environmental aesthetics (stanford encyclopedia of philosophy)

20
9/6/2015 Environmental Aesthetics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy) http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/environmentalaesthetics/ 1/20 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Environmental Aesthetics First published Mon Jan 29, 2007; substantive revision Mon Jan 26, 2015 Environmental aesthetics is a relatively new subfield of philosophical aesthetics. It arose within analytic aesthetics in the last third of the twentieth century. Prior to its emergence, aesthetics within the analytic tradition was largely concerned with philosophy of art. Environmental aesthetics originated as a reaction to this emphasis, pursuing instead the investigation of the aesthetic appreciation of natural environments. Since its early stages, the scope of environmental aesthetics has broadened to include not simply natural environments but also human and humaninfluenced ones. At the same time, the discipline has also come to include the examination of that which falls within such environments, giving rise to what is called the aesthetics of everyday life. This area involves the aesthetics of not only more common objects and environments, but also a range of everyday activities. Thus, early in the twentyfirst century, environmental aesthetics embraces the study of the aesthetic significance of almost everything other than art. 1. History 1.1 Eighteenth Century Aesthetics of Nature 1.2 Nineteenth Century Aesthetics of Nature 2. Twentieth Century Developments 2.1 The Neglect of the Aesthetics of Nature 2.2 The Emergence of Environmental Aesthetics 3. Basic Positions in Environmental Aesthetics 3.1 Cognitive Views 3.2 Noncognitive Views 4. Recent Developments in Environmental Aesthetics 4.1 The Aesthetics of Human Environments and Everyday Life 4.2 Environmental Aesthetics and Environmentalism Bibliography Academic Tools Other Internet Resources Related Entries 1. History Although environmental aesthetics has developed as a subfield of Western philosophical aesthetics only in the last forty years, it has historical roots in eighteenth and nineteenth century European and North American aesthetics. In these centuries, there were important advances in the aesthetics of nature, including the emergence of the concept of disinterestedness together with those of the sublime and the picturesque, as well as the introduction of the idea of positive aesthetics. These notions continue to play a

Upload: md-shahroz-alam

Post on 31-Jan-2016

247 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

DESCRIPTION

Environmental Aesthetics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Environmental Aesthetics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

9/6/2015 Environmental Aesthetics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/environmental­aesthetics/ 1/20

Stanford Encyclopedia of PhilosophyEnvironmental AestheticsFirst published Mon Jan 29, 2007; substantive revision Mon Jan26, 2015

Environmental aesthetics is a relatively new sub­field ofphilosophical aesthetics. It arose within analytic aesthetics in thelast third of the twentieth century. Prior to its emergence, aestheticswithin the analytic tradition was largely concerned with philosophyof art. Environmental aesthetics originated as a reaction to thisemphasis, pursuing instead the investigation of the aestheticappreciation of natural environments. Since its early stages, thescope of environmental aesthetics has broadened to include not

simply natural environments but also human and human­influenced ones. At the same time, the disciplinehas also come to include the examination of that which falls within such environments, giving rise towhat is called the aesthetics of everyday life. This area involves the aesthetics of not only more commonobjects and environments, but also a range of everyday activities. Thus, early in the twenty­first century,environmental aesthetics embraces the study of the aesthetic significance of almost everything other thanart.

1. History1.1 Eighteenth Century Aesthetics of Nature1.2 Nineteenth Century Aesthetics of Nature

2. Twentieth Century Developments2.1 The Neglect of the Aesthetics of Nature2.2 The Emergence of Environmental Aesthetics

3. Basic Positions in Environmental Aesthetics3.1 Cognitive Views3.2 Non­cognitive Views

4. Recent Developments in Environmental Aesthetics4.1 The Aesthetics of Human Environments and Everyday Life4.2 Environmental Aesthetics and Environmentalism

BibliographyAcademic ToolsOther Internet ResourcesRelated Entries

1. History

Although environmental aesthetics has developed as a sub­field of Western philosophical aesthetics onlyin the last forty years, it has historical roots in eighteenth and nineteenth century European and NorthAmerican aesthetics. In these centuries, there were important advances in the aesthetics of nature,including the emergence of the concept of disinterestedness together with those of the sublime and thepicturesque, as well as the introduction of the idea of positive aesthetics. These notions continue to play a

Page 2: Environmental Aesthetics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

9/6/2015 Environmental Aesthetics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/environmental­aesthetics/ 2/20

role in contemporary work in environmental aesthetics, especially in the context of its relationship toenvironmentalism.

1.1 Eighteenth Century Aesthetics of Nature

In the West, the first major philosophical developments in the aesthetics of nature occurred in theeighteenth century. During that century, the founders of modern aesthetics not only began to take natureas a paradigmatic object of aesthetic experience, they also developed the concept of disinterestedness asthe mark of such experience. Over the course of the century, this concept was elaborated by variousthinkers, who employed it to purge from aesthetic appreciation an ever­increasing range of interests andassociations. According to one standard account (Stolnitz 1961), the concept originated with the thirdEarl of Shaftesbury, who introduced it as a way of characterizing the notion of the aesthetic, wasembellished by Francis Hutcheson, who expanded it so as to exclude from aesthetic experience notsimply personal and utilitarian interests, but also associations of a more general nature, and was furtherdeveloped by Archibald Alison, who took it to refer to a particular state of mind. The concept was givenits classic formulation in Immanuel Kant's Critique of Judgment, in which nature was taken as anexemplary object of aesthetic experience. Kant argued that natural beauty was superior to that of art andthat it complemented the best habits of mind. It is no accident that the development of the concept ofdisinterestedness and the acceptance of nature as an ideal object of aesthetic appreciation went hand inhand. The clarification of the notion of the aesthetic in terms of the concept of disinterestednessdisassociated the aesthetic appreciation of nature from the appreciator's particular personal, religious,economic, or utilitarian interests, any of which could impede aesthetic experience.

The theory of disinterestedness also provided groundwork for understanding the aesthetic dimensions ofnature in terms of three distinct conceptualizations. The first involved the idea of the beautiful, whichreadily applies to tamed and cultivated European gardens and landscapes. The second centered on theidea of the sublime. In the experience of the sublime, the more threatening and terrifying of nature'smanifestations, such as mountains and wilderness, when viewed with disinterestedness, can beaesthetically appreciated, rather than simply feared or despised. These two notions were importantlyelaborated by Edmund Burke and Kant. However, concerning the appreciation of nature, a third conceptwas to become more significant than that of either the beautiful or the sublime: the notion of thepicturesque. Thus, by the end of the eighteenth century, there were three clearly distinct ideas eachfocusing on different aspects of nature's diverse and often contrasting moods. One historian of thepicturesque tradition (Conron 2000) argues that in “eighteenth­century English theory, the boundariesbetween aesthetic categories are relatively clear and stable”. The differences can be summarized asfollows: objects experienced as beautiful tend to be small and smooth, but subtly varied, delicate, and“fair” in color, while those experienced as sublime, by contrast, are powerful, vast, intense, terrifying,and “definitionless”. Picturesque items are typically in the middle ground between those experienced aseither sublime or beautiful, being complex and eccentric, varied and irregular, rich and forceful, andvibrant with energy.

It is not surprising that of these three notions, the idea of the picturesque, rather that of the beautiful orthe sublime, achieved the greatest prominence concerning the aesthetic experience of nature. Not onlydoes it occupy the extensive middle ground of the complex, irregular, forceful, and vibrant, all of whichabound in the natural world, it also reinforced various long­standing connections between the aestheticappreciation of nature and the treatment of nature in art. The term “picturesque” literally means “picture­like” and the theory of the picturesque advocates aesthetic appreciation in which the natural world isexperienced as if divided into art­like scenes, which ideally resemble works of arts, especially landscapepainting, in both subject matter and composition. Thus, since the concept of disinterestedness mandatedappreciation of nature stripped of the appreciator's own personal interests and associations, it helped to

Page 3: Environmental Aesthetics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

9/6/2015 Environmental Aesthetics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/environmental­aesthetics/ 3/20

clear the ground for experience of nature governed by the theory of the picturesque, by which theappreciator is encouraged to see nature in terms of a new set of artistic images and associations. In thisway the idea of the picturesque relates to earlier conceptions of the natural world as comprised of whatwere called “works of nature”, which, although considered in themselves to be proper and importantobjects of aesthetic experience, were thought to be even more appealing when they resembled works ofart. The idea also resonates with other artistic traditions, such as that of viewing art as the mirror ofnature. The theory of the picturesque received its fullest treatment in the late eighteenth century when itwas popularized in the writings of William Gilpin, Uvedale Price, and Richard Payne Knight. At thattime, it provided an aesthetic ideal for English tourists, who pursued picturesque scenery in the LakeDistrict, the Scottish Highlands, and the Alps.

1.2 Nineteenth Century Aesthetics of Nature

Following its articulation in the eighteenth century, the idea of the picturesque remained a dominantinfluence on popular aesthetic experience of nature throughout the entire nineteenth and well into thetwentieth century. Indeed, it is still an important component of the kind of aesthetic experiencecommonly associated with ordinary tourism—that which involves seeing and appreciating the naturalworld as it is represented in the depictions found in travel brochures, calendar photos, and picturepostcards. However, while the idea of the picturesque continued to guide popular aesthetic appreciationof nature, the philosophical study of the aesthetics of nature, after flowering in the eighteenth century,went into decline. Many of the main themes, such as the concept of the sublime, the notion ofdisinterestedness, and the theoretical centrality of nature in philosophical aesthetics, culminated withKant, who gave some of these ideas such exhaustive treatment that a kind of philosophical closure wasseemingly achieved. Following Kant, a new world order was initiated by Hegel. In Hegel's philosophy,art was the highest expression of “Absolute Spirit”, and it, rather than nature, was destined to become thefavored subject of philosophical aesthetics. Thus, in the nineteenth century, both on the continent and inthe United Kingdom, relatively few philosophers and only a scattering of thinkers of the RomanticMovement seriously pursued the theoretical study of the aesthetics of nature. There was no philosophicalwork comparable to that of the preceding century.

