submissiveness and deference, an expectation

    that can of course be resisted or deflected in

    many subtle and not so subtle ways) with each

    component or tier of this network having its own

    rules.7

    The task of identifying and elucidating the

    rules that establish this or that subalternity (qua

    intricate mesh of practices) is fraught with the

    pitfalls that typically attend ethnographic charac-

    terization.8 These pitfalls, now fairly well known

    thanks to the efforts of cultural anthropologists

    identified with the so-called reflexive turn in

    their subject, hinge on the principle that a funda-

    mental difference exists between a situation in

    which one is presented with a description of a

    particular cultural phenomenon (in our case the

    practices typically associated with the condition

    of being a subaltern) and a situation in which one

    is confronted in a directly self-involving way with

    that cultural phenomenon. The subalternist theo-

    rist is essentially in the former situation, while

    someone who self-involvingly employs an expres-

    sivity betokening the condition of subalternity is

    in the latter position. Thus, the theorist of the

    subaltern brings with her implicitly the historical

    and intellectual experience that makes her the

    thinker she is, but that experience may not

    belong to the place or culture she is studying.Her ideas, and the ways of living to which they

    apply, may mean that she is not at all like the

    persons who belong to the (subaltern) culture she

    is endeavoring to describe. It may also mean,

    conversely, that the members of the (subaltern)

    culture may not be in a position to recognize the

    theorists (putatively non-subaltern) thoughts

    as being germane to their condition or connected

    with it in a way that is interesting or salient or

    whatever. There are inherent limits and obstacles

    to any attempt to visit as a theorist all the reaches

    of a particular historical phase, or even those ofa particular culture, subaltern or otherwise. The

    subalternist theorist, like any theorist of culture,

    can never therefore be absolutely certain of the

    precise reach of her theories and concepts, nor

    can she be sure that these theories and concepts

    have any kind of adequate approximation to the

    expressivities of the subaltern culture in ques-

    tion, all the more so in that these expressivities

    happen to belong to a culture that is disaccom-modated or misrepresented in very decisive ways

    by its non-subaltern counterparts (and in that the

    theorist of the subaltern is invariably someone

    who is not in the position of being a subaltern).

    A cultures expressivities stand as an insur-

    mountable exteriority to the theory of (that)

    culture, and in so doing function from the begin-

    ning as irremovable etiolations of the ambition of

    cultural description and this even when the

    describer of the subaltern culture happens to be

    in profound sympathy or solidarity with the

    denizens of that marginalized culture.9 Another

    way of making this point would be to say that,

    while the subalterns expressivities or speech

    become the condition of possibility of the subal-

    ternist theorists writing and describing, this is a

    condition that the theorist cannot write or insti-

    tute, and this because expressivities are perforce

    irreducible to description (even though they can

    be transcoded into description, theory in this

    instance being expressivity rendered into descrip-

    tion or writing).

    There are two possible responses to this

    unavoidable circumscription or deflation of the

    ambition of cultural description. One is to inte-

    grate into ones projects of cultural description

    this lack of commensurability between expressiv-

    ity and description, to recognize that representa-tion or naming (the sine qua non of any project

    of cultural description) is inherently problematic,

    self-vitiating even, and that the ethnographer had

    better face up to this, and turn the ethnographic

    undertaking into an operation which, in the spirit

    of a certain theoretical asceticism, interrogates

    4 9

  • 7/29/2019 Surin, subalternity

    4/17

    the sovereign individual

    the very desire whose name is ethnography or

    cultural description. Why desire to name those

    who ostensibly have no desire to name them-

    selves? Why continue to produce concepts moti-

    vated by this desire to name those who happen to

    live their lives outside the confining epistemicspace that is home to the operation of naming,

    and especially when the context of this operation

    is one in which description can never hope to

    catch up with expressivity? Posing these ques-

    tions in ways that amount to a deflation of high

    ethnographic ambition is of course one of the

    defining features of the so-called reflexive turn

    in cultural anthropology that manifested itself in

    the 1980s, and it is an implication of the positiontaken in this article that the subalternist theorist

    is enjoined to make a similar reflexive turn for

    herself.10

    The second possible response (to this seem-

    ingly inescapable restriction or deflation of the

    aspiration of cultural description) is associated

    with the one just canvassed, and it requires the

    subalternist theorist to find ways of relating to

    the exteriority constituted by the expressivities of

    the subaltern that, more or less self-consciously,

    do not involve the creation of systems of knowl-

    edge that replicate the asymmetries of power that

    define the relation between the subalterns

    culture and the invariably non-subaltern culture

    of the subalternist theorist, but that instead

    regard the unbridgeable gap between expressivity

    and description as a problem posed essentially

    for the internal constitution of subalternist

    theory. That is to say, the inevitable outstripping

    of (subalternist) description by (subaltern)

    expressivity strikes at the heart of the enterprise

    of description, and it should therefore ensue in a

    displacement of the theorist rather than simply a

    displacement of the subaltern object of study. A

    rigorous theoretical askesis (self-disciplining) is

    therefore the only adequate way of responding to

    this problem. I shall return to the question of this

    theoretical askesis shortly, above all in connec-tion with the primary external variables of the

    field in which the concept of a subalternity is to

    be produced.

    Before I discuss some of the primary external

    variables of the field in which the concept of a

    subalternity is generated, something needs to be

    said about the mechanisms that underlie the

    constitution of the lived world that is the context

    from which the perceptions, desires, thoughts,

    and actions of social subjects are orchestrated.

    The daily round of life for the social subject is

    complexly mediated by ensembles of images andsigns, signs being images of images, and images

    in turn being orchestrations of temporal and

    spatial relations.11 Thus, the lived world of, say,

    the Bengali peasant who migrates from Calcuttas

    rural hinterland to Calcutta itself to work as a

    cargo loader in the port of Calcutta will be estab-

    lished by an ensemble of sign-images constituting

    the new world of the city of Calcutta, by a simi-

    lar ensemble constituting the old world of thesmall rural village 400 miles away, by the sign-

    images prevalent in the new world that is

    Calcutta that designate the small village that used

    to be home for the migrant peasant (This is

    how the typical inhabitant of Calcutta thinks of

    the place I came from), and by the sign-images

    designating Calcutta that prevailed in the old

    world of the small village (This is how the

    people of my village typically view Calcutta),

    and all this because the semiotic registers of the

    movements between different lived worlds have

    themselves to be incorporated into the constitu-

    tion of the worlds in question. The peasants

    conceptual rendition of the village-world left

    behind is now inflected by the peasants insertion

    into the new semiotic ensemble that is Calcutta,

    just as the semiotic ensemble that is Calcutta is

    always itself constituted by the semiotic ensem-

    ble that is the peasants previous lived world, the

    small village 400 miles away. The small village is

    always prehended in terms of the big city and

    vice versa, and the world I have left behind is

    prehended in terms of the world I have moved

    into, just as the world I have moved into is always

    prehended (if not entirely, then certainly

    partially) in terms of the world or worlds I previ-

    ously inhabited.12 In this way, a whole range of

    multiply-linked sign-image assemblages underliesones prehensions of the temporal and spatial

    relations embodied in the antecedents and prox-

    imities that enable a world (that peasants world,

    but still a public world) to be constituted out of

    the flux that is composed of these antecedents

    and proximities.13

    5 0

  • 7/29/2019 Surin, subalternity

    5/17

    surin

    These semiotic assemblages designating

    Calcutta, the rural village the peasant has

    migrated from, the ensemble regulating the tran-

    sition from the one to the other, and so on and

    so forth are criss-crossed by yet other assem-

    blages (each of course with an associated affectivecomponent) that designate such formations as

