allen, james_experience as a source and ground of theory in epicureanism_apeiron, 37, 4_2004!89!106

Upload: the-gathering

Post on 01-Jun-2018

215 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/9/2019 Allen, James_Experience as a Source and Ground of Theory in Epicureanism_Apeiron, 37, 4_2004!89!106

    1/18

  • 8/9/2019 Allen, James_Experience as a Source and Ground of Theory in Epicureanism_Apeiron, 37, 4_2004!89!106

    2/18

    90  James

      llen

    The Epicureans also defended theories  about  the  nonevident causes of

    astronomical phenomena  like  eclipses  and much else besides.  And  they

    achieved these

     results,

     or claimed to achieve them, by  rationalist means:

    inference

      or

      demonstration

      from

      signs

      or

      evidence furnished

      by the

    phenomena. By  these  measures,  Epicureanism is a  form   of rationalism.

    The aim of this paper  is to compare  Epicurean views about experience

    to other views

     available

     in the  Hellenistic period, including those  of the

    medical Empiricists.

     In

     this

     way I

     hope

     to

     throw light

     on the

     Epicureans

    distinctive attitude towards experience, an attitude whose

     af f in i t ies

     with

    empiricism sets Epicureanism apart  f rom   more  orthodox forms

     of ra-

    tionalism but permits  the  Epicureans  to base  on experience theories

      that

    orthodox empiricists would

      reject

     as

     unsupported

      by

     experience.

    Talk

     of

      experience

    involves a certain amount  of

     unclarity.

     The  word has

    several

     senses,

     whose history would make  an interesting study  in its own

    right. Present-day discussions

     of

     what

     is

     given

     in

     immediate experience,

    where this means something

      like

     bare sensation prior to interpretation

    or inference,  or about  the  quality  of conscious experience,  use the  term

    in a way that would,  I  think, have been  new to ancient Greek  and  Latin

    speakers  fami l ia r with  the  words experientia or

      empeiria.

    Clues that will help us  understand   the  ancient conception  of experi-

    ence  are   furnished   by the  medical Empiricists reflections about their

    terminology.

     Galen s

     Outline

     o f

     Empiricism

      Subfiguratio

      empirica;

     hence-

    forward  Subfig  emp), which

     is

     meant

     to be a  fa i thful

      presentation

      of the

    Empiricists own views, makes a point about one term in the Empiricist

    vocabulary

     that

     is

     also true

     of

     others. Though

      the

      term autopsia , seeing

    or observing   for oneself, ought

      strictly

      to be  applied  to an  activity,  he

    tells

     us, it was

     also  used

     by the

     Empiricists

     for

     knowledge, namely

     the

    knowledge

      one has as a

      result

     of

     observing

      for

     oneself  Subfig  emp

     47,

    14-26). The Empiricists used two terms that are traditionally translated

    as

      experience ,  peira

     and

      empeiria.

     The

     Outline

     o f

      Empiricism  defines them

    not as

      activities,

     but as

     psychic states

      or

      f o rm s

      of

     knowledge

      notitia:

    ãíþóéò).

      Peira

      is autoptic

      knowledge ,

     i.e., the knowledge one has as a

    result of an episode  of observation  (44,6  ff. .  Empeiria, on the  other hand,

    is

     knowledge or memory of what has been observed to  happen  many

    times in the  same  way   Subfig  emp 45,24;

     50,23).

     The mention  of memory

    is

     significant because the Empiricists seem to have held that knowledge

    Brought to you by | UNAM

    Authenticated

    Download Date | 2 23 15 10:23 PM

  • 8/9/2019 Allen, James_Experience as a Source and Ground of Theory in Epicureanism_Apeiron, 37, 4_2004!89!106

    3/18

    Experience

      as a

     Source  91

    was a form of

      memory

      (Galen,  On  Therapeutic Method;

     henceforward

    Meth

      med X 36, 3 K hn = fr. 46 Deichgr ber), but  that is another  story.

    1

    According

      to

     these definitions, then,

     em peiria  is a

     kind

     of

     knowledge

    that

     arises

     on the

     basis

     of

     many episodes

      of

     observation, each

     of

     which

    gives rise  to an  instance  of peira. One has  empeiria  as opposed  to  peira

    when

     one has

     observed something

     often

     enough

     for the

     knowledge that

    one now has as a

     result

     to be

     expressed

      in a

     theorem

      Subfig

      em p

     45, 24

    ff . ) .  And  this  is the case when one is in a position  to say, e.g., that  the

    administration  of such and  such a remedy in cases  of such and  such a

    kind

     is

     followed

     by

     recovery always,

     for the

     most part, roughly half

      the

    time

     or

      rarely.

     In

      this  favored

      sense,

     em peiria  applies

     to

     expert knowl-

    edge,

      many instances

      of

     which, when they

      form

      a

     cluster (Üèñïéóìá),

    make up a

     complete expertise

     or art

      On

     Sects for

      Beginners; henceforward

    Sect

      ingred  SM

      ÉÐ,  13-16 Helmreich).

      And in

     what

     is

     perhaps

      the

      most

    privileged  sense of all,  the  term

      empeiria

      applies  to the art as a  whole

     Subfig  emp 47, 26; 54,  10-13). This means   that  the  contrast  between

    experience  and  reason  is  indirect. Experience  as  knowledge  and the

    activities that give rise to it are opposed  to the activities of the

     faculty

     of

    reason

      (or a

     special

      form

      of it) and the

     knowledge

      to

     which they give

    rise, and

      reason

      as a

     faculty

     is

     opposed

     to the

     faculty

     or

     faculties which

    are

      responsible

      for

     experience (cf. Subfig

      emp

     86,23-87,12).

