practical film theory

Upload: alexander-valsamis

Post on 06-Apr-2018

216 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/3/2019 Practical Film Theory

    1/18

    1

    THERE IS NOTHING MORE PRACTICAL THAN A GOOD FILM

    THEORY

    By Henry BreitroseDepartment of Communication

    Stanford University

    USEFULL THEORIES FOR TEACHING DOCUMENTARY FILMMAKERS

    Im interested in useful theories for teaching the practice of

    documentary film making. Perhaps the most important word in that

    first sentence is useful because the arts and humanities in general,

    film in particular, and documentary film specifically, have not been

    deprived of theory. While film theory has provided considerable

    academic employment for humanists, which on the whole I take to be

    a social good, I believe that production students have been grievously

    misled by theories that are not only useless, for practical purposes,

    but frequently toxic to their ability to clearly see. The social

    psychologist Kurt Lewin said that there is nothing so challenging as a

    practical problem. He also said that there is nothing so practical as a

    good theory. While there is a plethora of theories about theory, we

    lack helpful theories about practical problems.

    In teaching documentary film and video making in a professional

    graduate program, I meet superbly well-qualified students who have

    been educated at some of the best universities in the world. While

    we insist that our students are well-educated and have some

    experience, we dont insist on an undergraduate film or media-

    studies degree. On the contrary, we are deeply suspicious of

    applicants who have studied film as undergraduates, because too

    1

  • 8/3/2019 Practical Film Theory

    2/18

    2

    frequently there is a need to de-toxify their imagination. They can

    tell us all about the gaze and the gays, and invoke Gledhill,

    Foucault, DeMan, Derrida, Deleuze, and proclaim that the very act of

    photographing an other is a statement of political oppression or

    that the very act of photographing an other is intrinsically

    transgressive, and thus an act of courage, or that the very act of

    photographing an other pushes the envelope too far because it is

    intrusive, or not far enough because it is not overtly reflexive, or

    that it invades personal space, or that it deconstructs the myth of

    autonomy, or that it constitutes symbolic assault.

    None of this strikes me as particularly useful in getting ideas on thescreen with clarity, precision, and economy, which, perhaps

    somewhat naively, I take to be the basic requirements of

    documentary, much as George Orwell took them to be the essential

    elements of the non-fiction essay.

    How could this have happened? In America, I think that this is the

    result of the rise of Cinema Studies as a distinct discipline,

    different from its antecedent, the plain-vanilla, slightly outlaw, and

    not quite academically respectable Film, which, compared with Art

    and Drama was the new kid on the creative arts block. It was

    signaled by the invention of the Society of Cinematologists, latterly

    known as the Society for Cinema Studies, whose founding actually

    preceded what a colleague refers The French Disease, the

    importation of the trendy, the transient, and the poorly translated

    latest news from the deep thinkers of the rive gauche.. I was present

    at the birth of the SCS, at the Museum of Modern Art in New York

    sometime around 1960, when Robert Gessner, who taught film at

    NYU, made the case that in order for film to be accepted as

    legitimate in academia, it must establish its scholarly credentials by

    forming a professional society that looked just like the older ones.

    Thus the origins of the great Anglo-Saxon schism, because being

    academically traditional meant that the new organization would not

    2

  • 8/3/2019 Practical Film Theory

    3/18

    3

    deal with the actual making of film, as did the existing University

    Film Association, many of whose members actually made films, but

    rather that it be about film. (It reminds me of the line in Beyond The

    Fringe, a popular English comedy review of the 1960s that spawned

    Dudley Moore, Peter Cook, Jonathan Miller, and Alan Bennett. Miller

    asks Bennett Do you know algebra? Bennett replies Certainly not,

    but I know about algebra. That Professor Gessner proposed that the

    constitution of the new group be modeled on that of the American

    Metaphysical Society was neither a shock nor a surprise. That the

    delegates from USC, who actually taught students how to make films,

    fled the meeting in horror was no surprise either.)

    But surely, the Theory and Practice dichotomy wasnt invented by

    Professor Gessner, nor was it uniquely about film. It was about ways

    of thinking about the world.