    family, job, education (if any), circle of friends

    and associates, gender, caste and class position,

    and so forth. The notion of (a) subalternity,

    therefore, is an abstraction denoting a particular

    kind of relationship between these assemblages

    subalternity is inevitably mischaracterized when

    it is viewed as an object or discursive entity that

    is directly denoted by the concept subalternityand its cognates. For, as has just been indicated,

    the object itself is already an abstraction from

    this nexus of assemblages and from the unstable

    linkages between them. The expressivities of the

    subaltern have the subalterns insertion into this

    matrix of assemblages as their condition of possi-

    bility: not to be embedded in them is perforce to

    be something other than a subaltern.14 (The

    crucial question here is whether or not the subal-

    ternist theorist is necessarily constituted in such

    a way that, while she may be able to reflect on

    the subalterns expressivities and thereby

    produce the concept of the subaltern as a theo-

    retical object, the constitution of the subalternist

    theorist unavoidably detaches the lived world of

    this theorist from the nexus of assemblages that

    bring about the existence of the subaltern.)

    The primary external variables of the field in

    which the concept of a subalternity is to be gener-

    ated today will be identified through an account

    of the conditions of possibility for the emergence

    of the semiotic assemblages that create the

    personage of the subaltern and the expressivities

    that define this personage. It would take an

    extended and complex narrative to enumerate the

    full range of these external variables, and the

    following account is unavoidably schematic.

    The basis for the applicability and intelligibil-ity of the concept of the subaltern is a particular

    structure of exploitation: the theoretical opera-

    tion involved in the production of the concept of

    subalternity has as an axiom that the subaltern is

    such precisely because they happen to be

    exploited in some way, and because they are

    subjected to the particularity of interests in ways

    that reflect fundamental asymmetries of power

    whose effect is to consign the subaltern to the

    margins of society.15 This structure of exploita-

    tion possesses two primary axes, namely, the

    mode of domination and the mode of production;the struggles of the subaltern take place along

    both these axes.16 Struggles over the mode of

    domination are primarily struggles for greater

    social visibility and for more effective social

    agency; struggles over the mode of production

    have the reallocation of value as their primary

    (though not necessarily exclusive) focus.

    In todays world, and as has been the case

    since the emergence of the modern world-system,the capitalist paradigm of production and accu-

    mulation is the primary engine driving this struc-

    ture of exploitation. Though not all forms or

    manifestations of subalternity have as their direct

    cause the workings of the capitalist system, the

    logic of the overall structure which organizes the

    particularity of interests is a logic whose rudi-

    ment is supplied by the axioms of capitalist

    expansion. The current phase of capitalist devel-

    opment (called real subsumption by Antonio

    Negri, or the epoch of the society of control by

    Deleuze) is also the period in which biopolitics

    is the name of the mode in which power is typi-

    cally constituted, and any attempt to produce the

    concept of subalternity calls for an analysis of

    both the mode of power or domination and the

    mode of production typically associated with this

    phase.17

    In this new phase of capitalist development,

    the mode of domination and the mode of produc-

    tion have entered into a qualitatively different

    kind of relationship. In previous capitalist

    dispensations, as Marx himself pointed out, it was

    necessary for the mode of domination and the

    mode of production to reinforce each other

    directly, so that a single, all-encompassing capi-

    tal logic regulated the dynamic of both these

    modes, and it did so basically by extirpating so-called precapitalist formations from each

    mode. Hence, from 1789 onwards, the modern

    liberal state and its bourgeois democratic appur-

    tenances were the typical form in which the mode

    of domination was constituted (in the industrial

    countries of the West, at any rate), and in this

    5 1

  • 7/29/2019 Surin, subalternity

    6/17

    the sovereign individual

    way it was possible for the prevailing mode of

    domination to be aligned in a relationship of

    structural affinity with the accumulation strategy

    governing the mode of production (i.e., the earli-

    est forms of monopoly capitalism in the first

    stage, and FordismKeynesianism in the second).Today, however, capitalism is becoming more

    abstract, more algorithmic, because this is the

    only way that it can ensure that it mediates every

    and any kind of production even that of a

    precapitalist variety and places them at the

    disposal of accumulation. The transition to this

    phase is marked in a number of registers: the

    creation of an international division of labor, the

    rise of an international debt economy, the modu-lation of Capital into the structures of transna-

    tional corporations, the introduction of flexible

    manufacturing systems and labor processes, the

    growth of decentralized and informal economies,

    the exponential growth (especially in the

    economies of the semiperipheral and peripheral

    nations) of standardized markets and patterns of

    consumption, the development of complex secu-

    rities and credit systems, the inauguration of a

    new semiotics of value, and so forth.

    In this new regime of accumulation, produc-

    tion, in the nineteenth-century sense of an activ-

    ity that typically requires the factory to function

    as a disciplinary space of enclosure or concen-

    tration owned and regimented by the capitalist, is

    effectively (though not entirely) relegated to the

    peripheral and semiperipheral nations. What

    takes place in the capitalist centers today is some-

    thing quite different, a kind of production that is

    akin to a production of production, a higher

    order or metaproduction associated with markets

    that deal not so much in goods or merchandise as

    in stocks and services and in the technological

    instruments for the telematic orchestration of

    images and spectacles. The domain in which

    these orchestrations take place is that of culture,

    and it is culture that allows the logic of Capital

    to become planetary and diffused.The current phase of capitalist expansion, with

    its progressively more extensive systems of

    metaproduction, has created a social order in

    which all the conditions of production and repro-

    duction have been directly absorbed by Capital

    by abolishing the boundary between society and

    capital, Capital has itself become social in nature.

    In order to enable further the extraction of new

    forms of surplus value, new forms it has to invent

    as a way of dealing with the crisis of the current

    paradigm of accumulation, Capital has to extend

    its logic of command to cover the entire domainof productive social cooperation, and thus effec-

    tively envelop the whole of society. Only in this

    way can Capital insert itself into the flows of

    social power, the power it needs to be precisely

    what it is Capital. Capitalist command is now

    universal and diffused, and Capital in this world-

    system is thus an immense machine, a machine

    that endlessly proliferates deconstitution after

    deconstitution, and, concomitantly, reconstitu-tion after reconstitution. One day I am a peasant

    laborer in rural Bengal, another day I am a cargo

    loader in Calcutta, another day I am

    The transnational algorithm that is Capital is

    able to ensure the isomorphy (a term I have

    taken from Gilles Deleuze and Flix Guattari) of

    very diverse formations. Isomorphy is not to be

    confused with homogeneity because, unlike the

    latter, it is compatible with the prevalence of a

    real diversity of formations. As a kind of grid

    or diagram whose logic is to secure the condi-

    tions of its own reproduction, Capital is situated

    at the crossing-point of all sorts of formations

    (commercial or economic, religious, artistic, and

    so on), and it therefore has the complementary

    capacity to integrate and recompose non-capital-

    ist sectors or modes of production. A case in

    point here would be a country like Brazil, in

    which there is every conceivable kind of produc-

    tion, from the tribal production of Amazonian

    Indians to computer technology as advanced as

    anything to be found in North America or

    Western Europe. It would seem that every and

    any kind of production even that of a precapi-

    talist variety can be mediated in countries like

    Brazil, and placed at the disposal of Capital.18

    In such an isomorphic world, literally everything

    can yield surplus value for capital. In a milieu inwhich Capital has become ubiquitous, productive

    labor (as always the sine qua non of Capital)

    is also positioned within every component of

    society. But then, equally, the whole of society

    has to be organized so that Capital is able to

    continue to reproduce itself. The outcome of this

    5 2

  • 7/29/2019 Surin, subalternity

    7/17

    surin

    twofold development is that the absolute spatial

    division between exploiters and exploited posited

    by a more conventional Marxism has effectively

    been eliminated the exploiters are everywhere,

    as too are the exploited. The sweatshop exists in

    Mexico and Macau, and it also exists in New Yorkand Los Angeles, just as it is a latter-day business

    imperative that IBM has a head office not only in

    New York and London but also in Jamaica

    (where IBM has had an office since 1950) and

    Malaysia (where it has had an office since

    1961).19

    This state of affairs poses an important ques-

    tion in regard to the issue of the mode of produc-

    tion, because it is now clearer than ever that therehas to be a prior organization of social power

    before production can even begin to take place.

