ressenya greek tradition in republican thought

Upload: bernat-montoya

Post on 14-Apr-2018

220 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/30/2019 Ressenya Greek Tradition in Republican Thought

    1/3

    The Greek Tradition in Republican Thought by Eric NelsonReview by: Paul A. RaheThe Historical Journal, Vol. 49, No. 2 (Jun., 2006), pp. 635-636Published by: Cambridge University PressStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/4091633 .

    Accessed: 08/08/2013 07:30

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    .JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of

    content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms

    of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    .

    Cambridge University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The

    Historical Journal.

    http://www.jstor.org

    This content downloaded from 193.54.110.35 on Thu, 8 Aug 2013 07:30:05 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=cuphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/4091633?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/4091633?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=cup
  • 7/30/2019 Ressenya Greek Tradition in Republican Thought

    2/3

    TheHistoricalournal, 9, 2 (2006),pp. 635-642 ? 2006 CambridgeUniversityPressPrinted n the United Kingdom

    OTHER REVIEWSTheHistoricalJournal, 9 (2oo6). doi:Io.IoI7/SooI8246Xo6215425,? 2006 CambridgeUniversityPressThe Greek raditionn republicanhought.By Eric Nelson. Cambridge: Cambridge UniversityPress, 2004. Pp. xiii+ 496. ISBN 0-521-83545-3. ?45.oo00.This elegantly written volume originated as a dissertation directed by Quentin Skinner atCambridge University. Along the way, it was read in its entirety byJ. G. A. Pocock, and itappears in the distinguished series 'Ideas in Context' that Skinner edits for the CambridgeUniversity Press. As one would expect, it exemplifies the approach to intellectual historythat Skinner and Pocock champion.When applied to professions, academic disciplines, and self-conscious schools ofthought, which really do generate their own peculiar procedures and vocabularies,linguistic contextualism can be an invaluable tool. There are no doubt other angles fromwhich to analyse the evolution of England's common law, the development of modernsociology, the history of Marxist doctrine, and the thinking of the Cambridge Platonists.But few would deny that, in such cases, attending to the peculiar language deployed and tothe procedures followed is likely to be fruitful.

    Linguistic contextualism is less satisfactory when applied to thinkers of high rank whoacknowledge no superintending authority, for figures such as Plato, Aristotle, Machiavelli,Montaigne, Hobbes, Harrington, Montesquieu, Jefferson, and Heidegger are perfectlycapable of generating their own vocabularies and of establishing their own procedures, andthey frequently appropriate existing vocabularies and procedures and redeploy them inradically novel ways. To locate these thinkers properly, to understand them fully, one musttreat them as if they were systematic thinkers (even when, in their writings, they havedirectly addressed only a circumscribed subject). In the process, one must distinguish intheir thought what is fundamental from what is epiphenomenal, and, while attending to'the alternatives available within the contemporary frameworks of ideas and institutions',one must resist the temptation to force them into a Procrustean bed constituted by that'context'. Before supposing that Aristotle, Machiavelli, Harrington, and Jefferson belongtogether within a hitherto unnoticed 'civic humanist' tradition, for example, one would bewell advised to consider whether they share the same teleology, whether they understandthe ends of government in the same way, whether they are in agreement concerningpolitical psychology, and whether they have the same thing in mind when they speak of'virtue'. Otherwise, one will be inclined repeatedly to lump, where one should split, asJ. G. A. Pocock did in TheMachiavellianmoment.Eric Nelson is no fan of Pocock's argument, but he does imitate the procedures the latterfollowed. Where Pocock treated Aristotle as the progenitor of republicanism, Nelsonsingles out Plato. Where Pocock contended that Machiavelli, Harrington, and Jeffersonwere Aristotle's heirs, Nelson makes Sir Thomas More, Harrington, his Whig admirers,Montesquieu, his heirs, and the American founding fathers Plato's disciples. Had he beencontent to follow the method prescribed by Arthur Lovejoy and to trace a 'unit idea' fromone author to another, attending closely to the differing ways in which the various authors