    In her paper Theory and Praxis in Aristotle and Heideggeri, Catriona

    Hanley notes that for Aristotle, Theora meant the activity of

    contemplation of necessary objects. Actual production, the making

    of things, consisted of praxis and posis, and unlike Theoria, which

    required only the necessary object for contemplation, it required

    knowledge of contingent objects, those objects and events

    necessary and sufficient for the existence of the object of

    contemplation. In film language, rawstock, laboratories, cameras,

    lenses, are examples of the stuff on which the film, the object of

    contemplation, is contingent. Theoria need deal with only the

    finished film, the necessary object of contemplation, stripped of

    praxis and posis.

    Posis aims at a goal, as distinct from the process of achieving the

    goal. It is the intention, the target audience, the purpose of the

    proposed film, while praxis is the process of attaining the goal. For

    Aristotle, theoria, the contemplation of the necessary object, and

    the posis and praxis which enabled its production, were two sides

    of the same drachma.

    3

  • 8/3/2019 Practical Film Theory

    4/18

    4

    For many of our students, very phrase theory and practice is

    associated with Karl Marx. Istvn Mszros gives us an interesting

    interpretation of this distinction in his discussion of Marxs Theory ofAlienation in the Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844.

    Marx, ever the dialectician, needed two categories for a proper

    dialectic (it wont work with three) so he combined Poeisis with

    Praxis as the action components, and he put them in opposition to

    Theoria, or as he put it in German, Theorie.

    Mszros tells us that Marx was greatly concerned about the

    separation of theorie and praxis in philosophy. Theorie, Marx

    argued, had somehow become divorced from practice, and functions

    as a domain unto itself, proclaiming independent and universal

    powers. He describes Marxs critique of theorie without praxis:

    Thus instead of being a universal dimension of

    all activity, integrated in practice and in its

    various reflections, it functions as an independent(verselbstndigt) alienated universality,

    displaying the absurdity of this whole system of

    alienations by the fact that this fictitious

    universality is realised as the most esoteric of

    all esoteric specialities, strictly reserved for the

    alienated high priests (the Eingeweihten) of

    this intellectual trade.

    the abstractly contemplative character of

    philosophy expresses the radical divorce of theory

    and practice in its alienated universality. ii

    Examining Marxs 1844 ideas reminds us of how prescient the great

    man was about certain aspects of the world to come, even if his theories

    4

  • 8/3/2019 Practical Film Theory

    5/18

    5

    about political and economic organization didn't work out very well in

    praxis. In 1844 Marx anticipated the contemporary academic theory

    industry, in which alienated high priests of the intellectual trade would

    make assertions of the universality of their theories, independent from

    practice. Those of us who have seen semiotics, structuralism, critical

    theory, deconstruction, post-modernism, and other esoteric specialities

    claim universality, and then fall out of fashion, will be tempted to a nod or

    perhaps even a smile of recognition. The problem is not that these werent

    good ideas, as much as it was that they became orthodoxies that

    pronounced Fatwa and declared intellectual Jihad on other theories.

    There are theories about why the very idea of documentary isimpossible, why objectivity is impossible, why Photoshop has made

    documentary untenable, why everything pretending to be factual or

    fictional is but a discourse and all discourses are equally privileged, why all

    discourses are fictions, and all reality is social construction. These are not

    useful theories. Indeed, they are profoundly unhelpful. They dont do a very

    good job of helping the film maker think deeply about what he or she is

    doing, which I take to be one of the more valuable aspects of theoreticalwork in other disciplines. Most film theories are not particularly useful as

    predictors, nor do they spawn useful ways for documentary film makers to

    make sense of the world. In my view, making sense of the world is what

    were really about when we teach documentary film making.

    Let me put aside the very useful physical theories of photography,

    optics and acoustics with which all film makers should be acquainted, and

    let us agree that the film theories of Kuleshov, Eisenstein, Pudokvin, even

    Dziga Vertov and Mitry, all informed by practice, can be useful to all film

    students. As a teacher, Im interested in theory that gives the young

    documentary-maker some confidence in the non-fiction enterprise, and

    theory that helps him or her craft a work that is honest and that succeeds in

    engaging the audience, and presenting the the really true story in ways that

    are clear, instructive, and edifying. I like the word edifying because of

    its precise derivation, from Late Latin aedificare, to instruct or improve

    5

  • 8/3/2019 Practical Film Theory

    6/18

    6

    spiritually. I think that understanding a complex aspect of the real world is

    literally edifying. An elegantly crafted work that helps us make sense of an

    aspect of our world gives us pleasure and lifts the spirit.

    In useful modern theory, I think that the Cognitive Theorists whowork mainly in psychology have a great deal to say about how we make

    sense of the world. Torben Grodal notes that while romantic and

    psychoanalytic theories of film, mainly imported from the academic study of

    literature, plumb the unconscious for the true context, cognitive

    psychology provides rather more satisfying results. iii The cognitivists tell us

    that by virtue of evolution and physiology, humans have developed certain

    ways of dealing with information. Some aspects of the world are moresalient to us than are others, and emotions have developed to represent our

    strongest interests and goals. Simply stated, we feel strongly about those

    things we are interested in: a romantic partner, the World Cup, social

    justice, protection of the environment, globalization, religion, for example.

    Our emotions are strong motivating forces that control our attention and

    action. Our cognitive skills enable us to analyze situations that are

    interesting to us, in ways that help us achieve our goals. Thus, depending onthe subject and the audience, we can expect that documentaries will be

    attended to in very different ways, and we can use theory to think about

    how the structure of the documentary ought to mediate between the

    content and the presumed audience.

    These analytic aspects of our cognitive skills are of great interest,

    because we share a strong tendency to analyze by inventing narrative in

    order to make sense of things that might otherwise be random objects and

    events. Dorrit Cohn gives us a useful definition of narrative as a series of

    statements that deal with a causally related sequence of events that

    concern human (or human-like) beings.iv David Bordwell and Kristin

    Thompson point out that audience postulate causal connections between

    the most disparate images, and even random montage attains narrative

    status. vAll useful theoretical perspectives.

    6

  • 8/3/2019 Practical Film Theory

    7/18

    7

    From the intensely practical outlook of documentary production,

    much of this translates to the observation that people tend to structure

    objects and events as narrative, composed of chains of cause-effect, in

    chronological time

    . The narratives are ways of analyzing persons, objects and events

    that are of interest, in ways that are consistent with furthering the

    achievement of their goals. (We meet posis in the strangest places. Here,

    it arises among the cognitive theorists. )

    Since cognitivists demonstrate that no matter what, narrative

    happens, then a useful theory would be one that helps our students

    understand narrative structure. There are several. Some prefer Bakhtin,

    others Propp, but my nominations for very useful theories are Aristotles

    Poetics, and Kenneth Burkes Grammar of Motives as a reasonable neo-

    Aristotelian alternative. Aristotle, in his Poetics, tells us about how to tell

    stories, and alerts us to the structural elements of exposition, complication,

    conflict, climax, and resolution. In short, he describes the narrative arc, or

    in documentary terms, a through-line.

    Burke elaborates this scheme and re-frames it. In his pentad of terms he

    tells us about structure and about the necessary elements of a narrative arc

    when we try to explain why something happened.

    We shall use five terms as generating principle of our

    investigation. They are: Act, Scene, Agent, Agency, Purpose. In

    a rounded statement about motives, you must have some word

    that names the act (names what took place, in thought or

    deed), and another that names the scene (the background of

    the act, the situation in which it occurred); also, you must

    indicate what person or kind of person (agent) performed the

    act, what means or instruments he used (agency), and the

    purpose. Men may violently disagree about the purposes

    behind a given act, or about the character of the person who

    did it, or how he did it, or in what kind of situation he acted;

    7

  • 8/3/2019 Practical Film Theory

    8/18

    8

    or they may even insist upon totally different words to name

    the act itself. But be that as it may, any complete statement

    about motives will offer some kind of answers to these five

    questions: what was done (act), when or where it was done

    (scene), who did it (agent), how he did it (agency), and why

    (purpose)' vi

    Aristotle and Burke, among others, are helpful with story telling, but

    if a documentary is, as I contend, a really true story, how do we help our

    students understand the idea of really true.