    In its metaproductive mode, Capital has

    bypassed a phase in which it needed only to

    concentrate exploitative power at this or that

    specific point of production. In order to be what

    they are today, the modes of production depend

    crucially on an enabling matrix of antecedent

    processes that organize power and desire so that

    production can become possible. Another way of

    saying this would be to view the modes of

    production as the outcome of expressions of

    desire, as the outcomes or derivations of this

    ceaselessly generative desire (or phantasy) which

    is produced in the mode of domination (and

    which therefore allows domination to take place

    in ways that do not necessarily look like domina-

    tion).

    What enables each mode of production to be

    constituted is a specific aggregation of desires,

    forces, and powers brought about in the mode of

    domination: it is this antecedent assemblage,

    lodged in the mode of domination, that is the

    enabling condition for the reproduction of the

    mode of production. A requisite organization of

    productive desire or phantasy has always

    preceded capitalist accumulation; today,

    however, the very existence and nature of thisdesire, the process of its composition into an

    economy, has to be permeated by Capital itself.

    The upshot is that nowadays Capital has started

    to do much of its work, in the mode of domina-

    tion, even before it becomes visible to us

    through its more overt manifestations (corpora-

    tions such as IBM and Siemens, stock exchanges,

    investment banks, entrepreneurs, shopping

    malls, and so on).

    If Capital is an axiomatic that transcodes or

    rearticulates a particular space of accumulation,

    culture is the site where Capital organizes anddistributes the kind of generative desire or phan-

    tasy that enables production and accumulation to

    take place. Capital has to saturate the spaces in

    which culture is organized and produced. And

    here the transnationalization of the capitalist

    axiomatic has as its necessary complement the

    transnationalization of the processes involved in

    the organization of generative desire (the locus of

    which is culture).Not everyone is a subaltern, obviously, but,

    just as obviously, subalternity is everywhere,

    since dclass subjects are found in every

    segment of the capitalist system in its current

    shape and form, whether at the peripheries, semi-

    peripheries, or centers of this system. The criti-

    cal question for those reflecting on the question

    of the proper or plausible form of a theory of the

    subaltern has to be the one that exercised Ranajit

    Guha in his pivotal Elementary Aspects of

    Peasant Insurgency in Colonial India, namely,

    what significance does this theory place on the

    insurgent or transgressive activity of the subal-

    tern? This question is central not simply because

    it was for Guha the decisive question posed for

    the historiography of colonial (and post-indepen-

    dent) India, but also because it is precisely the

    contours and outcomes of this transgressive

    activity that define the subaltern (rather than

    simply the matter of the subalterns conscious-

    ness or situation as a dclass individual).20

    Anyone convinced by Guha on this point would

    place the weight of significance in formulating a

    theory of the subaltern on the thematics of trans-

    gression and its expressivities, and also be

    persuaded that once we accept that transgres-

    sions expressivities are the determinative marker

    of subalternity, it will perhaps be clear: (i) thatsubalternity is best parsed as an abstraction

    (the term is Gyan Prakashs) that registers a surd

    or voiceless element, an internal theoretical

    fissure, confounding the theoretical ambitions of

    the subalternist theorist (in this sense, it has

    nothing really to do with real life peasants, the

    5 3

  • 7/29/2019 Surin, subalternity

    8/17

    the sovereign individual

    lumpen proletariat, and so on), so that subalter-

    nity is exactly what the theorist cannot produce

    as an adequate practico-theoretical object; and (ii)

    that a rigorous rendering of the concept of subal-

    ternity in terms of the notion of transgression

    opens up certain possibilities that may otherwisebe occluded, to wit, that the transgressor is some-

    one necessarily positioned in an economy of

    desire not totally constrained by a capitalist

    axiomatics, and, furthermore, that the space of

    this non-capitalist economy of desire is that of a

    paracoloniality possessing traits that are

    markedly different from those of its counterpart

    formation, postcoloniality.21

    I have already suggested that espousing a theo-retical askesis germane to the notion of a subal-

    ternity is an undertaking that best takes the form

    of a deconstitution of the speech (a majoritarian

    speech) of the subalternist theorist. Here one

    adverts to the paradox that lies at the heart of

    subalternist theory: namely, that the object of

    this theory is to all intents and purposes a minori-

    tarian historical and political subject (and, more-

    over, a subject often deemed by proponents of

    the majoritarian discourse to be outside the

    domains of rationality and the reach of history,

    as Gyan Prakash and others have pointed out),

    while the creator of this theory, the subalternist

    theorist, invariably an academic ensconced in a

    European or North American institution, some-

    what paradoxically employs what is intrinsically a

    majoritarian discourse to bring this minoritar-

    ian figure to speech.22 This seeming paradox

    owes its existence to the fact that the occupant of

    a majoritarian position is never capable of

    advance or becoming inasmuch as (s)he is

    already, analytically, the norm or standard of

    what is preeminent, excellent, desirable,

    absolute, and so on.23 Since the normatively

    majoritarian subject is already where he should

    be, he can only occupy the position, always

    pregiven, of the constant and of the mean (the

    cool majoritarian is always able to say: this iswhere its at, baby). Movement or transforma-

    tion can therefore only come from those who are

    not in the situation of being majoritarian; and the

    majoritarian subject can be transformed only by

    withdrawing from that which is majoritarian, just

    as minoritarian consciousness is transformed only

    by exceeding, and exceeding again and again, the

    standard where the minoritarian happens to be

    lodged. And since the minoritarian standpoint

    embodies all that differs from this majoritarian

    subjectivity, the latter consciousness being one

    that necessarily dispels difference (as when theslightest departure from a normative whiteness,

    say, already amounts to a crossing of the thresh-

    old into a problematic non-whiteness), the most

    radical becoming-minor is always directed

    towards difference and the different. In the face

    of the static implacability that inherently defines

    the normativity of the majoritarian subject, the

    proponent of difference becomes different

    precisely by striving to keep this pregiven norma-tivity at bay. The minoritarian can never differ

    enough from the normativity of the norm, even

    if (s)he happens already to be launched on a

    trajectory of becoming-minoritarian: hence, for

    instance, there can be no conceptual limit to the

    becoming non-white of someone deviating from

    the normativity of an unbending and quintessen-

    tial whiteness. Transformation or movement for

    the minoritarian consciousness therefore takes

    the form of an indispensable intensification of

    difference, and one becomes truly gay, for

    instance, only by making greater and greater

    distantiations from the majoritarian normativity

    that resides in being straight. There is a univer-

    sal in becoming-minor, and it is the more intense

    becoming-other of the one who is embarked on

    the movement towards that which is minoritar-

    ian. All minoritarian subjects are embarked on a

    trajectory of becoming-other simply by virtue of

    their being minoritarian.24

    I invoke Deleuze and Guattaris suggestive

    account of becoming-minoritarian for two

    reasons: (i) it provides us with a way of fleshing

    out the theoretical askesis that the subalternist

    theorist must take on; and (ii) it points to a

    conception of the transformation of social and

    historical subjects that links this work or project

    of transformation to the category of transgres-sion.