However, while the philosophical study of the aesthetics of nature languished in Europe, a new way ofunderstanding the aesthetic appreciation of the natural world was developing in North America. Thisconception of nature appreciation had roots in the American tradition of nature writing, as exemplified inthe essays of Henry David Thoreau. It was also inspired by the idea of the picturesque and, to a lesserextent, that of the sublime, especially in its artistic manifestations, such as the paintings of Thomas Coleand Frederic Church. However, as nature writing became its more dominant form of expression, theconception was increasingly shaped by developments in the natural sciences. In the middle of thenineteenth century, it was influenced by the geographical work of George Perkins Marsh (1865), whoargued that humanity was increasingly causing the destruction of the beauty of nature. The idea wasforcefully presented toward the end of the century in the work of American naturalist John Muir, whowas steeped in natural history. Muir explicitly distinguished this kind of understanding of aestheticappreciation from that governed by the idea of the picturesque. In a well­known essay, “A Near View ofthe High Sierra” (1894), two of Muir's artist companions, who focus on mountain scenery, exemplifyaesthetic experience of nature as guided by the idea of the picturesque. This differs from Muir's ownaesthetic experience, which involved an interest in and appreciation of the mountain environmentsomewhat more akin to that of a geologist. This way of experiencing nature eventually brought Muir tosee the whole of the natural environment and especially wild nature as aesthetically beautiful and to findugliness primarily where nature was subject to human intrusion. The range of things that he regarded asaesthetically appreciable seemed to encompass the entire natural world, from creatures consideredhideous in his day, such as snakes and alligators, to natural disasters thought to ruin the environment,

Page 4: Environmental Aesthetics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

9/6/2015 Environmental Aesthetics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/environmental­aesthetics/ 4/20

such as floods and earthquakes. The kind of nature appreciation practiced by Muir has become associatedwith the contemporary point of view called “positive aesthetics” (Carlson 1984). Insofar as suchappreciation eschews humanity's marks on the natural environment, it is somewhat the converse ofaesthetic appreciation influenced by the idea of the picturesque, which finds interest and delight inevidence of human presence.

2. Twentieth Century Developments

Western philosophical study of the aesthetics of the natural world reached a low point in the middle ofthe twentieth century, with the focus of analytic aesthetics almost exclusively on philosophy of art. At thesame time, the view that aesthetic appreciation of nature is parasitic upon that of art and even the ideathat it is not in fact aesthetic appreciation at all were defended by some thinkers. However, in the lastthird of the century, there was a reaction to the neglect of the natural world by the discipline of aesthetics,which initiated a revival of the aesthetic investigation of nature and led to the emergence ofenvironmental aesthetics.

2.1 The Neglect of the Aesthetics of Nature

In the first half of the twentieth century, Anglo­American philosophy largely ignored the aesthetics ofnature. However, there were some noteworthy exceptions. For example, in North America, GeorgeSantayana investigated the topic as well as the concept of nature itself. Somewhat later, John Deweycontributed to the understanding of the aesthetic experience of both nature and everyday life, and CurtDucasse discussed the beauty of nature as well as that of the human form. In England, R. G. Collingwoodworked on both the philosophy of art and the idea of nature, but the two topics did not importantly cometogether in his thought. However, other than a few such individuals, as far as aesthetics was pursued,there was little serious consideration of the aesthetics of nature. On the contrary, the discipline wasdominated by an interest in art. By the mid­twentieth century, within analytic philosophy, the principalphilosophical school in the English­speaking world at that time, philosophical aesthetics was virtuallyequated with philosophy of art. The leading aesthetics textbook of the period was subtitled Problems inthe Philosophy of Criticism and opened with the assertion: “There would be no problems of aesthetics, inthe sense in which I propose to mark out this field of study, if no one ever talked about works of art”(Beardsley 1958). The comment was meant to emphasize the importance of the analysis of language, butit also reveals the art­dominated construal of aesthetics of that time. Moreover, if and when the aestheticappreciation of nature was discussed, it was treated, by comparison with that of art, as a messy,subjective business of less philosophical interest. Some of the major aestheticians of the second half ofthe century argued that aesthetic judgments beyond what became known as the “artworld” must remainrelative to conditions of observation and unfettered by the kind of constraints that govern the appreciationof art (Walton 1970, Dickie 1974).

The domination of analytic aesthetics by an interest in art had two ramifications. On the one hand, ithelped to motivate a controversial philosophical position that denied the possibility of any aestheticexperience of nature whatsoever. The position held that aesthetic appreciation necessarily involvesaesthetic judgments, which entail judging the object of appreciation as the achievement of a designingintellect. However, since nature is not the product of a designing intellect, its appreciation is not aesthetic(Mannison 1980). In the past, nature appreciation was deemed aesthetic because of the assumption thatnature is the work of a designing creator, but this assumption is simply false or at least inadequate forgrounding an aesthetics of nature. On the other hand, the art­dominated construal of aesthetics also gavesupport to approaches that stand within the many different historical traditions that conceptualize thenatural world as essentially art­like—for example, as a set of the “works of nature”, or as the“handiwork” of a creator, or as picturesque scenery. For example, what might be called a landscape

Page 5: Environmental Aesthetics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

9/6/2015 Environmental Aesthetics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/environmental­aesthetics/ 5/20

model of nature appreciation, which stems directly from the tradition of the picturesque, proposes that weshould aesthetically experience nature as we appreciate landscape paintings. This requires seeing it tosome extent as if it were a series of two­dimensional scenes and focusing either on formal aestheticqualities or on artistic qualities dependent upon the kind of romantic images associated with the idea ofthe picturesque. Such art­oriented models of the aesthetic appreciation of nature, in addition to beingsupported by powerful and long­standing traditions of thought (Biese 1905, Nicolson 1959), are defendedin some recent work in environmental aesthetics (Stecker 1997, Crawford 2004, Leddy 2005a). Likewise,the defense of formal aesthetic appreciation of nature has recently been renewed (Zangwill 2001 2013),although not without debate (Parsons 2004, Parsons and Carlson 2004, Moore 2006).

2.2 The Emergence of Environmental Aesthetics

In the last third of the twentieth century, a renewed interest in the aesthetics of nature emerged. Thisrevival was the result of several different factors. In part, it was a response to the growing public concernabout the apparent degeneration of the environment, aesthetic and otherwise. It was also the result of theacademic world becoming aware of the significance of the environmental movement—at the level ofboth theoretical discussion and practical action. It is noteworthy that the emergence of the philosophicalstudy of environmental ethics also dates from this time. Some of the earlier work in environmentalaesthetics focused on empirical research conducted in response to public apprehension about the aestheticstate of the environment. Critics argued that the landscape assessment and planning techniques used inenvironmental management were inadequate in stressing mainly formal properties, while overlookingexpressive and other kinds of aesthetic qualities (Sagoff 1974, Carlson 1976). Empirical approaches werealso faulted as fixated on “scenic beauty” and overly influenced by ideas such as that of the picturesque(Carlson 1977). In general, the area was thought beset by theoretical problems (Sparshott 1972), and theempirical research in particular was said to lack an adequate conceptual framework, often beingconducted in what one critic called a “theoretical vacuum” (Appleton 1975b). Attempts to fill thisvacuum prompted the idea of sociobiological underpinnings for the aesthetic appreciation of nature, suchas “prospect­refuge theory” (Appleton 1975a 1982), as well as other evolution­related accounts (Oriansand Heerwagen 1986 1992). In addition, the concerns of this period motivated the development of avariety of theoretical models of aesthetic response grounded in, for example, developmental andenvironmental psychology (Kaplan and Kaplan 1989, Bourassa 1991). There are overviews (Zube 1984,Cats­Baril and Gibson 1986, Daniel 2001) and collections (Saarinen et al 1984, Nasar 1988, Sheppardand Harshaw 2001) of this and related kinds of research, as well as more recent studies that, althoughthey have an essentially empirical orientation, are of considerable theoretical interest (Porteous 1996,Bell 1999, Parsons and Daniel 2002, Gobster et al 2007, Hill and Daniel 2008, Gobster 2008 2013).

Within philosophical aesthetics itself, the renewed interest in the aesthetics of nature was also fueled byanother development: the publication of Ronald Hepburn's seminal article “Contemporary Aesthetics andthe Neglect of Natural Beauty” (1966). Hepburn's essay helped to set the agenda for the aesthetics ofnature in the late twentieth century. After noting that by essentially reducing all of aesthetics tophilosophy of art, analytic aesthetics had virtually ignored the natural world, Hepburn argued thataesthetic appreciation of art frequently provides misleading models for the appreciation of nature.However, he nonetheless observed that there is in the aesthetic appreciation of nature, as in theappreciation of art, a distinction between appreciation that is only trivial and superficial and that which isserious and deep. He furthermore suggested that for nature such serious appreciation might require newand different approaches that can accommodate not only nature's indeterminate and varying character,but also both our multi­sensory experience and our diverse understanding of it. By focusing attention onnatural beauty, Hepburn demonstrated that there could be significant philosophical investigation of theaesthetic experience of the world beyond the artworld. He thereby not only generated renewed interest inthe aesthetics of nature, he also laid foundations for environmental aesthetics in general as well as for the

Page 6: Environmental Aesthetics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

9/6/2015 Environmental Aesthetics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/environmental­aesthetics/ 6/20

aesthetics of everyday life.