    Epistemology, together with aesthetics and ethics, is the tripod on

    which classical philosophy rests. It is a recurring concern in the discussion of

    documentary, and to borrow a phrase from Bordwell, et al, these days

    pretty well post-theory in that it is a discipline suspicious of sweeping

    claims of universality, and relies on logic and rationality.viiThe most useful

    contemporary theory is Critical Realism. Two important proponents are John

    Searle, who is a logician and linguistic philosopher, and Nol Carroll, who isan aesthetician and film scholar and whose home, unlike most writers on

    the aesthetics of film, is in an actual department of philosophy. They both

    deal with critical realism.

    In an article entitled "Literary Theory and its Discontents," John

    Searleviii argues that there are three different theoretical approaches to

    questions concerning the meaning of texts. Here, Searle appears to refer

    specifically to literary texts and literary theory, but to separate his

    argument from film is to create a distinction without making a difference.

    The three approaches are those of Stanley Fish, who believes that

    meaning resides solely in the response of the reader; Stephen Knapp and

    Walter Michaels, who assert that that meaning is entirely a matter of the

    authors intention; and Jacques Derrida, whose position seems to be that

    that meanings are undecidable and have relative indeterminacy'or

    not. Searle illustrates by quoting Derridas statement that , there is

    8

  • 8/3/2019 Practical Film Theory

    9/18

    9

    rather the free play of signifiers and the grafting of texts onto texts within

    the textuality and intertextuality of the text. ix

    Ironically, Derridarians and other post-modernists are very concerned

    about clearly drawn categorical distinctions, such as the distinction betweenfiction and fact. This may well be the residue of the French encyclopedistes,

    who specialized in the manufacture of exquisite intellectual pigeon holes

    and clearly mutually exclusive categories.

    Curiously, Critical Realism, which derives from the rigorous British

    tradition of analytic philosophy (Searle was a student of Ludwig

    Wittgensteins student, Peter Strawson, at Oxford) is comfortable with the

    absence of precisely drawn boundaries, and accepts that philosophical

    distinctions inevitably have imprecise edges that allow for rough more or

    less kinds of distinctions. That is to say, while there may be certain

    similarities between two objects and events, we recognize that they are

    more-or-less different from one another.

    The relevance for the documentary maker is that the categorical

    distinction between fictional and factual, or literal and metaphorical, oreven true and false are valid even if they are not sharply exclusive. In my

    view, thats why Chris Marker and Robert Flaherty and Frederic Wiseman,

    and Dziga Vertov and Michael Apted all are appropriately described as

    documentary film makers. In a nutshell, something may be different from

    something else even if it is more or less different, and not absolutely

    different. Even a rough distinction is a difference, if there is general

    acceptance. Derrida and the Derridarians dont agree, and his that unlessthere is a sharply drawn dichotomous distinction, there is no difference at

    all.

    In the introduction to his anthology Theorizing Documentary, a

    deceptive title for an un-useful book, Michael Renov essentially

    attacks the fundamental and underlying premise of documentary,

    which is that there is a difference between fact and fiction.x He

    basis this on the claim that all discursive forms use similar methods

    9

  • 8/3/2019 Practical Film Theory

    10/18

    10

    and rhetorical figures. He quotes Hayden White, who argues that

    there are no objects, only social constructions, that all discourse

    constitutes the objects which it pretends only to describe realistically

    and to analyze objectively.xiRenov argues that the techniques used

    in fiction films, like cross-cutting and flashbacks are used in films

    that represent themselves as nonfiction, and that techniques

    associated with non-fiction films, such as handheld camera are used

    in fiction films.

    Nol Carroll points out that the distinction between fiction and

    nonfiction is not one of formal technique, and the extent to which

    one uses formal methods associated with the other is of no particularrelevance.