    635

    This content downloaded from 193.54.110.35 on Thu, 8 Aug 2013 07:30:05 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/30/2019 Ressenya Greek Tradition in Republican Thought

    3/3

    636 HISTORICAL JOURNALintegrated the notion within their quite different systems of thought, this would have beena highly valuable book - for Nelson has rightly identified as a trope the notion thatrepublican government presupposes on the part of the citizens a modicum of equality and,therefore, limits on the concentration of property, and he does a fine job of showing thatthe authors he discusses deployed this 'unit idea'. In asserting that these thinkers constitutea 'tradition' and that they share 'an orientation on questions relating to justice' and 'thegood life' as well as 'property' (p. 17),however, he goes astray - for this forces him to doconsiderable violence to the figures he treats. In consequence, at times, this book readsmore like a lawyer's brief than a scholarly exploration.More is, to be sure, an example that belies my claim. He really was a Platonist, and it isappropriate to read Utopiaas a self-conscious restatement of some of the principal themesannounced in TheRepublic.But Harrington's Oceanas another matter. Its author boasts thathe is a disciple of Machiavelli, and in the crucial sphere of political psychology he an-nounces his adherence to Thomas Hobbes - whom he judges in most things, apart from hismonarchist bias, 'the best writer, at this day, in the world'. That Harrington lifts Oceana'sproperty legislation from Plato's Laws is an indication of debt in this particular and nothingmore. His treatment of the ends of government, his account of human psychology, theprinciples underpinning his constitutionalism - these he shares with Machiavelli, Bacon,and Hobbes, and not with Plato. He reiterates Machiavelli's contention that 'it is thedutyofaLegislator topresume ll men tobe wicked'.He quotes with approval Hobbes's dictum that 'asoftenas reason s againsta man,sooftenwill a manbeagainstreason'.He concedes that, in practice,' reason s nothing but interest';and he concludes that 'there be divers interests, nd so diversreasons'.These claims are not consistent with the argument presented in Plato's Republic.Nelson's treatment of Montesquieu is an even more obvious case of special pleading.That Montesquieu relied heavily on Plato for his depiction of the republics of ancientGreece there can be no doubt. But there is little reason to suppose that he derived his firstprinciples from the Greek. Montesquieu listed Plato among the 'great poets', not amongthe philosophers. He described him as a legislator who gave way to his 'passions andprejudices', while priding himself on having drawn his own 'principles' not from his'prejudices but from the nature of things'.Of course, Montesquieu really was interested in the phenomenon of ancient virtue, andin this regard he did remark that 'the less we can satisfy our particular passions, the morewe give ourselves up to passions for the general order' (p. 167). But, in citing this passage,Nelson fails to reflect on what it means to be in the grips of passion and to consider just howalien this is to the account given of moral virtue by Aristotle, Cicero, Aquinas, and the like,and he neglects the observation's immediate sequel:Why aremonks so fond of theirorder? Preciselybecauseof thosethingswhich makeit insupportable.Their rule deprivesthem of all the thingson which the ordinarypassionsrest: there remains,then,only that passionfor the rule which torments them. The more austerethe rule, that is, the more itcurbs theirinclinations, he more force it givesto the one inclinationwhich it leavesthem with.No one who pauses to digest this passage can think Montesquieu an unmitigated admirerof the virtue he attributes to the ancient Greek republics. It is no wonder that he laterdenies that such republics are 'in their nature free states' and that he insists that virtue canitself give rise to the 'abuse of power'. Neither of Nelson's two claims - that 'Montesquieugives us substantial grounds for believing that only republics will maximize human virtueand create a morally 'natural' life for human beings' (p. 166), and that for Montesquieu'"political virtue " is the root of free government' (p. 169) - can be sustained.UNIVERSITY OF TULSA PAUL A. RAHE

    This content downloaded from 193.54.110.35 on Thu, 8 Aug 2013 07:30:05 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp