nicolaus tideman: resolving the apparent conflict between land as our common heritage and land as...

18
Resolving the Apparent Conflict between Land as Our Common Heritage and Land as Private Property Nicolaus Tideman For the conference: “Economics for Conscious Evolution” We understand, and we seek to lead others to understand, that land is everyone’s common heritage, that we all have equal rights to the earth. This understanding is central to our efforts to promote conscious evolution toward a world that truly works. When we try to persuade others that land is our common heritage, we often encounter a barrier: People tend to see land as private property. This prevents them from seeing land as everyone’s common heritage. I propose to explore the foundations and the implications of both land as our common heritage and land as private property, and identify the desirable parts of these two ideas are compatible. Land as Our Common Heritage

Upload: theiuorg

Post on 19-Jan-2015

38 views

Category:

News & Politics


2 download

DESCRIPTION

Nicolaus Tideman: Resolving the Apparent Conflict between Land as Our Common Heritage and Land as Private Property. A presentation at the TheIU.org 2013 Conference 'Economics for Conscious Evolution', London, UK, July 2013.

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Nicolaus Tideman: Resolving the Apparent Conflict between Land as Our Common Heritage and Land as Private Property

Resolving the Apparent Conflict between

Land as Our Common Heritage and Land as Private Property

Nicolaus Tideman

For the conference: “Economics for Conscious Evolution”

We understand, and we seek to lead others to understand, that land is

everyone’s common heritage, that we all have equal rights to the earth. This

understanding is central to our efforts to promote conscious evolution toward a

world that truly works.

When we try to persuade others that land is our common heritage, we often

encounter a barrier: People tend to see land as private property. This prevents

them from seeing land as everyone’s common heritage.

I propose to explore the foundations and the implications of both land as our

common heritage and land as private property, and identify the desirable parts

of these two ideas are compatible.

Land as Our Common Heritage

Land as our common heritage has its origin in the idea that there are valuable

“natural opportunities” that are not the product of anyone’s efforts.

Furthermore, people have an obligation to give equal respect to the wishes of all

persons to appropriate for their own uses the scarce opportunities provided by

nature. Thus we have an obligation to share natural opportunities as our

common heritage.

The idea of equal rights to our common heritage in natural opportunities is

not as simple as it may seem. It does not mean dividing the earth into equal

parcels for everyone on earth—some people have neither the talent nor the

inclination to take over their shares of the earth. Nor does it mean that we all

Page 2: Nicolaus Tideman: Resolving the Apparent Conflict between Land as Our Common Heritage and Land as Private Property

participate equally in a democratic process that decides on the use of every

parcel of ground. That would leave no scope for individual initiative.

If there were no scarcity of natural opportunities, then equal rights to natural

opportunities would mean that every person was allowed to use natural

opportunities in whatever ways he or she wished. The principle of equal rights

to natural opportunities restricts what people may do only when action by one

person limits the ability of one or more other persons to achieve their desires.

Scarcity alone is not sufficient for the principle of equal rights to be

applicable. There must also be less than perfect harmony. If natural

opportunities were scarce but everyone agreed on how they should be used,

then, whether the agreed allocation was equal or not, there would be no need to

employ a principle of equal rights. If there is no disagreement, then there is no

need to invoke equal rights.

It might be tempting to think of a principle of equal rights as emerging

historically, when humans first began to grow in numbers to where some natural

opportunities became scarce. But such a sequence is unlikely to have had any

historical relevance. It seems much more likely that there were scarcities of

natural opportunities before and while our ancestors were becoming human.

Our pre-human, partially human, and early human ancestors can reasonably be

presumed to have dealt with resource scarcity the way animals typically do: by

driving off or killing competitors. Selection through aggression is the way of

nature.

At the same time that early humans were, presumably, driving off and killing

competitors, they would have been under natural selection pressure to cooperate

with one another within groups: for hunting and other forms of cooperative

production, for child-raising, and for more effective fighting against other

groups. For many thousands of years, human success has entailed the

combination of cooperation and sharing within a reference group and the

2

Page 3: Nicolaus Tideman: Resolving the Apparent Conflict between Land as Our Common Heritage and Land as Private Property

opportunistic driving-off, enslaving, or killing of outsiders who were not strong

enough to resist.