    Carroll argues that audiences generally are able to determine

    whether a film is fiction or nonfiction by virtue of the film coming to the

    audience with its factual or fictional status inherently visible. As he and

    Carl Plantinga put it, it arrives indexed. Audiences are generally pretty

    smart about distinguishing between fictional and non-fictional films, and

    film makers who index fiction as non-fiction inevitably reveal the fictional

    nature as part of the plot structure of the film, usually through some absurd

    assertion. One need only think of Zelig or This is Spinal Tap to get this idea.

    Searle, a philosopher, clarifies the situation of the documentary film

    maker, who by the very act of making a film imposes a narrative structure

    on a set of sounds and images. In the same manner as Renov, one might

    argue, and many do, that the use of narrative is what fiction film makers

    do, and therefore there is no fundamental categorical distinction between

    fiction and so-called factual or non-fiction or documentary film makers. But,

    even roughly speaking, there is an immense difference, a veritable chasm,

    between drawing sounds and images from the imagination and using the

    artistic imagination to make sense of the sounds and images that one finds

    in the real world.

    10

  • 8/3/2019 Practical Film Theory

    11/18

    11

    Brian Winston recognized that even so obviously reconstructed a film

    as Humphrey Jennings Fires Were Started was properly a documentaryxii.

    Winston drastically revised his previous position,xiii in which he seemed to

    negate the very possibility of documentary. Writing about Griersons

    famously elusive definition of documentary, the creative treatment of

    actuality, Winston wrote Surely, no actuality (that is, evidence and

    witness) can remain after all this brilliant interventionist creative

    treatment (that is, artistic and dramatic structuring) has gone on.

    Griersons enterprise was too self-contradictory to sustain any claims on the

    real, and renders the term documentary meaningless.

    While the truth claims of Fires Were Started differ radically from the

    observational fly-on-the-wall or reflexive fly-in-the-soup direct cinema

    paradigms, it is certainly is a documentary. As Grierson rather modestly put

    it in the original coinage, when describing Robert Flahertys Moana, it has

    a certain documentary quality. The documentary quality, I believe, derives

    from the correspondence between the subject matter on the screen and

    what we know of the world, but even more importantly, from the ways in

    which Jennings organized images and sounds drawn from the real world to

    create a credible model of the world on the screen.

    Searles theoretical ideas are useful in several other ways. Ever since Jean

    Rouch brought his clair camera and Perfectone tape recorder to Ghana and

    made Le Maitre Fou, observational film makers have avoided expending very

    much energy to helping their audiences understand what they were seeing

    on the screen. The usual explanation often invoked purity, or

    objectivity, or protecting against bias, and many audiences were

    suitably confounded.

    Implicit interpretation, by means of the selection of subject, structure,

    frame, usable takes, sounds, and the other means of film making was

    accepted as pure, or ethically superior to overt explanation narration,

    because words somehow interfered with the proper allegedly unbiased

    11

  • 8/3/2019 Practical Film Theory

    12/18

    12

    apprehension of the film. The standard Frederick Wiseman-model

    documentary makers response to a puzzled audiences was that the film

    speaks for itself.

    Searle helpfully points out that meanings, concepts, and

    intentionality by themselves are never sufficient to determine the full

    import of what is said or thought because they only function within a

    Network of other intentionality and against a Background of capacities that

    are not and could not be included in literal meaning, concepts, or

    intentional states.xiv In other words, the meaning of a communication, a

    shot, a sequence, a film, relies on the understanding of a rich bed of

    contexts in which the communication itself resides.

    The student documentary maker would be well advised to consider

    his or her intentions and the intentional systems of the audience, as well as

    the background of knowledge and abilities that the audience brings to the

    screen. In plain language, it is useful for the student to deeply consider his

    intentions and goals in the film (poesis, yet again) and give thought to the

    predispositions, and the degree of knowledge and concern that both film

    maker and audience bring to the documentary transaction. It is useful for

    the audience to understand whats on the screen, and for the film maker to

    understand that if the audience doesnt get it then it is a film makers

    problem and not the problem of the audience.