In the wake of Hepburn’s article, the next major developments in the emerging field of environmentalaesthetics challenged both the idea that nature appreciation is not aesthetic and the persistence of art­oriented approaches to the aesthetic appreciation of nature. Although these views about the appreciationof nature had found some grounding in analytic aesthetics' reduction of aesthetics to philosophy of art, asart’s monopoly on philosophical aesthetics began to weaken, they were increasing recognized to bedeeply counterintuitive. Concerning the former, many of our fundamental paradigms of aestheticexperience seem to be instances of appreciation of nature, such as our delight in a sunset or in a bird inflight. Moreover, the Western tradition in aesthetics, as well as other traditions, such as the Japanese, haslong been committed to doctrines that explicitly contradict the nonaesthetic conception of natureappreciation, such as the conviction that, as one philosopher expresses it, anything that can be viewed canbe viewed aesthetically (Ziff 1979). Concerning the art­oriented models, it was argued by some that suchapproaches do not fully realize serious, appropriate appreciation of nature, but rather distort the truecharacter of natural environments. For example, the landscape model recommends framing and flatteningenvironments into scenery. Moreover, in focusing heavily on artistic qualities, these accounts are thoughtto neglect much of our normal experience and understanding of nature (Hepburn 1966, Carlson 1979,Berleant 1985 1988 1992, Saito 1998a 1998b). The problem, in short, is that they do not acknowledge theimportance of aesthetically appreciating nature, as one aesthetician puts it, “as nature” (Budd 2002).

3. Basic Positions in Environmental Aesthetics

After the emergence of environmental aesthetics as a significant area of philosophical research, somebasic positions crystallized. In the last part of the last century, these positions developed distinct points ofview concerning the nature of the aesthetic appreciation of natural environments. At that time, thepositions were frequently distinguished as belonging in one or the other of two groups, alternativelylabeled cognitive and non­cognitive (Godlovitch 1994, Eaton 1998, Carlson and Berleant 2004),conceptual and non­conceptual (Moore 1999), or narrative and ambient (Foster 1998). The distinctionmarks a crucial division between those positions that take knowledge and information to be essential toaesthetic appreciation of environments and those that take some other feature, such as engagement,emotion arousal, or imagination, to be paramount. It thereby gives structure and organization to thediverse points of view represented in the field. Moreover, it is in line with similar distinctions used inaesthetic theory concerning the appreciation of art, music, and literature.

3.1 Cognitive Views

What are called cognitive, conceptual, or narrative positions in environmental aesthetics are united by thethought that knowledge and information about the nature of the object of appreciation is central to itsaesthetic appreciation. Thus, they champion the idea that nature must be appreciated, as one author putsit, “on its own terms” (Saito 1998b). These positions tend to reject aesthetic approaches to environments,such as that governed by the idea of the picturesque, that draw heavily on the aesthetic experience of artfor modeling the appreciation of nature. Yet they affirm that art appreciation can nonetheless show someof what is required in an adequate account of nature appreciation. For example, in serious, appropriateaesthetic appreciation of works of art, it is taken to be essential that we experience works as what they infact are and in light of knowledge of their real natures. Thus, for instance, appropriate appreciation of awork such as Picasso's Guernica (1937) requires that we experience it as a painting and moreover as acubist painting, and therefore that we appreciate it in light of our knowledge of paintings in general andof cubist paintings in particular (Walton 1970). Adopting this general line of thought, one cognitiveapproach to nature appreciation, sometimes labeled the natural environmental model (Carlson 1979) orscientific cognitivism (Parsons 2002), holds that just as serious, appropriate aesthetic appreciation of art

Page 7: Environmental Aesthetics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

9/6/2015 Environmental Aesthetics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/environmental­aesthetics/ 7/20

requires knowledge of art history and art criticism, such aesthetic appreciation of nature requiresknowledge of natural history—the knowledge provided by the natural sciences and especially sciencessuch as geology, biology, and ecology. The idea is that scientific knowledge about nature can reveal theactual aesthetic qualities of natural objects and environments in the way in which knowledge about arthistory and art criticism can for works of art. In short, to appropriately aesthetically appreciate nature “onits own terms” is to appreciate it as it is characterized by natural science (Carlson 1981 2000 2007,Rolston 1995, Eaton 1998, Matthews 2002, Parsons 2002 2006b).

Other cognitive or quasi­cognitive accounts of the aesthetic appreciation of environments differ fromscientific cognitivism concerning either the kind of cognitive resources taken to be relevant to suchappreciation or the degree to which these resources are considered relevant. On the one hand, severalcognitive approaches emphasize different kinds of information, claiming that appreciating nature “on itsown terms” might well involve experiencing it in light of various cultural and historical traditions. Thus,in appropriate aesthetic appreciation, local and regional narratives, folklore, and even mythologicalstories about nature are endorsed either as complementary with or as alternative to scientific knowledge(Sepänmaa 1993, Saito 1998b, Heyd 2001). On the other hand, another at least quasi­cognitive approachstrongly supports the idea that nature must be appreciated “as nature”, but does not go beyond thatconstraint. The justification for accepting the “as nature” restriction is that the aesthetic experience ofnature should be true to what nature actually is. This, however, is the extent of the position's commitmentto cognitivism and marks the limits of the similarity that it finds between art appreciation and theappreciation of nature. It rejects the idea that scientific knowledge about nature can reveal the actualaesthetic qualities of natural objects and environments in the way in which knowledge about art historyand art criticism can for works of art. Moreover, it holds that, unlike the case with art, many of the mostsignificant aesthetic dimensions of natural objects and environments are extremely relative to conditionsof observation. The upshot is that aesthetic appreciation of nature is taken to allow a degree of freedomthat is denied to the aesthetic appreciation of art (Fisher 1998, Budd 2002).

3.2 Non­cognitive Views

Standing in contrast to the cognitive positions in environmental aesthetics are several so­called non­cognitive, non­conceptual, or ambient approaches. However, “non­cognitive” here should not be taken inits older philosophical sense, as meaning primarily or only “emotive”. Rather it indicates simply thatthese views hold that something other than a cognitive component, such as scientific knowledge orcultural tradition, is the central feature of the aesthetic appreciation of environments. The leading non­cognitive approach, called the aesthetics of engagement, draws on phenomenology as well as on analyticaesthetics. In doing so, it rejects many of the traditional ideas about aesthetic appreciation not only fornature but also for art. It argues that the theory of disinterestedness involves a mistaken analysis of theconcept of the aesthetic and that this is most evident in the aesthetic experience of natural environments.According to the engagement approach, disinterested appreciation, with its isolating, distancing, andobjectifying gaze, is out of place in the aesthetic experience of nature, for it wrongly abstracts bothnatural objects and appreciators from the environments in which they properly belong and in whichappropriate appreciation is achieved. Thus, the aesthetics of engagement stresses the contextualdimensions of nature and our multi­sensory experiences of it. Viewing the environment as a seamlessunity of places, organisms, and perceptions, it challenges the importance of traditional dichotomies, suchas that between subject and object. It beckons appreciators to immerse themselves in the naturalenvironment and to reduce to as small a degree as possible the distance between themselves and thenatural world. In short, appropriate aesthetic experience is held to involve the total immersion of theappreciator in the object of appreciation (Berleant 1985 1988 1992 2013).

Other non­cognitive positions in environmental aesthetics contend that dimensions other than

Page 8: Environmental Aesthetics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

9/6/2015 Environmental Aesthetics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/environmental­aesthetics/ 8/20

engagement are central to aesthetic experience. What is known as the arousal model holds that we mayappreciate nature simply by opening ourselves to it and being emotionally aroused by it. On this view,this less intellectual, more visceral experience of nature constitutes a legitimate way of aestheticallyappreciating it that does not require any knowledge gained from science or elsewhere (Carroll 1993).Another alternative similarly argues that neither scientific nor any other kind of knowledge facilitatesreal, appropriate appreciation of nature, but not because such appreciation need involve only emotionalarousal, but rather because nature itself is essentially alien, aloof, distant, and unknowable. This position,which may be called the mystery model, contends that appropriate experience of nature incorporates asense of being separate from nature and of not belonging to it—a sense of mystery involving a state ofappreciative incomprehension (Godlovitch 1994). A fourth non­cognitive approach brings togetherseveral features thought to be relevant to nature appreciation. It attempts to balance engagement and thetraditional idea of disinterestedness, while giving center stage to imagination. This position distinguishesa number of different kinds of imagination—associative, metaphorical, exploratory, projective,ampliative, and revelatory. It also responds to concerns that imagination introduces subjectivity byappealing to factors such as guidance by the object of appreciation, the constraining role ofdisinterestedness, and the notion of “imagining well” (Brady 1998 2003). A related point of view, whichstresses the metaphysical dimensions of imagination, might also be placed in the non­cognitive group,although doing so requires making certain assumptions about the cognitive content of metaphysicalspeculation. According to this account, the imagination interprets nature as revealing metaphysicalinsights: insights about things such as the meaning of life, the human condition, or our place in thecosmos. Thus, this position includes within appropriate aesthetic experience of nature those abstractmeditations and ruminations about ultimate reality that our encounters with nature sometimes engender(Hepburn 1996).