Thus the idea of land as common heritage did not emerge as a way of dealing

with the initial human experience of scarcity of natural opportunities. Rather, it

emerged as a component of the moral evolution of humanity. When Thomas

Jefferson wrote in the Declaration of Independence, “We hold these truths to be

self-evident, that all men are created equal, that they are endowed by their

Creator with certain unalienable Rights, that among these are Life, Liberty and

the pursuit of Happiness . . .” people felt the rightness of what he had written.

The resonance of these words helped to end slavery and to produce a world

where, today, virtually all civilized discourse presumes that women and

minorities must be accorded the same civil and political rights as men of the

ethnically dominant group in a society. These are important achievements in

moral evolution.

This moral evolution has also begun to be understood to include a principle

of natural opportunities as a common heritage to which we all have equal rights.

A principle of equal rights is not the same as equality. “Equal rights”

incorporates recognition of our individuality, the right of each of us to pursue

happiness in whatever way he or she chooses. If we are not interfering with

others, we may do as we wish, and we may cooperate with whom we choose in

whatever activities are mutually agreed.

A complication arises from the fact that one of the ways in which we often

wish to cooperate with others is in the formation of communities that impose

standards of conduct that have no obvious necessity. Why should we be able to

specify the amount of clothing our fellow citizens must wear in public, or how

sober they must be, or what pornography they may consume? From the

perspective of equal rights to our common heritage, the answer is that we may

impose all of these restrictions and any others that we choose, because those of

us who want to live in a community with such restrictions have a right to use

3

Page 4: Nicolaus Tideman: Resolving the Apparent Conflict between Land as Our Common Heritage and Land as Private Property

our share of our common heritage to form the kind of community that expresses

our agreed idea of what a good community is. Those who don’t like such

restrictions can form their own communities somewhere else. Of course, this

presumes that there is an actual opportunity for every dissenter to have a share

of our common heritage on which to pursue his or her conception of the good.

Thus the idea of coming together by choice, and choosing to separate when

we cannot agree, is an integral part of equal rights to our common heritage. But

the right of people to form whatever kinds of communities they wish only

makes sense if there is an adequate opportunity for those who disagree to leave.

And it might happen that all of the space on earth was already occupied by

communities that had no interest in including the persons who wished to leave

their present communities. Therefore the idea of equal rights to our common

heritage must include the understanding that a group who are unhappy with the

rules of their community have a right to require that the territory of the

community be divided into a portion for those who are content with the rules of

the community and a separate portion for those who wish to live under a

different set of rules. Equal rights to our common heritage means recognizing

that dissatisfied minorities must have opportunities to live under the rules that

they choose. To deny this opportunity is unjustifiable tyranny of the majority.

Of course, splitting up communities will often mean losing economies of

scale. That is a loss that is shared by all who cannot agree on a set of rules by

which to live. It is the price of not agreeing and a stimulus to finding a

compromise that all can accept.

The principle of equal rights to our common heritage has an important

implication for justice among communities. A community’s claim to control

over the territory that it occupies is justified only if one of the following two

conditions is met:

4

Page 5: Nicolaus Tideman: Resolving the Apparent Conflict between Land as Our Common Heritage and Land as Private Property

1) The value of the natural opportunities that the community uses is not

disproportionately large in relation to the number of people in the

community; or

2) The community provides compensation, in the amount of the excess of its

appropriation of natural opportunities beyond the average that all can have,

for those who have disproportionately small shares of natural opportunities.

Then the question arises as to how one determines whether a community has

more than its share of natural opportunities. There can never be perfection in

answering such a question. The most that can be achieved is an unbiased,

serious effort. A community that wants to satisfy its obligation to respect the

equal rights of all people to natural opportunities can hire an appraiser who

would estimate the rental value of the natural opportunities appropriated by the

community and the rental value of the rest of the natural opportunities on earth.

Then, with the population of the community and that of the rest of the world and

a bit of arithmetic, one can calculate an estimate of the amount by which the

community’s appropriation of natural opportunities exceeds or falls short of its

share. If its appropriation exceeds its share, it would pay into a fund to

compensate the communities that had less than their shares.

When counting the natural opportunities that a community appropriates, one

would count such things as emissions of greenhouse gasses and other things that

pollute the air and water beyond its borders, and the community’s appropriation

of minerals, migratory fish and birds, fresh water that would be available to

other communities if not appropriated, the frequency spectrum beyond the

borders of the community, and geo-synchronous orbits. All resources would be

evaluated by the estimated loss to the rest of the world from the fact that this

community was appropriating these resources.