    The imperative that the speech of the subal-

    ternist theorist incorporate a theoretical askesis

    that is in line with the conception of a becoming-

    minoritarian sketched out here requires the theo-

    rist to find a line leading away from his/her

    5 4

  • 7/29/2019 Surin, subalternity

    9/17

    surin

    theory that can initiate a becoming-minor for

    himself/herself and his/her characteristic (theo-

    retical) speech. In so doing, the theorist moves

    away from the speech of language A to language

    B, and in the process finds a language X that

    gives him/her a line to the becoming-other of theone designated subaltern; mutatis mutandis,

    the theorist finds, through immersion in

    language X and through the complementary

    engagement with the becoming-other of the

    subaltern, his/her own unanticipated becoming-

    minoritarian and its attendant becoming-other.25

    It should be emphasized that this becoming-

    minoritarian of the theorist does not serve as an

    exemplification of the injunction Theorist!Always show solidarity with the oppressed!

    which is often taken to express the basic disposi-

    tion of someone writing in a politically engaged

    manner. A becoming-minoritarian of the kind

    envisaged here may in fact show that, in some

    circumstances, the very possibility of such a soli-

    darity is preempted until the theorist is able to

    become something other than a theorist, and the

    oppressed victim something other than a victim.

    Becoming-minoritarian consequently involves

    the simultaneous breaching and closing of limits

    that have been instituted by the majoritarian

    rulers of society. The propensity to excess or to

    dereliction that constitutes becoming-minoritar-

    ian is thus inherently transgressive. This trans-

    gressiveness is not, however, necessarily to be

    taken in the sense of a war against majoritarian

    limits, but is rather the creation of something

    else, the space of a transvaluation in which these

    limits become something they could not have

    been, had the transgression not taken place. This

    characterization of the transgressive act brings to

    mind Georges Batailles discussion of transgres-

    sion in his Lerotisme, which begins with the

    formula: The transgression does not deny the

    taboo but transcends it and completes it

    (Eroticism 63).26 According to this logic of the

    transgressive act, the transgression impels thelimit or interdiction in another direction, a direc-

    tion that culminates (in principle) in something

    that resists the possibility of being expressed in

    the form of an interdiction, something that, on

    the contrary, decodifies the interdiction and in so

    doing evades the majoritarian apparatuses that

    subtend the upholding of all such interdictions.

    Related to this conception of transgression are

    the notions of the sovereign individual and the

    sovereign operation developed by Bataille in

    La Part Maudite (The Accursed Share), and it is

    to these that I now turn.Demarcating his notion of sovereignty from

    the one more obviously and traditionally associ-

    ated with such majoritarian figures as the

    pharaoh, king, king of kings, various divini-

    ties, as well as the priests who served and

    incarnated them, Bataille adumbrates an

    apparently lost sovereignty to which the beggar

    can sometimes be as close as the great nobleman,

    and from which, as a rule, the bourgeois is volun-tarily the most far removed, and this because

    life beyond utility is the domain of sovereignty

    (The Accursed Share 19798; emphasis in origi-

    nal).27 The sovereign individual is thus someone

    whose subjectivity is not finally constrained by

    capitalist relations of production, with their

    apotheosizing of the principle of utility; its exem-

    plary and essentially utopian embodiment is for

    Bataille the person who, even fleetingly, has an

    object of desire that is not defined by the neces-

    sity conferred by suffering (The Accursed Share

    199). This extension of the notion of the sover-

    eign being to dclass or minoritarian subjects is

    crucially important, if only for the following

    reason. Standard accounts conceive of the subal-

    tern as someone engaged in forms of palpable

    insurgency or quiet resistance that escapes the

    purview not only of state formations, but also of

    the more official forms of opposition to the state

    (elite-dominated nationalism or neo-nationalism

    in colonial and independent India, for instance),

    as well as the academically legitimated histories

    of these opposition movements. Subalternist

    theory traffics in such notions, seemingly essen-

    tial to it, as the people, the masses, and so

    forth, and it derives much of its theoretical

    energy from an identification with the figures

    designated via recourse to such abstract notions,whose hitherto effaced histories it then under-

    takes to recover.28 The outcome, and here I agree

    with Rosalind OHanlon, is that subalternist

    theory effectively gives us a new if cleaned-up,

    pristine, version of the classic unitary self-

    constituting subject-agent of liberal humanism

    5 5

  • 7/29/2019 Surin, subalternity

    10/17

    the sovereign individual

    (80), since the requirement that the subaltern be

    understood as an effective historical agent

    involves positing this agent as a parallel and

    equally assertive counterpart-subject to the

    agents and agencies posited in the official histo-

    ries. In this way, the representative subalternfigures invoked by subalternist theory come to be

    understood as owners and makers of their

    pasts, and so forth, and therefore constitute a

    rival or shadow being-majoritarian that is a coun-

    terpoint to the states and the social elites own

    official versions of being-majoritarian. The

    upshot is that the subaltern is someone who

    escapes the full reach of the states exercise of

    sovereignty (i.e., its authoritative rendition of theprinciple of utility), but is nonetheless still

    constrained by some manifestation or other of

    the principle of utility. The subaltern or dclass

    subject has no real becoming-minoritarian in this

    particular historiographical scheme of things, and

    is not able to exercise a sovereignty not ulti-

    mately predicated on the principle of utility.

    By contrast, a sovereignty compatible with a

    becoming-minoritarian (Bataillean sovereignty,

    we could call it) will involve the dissolution of

    majoritarian limits in ways that could not have

    been anticipated from any of the epistemically

    available standpoints in that particular society.

    Hence, a state of affairs hitherto thought impos-

    sible or unreasonable can now manifest itself to

    that societys subject-citizens, even though this

    manifestation of the new does retain certain

    qualities of the mysterium even as it is revealed.

    This state of affairs becomes an instance of what

    Bataille calls the sovereign exigency, that is,

    the impossible coming true, in the reign of the

    moment (The Accursed Share 211; emphasis in

    original) in the course of which the rule of

    exchange-value and the commodity-form are

    breached. It should be acknowledged that

    Bataille takes this exigency to indicate not a

    reality that is realized, but rather an unending

    dialectic between the principle of utility andsovereignty (the telos of which is the negation of

    utilitys conditions). For Bataille it is the case

    that:

    [w]e cannot reduce ourselves to utility and

    neither can we negate our conditions. That is

    why we find the human quality not in some

    definite state but in the necessarily undecided

    battle of the one who refuses the given what-

    ever this may be, provided it is the given. (The

    Accursed Share 348; emphasis in original)29

    The expansion, along the lines specified by

    Bataille, of the notion of sovereign being toencompass the dclass or subaltern individual is

    perhaps more apparent in the works of such

    cultural anthropologists as Michael Taussig

    (Shamanism, Colonialism, and the Wild Man)

    and Marjorie Mandelstam Balzer (The Tenacity

    of Ethnicity) than it is in the writings of self-

    identified subalternist theorists. Taussig and

    Balzer both provide narratives that, among other

    things, characterize shamanism and sorcery aspractices grounding the lineaments of a counter-

    history which places its subjects in a divergent

    universe in which the sufferings visited on subju-

    gated peoples by the colonial and neo-colonial

    dispensations are conclusively abolished. The

    complementary universe opened up by these

    shamanistic practices is therefore utopian, and

    this in at least two senses. It is utopian in that the

    dispossessed Putumayo people of Southwestern

    Colombia (Taussig) and the Khanty people of

    Northwestern Siberia (Balzer) come to encounter

    alternative realities in which they are liberated,

    even if only for a short while, from the rule of

    necessity (Batailles given?) imposed by neo-

    colonialism in its variant manifestations; and also

    because the shaman, in tendering this counter-

    reality, draws his/her clients into the space of a

    healed reality which has as its raison dtre the

    abolishment of the affliction and pain caused by

    the ruinous prevailing order (i.e., that given).