4. Recent Developments in Environmental Aesthetics

Since they first took form in the late twentieth century, the basic positions in environmental aestheticshave expanded from their initial focus on natural environments to consider human and human­influencedenvironments and developed such as to include an aesthetic investigation of everyday life in general. Atthe same time, the relationship between environmental aesthetics and environmentalism has beenincreasingly scrutinized, resulting in criticism of earlier work in the aesthetics of nature as well asdetailed assessments of contemporary positions. Concerning both the aesthetics of human environmentsand environmentalism, approaches that combine the resources of both cognitive and non­cognitive pointsof views have become more common and seem especially fruitful.

4.1 The Aesthetics of Human Environments and Everyday Life

Both the cognitive and the non­cognitive orientations in environmental aesthetics have resources that arebrought to bear on the aesthetic investigation of human and human­influenced environments as well ason that of everyday life in general. Of the basic positions, some non­cognitive approaches have made themost substantial contributions to these areas of research. The aesthetics of engagement is particularlysignificant in this regard, constituting a model for the aesthetic appreciation of not simply both nature andart, but also of every other aspect of human experience; it studies the aesthetic dimensions of ruralcountrysides, small towns, large cities, theme parks, gardens, museums, and even human relationships.Moreover, unlike most other approaches in environmental aesthetics, from early on in the developmentof the field, the aesthetics of engagement focused not only on natural environments, but also on humanenvironments and especially on urban environments (Berleant 1978 1984 1986). Much of this material isavailable in more recently published volumes (Berleant 1997 2005 2010 2012). Consequently, it hasbecome a foundation for a substantial body of research on the aesthetic appreciation of urban

Page 9: Environmental Aesthetics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

9/6/2015 Environmental Aesthetics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/environmental­aesthetics/ 9/20

environments (Haapala 1998, von Bonsdorff 2002, Blanc 2013, Paetzold 2013). Other non­cognitiveaccounts, such as that which stresses imagination, likewise illuminate our aesthetic responses to a rangeof human environments as well as to our uses of them for resource extraction and agricultural production(Brady 2003 2006).

Cognitive accounts also investigate the aesthetic appreciation of human environments, arguing that, aswith natural environments, appropriate appreciation depends on knowledge of what something is, what itis like, and why it is as it is. Scientific cognitivism claims that for human environments knowledgeprovided by the social sciences, especially history, is equally as relevant to aesthetic appreciation as thatgiven by the natural sciences (Carlson 2008). For appropriate appreciation of rural and urbanenvironments, as well as specialized environments such as those of industry and agriculture, what isneeded is information about their histories, their functions, and their roles in our lives (Carlson 19852001, Parsons 2008b, Parsons and Carlson 2008). Other approaches emphasize the aesthetic potential ofcultural traditions, which seem especially relevant to the appreciation of what might be termed culturallandscapes—environments that constitute important places in the cultures and histories of particulargroups of people. What is often called a sense of place, together with ideas and images from folklore,mythology, and religion, frequently plays a significant role in individuals' aesthetic experience of theirown home landscapes (Saito 1985, Sepänmaa 1993, Carlson 2000, Firth 2008).

Fruitful approaches to the aesthetic appreciation of human environments as well as to other aspects ofeveryday life also can be found in views that draw on both cognitive and non­cognitive positions. Therehave been several attempts to explicitly forge connections between the two orientations (Foster 1998,Moore 1999 2008, Berleant and Carlson 2007). Moreover, there are numerous studies that, movingbeyond the cognitive/non­cognitive distinction, inform our understanding of the appreciation of humanenvironments (Arntzen and Brady 2008, Herrington 2009), such as rural countrysides (Sepänmaa 2005,von Bonsdorff 2005, Andrews 2007, Leddy 2008) and urban cityscapes (von Bonsdorff 2002, Macauley2007) as well as more specialized environments, such as industrial sites (Saito 2004, Maskit 2007) andshopping centers (Brottman 2007, Vogel 2014). Beyond the consideration of these larger, publicenvironments, the aesthetics of everyday life becomes especially relevant. It investigates not only theaesthetic qualities of smaller, more personal environments, such as individual living spaces, for example,yards and houses (Melchionne 1998 2002, Lee 2010), but also the aesthetic dimensions of normal day­to­day experiences (Leddy 1995 2005b 1012b, Saito 2001 2007a 2012, Haapala 2005, Mandoki 2007, Irvin2008a 2008b, Maskit 2011) as well as everyday activities such as playing sports (Welsch 2005) anddining (Korsmeyer 1999). There are several collections focusing on this kind of research that yieldinsight into and encourage appreciation of almost every aspect of day to day life (von Bonsdorff andHaapala 1999, Light and Smith 2005, Yuedi and Carter 2014). However, although the various lines ofresearch are clearly very productive, the credentials of the aesthetics of everyday life as an investigationof genuine aesthetic experiences have recently been challenged and debated (Dowling 2010, Melchionne2011 2013 2014, Leddy 2012a, Naukkarinen 2013).

Nonetheless, in spite of these challenges and concerns about the aesthetics of everyday life, when it turnsto the investigation of things such as sports and food, it begins to come full circle, connectingenvironmental aesthetics back to the edges of more traditional aesthetics and to the study of clearlygenuine aesthetic experiences. By way of the aesthetics of everyday life, environmental aesthetics makescontact with the philosophy of borderline art forms, not only the “arts” of sport and cuisine, but also theart of gardening (Miller 1993, Carlson 1997, Ross 1998, Cooper 2006, Parsons 2008a) and the arts oflandscaping, architecture, and design (Stecker 1999, Carlson 2000, Parsons 2008b 2011, Forsey 2013). Inaddition, but now within the context of environmental aesthetics, traditional art forms, such as poetry andliterature (Berleant 1991 2004, Ross 1998, Sepänmaa 2004) and painting, sculpture, dance, and music(Berleant 1991 2004, Ross 1998, Mullis 2014) as well as newer forms, such as environmental art with itsspecial relevance to environmental aesthetics (Crawford 1983, Carlson 1986, Ross 1993, Brady 2007,

Page 10: Environmental Aesthetics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

9/6/2015 Environmental Aesthetics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/environmental­aesthetics/ 10/20

Brook 2007, Fisher 2007, Lintott 2007, Parsons 2008a, Simus 2008b), are explored and re­explored—both as aesthetically significant dimensions of our everyday experiences and concerning their roles inshaping aesthetic appreciation of both natural and human environments.

4.2 Environmental Aesthetics and Environmentalism

The relationships between contemporary environmentalism and the positions and ideas of environmentalaesthetics have sources in the aesthetics of nature developed in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries.As noted, early environmental movements, especially in North America, were fueled by a mode ofaesthetic appreciation shaped not only by the notion of the picturesque but also by ideas developed bythinkers such as Muir (Hargrove 1979, Callicott 1994, Wattles 2013). However, more recently therelationships between environmental aesthetics and environmentalism have been less congenial (Carlson2010). Some individuals interested in the conservation and protection of both natural and human heritageenvironments have not found in traditional aesthetics of nature the resources that they believe are neededin order to carry out an environmentalist agenda (Loftis 2003). Others investigate problems posed byenvironments with unique features, such as isolation (Parsons 2015). The problem is especially acuteconcerning environments, such as wetlands, that do not fit conventional conceptions of scenic beauty(Rolston 2000, Callicott 2003). Moreover, in line with earlier criticisms that much of the empirical workin landscape assessment and planning was focused only on scenic, picturesque environments, much ofthe historical tradition concerning the aesthetic appreciation of nature has come under attack. Variousthemes in the aesthetics of nature, such as appreciation grounded in the idea of the picturesque, have beencriticized in a number of ways: as anthropocentric (Godlovitch 1994), scenery­obsessed (Saito 1998a),trivial (Callicott 1994), subjective (Thompson 1995), and/or morally vacuous (Andrews 1998). Similarly,in agreement with the aesthetics of engagement's critique of the theory of disinterestedness, some findthat concept to be questionable from an environmental standpoint (Rolston 1998).

There are a variety of responses to these kinds of criticisms of traditional aesthetics of nature and of thenotions of disinterestedness and the picturesque. Some reassess and defend the picturesque tradition,arguing that it, as well as some other aspects of the tradition, has been misunderstood by somecontemporary aestheticians (Brook 2008, Paden 2013, Paden et al 2013). Others turn to the investigationof the too­long neglected member of the original eighteenth­century triumvirate of the beautiful, thesublime, and the picturesque, finding in the sublime new resources for approaching the aestheticappreciation of the natural world (Brady 2012 2013, Shapshay 2013). However, whatever the finalverdict about the significance of the picturesque and the sublime, the resources of non­cognitivepositions, especially the aesthetics of engagement, are taken to counter the criticisms that, due to theinfluence of ideas such as that of the picturesque, aesthetic experience of nature must be bothanthropocentric and scenery­obsessed (Rolston 1998 2002). The charge of anthropocentricity is alsoexplicitly addressed by the mystery approach, which attempts to give aesthetic appreciation of nature an“acentric” basis (Godlovitch 1994). Concerning the concept of disinterestedness, some philosophers yethold the view that some form of the theory of disinterestedness is essential, since without it the notion ofthe aesthetic itself lacks conceptual grounding (Budd 2002), while others claim that an analysis ofaesthetic experience in terms of the concept of disinterestedness helps to meet the charges that traditionalaesthetics is anthropocentric and subjective, since such an analysis supports the objectivity of aestheticjudgments (Brady 2003). Similarly, cognitive accounts also furnish replies to some of these charges.Scientific cognitivism in particular, with its focus on scientific knowledge, is claimed to help meet theworry that aesthetic appreciation of environments is of little significance in environmental conservationand preservation since aesthetic appreciation is trivial and subjective (Hettinger 2005, Parsons 2006a2008a). However, the extent to which scientific cognitivism and related views can underwrite a robustobjectivism concerning the appropriate aesthetic appreciation of nature is questioned on various grounds(Budd 2002, Hettinger 2007, Bannon 2011, Stecker 2012).