    In his book The Construction of Social Reality, xv Searle addresses the issue

    of socially constructed reality. The title of his book is a sly word-play, by re-

    ordering social construction to read construction of social " much the

    same way as Marx re-ordered the title of Proudhons book Philosophy of

    Poverty to entitle his book The Poverty of Philosophy. Like Marxs

    response to Proudhon, it Searle gives a critique of the view that reality is a

    social construct and exists only as it is subjectively perceived. For Prudhon,

    poverty was a social construct. For Marx is was an objective fact. The

    recognition of objective facts, people, objects and events that exist in the

    12

  • 8/3/2019 Practical Film Theory

    13/18

    13

    world whether or not we see them, is a most useful conjoining of theory and

    practice for documentary film makers, The confounding of subjective

    perception with what Noel Carroll, describes as post-modern skepticism

    about whether the world exists apart from ourselves is endemic among

    students, especially non-scientists, but for the documentary student, the

    existence of an objective world is a fundamental concern, because it lies

    directly on the cleavage plane between objective fact and subjectively

    imagined fiction.

    Searle helps students understand that there is indeed a real world out

    there, that it is comprised of facts, and that the facts are of two types:

    some facts are "brute facts" that they exist independently of what humans

    think, and others are social facts, which depend for their existence on

    human thought. The first sort are mental facts, such as that one is in pain,

    and the physical facts that Mount Everest has snow and ice at its summit,

    and hydrogen atoms have one electron.xvi

    Examples of social facts, are that this piece of paper is a five dollar bill,

    that he is a citizen of the U. S., and that the New York Giants won the 1991

    Superbowl. Social facts exist as a layer superimposed on physical facts.

    Thus, the physical fact of particular ink inscribed on specific paper in a

    unique way is a physical fact. The social fact is that its a dollar bill, is

    incontestably objective, too. If the ink and the paper and the inscription are

    not correct, then we may argue about whether or not it is counterfeit, but

    this can be objectively determined.

    As a logician and a philosopher of language, Searle observes that At least

    one of the functions of language is to communicate meanings from speakers

    to hearers, and sometimes those meanings enable the communication to

    refer to objects and states of affairs in the world that exist independently

    of language.xvii Although film and video are not precisely languages, but are

    language-like, the formulation still makes sense for documentary. We make

    documentaries to communicate meanings from film makers to audience

    13

  • 8/3/2019 Practical Film Theory

    14/18

    14

    members, and sometimes those meanings enable the documentary to refer

    to objects and states of the world that exist independently of language. The

    process of acquiring and displaying images enables us to replace the verbal

    description of objects and states of affairs in the real world with more

    direct and less abstracted representations than words. The goal, not always

    realized, is for the film maker and the audience member to share the same

    thought about a reality independent of either.

    What, then, is a useful way of helping students struggle with the idea of

    truth in documentary? The correspondence theory in epistemology, which is

    a pretty useful theory, states that truth is whether the things in the world

    really are the way we say they are. In philosophical language, a statement is

    true if and only if the statement corresponds with the facts. One of the

    functions of language, and I would argue one of the functions of

    documentary, is to truthfully represent how things are in the world by

    ensuring that statements correspond to facts.

    Nol Carrol asks whether the non-fiction film delivers truth? Does it

    or can it represent the world in objective ways? The argument goes like this:

    After all, the acts of framing and editorial choice are acts of selection, and

    selectivity is necessarily biased. The problem is built into the very apparatus

    of cinema. Since cinema is, by its very nature, selective, it is by its very

    nature biased, and incapable of objectivity.xviiiBut is there something in the

    preceding argument that makes nonfiction film any more incapable of

    objectivity than, say, a sociological treatise? Does selectivity guarantee

    bias? If thats the case, we may as well abandon the documentary

    enterprise, and sociology, and science, all of which are based on the twin

    ideas of selectivity and objectivity.

    Carroll argues that selectivity isnt particularly unique to film. Every

    mode of inquiry is selective, whether it be physics or history or journalism.

    But if we dont consider that the selectively accumulated facts of history or

    physics or economics or chemistry are exiled from objectivity in

    14

  • 8/3/2019 Practical Film Theory

    15/18

    15

    Carrolls words, why should we assume that nonfiction films can never, a

    priori, be objective?