    The shaman and his dispossessed clients, no

    matter how dclass and in however unpromising

    a situation, find ways to become sovereign

    beings, political and epistemic equivocalness

    notwithstanding.

    In such accounts, dclass subjects have the

    possibility of speaking for so long as they can

    transgress against the given. Taussigs andBalzers ethnographies show with devastating

    clarity how persecution and its accompanying

    distress soon await those who reconcile them-

    selves to the given. Yet the same ethnographies

    also show how refusing to accommodate oneself

    to the given may likewise betoken death and

    5 6

  • 7/29/2019 Surin, subalternity

    11/17

    surin

    misery. Tragedy always lurks for the subaltern,

    or so it would seem. But these ethnographies

    demonstrate that, as long as it is possible to trans-

    gress, there is hope for the hopeless.

    The space in which this sovereign hope, a

    becoming-minoritarian hope for the hopeless, isactive is in part the space of what I am calling a

    paracoloniality. This is a realm in which the

    being-minoritarian of the dclass subject is

    amplified into further and perhaps more intense

    becomings-minor, and the subject repositioned

    accordingly. Each becoming-minor is a becom-

    ing-other, so that the subject is a kind of fermen-

    tation, a crystallization of forces and passions,

    that can be moved on: (s)he can become indefi-nite, then definite, then indefinite again; (s)he

    can become other other other

    other. Each becoming permeates and

    displaces adjacent becomings, as the movement

    from becoming A to becoming B is always

    through an Xthat is neither A nor B but which

    enables A to become B, then C (through a Y),

    and so forth. Each becoming therefore estab-

    lishes the relativity and mobility of its counter-

    parts. The subject, from this viewpoint, is an

    assemblage of multiplicities (Freud, for example,

    is all the objects father, mother, siblings, teach-

    ers, friends, wife, Jung, Adler, Ferenczi, and so

    on who populate the assemblage or conscious-

    ness whose title is Freud), a dynamic

    panorama of becoming (so Freud is all those vari-

    able relations of becoming that obtain between

    him and all those he approaches), and a

    condensation of forces (so Freud is a matrix of

    forces that are transmitted to him and those

    forces that he transmits).30 There can be

    segments of this space of enunciation-visualiza-

    tion, in which the subject is constituted as a semi-

    otic ensemble, that register the impossibility of

    pronouncing emphatically the difference between

    white and non-white, Western and non-

    Western, European and non-European, just

    as there can be other segments of this space inwhich such differences can be palpably felt and

    stated. Neither kind of segment is able to abolish

    the possibility of the other, and what is crucial

    for the constitution of the subject is the trajec-

    tory taken across these segments as one moves

    through ones various becomings-other. A partic-

    ular and specific trajectory, but not another,

    may establish a heterotopian segment of

    this space in which other segments bearing the

    names coloniality, Empire, and even post-

    coloniality may be decomposed, even if only

    momentarily, through the amplification of theheterotopian segment. A heterotopian segment

    functions as the unthought of the segments

    that bear the names coloniality, Empire,

    postcoloniality, and so forth, since the very

    conditions of possibility of the heterotopian

    segment necessitate a preemption of the semiotic

    assemblage that is coloniality, Empire, or

    postcoloniality. Each becoming-other expresses

    one or more possible worlds that may beunknown to the subject undergoing that becom-

    ing-other. These are not worlds that the subject

    in question has necessarily to see or know, for

    they could be possible worlds in which the

    subject comes to be seen or known, in which one

    is rendered visible or knowable to oneself, even

    if only transiently. One may have to see others,

    the inhabitants of this possible world, looking at

    oneself before one can come to see oneself.

    In taking this itinerary through the segment of

    the discursive space that is paracoloniality, a

    space that can exist in the midst of Empire, the

    subject traverses possible worlds in which her

    consciousness is reconstituted in ways that

    decompose the realities of Empire. As a result

    of this reconstitution, the subject discovers that

    she, and the worlds into which she is drawn, are

    only the concretions of a specific desire. The

    upshot is that the subject and these worlds can be

    dismantled by other, alternative, configurations

    of desire, in a dismantling that does not involve

    an act of negation on the part of the subject and

    the inhabitants of these paracolonial worlds. In

    taking the lines of flight constitutive of these

    worlds, the dclass subject finds a liberty that is

    not defined in relation to a master, a master

    who, in the manner prescribed in Hegels

    masterslave dialectic, would have to be negatedby the slave before the latter can become

    free.31 In the realm of this paracoloniality,

    liberty is attainable in principle without recourse

    to the strategies of a mastery, of a counter-domi-

    nation that is only the obverse of the mastery and

    ascendancy embodied in the figure of the colonial

    5 7

  • 7/29/2019 Surin, subalternity

    12/17

    the sovereign individual

    master. In these admittedly rare realms (I am

    thinking here specifically of the worlds of

    shamanistic practice as described by Taussig,

    Balzer, and others), the actualities of mastery and

    domination are comprehensively dissolved. For

    imperial dispensations are situated in a constella-tion of myriad possible worlds, each of which

    affects the others. These are worlds that in the

    texts of Taussig and Balzer are expressed by

    sorcerers, individuals of different races and

    nationalities, persons of mixed ethnicity, subtly

    arcane rituals, the sharing of food, a stereoscope

    of landscapes, the brutalities of colonial occupa-

    tion, an immense proliferation of states of

    consciousness, and so forth.In these multiply-constellated worlds, subjects

    do not necessarily have their identifications and

    affects structured on the basis of a differentiation

    from an other who would be, according to the

    logic of the dialectic, necessarily a second. In

    such worlds, there are others, certainly, but

    these constitute thirds, fourths, fifths,

    sixths, and so on, each of whom is related to

    its counterparts in ways that do not conform to a

    dialectical logic. In paracoloniality we find prin-

    ciples of differentiation that spawn identifications

    according to several, if not many, logics, logics

    which in some cases may be non-commensurable,

    and hence not in any kind of direct or discernible

    opposition to each other.32

    It is important, in conclusion, that we should

    not inflate the claims made on behalf of the

    concept of this paracoloniality that is a counter-

    point to the coloniality and postcoloniality of

    the subalternist theorist. Suffice to say that

    paracoloniality exists in the midst of coloniality

    and postcoloniality, and more often than not

    is overwhelmed by them. Heterotopian spaces

    can be beset by a tragic fragility. But where

    they exist, they make it possible for their

    denizens, however dclass they may be, to

    live the lives of sovereign beings freed from

    the constraint of exchange relations.The expressivities of these

    sovereign beings provide what

    is perhaps the decisive impetus

    for an internal delimitation of

    the descriptive ambitions of the

    subalternist theorist.

    notes

    1 There are several or indeed many subalternities.

    The locus classicus of the concept is of course the

    Subaltern Studies project based in the area of

    South Asian history, with a particular initial

    emphasis on the history of British rule in India,though later works associated with the notion of

    a subaltern studies have extended themselves

    geopolitically beyond the domain of India and

    intellectually beyond the field of historiography.