Page 11: Environmental Aesthetics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

9/6/2015 Environmental Aesthetics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/environmental­aesthetics/ 11/20

In spite of such reservations about cognitivist positions and objectivity, in light of the seeming relevanceof scientific cognitivism to environmental preservation and its stress on the importance of naturalsciences such as geology, biology, and especially ecology in aesthetic appreciation of nature, it issometimes interpreted as an “ecological aesthetic” in the tradition of Aldo Leopold, who linked thebeauty of nature to ecological integrity and stability (Callicott 1994 2003, Gobster 1995). However,although it has roots in Leopold’s thought, the explicit idea of an ecological aesthetic, or as it issometimes called, an ecoaesthetic, seems to have somewhat later origins (Meeker 1872, Koh 1988).Moreover, although the idea has a role within analytic environmental aesthetics, perhaps best filled byscientific cognitivism, it has also been adopted by some philosophers working in the continentaltradition. For example, it is claimed that although phenomenological work in “ecological aesthetics” is“still in its infancy”, the work of Husserl, Heidegger, and Merleau­Ponty is applicable to its developmentand, moreover, that the aesthetics of engagement is the first and currently the strongest “comprehensivephenomenological theory of ecological aesthetics” (Toadvine 2010). There is also more recent researchin environmental aesthetics that draws on both analytic and continental traditions (Tafalla 2011, Leddy2012b, Maskit 2014).

There is, in addition, considerable interest in environmental aesthetics in China (Chen 2015) andespecially in ecological aesthetics. The research is pursued by several Chinese aestheticians, who arelikewise influenced by work in phenomenology and have developed robust versions of ecologicalaesthetics. Although much of this work is only available in Chinese, one version accessible in Englishembraces, as the “four keystones of ecological aesthetic appreciation”, not only the centrality ofecological knowledge defended by scientific cognitivism and the rejection of the duality of humanity andthe natural world endorsed by the aesthetic of engagement, but also the over­arching value of ecosystembiodiversity and health and the continued guidance of ecological ethics (Cheng 2013a 2013b). The focuson the last two of these four “keystones” is comparable to attempts by some Western aestheticians tobring aesthetic appreciation of environments, both natural and human, in line with environmental andmoral obligations to maintain ecological health (Rolston 1995, Eaton 1997 1998, Lintott 2006, Saito2007a 2007b) and to forge strong positive links between aesthetic appreciation of nature and naturepreservation (Rolston 2002, Brady 2003, Carlson and Lintott 2007, Parsons 2008a, Lintott and Carlson2014). In this sense, ecological aesthetics speaks to the charge that traditional aesthetic appreciation ofnature is morally vacuous, although the degree to which moral considerations and appropriate aestheticappreciation of nature are importantly related remains a matter of discussion and debate (Loftis 2003,Bannon 2011, Stecker 2012).

Like the movement toward more ecologically informed aesthetic appreciation, the tradition that connectsthe aesthetic appreciation of nature with positive aesthetics has also been supported by someenvironmental philosophers (Rolston 1988, Hargrove 1989). The contention that untouched, pristinenature has only or primarily positive aesthetic qualities has been related to scientific cognitivism. Somesuggest that linking the appreciation of nature to scientific knowledge explains how positive aestheticappreciation is nurtured by a scientific worldview that increasingly interprets the natural world as havingpositive aesthetic qualities, such as order, balance, unity, and harmony (Carlson 1984). Otherphilosophers see the relationship between scientific cognitivism and positive aesthetics somewhatconversely, arguing that the latter should simply be assumed, in which case it provides support for theformer (Parsons 2002). Nonetheless, several aestheticians and environmental philosophers find positiveaesthetics generally problematic, either since it appears to undercut the possibility of the kind ofcomparative assessments thought to be necessary for environmental planning and preservation(Thompson 1995, Godlovitch 1998a) or because the idea itself seems unintuitive, obscure, and/orinadequately justified (Godlovitch 1998b, Saito 1998a, Budd 2002, Stecker 2012). Even philosopherswho are somewhat open to the idea of positive aesthetics have some reservations about its originalformulation, arguing that it depends too heavily on a now out­dated conception of ecology and/or doesnot adequately include an evolutionary understanding of nature as an essential component of its aesthetic

Page 12: Environmental Aesthetics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

9/6/2015 Environmental Aesthetics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/environmental­aesthetics/ 12/20

appreciation (Simus 2008a, Paden et al 2012). Such considerations may point to a more plausible versionof positive aesthetics.

In view of this kind of fruitful discussion both within and among the various positions represented incontemporary environmental aesthetics, perhaps the proposals most useful for promoting and supportingthe aesthetic appreciation and preservation of all kinds of environments, both natural and human, arethose that depend not simply on any one particular model or theory of aesthetic experience, but ratherattempt to constructively bring together the resources of several different positions (Nassauer 1997,Lintott 2006, Carlson 2008, Moore 2008, Cheng et al 2013). For example, there are efforts to combineelements of cognitive approaches with non­cognitive points of view, such as imagination­based accounts(Fudge 2001) or the aesthetics of engagement (Rolston 1998 2002, Saito 2007b). In addition, somethinkers explore new avenues that can be constructively related to environmental aesthetics, for instance,feminist theory (Lee 2006, Lintott 2010), social and political theory (Berleant 2005 2012, Ross 2005,Simus 2008b), philosophy of biology (Parsons and Carlson 2008), and animal treatment and protectionissues (Parsons 2007, Hettinger 2010, Semczyszyn 2013, Brady 2014a). Others explicitly pursue theapplication of theory to environmental policy and practice (Saito 2007b, Berleant 2010 2012, Parsons2010, Sepänmaa 2010, Robinson and Elliott 2011, Brady 2014b). All these contributions continue toshape the future directions of environmental aesthetics (Saito 2010, Blanc 2012, Drenthen and Keulartz2014). Such innovative, eclectic approaches may be the most successful not only in furthering a widerange of environmental goals and practices but also in fostering a deeper understanding and appreciationof the aesthetic potential of the world in which we live.

Bibliography

Andrews, M., 1989, The Search for the Picturesque, Stanford: Stanford University Press.–––, 2007, “The View from the Road and the Picturesque,” in The Aesthetics of Human Environments, A.

Berleant and A. Carlson (ed.), Peterborough: Broadview Press.Appleton, J., 1975a, The Experience of Landscape, London: John Wiley and Sons.–––, 1975b, “Landscape Evaluation: The Theoretical Vacuum,” Transactions of the Institute of British

Geographers, 66: 120–123.–––, 1982, “Pleasure and the Perception of Habitat: A Conceptual Framework,” in Environmental

Aesthetics: Essays in Interpretation, B. Sadler and A. Carlson (eds.), Victoria: University ofVictoria.

Arntzen, S. and Brady E., (ed.), 2008, Humans in the Land: The Ethics and Aesthetics of the CulturalLandscape, Oslo: Oslo Academic Press.

Bannon, B. E., 2011, “Re­Envisioning Nature: The Role of Aesthetics in Environmental Ethics,”Environmental Ethics, 33: 415–436.

Beardsley, M. C., 1958, Aesthetics: Problems in the Philosophy of Criticism, New York: Harcourt, Brace& World.

Bell, S., 1999, Landscape: Pattern, Perception and Process, London: Routledge.Berleant, A. 1978, “Aesthetic Paradigms for an Urban Ecology,” Diogenes, 103: l–28.–––, 1984, “Aesthetic Participation and the Urban Environment,” Urban Resources, 1: 37–42.–––, 1985, “Toward a Phenomenological Aesthetics of Environment,” in Descriptions, H. Silverman and

D. Idhe (ed.), Albany: SUNY Press.–––, 1986, “Cultivating an Urban Aesthetic,” Diogenes, 136: 1–18.–––, 1988, “Environment as an Aesthetic Paradigm,” Dialectics and Humanism, 15: 95–106.–––, 1991, Art and Engagement, Philadelphia: Temple University Press.–––, 1992, The Aesthetics of Environment, Philadelphia: Temple University Press.–––, 1997, Living in the Landscape: Toward an Aesthetics of Environment, Lawrence: University Press

of Kansas.