When appraising the land occupied by the community, the relevant question

would be, “What would the rental value of the territory occupied by the

community be if there were no community here?” The community would have

5

Page 6: Nicolaus Tideman: Resolving the Apparent Conflict between Land as Our Common Heritage and Land as Private Property

no obligation to pay for the addition to the rental value of its territory from its

infrastructure and development. To the extent that activities in the community

raised the rental value of land elsewhere, this would count as a credit against its

appropriations.

Then the question arises of whether an above-average birth rate counts as an

appropriation of natural opportunities. If a community has an above-average

birth rate, then in the next generation, the grown children of that community

will have a claim on a larger share of resources than their parents had. Other

communities will need to reduce the shares of global natural opportunities that

they claim. Thus there is a prima facie case for the proposition that having an

above-average birth rate represents an appropriation of natural opportunities

that requires compensation.

However, there are other considerations. A larger world population means

lower costs for software, movies, books, and anything else for which average

costs decline as output increases. It means more geniuses who benefit the world

much more than they are ever compensated. It means a greater variety of

associations with specialized interests. For all these reasons having a larger

population produces benefits while also reducing per capita resources, so that it

is not clear a priori whether the net effect of a larger population on average

income in the world is positive or negative. It almost certainly depends on the

level of world population. At low levels of population the benefits can be

expected to dominate, while at high levels the costs would dominate. So it is a

question for empirical inquiry whether an above-average birth rate is something

for which a community should compensate for or be compensated for.

So let’s review the foundations and implications of land as our common

heritage. From the understanding that there are valuable natural opportunities

that no one created, and that all people are created equal, so that we have an

obligation to accord equal respect to the desires of all to use natural

opportunities, there arises an obligation of individuals and communities not to

6

Page 7: Nicolaus Tideman: Resolving the Apparent Conflict between Land as Our Common Heritage and Land as Private Property

appropriate a more valuable share of natural opportunities than others can have.

“Natural opportunities” includes not just land, but minerals, wild animals,

water, the frequency spectrum, geosynchronous orbits, the capacity of the

environment to absorb pollutants, other harmful effects of communities on their

neighbours, and, potentially, the limited capacity of the earth to absorb more

people without having levels of well-being fall. Because we want to live in

communities that express our varying ideas about what a good community is,

we have an obligation to allow our territories to be divided up when we are

unable to agree on rules under which to live. These are challenging ideas, but

they have the potential to provide a framework for a world that operates much

more efficiently than the world we have.

Land as Private Property

The word “property” shares an origin with the word “proper,” going back to

the Latin word “proprius,” meaning “one’s own.” The idea that what one

produces is one’s own (is one’s property) serves the very important function of

ensuring that people will have the incentive to be productive.

Animals appear to have only a rudimentary concept of property, associated

with protecting territory. It was a very important development in human

evolution for the value of a person’s efforts to be protected by a shared social

concept of property.

The idea that the land that one occupies is one’s property has at least two

important functions. First, because some things that people produce (structures)

are highly immobile, having long-lasting control over locations serves to ensure

that people are able to benefit from their investments in structures. Second,

there is the idea that a man’s home is his castle. Having a parcel of land as

one’s property gives expression to the idea that there is a place where a person

can be the person that he or she wants to be, to do the things that he or she

wants to do, where no one else will interfere.

7

Page 8: Nicolaus Tideman: Resolving the Apparent Conflict between Land as Our Common Heritage and Land as Private Property

There is another consequence of land as private property that has an element

of efficiency. This is the fact that giving ownership of a resource to the person

who discovers it motivates people to discover resources that would otherwise go

undiscovered and therefore unused. The trouble with this argument is that the

reward is too great. Granting complete ownership to the discoverer motivates

people to invest excessively in discovery, to try to ensure that they are first.

Discovery is valuable, but to motivate efficient discovery one must offer a

reward of a size such that only the person with the lowest cost of discovery is

motivated to put resources into discovery. Granting complete ownership to

discoverers is not efficient.