    The Nia, Pinta, and Santa Maria, the boiling point of water at sea

    level, the value of the Euro in U.S. dollars, sodium chloride are selectedfacts, but objective facts nevertheless. Searle suggests that if you dont

    accept this, take your car to the post-modernist garage and listen to the

    post-modernist theorist tell you that theres nothing wrong with your

    carburetor, because after all, the carburetor is a selective social

    construction.

    Does selectivity necessarily entail bias? Carroll points out that

    selectivity certainly invites bias, but it does not guarantee bias. Neither

    does the non-fiction nature of documentary guarantee objectivity, but it

    certainly allows it.

    Protection against bias. and need to ensure of the objectivity of any

    statement is not unique to film. All manner of discourses have protocols

    that work to diminish the opportunity for bias. Do they work all the time?

    Certainly not, but they work much, perhaps most, of the time. For thestudent, I would argue the most important protocol, the most important

    protection against bias and assurance of truth, is self-awareness. Being

    aware of what one is doing is a powerful way of encouraging self-regulation.

    In documentary, the normative assumption is that the film maker tells the

    truth, and bias or untruth is open to determination by colleagues and critics

    in the public forum. After all, documentary film is not a private art.

    As an example of how this works, consider the case of Michael

    Moore and his film about the ethical failings of General Motors, Roger

    and Me. To a great extent, the film, like many films, bases its

    argument and analysis on causal connections and chronological

    narrative. The argument is roughly that General Motors did something

    in its self-interest, which caused bad things to happen to its workers.

    In this more of argument, when the historical facts and causal

    connections are distorted because of bias, the film maker is put in

    15

  • 8/3/2019 Practical Film Theory

    16/18

    16

    the uncomfortable position of defending a falsified argument, usually

    on grounds that some higher truth justifies playing fast and loose

    with facts and chronology. The film critic Pauline Kaels criticized

    Roger and Me because events were presented out of chronological

    order and the implied chain of causation was incorrect. A newspaper

    reporter described Moores reaction as follows: Moore has heard

    this criticism a lot lately. Yes, events are presented out of order in

    his film, he says. ``So what? I'm tired of it. It avoids talking about the

    politics of the story. Your story is not gonna be in the sequential

    order you reported it in. So what's the accusation, that I'm a

    journalist?xix

    Essentially Moore is saying that the altering of chronology to

    make causal connections for his noble purposes is well within the

    canons of journalism, what one might describe as the history will

    absolve me defense. Journalists frequently lose their jobs for that

    sort of logic. Thus, the protocol of film criticism serves to guard

    against bias.

    But what is allowable? How much may the documentarian

    creatively treat actuality? In my view, the appropriate standards of

    objectivity depend on the context. Take, for example, the films of

    the Canadian/Australian film maker Michael Rubbo. My favorite is

    probably Daisy, which uses the objective events of Daisy de

    Bellefeuilles, face-lift as an armature around which to construct a

    meditation on the idea of physical beauty.

    Daisy is a colleague of Rubbos at the National Film Board of

    Canada.. Rubbo uses the tropes of observational documentary to

    record the objective reality of Daisys facelift, but as he does in

    many of his films, he introduces a deeply reflexive accompanying

    through-line, which is his clearly personal, biased and somewhat

    idiosyncratic meditation on the idea of beauty. Does the bias matter?

    Hardly, because in the context of the film, he presents what Searle

    would recognize as objects and states of the world that exist

    16

  • 8/3/2019 Practical Film Theory

    17/18

    17

    independently of language, and one side of a conversation into which

    the audience member is invited to participate, on the meaning of the

    face lift as a social fact.

    There are other useful theories for documentary practice, butlittle time in which to discuss them in detail. I think that cognitive

    theory is rich mine of ideas, especially as documentary intersects

    with digital technologies and non-linear modes of presentation.

    Knowing how human beings organize their perceptual and conceptual

    worlds cannot but be useful.