Page 13: Environmental Aesthetics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

9/6/2015 Environmental Aesthetics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/environmental­aesthetics/ 13/20

–––, 2004, Re­thinking Aesthetics: Rogue Essays on Aesthetics and the Arts, Aldershot: Ashgate.–––, 2005, Aesthetics and Environment: Variations on a Theme, Aldershot: Ashgate.–––, 2010, Sensibility and Sense: The Aesthetic Transformation of the Human World, Exeter: Imprint

Academic.–––, 2012, Aesthetics Beyond the Arts: New and Recent Essays, Aldershot: Ashgate.–––, 2013, “What is Aesthetic Engagement?” Contemporary Aesthetics, 11, [available online].––– and Carlson, A., (ed.), 2007, The Aesthetics of Human Environments, Peterborough: Broadview

Press.Biese, A., 1905, The Development of the Feeling for Nature in the Middle Ages and Modern Times, New

York: Burt Franklin.Blanc, N., 2012, “From Environmental Aesthetics to Narratives of Change,” Contemporary Aesthetics,

10, [available online].–––, 2013, “Aesthetic Engagement in the City,” Contemporary Aesthetics, 11, [available online].Bourassa, S. C., 1991, The Aesthetics of Landscape, London: Belhaven.Brady, E., 1998, “Imagination and the Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art

Criticism, 56: 139–147.–––, 2003, Aesthetics of the Natural Environment, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.–––, 2006, “The Aesthetics of Agricultural Landscapes and the Relationship between Humans and

Nature,” Ethics, Place and Environment, 9: 1–19.–––, 2007, “Aesthetic Regard for Nature in Environmental and Land Art,” Ethics, Place and

Environment, 10: 287–300.–––, 2012, “Reassessing Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature in the Kantian Sublime,” Journal of Aesthetic

Education, 46: 91–109.–––, 2013, The Sublime in Modern Philosophy: Aesthetics, Ethics, and Nature, Cambridge: Cambridge

University Press.–––, 2014a, “Aesthetic Value and Wild Animals,” in Environmental Aesthetics: Crossing Divides and

Breaking Ground, M. Drenthen and J. Keulartz, (ed.), New York: Fordham University Press.–––, 2014b, “Aesthetic Value, Ethics, and Climate Change,” Environmental Values, 23: 551–570.Brook, I., 2007, “Aesthetic Aspects of Unauthorised Environmental Interventions,” Ethics, Place and

Environment, 10: 307–318.–––, 2008, “Wilderness in the English Garden Tradition: A Reassessment of the Picturesque from

Environmental Philosophy,” Ethics and the Environment, 13: 105–119.Brottman, M., 2007, “The Last Stop of Desire: The Aesthetics of the Shopping Center,” in The Aesthetics

of Human Environments, A. Berleant and A. Carlson (ed.), Peterborough: Broadview Press.Budd, M., 2002, The Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Callicott, J. B., 1994, “The Land Aesthetic,” in Ecological Prospects: Scientific, Religious, and Aesthetic

Perspectives, C. K. Chapple (ed.), Albany: SUNY Press.–––, 2003, “Wetland Gloom and Wetland Glory,” Philosophy and Geography, 6: 33–45.Carlson, A., 1976, “Environmental Aesthetics and the Dilemma of Aesthetic Education,” Journal of

Aesthetic Education, 10: 69–82.–––, 1977, “On the Possibility of Quantifying Scenic Beauty,” Landscape Planning, 4: 131–172.–––, 1979, “Appreciation and the Natural Environment,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 37:

267–276.–––, 1981, “Nature, Aesthetic Judgment, and Objectivity,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 40:

15–27.–––, 1984, “Nature and Positive Aesthetics,” Environmental Ethics, 6: 5–34.–––, 1985, “On Appreciating Agricultural Landscapes,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 43:

301–312.–––, 1986, “Is Environmental Art an Aesthetic Affront to Nature?” Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 16:

635–650.

Page 14: Environmental Aesthetics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

9/6/2015 Environmental Aesthetics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/environmental­aesthetics/ 14/20

–––, 1997, “On the Aesthetic Appreciation of Japanese Gardens,” British Journal of Aesthetics, 37: 47–56.

–––, 2000, Aesthetics and the Environment: The Appreciation of Nature, Art and Architecture, London:Routledge.

–––, 2001, “On Aesthetically Appreciating Human Environments,” Philosophy and Geography, 4: 9–24.–––, 2007, “The Requirements for an Adequate Aesthetics of Nature,” Environmental Philosophy, 4: 1–

12.–––, 2008, Nature and Landscape: An Introduction to Environmental Aesthetics, New York: Columbia

University Press.–––, 2010, “Contemporary Environmental Aesthetics and the Requirements of Environmentalism,”

Environmental Values, 19: 289–314.––– and Berleant, A., (ed.), 2004, The Aesthetics of Natural Environments, Peterborough: Broadview

Press.––– and Lintott, S., (ed.), 2007, Nature, Aesthetics, and Environmentalism: From Beauty to Duty, New

York: Columbia University Press.Carroll, N., 1993, “On Being Moved By Nature: Between Religion and Natural History,” in Landscape,

Natural Beauty and the Arts, S. Kemal and I. Gaskell (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge UniversityPress.

Cats­Baril, W. L. and Gibson, L., 1986, “Evaluating Aesthetics: The Major Issues and a Bibliography,”Landscape Journal, 5: 93–102.

Chen, W., 2015, Chinese Environmental Aesthetics, F. Su (trans.), G. Cipriani (ed.), London: Routledge.Cheng, X., 2013a, “Environmental Aesthetics and Ecological Aesthetics: Connections and Differences,”

in X. Cheng, A., Berleant, P. Gobster, and X. Wang, Ecological Aesthetics and EcologicalAssessment and Planning, Zhengzhou: Henan People’s Press.

–––, 2013b, “On the Four Keystones of Ecological Aesthetic Appreciation,” in East Asian Ecocriticisms:A Critical Reader, S. C. Estok and W. Kim (ed.), New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

–––, Berleant, A., Gobster, P., and Wang, X., 2013. Ecological Aesthetics and Ecological Assessmentand Planning, Zhengzhou: Henan People’s Press.

Conron, J., 2000, American Picturesque, University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press.Cooper, D., 2006, A Philosophy of Gardens, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Crawford, D., 1983, “Nature and Art: Some Dialectical Relationships,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art

Criticism, 62: 49–58.–––, 2004, “Scenery and the Aesthetics of Nature,” in The Aesthetics of Natural Environments, A.

Carlson and A. Berleant (ed.), Peterborough: Broadview Press.Daniel, T. C., 2001, “Whither Scenic Beauty? Visual Landscape Quality Assessment in the 21st

Century,” Landscape and Urban Planning, 54: 276–281.Dickie, G., 1974, Art and the Aesthetic: An Institutional Analysis, Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Dowling, C., 2010, “The Aesthetics of Daily Life,” British Journal of Aesthetics, 50: 225–242.Drenthen, M. and Keulartz, J., (ed.), 2014, Environmental Aesthetics: Crossing Divides and Breaking

Ground, New York: Fordham University Press.Eaton, M. M., 1997, “The Beauty that Requires Health,” in Placing Nature: Culture and Landscape

Ecology, J. I. Nassauer (ed.), Washington, D.C.: Island Press.–––, 1998, “Fact and Fiction in the Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art

Criticism, 56: 149–156.Firth, D., 2008, “The Role of Aesthetic Considerations in a Narrative Based Approach to Nature

Conservation,” Ethics and the Environment, 13: 77–100.Fisher, J. A., 1998, “What the Hills Are Alive With: In Defense of the Sounds of Nature,” Journal of

Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 56: 167–179.–––, 2007, “Performing Nature,” Environmental Philosophy, 4: 15–28.Forsey, J., 2013, The Aesthetics of Design, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Page 15: Environmental Aesthetics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

9/6/2015 Environmental Aesthetics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/environmental­aesthetics/ 15/20

Foster, C., 1998, “The Narrative and the Ambient in Environmental Aesthetics,” Journal of Aestheticsand Art Criticism, 56: 127–137,

Fudge, R., 2001, “Imagination and the Science­based Aesthetic Appreciation of Unscenic Nature,”Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 59: 275–285.

Gobster, P. H., 1995, “Aldo Leopold's Ecological Esthetic: Integrating Esthetic and Biodiversity Values,”Journal of Forestry, 93: 6–10.

–––, 2008, “Yellowstone Hotspot: Reflections on Scenic Beauty, Ecology, and the Aesthetic Experienceof Landscape,” Landscape Journal, 27: 291–308.

–––, 2013, “Ecological Aesthetics and Landscape Perception and Assessment,” in X. Cheng, A.,Berleant, P. Gobster, and X. Wang, Ecological Aesthetics and Ecological Assessment and Planning,Zhengzhou: Henan People’s Press.

–––, Nassauer, J. I., Daniel, T. C., and Fry, G., 2007, “The Shared Landscape: What does Aesthetics haveto do with Ecology?” Landscape Ecology, 22: 959–972.

Godlovitch, S., 1994, “Icebreakers: Environmentalism and Natural Aesthetics,” Journal of AppliedPhilosophy, 11: 15–30.

–––, 1998a, “Evaluating Nature Aesthetically,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 56: 113–125.–––, 1998b, “Valuing Nature and the Autonomy of Natural Aesthetics,” British Journal of Aesthetics, 38:

180–197.Haapala, A., (ed.), 1998, The City as Cultural Metaphor: Studies in Urban Aesthetics, Lahti:

International Institute of Applied Aesthetics.–––, 2005, “On the Aesthetics of the Everyday: Familiarity, Strangeness, and the Meaning of Place,” in

The Aesthetics of Everyday Life, A. Light and J. M. Smith (ed.), New York: Columbia UniversityPress.

Hargrove, E. C., 1979, “The Historical Foundations of American Environmental Attitudes,”Environmental Ethics, 1: 209–240.