    For a brief but excellent conspectus of the emer-

    gence and development of Subaltern Studies, see

    Vinayak Chaturvedis Introduction to his collec-

    tionMapping Subaltern Studies and the Postcolonial

    (viixix). All the essays in Chaturvedis collection,

    many by the projects key and originating protago-nists, reflect the different and varied phases of its

    development and extension.

    The account of conceptual practice given below

    was developed in my On Producing the Concept

    of a Global Culture, from which several

    sentences have been taken. This account is greatly

    indebted to Gilles Deleuze and Flix Guattaris

    What is Philosophy?

    2 It is an implication of (iii) that a currently exist-

    ing conceptuality can always be superseded by a

    newer one: no conceptuality expresses or deter-

    mines the condition or situation that it brings to

    expression in a way that is completely exhaustive.

    An expressivity works by naming things, yet the

    thing named is never the thing itself, but is rather

    the affects associated with the thing in question.

    Spinoza was the thinker who first perceived this,

    and Gilles Deleuze is to be credited with the

    systematization of this insight. The thing is a

    concrescence of its affects (it is the event of thisconcrescence), and the affects in question vary

    with the interactions that have that thing as their

    point of focus. Hence, say, the horse that races is

    a very different thing (especially for its jockey

    and horse-racing fans) from the horse that draws

    a plow (especially for the peasant farmer using the

    horse for this purpose). On this, see Deleuze and

    Claire Parnet, Dialogues 60. The thing being an

    assemblage of affects, and there being in principle

    a huge variability in the way in which these assem-blages can be organized, no expressivity (qua the

    name of the assemblage in question) can eliminate

    its competitor names and the assemblages desig-

    nated by them.

    3 This is another way of indicating that hardly

    deniable effectivity of thought with which the

    5 8

  • 7/29/2019 Surin, subalternity

    13/17

    surin

    idealist philosophical traditions have always been

    impressed, but which materialist traditions have

    usually found awkward or insusceptible of satisfac-

    tory description and analysis, or else reducible in

    general to something more constitutive and

    emphatic, namely, matter.

    4 Thus the formulations of a Gayatri Chakravorty

    Spivak or Ranajit Guha constitute a theory

    about subalternity, while the concepts ofsubal-

    ternity are likely to include the notions (which may

    be inchoate or half-formed) of rank and entitle-

    ment, property division, and so forth, actually

    operative in the thought and practice of the

    Bengali peasant (say) of a particular historical

    period.

    5 For Guhas triptych (worker, peasant, urbanpetty bourgeois) see his opening article in

    Subaltern Studies (Vol. 1). The fifth volume of

    Subaltern Studies adds women to this grouping, and

    another member of the Subaltern Studies collec-

    tive, David Hardiman, has written three articles on

    tribal groups in Gujerat. Interestingly, the dalits

    (or untouchables) have never been designated

    as subalterns by the collective (see Talwalker

    17ff.).

    6 It is possible to view this complexity in ways akin

    to Althussers notion of an overdetermined

    relation between formations, and between forma-

    tions and the points from which subject-positions

    are constituted.

    7 On the contestation of symbols of authority as a

    feature of peasant rebellions in India, see Guha,

    Elementary Aspects of Peasant Insurgency, especially

    the first two chapters.

    8 It is an open question whether or not there has

    to be an irreducible ethnographic component to

    any attempt to study the subaltern. I am inclined

    to think that there has to be some kind of ethno-

    graphic dimension to such an attempt, and this

    because the very identification of the practices of

    the subaltern requires a kind of transcoding of the

    expressivities of the subaltern into the theoretical

    idioms of the individual seeking to formulate a

    theory of the subaltern/subalternity. Even if thereis no such recourse to ethnography, there has to

    be some way that enables the theorist of the

    subaltern or of subalternity to reflect upon these

    expressivities in all their context-bound specificity.

    The subalternist theorist has willy-nilly to

    construct the text of her inquiry, and so she has to

    try and grasp the functions and intent of the subal-

    terns Sprache before these expressivities can be

    transcoded into theoretical discourse. Certain

    forms of historical inquiry can do this job just as

    well as an ethnography, so there is no suggestion

    here that the study of the subaltern or of subal-

    ternity is the prerogative of the ethnographer and

    no one else.

    9 The position outlined here is an amalgam of two

    claims which have to be separated analytically: (i) a

    principio, the expressivities of a culture always

    outstrip the cultural aspirations of description; and

    (ii) given the fact that a subaltern culture invariably

    occupies a position of subordination in relation to

    its dominant counterparts, the expressivities of a

    subaltern culture have a systemic propensity to

    elude the conceptual reach of the subalternisttheorist (in this case someone typically belonging

    to a dominant culture). Almost all versions of

    subalternist theory dealing with the asymmetries

    that exist between subaltern and dominant

    cultures tend to characterize these asymmetries in

    terms of (ii). In the meantime, the intractability

    represented by (i) remains unaddressed. This

    intractability, which is the outcome of a general-

    ized skepticism regarding representational or

    symbolic systems per se, affects all theories ofculture, and ought therefore to be addressed by

    the subalternist theorist.

    My formulations here are indebted to some

    more general theses adumbrated by Bernard

    Williams (The End of Explanation?). My argu-

    ment regarding sense (ii) of the incommensurabil-

    ity between expressivity and description is in line

    with sentiments expressed by Daniel Mato (Not

    Studying the Subaltern). Mato finds problematic

    the notion of studying the other that is integralto many versions of subaltern studies, since this

    way of producing information about the subaltern

    invariably overlooks the privileged situation of the

    one able to generate knowledge that, struc-

    turally, is withheld from those who happen to be

    the powerless and specularized objects of this kind

    of study. Matos is clearly a version of subalternist

    theory in sense (ii) above.

    10 This is also the position taken by Mato in NotStudying the Subaltern and by Gyan Prakash in

    The Impossibility of Subaltern History. Prakash

    claims that many forms of subalternist theory are

    undermined by a paradox: the subaltern is typically

    placed outside prevalent systems of rationality but

    is still deemed to be knowable as the embodi-

    ment of irrationality, and superstition, and so

    5 9

  • 7/29/2019 Surin, subalternity

    14/17

    on in terms of just these forms of rationality. As

    a way of avoiding this paradox, Prakash proposes

    a kind of theoretical askesis in which we under-

    stand subalternity as an abstraction used in order

    to identify the intractability that surfaces inside the

    dominant system it signifies that which the domi-

    nant discourse cannot appropriate completely, an

    otherness that resists containment (288; empha-

    sis in original). The position developed in this

    paper builds on Prakashs counsel of a needed

    self-reflexivity in thinking of the inside of a domi-

    nant system. Another version of this paradox

    afflicting subalternist theory is to be found in

    Dipesh Chakrabartys Postcoloniality and the

    Artifice of History.

    For the self-reflexive turn in cultural anthropol-

    ogy, see James Clifford and George E. MarcussWriting Culture. As a consequence of the self-

    targeted skepticism enjoined by the self-reflexive

    turn, it was no longer possible for the ethnogra-

    pher to say with a straight face what Margaret

    Mead said when she was completing her study of

    the people later to be named the Mountain

    Arapesh: We are just completing the culture of a

    mountain group here in the lower Torres Chelles.

    They have no name and we havent decided what

    to call them yet (Mead, letter of 21 October1932, quoted Clifford, The Predicament of Culture

    230). Of course, this skepticism regarding repre-

    sentational systems or symbolic orders based on

    the positing of a pure and intact speaking I, an I

    (the ethnographer in this case) blessed with the

    capacity to name and designate from a position

    seemingly outside of discourse itself, was a defin-

    ing feature of the work of Barthes, Kristeva, Lacan,

    and others in the 1960s and 1970s.

    11 This understanding of the image and sign is

    derived from Gilles Deleuze. According to

    Deleuze, [t]he image itself is the system of the

    relationship between its elements, that is, a set of

    relationships of time from which the variable

    present only flows. What is specific to the

    image is to make perceptible, to make visible,

    relationships of time which cannot be seen in the

    represented object and do not allow themselves

    to be reduced to the present (Cinema 2 xii). Signsare second-order images that render these

    temporal relations visible in the first-order

    images that embody them (the first-order

    images being constituted intrinsically by the

    modalities of movement and time), through the

    intervention of a third-order image-sign that

    functions as the interpretant between the first-

    and second-order images (30). In other words, a

    sign functions as a packet of knowledge and affect

    regarding its object, but this knowledge and affect

    is released only through the intervention of the

    sign-image that is the interpretant, the latter

    increasing and adding news packets of knowledge

    and affect to the first-order image-sign. Images and

    signs are plastic, changeable assemblages.

    12 I take the concept of prehension from

    Whitehead who, in Process and Reality, uses it to

    denote the registering of sense by the conscious-

    ness in a way that does not involve the operation

    of the cogito.

    13 Using a theoretical apparatus borrowed from

    Deleuzes Logique du sens, I give a more theoreti-

    cal account of the semiotic ensemble that is thesubject below.

    14 The signs that compose an assemblage can be

    assigned to at least three levels or components of

    the assemblage. One set of signs will relate to the

    political subjects agency and practices; another

    will designate the forces, structures, and forma-

    tions in which this agency and these practices are

    exercised; and a third will supply the particular

    context in which forces, structures, and forma-tions are efficacious, and in which the political

    subjects practices are undertaken. Forces, struc-

    tures, and formations (on the one hand) and

    agency and practices (on the other), along with the

    context in which both are manifested, together

    constitute an amalgam that is the social and politi-

    cal process in which social agents are inserted.

    Social agents always stabilize this process and

    reduce its complexity as a condition of their being

    able to act.15 The presence of this structure of exploitation

    is a necessary, but not in itself sufficient, condition

    for the emergence and perpetuation of the condi-

    tion that is subalternity. It should be noted that

    here I depart from the Subaltern Studies move-

    ments stress on the need to keep the history

    of power separate from a universalist history

    of Capital (as provided by most Marxist or

    Marxisant narratives of Capital). For this feature of

    the Subaltern Studies project, see DipeshChakrabarty (Subaltern Studies and Postcolonial

    Historiography 15).

    16 On the need to analyze capitalist formations

    in terms of both the mode of domination and

    the mode of production, see Samir Amin

    (Maldevelopment 2).

    the sovereign individual

    6 0

  • 7/29/2019 Surin, subalternity

    15/17

    surin

    17 On real subsumption, see Negri, The Politics

    of Subversion (17790). On the society of

    control, see Gilles Deleuze, Postscript on

    Control Societies. On biopolitics and biopolit-

    ical production, see Negri and Michael Hardt,

    Empire. The following account of the relation

    between the current regime of capitalist accumu-

    lation and the conditions in which subalternity is

    generated is taken from my own On Producing

    the Concept of a Global Culture.

    18 I owe the example of Brazil to Antonio Negri

    (Interview with Alice Jardine and Brian Massumi

    83). According to Dipesh Chakrabarty, Ranajit

    Guha is to be credited with the realization that

    the global history of capitalism does not have to

    reproduce everywhere the same history ofpower (Subaltern Studies 20). Guhas proposi-

    tion is strongly confirmed by an analysis of the

    current disposition of capitalism, where the global

    history of capitalism does not even ensue in a

    single and homogeneous mode of production, but

    rather has the form of a concatenation of several

    differing modes of production. As a result, there is

    no rigid hierarchy among the modes of produc-

    tion, and certainly no comprehensively prevalent

    capitalist culture.

    19 IBM currently operates in 164 countries.

    On this see

    (accessed on 12 Dec. 2000).

    20 Chakrabarty makes this point well on Guhas

    behalf (Subaltern Studies).

    21 Chakrabarty has made explicit this perceived

    convergence between Subaltern Studies and

    recent work in postcolonial theory (SubalternStudies).

    22 This is of course the problematics that is the

    subject of Gayatri Chakravorty Spivaks important

    Can the Subaltern Speak?

    23 Here I am deeply indebted to the account of

    becoming minoritarian in Deleuze and Guattari

    (A Thousand Plateaus 29193; see also 106). It

    should be stressed that being majoritarian in thissense has nothing necessarily to do with quantities

    or numerical proportions: in relation to the

    analytically or normatively majoritarian, even large

    numbers can be minoritarian (as when white-

    ness is majoritarian even when surrounded by

    numerically overwhelming instantiations of non-

    whiteness).

    24 Deleuze and Guattari put this well:

    Minorities are objectively definable states,

    states of language, ethnicity, or sex with their

    own ghetto territorializations, but they must

    also be thought of as seeds, crystals of

    becoming whose value is to trigger uncon-trollable movements and deterritorializations

    of the mean or majority. There is a univer-

    sal figure of minoritarian consciousness as the

    becoming of everybody, and that becoming is

    creation. One does not attain it by acquiring

    the majority. The figure to which we are

    referring is continuous variation, as an ampli-

    tude that constantly oversteps the represen-

    tative threshold of the majoritarian standard,

    by excess or default. In erecting the figure ofa universal minoritarian consciousness, one

    addresses powers (puissances) of becoming

    that belong to a different realm from that of

    Power (Pouvoir) and Domination. Continuous

    variation constitutes the becoming-minori-

    tarian of everybody, as opposed to the

    becoming-majoritarian Fact of Nobody.

    Becoming-minoritarian as the universal figure

    of consciousness is called autonomy. (A

    Thousand Plateaus 106)

    25 I am referring here to Deleuze and Guattaris

    invocation of Pasolinis work Lexprience hr-

    tique: That is why Pasolini demonstrated that the

    essential thing is to be found in neither language

    A, nor in language B, but in language X, which is

    none other than language A in the actual process

    of becoming language B (A Thousand Plateaus 106).

    Xis neitherA nor B, but rather that which enables

    A and B to become that which they are in theprocess of becoming. This is the kind of move-

    ment captured by Michel Leiris in an exemplary

    moment of theoretical askesis, when he said at

    the end of the 193032 French DakarDjibouti

    expedition that Id rather be possessed than

    study possessed people, have carnal knowledge

    of a zarine rather than scientifically know all

    about her (quoted in Clifford, The Predicament of

    Culture 169; French original in LAfrique fantme

    324).

    26 For Bataille, the socius is constituted by a

    double alogic that includes both the interdiction

    and the accompanying transgressive act. The

    taboo and its violation are alogically consistent or

    compatible, and are required to complete each

    other.