    In my own thinking, Ive been influenced by two books, that

    are actually and specifically about documentary film, each deeply

    influenced by Critical Realism, and intelligently in tune with the

    interests and concerns of documentary film makers. Carl Plantingas

    Rhetoric and Representation in Non-Fiction Filmxxand the somewhat

    less well known What is Non-Fiction Cinema?xxiby Trevor Ponech, are

    chock full of interesting and challenging ideas for students of

    documentary production, and I recommend them with enthusiasm, as

    ways to help our students learn how to tell really true stories.

    iPresented at the Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy, in Boston, Massachusetts from

    August 10-15, 1998. Available on-line at http://www.bu.edu/wcp/Papers/Acti/ActiHanl.htmiiIstvn Mszros, Marxs Theory of Alienation, New York:1972, Harper Torchbooks, p. 103

    iiiTorben Grodal. Emotions, Cognitions and Narrative Patterns in Film in Carl Plantinga and

    Greg M. Smith, Passionate Views, Baltimore and London: 1998, Johns Hopkins UniversityPress, p. 127iv

    Dorrit Cohn , The Distinction of Fiction, Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1999, p.12v

    David Bordwell and Kristin Thompson, Film As Art, 3rd

    . ed. New York: McGraw Hill, 1990. p.

    55viBurke, Kenneth.. A Grammar of Motives. Berkeley: Univ. of California 1945p.XV

    viiDavid Bordwell and Nol Carroll (eds), Post-theory : Reconstructing Film Studies, Madison,

    University of Wisconsin Press, 1996.viii

    John R. Searle, Literary Theory and its Discontents, New Literary History, 1994, 25:637667ix

    Searle, (1994) p. 7x

    Michael Renov, Introduction: The Truth About Non-Fiction in Theorizing Documentary,(ed.) Michael Renov. NY:Routledge, 1993, p. 3xi

    ibid. p.7xii

    Brian Winston, Fires Were Started, London: British Film Institute, 1999. 79p.xiii

    Brian Winston, Claiming the Real, London : British Film Institute, 1995.xiv

    Searle (1994) p. 6xv John R. Searle, The Construction of Social Reality, New York: Free Press, 1995xvi

    Searle, 1995, p.35

    17

    http://www.bu.edu/wcp/Papers/Acti/ActiHanl.htmhttp://jenson.stanford.edu:9081/pls/sirwebdad/su_in_get?key_action=fsearch&inrowid=19578&sid=4087&pgcnt=2&lnum=1&authid=http://jenson.stanford.edu:9081/pls/sirwebdad/su_in_get?key_action=fsearch&inrowid=19578&sid=4087&pgcnt=2&lnum=1&authid=http://jenson.stanford.edu:9081/pls/sirwebdad/su_in_get?key_action=fsearch&inrowid=19578&sid=4087&pgcnt=2&lnum=1&authid=http://jenson.stanford.edu:9081/pls/sirwebdad/su_in_get?key_action=fsearch&inrowid=19578&sid=4087&pgcnt=2&lnum=1&authid=http://jenson.stanford.edu:9081/pls/sirwebdad/su_in_get?key_action=fsearch&inrowid=19578&sid=4087&pgcnt=2&lnum=1&authid=http://jenson.stanford.edu:9081/pls/sirwebdad/su_in_get?key_action=fsearch&inrowid=19578&sid=4087&pgcnt=2&lnum=1&authid=http://www.bu.edu/wcp/Papers/Acti/ActiHanl.htm
  • 8/3/2019 Practical Film Theory

    18/18

    18

    xvii

    John R. Searle. Rationality and Realism, What is at Stake Daedalus, Fall, 1993, p. 61xviii

    Nol Carrol, Nonfiction Film and Postmodernist Skepticism, in David Bordwell and NoelCarroll (eds.) Post-theory : Reconstructing Film Studies, Madison : University of WisconsinPress, 1996, p.283xix

    Sheryl James, A hometown film maker's drama in Wheel Life // Film drives home a point

    about GM and the fall of Flint, Mich., St. Petersburg Times; St. Petersburg; Jan 21, 1990;xxCarl R. Plantinga, Rhetoric and Representation in Non-Fiction Film, Cambridge ; New York

    : Cambridge University Press, 1997.xxi

    Trevor Ponech, What is Non-Fiction Cinema On the Very Idea of Motion PictureCommunication, Boulder, Colorado, Westview Press, 1999.

    18