–––, 1989, Foundations of Environmental Ethics, Englewood Cliffs: Prentice Hall.Hepburn, R. W., 1966, “Contemporary Aesthetics and the Neglect of Natural Beauty,” in British

Analytical Philosophy, B. Williams and A. Montefiore (ed.), London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.–––, 1996, “Landscape and the Metaphysical Imagination,” Environmental Values, 5: 191–204.Herrington, S., 2009, On Landscapes, London: Routledge.Hettinger, N., 2005, “Carlson's Environmental Aesthetics and the Protection of the Environment,”

Environmental Ethics, 27: 57–76.–––, 2007, “Objectivity in Environmental Aesthetics and Protection of the Environment,” in Nature,

Aesthetics, and Environmentalism: From Beauty to Duty, A. Carlson and S. Lintott (ed.), NewYork: Columbia University Press.

–––, 2010, “Animal Beauty, Ethics, and Environmental Preservation,” Environmental Ethics, 32: 115–134.

Heyd, T., 2001, “Aesthetic Appreciation and the Many Stories about Nature,” British Journal ofAesthetics, 41: 125–137.

Hill, D. and Daniel, T. C., 2008, “Foundations for an Ecological Aesthetic: Can Information AlterLandscape Preferences?” Society and Natural Resources, 21: 34–49.

Irvin, S., 2008a, “The Pervasiveness of the Aesthetic in Everyday Experience,” British Journal ofAesthetics, 48: 486–500.

–––, 2008b, “Scratching an Itch,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 66: 25–35.Kaplan, R. and Kaplan, S., 1989, The Experience of Nature: A Psychological Perspective, Cambridge:

Cambridge University Press.Koh, J., 1988, “An Ecological Aesthetic,” Landscape Journal, 7: 177–191.Korsmeyer, C., 1999, Making Sense of Taste: Food and Philosophy, Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Leddy, T., 1995, “Everyday Surface Qualities: ‘Neat’, ‘Messy’, ‘Clean’, ‘Dirty’,” Journal of Aesthetics

and Art Criticism, 53: 259–268.

Page 16: Environmental Aesthetics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

9/6/2015 Environmental Aesthetics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/environmental­aesthetics/ 16/20

–––, 2005a, “A Defense of Arts­Based Appreciation of Nature,” Environmental Ethics, 27: 299–315.–––, 2005b, “The Nature of Everyday Aesthetics,” in The Aesthetics of Everyday Life, A. Light and J. M.

Smith (ed.), New York: Columbia University Press.–––, 2008, “The Aesthetics of Junkyards and Roadside Clutter,” Contemporary Aesthetics, 6, [available

online].–––, 2012a, “Defending Everyday Aesthetics and the Concept of ‘Pretty’,” Contemporary Aesthetics, 10,

[available online].–––, 2012b, The Extraordinary in the Ordinary: The Aesthetics of Everyday Life, Peterborough:

Broadview.Lee, J. J., 2010, “Home Life: Cultivating a Domestic Aesthetic,” Contemporary Aesthetics, 8, [available

online].Lee, W. L., 2006, “On Ecology and Aesthetic Experience: A Feminist Theory of Value and Praxis,”

Ethics and the Environment, 11: 21–41.Light, A. and Smith, J. M., (ed.), 2005, The Aesthetics of Everyday Life, New York: Columbia University

Press.Lintott, S., 2006, “Toward Eco­Friendly Aesthetics,” Environmental Ethics, 28: 57–76.–––, 2007, “Ethically Evaluating Land Art: Is It Worth It?” Ethics, Place and Environment, 10: 263–277.–––, 2010, “Feminist Aesthetics and the Neglect of Natural Beauty,” Environmental Values, 19: 315–

333.––– and Carlson, A., 2014, “The Link between Aesthetic Appreciation and the Preservation Imperative,”

in Linking Ecology and Ethics for a Changing World: Values, Philosophy, and Action, R. Rozzi, S.T. A. Pickett, C. Palmer, J. J. Armesto, and J. B. Callicott, (ed.), New York/Heidelberg: Springer.

Loftis, R. J., 2003, “Three Problems for the Aesthetic Foundations of Environmental Ethics,” Philosophyin the Contemporary World, 10: 41–50.

Macauley, D., 2007, “Walking the City,” in The Aesthetics of Human Environments, A. Berleant and A.Carlson (ed.), Peterborough: Broadview Press.

Mandoki, K., 2007, Everyday Aesthetics: Prosaics, the Play of Culture and Social Identities, Aldershot:Ashgate.

Mannison, D., 1980, “A Prolegomenon to a Human Chauvinistic Aesthetic,” in EnvironmentalPhilosophy, D. Mannison, M. McRobbie, and R. Routley (ed.), Canberra: Australian NationalUniversity.

Marsh, G. P., 1865, Man and Nature; or Physical Geography as Modified by Human Action, New York:Charles Scribner.

Maskit, J., 2007, “‘Line of Wreckage’: Toward a Postindustrial Environmental Aesthetics,” Ethics, Placeand Environment, 10: 323–337.

–––, 2011, “The Aesthetics of Elsewhere: An Environmentalist Everyday Aesthetics,” AestheticPathways, 1: 92–107.

–––, 2014, “On Universalism and Cultural Historicism in Environmental Aesthetics,” in EnvironmentalAesthetics: Crossing Divides and Breaking Ground, M. Drenthen and J. Keulartz, (ed.), New York:Fordham University Press.

Matthews, P., 2002, “Scientific Knowledge and the Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature,” Journal ofAesthetics and Art Criticism, 60: 37–48.

Meeker, J., 1972, “Notes Toward an Ecological Esthetic,” Canadian Fiction Magazine, 2: 4–15.Melchionne, K., 1998, “Living in Glass Houses: Domesticity, Interior Decoration, and Environmental

Aesthetics,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 56: 191–200.–––, 2002, “Front Yards,” in Environment and the Arts: Perspectives on Environmental Aesthetics, A.

Berleant (ed.), Aldershot: Ashgate.–––, 2011, “Aesthetic Experience in Everyday Life: A Reply to Dowling,” British Journal of Aesthetics,

51: 437–442.–––, 2013, “The Definition of Everyday Aesthetics,” Contemporary Aesthetics, 11, [available online].

Page 17: Environmental Aesthetics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

9/6/2015 Environmental Aesthetics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/environmental­aesthetics/ 17/20

–––, 2014, “The Point of Everyday Aesthetics,” Contemporary Aesthetics, 12, [available online].Miller, M., 1993, The Garden As Art, Albany: SUNY Press.Moore, R., 1999, “Appreciating Natural Beauty as Natural,” Journal of Aesthetic Education, 33: 42–59.–––, 2006, “The Framing Paradox,” Ethics, Place and Environment, 9: 249–267.–––, 2008, Natural Beauty: A Theory of Aesthetics Beyond the Arts, Peterborough: Broadview Press.Muir, J., 1894, “A View of the High Sierra,” in The Mountains of California, New York: The Century

Company.Mullis, E. C., 2014, “Fitness for Function and Dance Aesthetics,” Contemporary Aesthetics, 12,

[available online].Nasar, J. L., (ed.), 1988, Environmental Aesthetics: Theory, Research, and Applications, Cambridge:

Cambridge University Press.Nassauer, J. I., 1997, “Cultural Sustainability: Aligning Aesthetics and Ecology,” in Placing Nature:

Culture and Landscape Ecology, J. I. Nassauer (ed.), Washington, D.C.: Island Press.Naukkarinen, O., 2013, “What is ‘Everyday’ in Everyday Aesthetics?” Contemporary Aesthetics, 11,

[available online].Nicolson, M. H., 1959, Mountain Gloom and Mountain Glory, Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Orians, G. H. and Heerwagen J. H., 1986, “An Ecological and Evolutionary Approach to Landscape

Aesthetics,” in Landscape Meanings and Values, E. C. Penning­Rowsell and D. Lowenthal (ed.),London: Allen and Unwin.

–––, 1992, “Evolved Responses to Landscapes,” in The Adapted Mind: Evolutionary Psychology and theGeneration of Culture, J. Barkow, L. Cosmides, and J. Tooby (ed.), New York: Oxford UniversityPress.

Paden, R., 2013. “A Defense of the Picturesque,” Environmental Philosophy, 10: 1–21.Paden, R., Harmon, L. K., and Milling, C. R., 2012, “Ecology, Evolution, and Aesthetics: Towards an

Evolutionary Aesthetics of Nature,” British Journal of Aesthetics, 52: 124–139.–––, 2013, “Philosophical Histories of the Aesthetics of Nature,” Environmental Ethics, 35: 57–77.Paetzold, H., 2013, “The Aesthetics of City Strolling,” Contemporary Aesthetics, 11, [available online].Parsons, G., 2002, “Nature Appreciation, Science, and Positive Aesthetics,” British Journal of Aesthetics,

42: 279–295.–––, 2004, “Natural Functions and the Aesthetic Appreciation of Inorganic Nature,” British Journal of

Aesthetics, 44: 44–56.–––, 2006a, “Freedom and Objectivity in the Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature,” British Journal of

Aesthetics, 46: 17–37.–––, 2006b, “Theory, Observation, and the Role of Scientific Understanding in the Aesthetic

Appreciation of Nature,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 36: 165–186.–––, 2007, “The Aesthetic Value of Animals,” Environmental Ethics, 29: 151–169.–––, 2008a, Aesthetics and Nature, London: Continuum Press.–––, 2008b, “Nature, Aesthetic Values and Urban Design: Building the Natural City,” in Philosophy and

Design: From Engineering to Architecture, P. Vermaas, P. Kroes, and A. Light (ed.), NewYork/Heidelberg: Springer.