    6 1

  • 7/29/2019 Surin, subalternity

    16/17

    27 Bataille goes on to say: Sometimes the bour-

    geois has resources at his disposal that would

    allow him to enjoy the world in a sovereign

    manner, but then it is in his nature to enjoy them

    in a furtive manner, to which he strives to give the

    appearance of servile utility (198). Several

    sentences in the ensuing paragraphs are taken

    from my own The Sovereign Individual.

    28 In the words of Rosalind OHanlon, a sympa-

    thetic critic of the Subaltern Studies movement:

    It is this central ground, the masses and the

    recovery of their own specific and distinctive

    histories, with all of the legitimating power

    implied in such a concern, which the Subaltern

    contributors claim as the hallmark of theirproject. Their task, and that of all historians

    who write in the same idiom, thus becomes

    one of filling up: of making absences into

    presences, of peopling a vacant space with

    figures dissimilar in their humble and work-

    worn appearance, no doubt, but bearing in

    these very signs of their origin the marks of a

    past and a presence which is their own. (79)

    29 Batailles repudiation of the principle of utility

    demands a corresponding disavowal of exchange

    value and the commodity form (the impossibility

    of this companion disavowal would mean that the

    principle of utility is positively irremovable and

    that sovereignty is not attainable). Bataille does of

    course reject the principle of utility, and while his

    position is strictly utopian, it is nonetheless

    profoundly political, since for him the exercise of

    sovereignty clearly lies not in the eradication of

    the given, but in the struggle against it.

    30 Here I use a number of concepts derived from

    Gilles Deleuze, Logique du sens 292372.

    31 Here I follow Deleuze and Guattari, who distin-

    guish between flight or escape (which does

    not require an act of negation on the part of the

    escapee) and freedom (which requires precisely

    such a negation, but which in the process imposes

    an unequivocal, and thus delimiting horizon that

    of a relation to the master on the escapeesquest for liberty) (Kafka 59).

    32 I refer here to the logic of hyperdifferentia-

    tion identified by Brian Massumi as something

    quite different from the dialectic (A Users Guide to

    Capitalism and Schizophrenia, especially 91 and

    17778n73).

    bibliography

    Amin, Samir.Maldevelopment: Anatomy of a Global

    Failure. Trans. Michael Wolfers. Atlantic Highlands,

    NJ: Zed, 1990.

    Balzer, Marjorie Mandelstam. The Tenacity ofEthnicity: A Siberian Saga in Global Perspective.

    Princeton: Princeton UP, 1999.

    Bataille, Georges. Eroticism: Death and Sensuality.

    Trans. Mary Dalwood. San Francisco: City Lights,

    1986.

    Bataille, Georges. The Accursed Share: An Essay on

    General Economy. Vols. II and III. Trans. Robert

    Hurley. New York: Zone, 1991.

    Bourdieu, Pierre. Outline of a Theory of Practice.

    Trans. Richard Nice. Cambridge: Cambridge UP,

    1977.

    Chakrabarty, Dipesh. Postcoloniality and the

    Artifice of History: Who Speaks for Indian

    Pasts? Representations 37 (1992): 126.

    Chakrabarty, Dipesh. Subaltern Studies and

    Postcolonial Historiography. Nepantla: Views from

    South 1.1 (2000): 932.

    Chaturvedi, Vinayak. Introduction. Mapping

    Subaltern Studies and the Postcolonial. Ed. Vinayak

    Chaturvedi. London: Verso, 2000. viixix.

    Clifford, James. The Predicament of Culture:

    Twentieth-Century Ethnography, Literature, and Art.

    Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP, 1988.

    Clifford, James and George E. Marcus, eds. Writing

    Culture: The Poetics and Politics of Ethnography.

    Berkeley: U of California P, 1986.

    Deleuze, Gilles. Logique du sens. Paris: Minuit,

    1969.

    Deleuze, Gilles. Cinema 2: The Time-Image. Trans.

    Hugh Tomlinson and Robert Galeta. Minneapolis:

    U of Minnesota P, 1989.

    Deleuze, Gilles. Postscript on Control Societies.

    Negotiations, 19721990. Trans. Martin Joughlin.

    New York: Columbia UP, 1995. 17782.

    Deleuze, Gilles and Flix Guattari. Kafka: Towards

    a Minor Literature. Trans. Dana Polan. Minneapolis:

    U of Minnesota P, 1986.

    Deleuze, Gilles and Flix Guattari. A Thousand

    Plateaus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia. Trans. Brian

    Massumi. Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P, 1987.

    the sovereign individual

    6 2

  • 7/29/2019 Surin, subalternity

    17/17

    surin

    Deleuze, Gilles and Flix Guattari. What is

    Philosophy? Trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Graham

    Burchell. New York: Columbia UP, 1994.

    Deleuze, Gilles and Claire Parnet. Dialogues.

    Trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Barbara Habberjam.

    New York: Columbia UP, 1987.

    Guha, Ranajit, ed. Subaltern Studies: Writings on

    South Asian History and Society. Vol. 1. Delhi:

    Oxford UP, 1982.

    Guha, Ranajit. Elementary Aspects of Peasant

    Insurgency in Colonial India. Delhi: Oxford UP, 1983.

    Leiris, Michel. LAfrique fantme. Paris: Gallimard,

    1950.

    Massumi, Brian. A Users Guide to Capitalism and

    Schizophrenia: Deviations from Deleuze and Guattari.

    Cambridge, MA: MIT P, 1992.

    Mato, Daniel. Not Studying the Subaltern but

    Studying with Subaltern Social Groups, or, at

    Least, Studying the Hegemonic Articulations of

    Power. Nepantla: Views from South 1.1 (2000):

    479502.

    Negri, Antonio. Interview with Alice Jardine and

    Brian Massumi. Copyright 1 (1988): 7489.

    Negri, Antonio. The Politics of Subversion: A

    Manifesto for the Twenty-First Century. Trans. James

    Newell. Cambridge: Polity, 1989.

    Negri, Antonio and Michael Hardt. Empire.

    Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP, 2000.

    OHanlon, Rosalind. Recovering the Subject:

    Subaltern Studies and Histories of Resistance in

    Colonial South Asia. Mapping Subaltern Studiesand the Postcolonial. Ed. Vinayak Chaturvedi.

    London: Verso, 2000. 72115.

    Prakash, Gyan. The Impossibility of Subaltern

    History. Nepantla: Views from South 1.1 (2000):

    28794.

    Scott, James C. Weapons of the Weak. New Haven:

    Yale UP, 1985.

    Spivak, Gayatri Chakravorty. Can the SubalternSpeak? Colonial Discourse and Postcolonial Theory: A

    Reader. Ed. Patrick Williams and Laura Chrisman.

    New York: Columbia UP, 1994. 66111.

    Surin, Kenneth. On Producing the Concept of a

    Global Culture. South Atlantic Quarterly94 (1995):

    117999.

    Surin, Kenneth. The Sovereign Individual and

    Michael Taussigs Poetics of Defacement.

    Nepantla: Views from South 2.1 (2001): 20317.

    Talwalker, Clare. Like Chutney for Rice:

    Untouchable Interventions in Indian Modernity.

    PhD diss. Duke U, 2000.

    Taussig, Michael. Shamanism, Colonialism, and the

    Wild Man: A Study in Terror and Healing. Chicago: U

    of Chicago P, 1987.

    Whitehead, Alfred North. Process and Reality: An

    Essay in Cosmology. New York: Macmillan, 1936.

    Williams, Bernard. The End of Explanation? The

    New York Review of Books (19 November 1998):

    4044.

    Kenneth Surin

    Program in Literature

    Box 90670

    Duke University

    Durham

    NC 27708-90670

    USA

    E-mail: [email protected]