Economists sometimes make the argument that those who have land are only

making normal returns on their investments. This is true, but this economic fact

does not mean that the institution of private ownership of land produces better

results than some other institutional arrangement under which one would also

find economic agents making only ordinary returns on their investments. The

fact that under competition people make ordinary returns on their investments in

land is not directly relevant to the question of what institutions are best.

Then there is the psychological fact that people tend to have a sense of

entitlement to the things that they have, especially if they sacrificed something

to obtain them. This aspect of human psychology is related to the phenomenon

of territoriality in animals. Animals tend to become aggressive when the

territory they regard as theirs is invaded. People tend to become aggressive

when the property they regard as theirs is threatened or when the economic

opportunities that they have come to expect are no longer available. This

psychological fact has implications for the cost and the political difficulty of

achieving reforms, but it does not affect the long-run value of reforms.

Summarizing the foundations and implications of private property in land:

Property can be presumed to have evolved from its value in motivating people

to be economically productive. Property in land makes it efficient for people

8

Page 9: Nicolaus Tideman: Resolving the Apparent Conflict between Land as Our Common Heritage and Land as Private Property

to make investments that are attached to land, and it provides a place where a

person can exercise individual liberty. Property rights in what one finds create

an inefficiently large incentive for discovery. In any competitive economy,

people make normal returns, on average, on their investments, but this has no

implication for the efficiency of institutions. Psychologically, people tend to

become aggressively unhappy when their ownership of property or their other

expectations of economic benefit are disappointed.

Resolving the Apparent Conflict

The apparent conflict between land as our common heritage and land as

private property cannot be completely resolved, but substantial parts of it can.

We cannot let people have complete ownership of indefinitely large amounts of

land while also recognizing the equal rights of all to land as our common

heritage. But we can recognize each person’s right to a share of land and other

natural opportunities. This recognition means that the idea of “a man’s home as

his castle,” the idea of a place where a person can exercise liberty, can express

his or her individuality, can pursue happiness in the way the he or she chooses,

is entirely compatible with land as our common heritage. In fact, to ensure that

all persons have liberty, it is essential to ensure that each person has a right to a

place where that liberty can be exercised. If some of the people have all of the

land, there will be no place for others to exercise their liberty.

A person’s share of natural opportunities is the amount that every other

person can also have. The addition to the rental value of land from

infrastructure and the economic growth of communities is not part of anyone’s

share; it is for the community to dispose of as it chooses.

If a person wishes to have his share of natural opportunities in a place where

infrastructure and the growth of the community add to the value of land, he

should expect to pay that much of the rental value of the land he occupies to the

9

Page 10: Nicolaus Tideman: Resolving the Apparent Conflict between Land as Our Common Heritage and Land as Private Property

community. If he wishes to have a smaller piece of land, his obligation to the

community will shrink and perhaps even become negative.

The benefit of private property in land in ensuring that people who build

structures will benefit from those investments can also be obtained in a

framework that recognizes land as everyone’s common heritage. All that is

needed is a continuation of the system of titles to land. The land title provides

social recognition of the right of the title holder to decide how the land will be

used into the indefinite future. If land is recognized as everyone’s common

heritage, then holding title to land also carries an obligation to pay to the

community the excess of the rental value of the land above a person’s equal

share of natural opportunities. This obligation does not interfere with the title

holder’s opportunity to benefit from any enduring improvements to the land that

he has made.

One might object: It could happen that a person builds a lasting

improvement, and then, unexpectedly, the rental value of the land rises because

of growth of the community. This rise in the value of the land and

corresponding rise in the rental value that the title holder must pay to the

community could destroy the value of the improvement. Yes, this can happen.

The economic way of dealing with this risk is by having improvers of land who

are worried about it buy insurance. An improvement is only truly worthwhile if

it has a positive return when one includes in its cost the cost of insurance

against a rise in land value that makes the improvement obsolete. It is not

necessary for the holder of title to land to have a guarantee that taxes will not

rise.

Then there is the issue of efficient motivation of resource discoveries. It is

difficult to devise a system that motivates people to spend efficiently on seeking

to discover resources. Some compensation is appropriate; full ownership of the

resources that are found is excessive and motivates wasteful expenditures on

discovery.

10

Page 11: Nicolaus Tideman: Resolving the Apparent Conflict between Land as Our Common Heritage and Land as Private Property

Thus it is possible to incorporate the most valuable aspects of land as private

property into a framework that recognizes land as a common heritage, to which

we all have equal rights.

11