–––, 2010, “Beauty and Public Policy,” People and Places, London: The Commission for Architectureand the Built Environment, [available online].

–––, 2011, “Fact and Function in Architectural Criticism,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 69:21–30.

–––, 2015, “Why Should We Save Nature's Hidden Gems?” Journal of Applied Philosophy, 32(1): 98–110.

––– and Carlson, A. 2004, “New Formalism and the Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature,” Journal ofAesthetics and Art Criticism, 62: 363–376.

–––, 2008, Functional Beauty, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Parsons, R. and Daniel T. C., 2002, “Good Looking: In Defense of Scenic Landscape Aesthetics,”

Page 18: Environmental Aesthetics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

9/6/2015 Environmental Aesthetics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/environmental­aesthetics/ 18/20

Landscape and Urban Planning, 60: 43–56.Porteous, D. J., 1996, Environmental Aesthetics: Ideas, Politics and Planning, London: Routledge.Robinson, K. W. and Elliott, K. C., 2011, “Environmental Aesthetics and Public Environmental

Philosophy,” Ethics, Policy and Environment, 14: 175–191.Rolston, H., 1988, Environmental Ethics: Duties to and Values in the Natural World, Philadelphia:

Temple University Press.–––, 1995, “Does Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature Need to be Science Based?” British Journal of

Aesthetics, 35: 374–386.–––, 1998, “Aesthetic Experience in Forests,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 56: 157–166.–––, 2000, “Aesthetics in the Swamps,” Perspectives in Biology and Medicine, 43: 584–597.–––, 2002, “From Beauty to Duty: Aesthetics of Nature and Environmental Ethics,” in Environment and

the Arts: Perspectives on Environmental Aesthetics, A. Berleant, (ed.), Aldershot: Ashgate.Ross, S., 1993, “Gardens, Earthworks, and Environmental Art,” in Landscape, Natural Beauty and the

Arts, S. Kemal and I. Gaskell (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.–––, 1998, What Gardens Mean, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.–––, 2005, “Landscape Perception: Theory­Laden, Emotionally Resonant, Politically Correct,”

Environmental Ethics, 27: 245–263.Saarinen, T. F., Seamon, D., and Sell, J. L., (ed.), 1984, Environmental Perception and Behavior: An

Inventory and Prospect, Chicago: Department of Geography, University of Chicago.Sagoff, M., 1974, “On Preserving the Natural Environment,” Yale Law Journal, 84: 205–267.Saito, Y., 1985, “The Japanese Appreciation of Nature,” British Journal of Aesthetics, 25: 239–251.–––, 1998a, “The Aesthetics of Unscenic Nature,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 56: 101–111.–––, 1998b, “Appreciating Nature on its Own Terms,” Environmental Ethics, 20: 135–149.–––, 2001, “Everyday Aesthetics,” Philosophy and Literature, 25: 87–95.–––, 2004, “Machines in the Ocean: The Aesthetics of Wind Farms,” Contemporary Aesthetics, 2,

[available online].–––, 2007a, Everyday Aesthetics, Oxford: Oxford University Press.–––, 2007b, “The Role of Aesthetics in Civic Environmentalism,” in The Aesthetics of Human

Environments, A. Berleant and A. Carlson (ed.), Peterborough: Broadview Press.–––, 2010, “Future Directions for Environmental Aesthetics,” Environmental Values, 19: 373–391.–––, 2012, “Everyday Aesthetics and Artification,” in Contemporary Aesthetics, 4 [available online].Semczyszyn, N., 2013, “Public Aquariums and Marine Aesthetics,” Contemporary Aesthetics, 11,

[available online].Sepänmaa, Y., 1993, The Beauty of Environment: A General Model for Environmental Aesthetics,

Second Edition, Denton: Environmental Ethics Books.–––, 2004, “Environmental Stories: Speaking and Writing Nature,” in The Aesthetics of Natural

Environments, A. Carlson and A. Berleant (ed.), Peterborough: Broadview Press.–––, 2005, “The Aesthetics of the Road, Road Art, and Road Traffic,” Contemporary Aesthetics, 1,

[available online].–––, 2010, “From Theoretical to Applied Environmental Aesthetics: Academic Aesthetics Meets Real­

World Demands,” Environmental Values, 19: 393–405.Shapshay, S. 2013, “Contemporary Environmental Aesthetics and the Neglect of the Sublime,” British

Journal of Aesthetics, 53: 181–198.Sheppard, S. and Harshaw, H., (ed.), 2001, Forests and Landscapes: Linking Ecology, Sustainability and

Aesthetics, New York: CAB International Publishers.Simus, J. B., 2008a, “Aesthetic Implications of the New Paradigm in Ecology,” Journal of Aesthetic

Education, 42: 63–79.–––, 2008b, “Environmental Art and Ecological Citizenship,” Environmental Ethics, 30: 21–36.Sparshott, F., 1972, “Figuring the Ground: Notes on some Theoretical Problems of the Aesthetic

Environment,” Journal of Aesthetic Education, 6: 11–23.

Page 19: Environmental Aesthetics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

9/6/2015 Environmental Aesthetics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/environmental­aesthetics/ 19/20

Stecker, R., 1997, “The Correct and the Appropriate in the Appreciation of Nature,” British Journal ofAesthetics, 37: 393–402.

–––, 1999, “Reflections on Architecture: Buildings as Artworks, Aesthetic Objects, and ArtificialEnvironments,” in Architecture and Civilization, M. Mitias (ed.), Amsterdam: Rodopi.

–––, 2012, “Epistemic Norms, Moral Norms, and Nature Appreciation,” Environmental Ethics, 34: 247–264.

Stolnitz, J., 1961, “Of the Origins of ‘Aesthetic Disinterestedness’,” Journal of Aesthetics and ArtCriticism, 20: 131–143.

Tafalla, M., 2011, “Rehabilitating the Aesthetics of Nature: Hepburn and Adorno,” EnvironmentalEthics, 33: 45–56.

Thompson, J., 1995, “Aesthetics and the Value of Nature,” Environmental Ethics, 17: 291–305.Toadvine, T., 2010, “Ecological Aesthetics,” in Handbook of Phenomenological Aesthetics, H. R. Sepp

and L. Embree (ed.), New York/Heidelberg: Springer.Vogel, S., 2014, “Thinking Like a Mall,” in Environmental Aesthetics: Crossing Divides and Breaking

Ground, M. Drenthen and J. Keulartz, (ed.), New York: Fordham University Press.von Bonsdorff, P., 2002, “Urban Richness and the Art of Building,” in Environment and the Arts:

Perspectives on Environmental Aesthetics, A Berleant (ed.), Aldershot: Ashgate.–––, 2005, “Agriculture, Aesthetic Appreciation and the Worlds of Nature,” Contemporary Aesthetics, 3,

[available online].––– and Haapala, A., (ed.), 1999, Aesthetics in the Human Environment, Lahti: International Institute of

Applied Aesthetics.Walton, K., 1970, “Categories of Art,” Philosophical Review, 79: 334–367.Wattles, J., 2013, “John Muir as a Guide to Education in Environmental Aesthetics,” Journal of Aesthetic

Education, 47: 56–71.Welsch, W., 2005, “Sport Viewed Aesthetically, or Even as Art,” in The Aesthetics of Everyday Life, A.

Light and J. M. Smith (ed.), New York: Columbia University Press.Yuedi, L. and Carter, C. L., (ed.), 2014, Aesthetics of Everyday Life: West and East, Newcastle upon

Tyne: Cambridge Scholars Publishing.Zangwill, N., 2001, “Formal Natural Beauty,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 101: 209–224.–––, 2013, “Clouds of Illusion in the Aesthetics of Nature,” Philosophical Quarterly, 63: 576–596.Ziff, P., 1979, “Anything Viewed,” in Essays in Honour of Jaakko Hintikka On the Occasion of His

Fiftieth Birthday on January 12, 1979, E. Saarinen, R. Hilpinen, I. Niiniluoto, and M. Hintikka(ed.), Dordrecht: Reidel.

Zube, E. H., 1984, “Themes in Landscape Assessment Theory,” Landscape Journal, 3: 104–110.

Academic Tools

How to cite this entry.Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP Society.Look up this entry topic at the Indiana Philosophy Ontology Project (InPhO).Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers, with links to its database.

Other Internet Resources

Aesthetics on­line, maintained by the American Society for Aesthetics.Teaching Environmental Aesthetics, by Allen Carlson, at the Aesthetics on­line website

Page 20: Environmental Aesthetics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

9/6/2015 Environmental Aesthetics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/environmental­aesthetics/ 20/20

Related Entries

aesthetic, concept of the | aesthetics: British, in the 18th century | Dewey, John: aesthetics | ethics:environmental

Copyright © 2015 by Allen Carlson <[email protected]>

Open access to the SEP is made possible by a world­wide funding initiative.Please Read How You Can Help Keep the Encyclopedia Free

The SEP would like to congratulate the National Endowment for the Humanities on its 50th anniversaryand express our indebtedness for the five generous grants it awarded our project from 1997 to 2007.

Readers who have benefited from the SEP are encouraged to examine the NEH’s anniversary page and, ifinspired to do so, send a testimonial to [email protected].

The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy is copyright © 2014 by The Metaphysics Research Lab, Centerfor the Study of Language and Information (CSLI), Stanford University

Library of Congress Catalog Data: ISSN 1095­5054