    In  Empiricist usage, however,

      the

     words

      for

     experience

      are not re-

    stricted to these meanings any more than  autopsia  is restricted to its

    official  meaning.  Empeiria, in  particular, is  often  used  in place of peira,

    and

     both

     are

     frequently used

     for the

     activities

     of

     perception

      and

      obser-

    vation that give rise to

     peira

     and

      empeiria

     in the

     sense

     of knowledge, just

    as activity words like

      autopsy

    and

      Observation

    ôÞñçóéò)

      are some-

    times used of the knowledge to which the activities give rise  Subfig  emp

    47,26-48,4;

     48,11-21).

    2

     Nevertheless,

     the

     distinctions that

     we

     have seen

    are available make it easier to characterize ancient empiricism. Art or

    expertise

      is

      experience  empeiria)

      and

      experience, both

      in the

      sense

     of

    empeiria

     and  that

     of

      peira, has its source in the activities  of perception  and

    observation. This knowledge is confined to what can be perceived or

    observed, items which are called phenomena, evident matters  or percep-

    tibles by the Empiricists. One can, however, supplement   the experience

    1 On this poin t see

     Frede,

     1990.

    2 ðåßñá

     for

      å ì ð åéñß á [Galen], On the best

      sect,

     1131,

     8-9

     K

      hn = fr. 51 Deichgr ber.

    rought to you by | UNAM

    Authenticated

    Download Date | 2 23 15 10:23 PM

  • 8/9/2019 Allen, James_Experience as a Source and Ground of Theory in Epicureanism_Apeiron, 37, 4_2004!89!106

    4/18

    92  James  llen

    one has as a   result  of one s  own  observation w i th  history

      É ó ô ï ñ ß á )

     —

    w hat one

     learns

     by

     reading

      and

      evaluating

     the

     reports

     of

     other people,

    which

      is

      ultimately based

      on

      their

      own

      observations

      Subf ig  emp  47,

    14-26).

    II

    It

     should

     be

     plain that

     a

     rather generous conception

     of

     experience, both

    in

      the

     sense

     of the

      activities

     of

     perception

      and

      observation

      and in the

    sense

     of the knowledge they yield,  is  presupposed.  The phenomena  or

    evident matters that are perceived   or observed  are  things like people,

    animals,  mountains

      or

      trees

      as

      well

      as

      certain states, qualities

      and

    activities o f theirs like being green   or running  or having a  fever.  Ques-

    tions about how   observation conceived   in this way is ultimately based

    on  what modem philosophers

      call

     immediate experience  or bare sensa-

    tion receive little attention. Instead the

     focus

     is on how  expert knowledge

    complete

      and

     systematic enough

      to

     qualify

      as an

     art, e.g.,

     o f

      medicine,

    can

      arise

      out of

     observation

      or

      experience

      of

      people, their activities,

    habits, diets, environments, symptoms and the like. Nonetheless, gener-

    ous as this conception  of experience  is, it restricts experience to  knowl-

    edge

      that

      certain patterns

      o f

      sequence

      an d

      correlation among

    phenomena obtain.

     T he

     causes which would  explain

      wh y the

      patterns

    occur  and  recur as  they  do can be  grasped,  if at all, only  by  means of

    faculties other than those responsible

      for

     experience.

    The

     idea that

     it is

     only

     facts

      that

     which

     are

     accessible

     to

     experience

      is

    behind a way in  which  we use the  term   empirical ,  e.g., when  we  speak

    of

     an

      empirical

     question .  Our

     point when speaking

     in

     this

     way is

     less

    that the question  has been  or is likely to be resolved  by experience than

    that, because  the  truth  at  issue  is not  determined  by  laws of nature  or

    laws of reason or relations o f ideas or the like — and therefore cannot  be

    known

     by

     grasping

     h ow it is

     determined

      in one of

     these privileged ways

      it is a  contingent matter  of  fact  that  can be  known,  if at  all,   by

    experience.

     B ut it is

     important

      to

     note that

     it is

     possible

      to

     grasp

      facts,

    which  are not  empirical questions  in   this sense,   as empirical truths.

    Something that

     we

     grasp

     as a

     fact  that

     on the

     basis

     of

     experience

     may be

    th e

     necessary consequence

     of the

     inalterable nature

     of

     things;

     and

      some-

    one in a   position   to   grasp   it as the   necessary consequence   of

      first

    principles will grasp

      it as

      more than

      a  fact  that.

     Aristotle s theory

      of

    knowledge, for example, depends

     on

     a contrast between grasping  a truth

    Brought to you by | UNAM

    Authenticated

    Download Date | 2 23 15 10:23 PM

  • 8/9/2019 Allen, James_Experience as a Source and Ground of Theory in Epicureanism_Apeiron, 37, 4_2004!89!106

    5/18

    Experience  as a  ource  93

    as a  fact  of  experience  and  grasping  that same truth  as  required  and

    explained

     by

      first  principles.

    The

     disagreement between rationalism

     and

      empiricism,

     as it is

     usu-

    ally

     understood, presupposes

      a

     f ramework

     of

     common assumptions that

    was

     widely if not universally shared. They emerge especially clearly, for

    instance,  in the

      account

      of the

      dif ferent  epistemic conditions

      at the

    beginning  of Aristotle s

     M etaphysics

      A l,  980a27 f f . , 981a27  f f . .

      i)

      Experience grasps only

     facts  that;

      ii)  The causes that supply the reasons w h y  these facts obtain, if they

    can be

     known

     a t

     all,

     are the

     object

     of a

     separate rational

      faculty;

      iii)

      Experience is prior to this rational faculty, whose  insights, if and

    when

     possible,  are

     nonetheless somehow based

     on

     experience.

    This

      framework

      was

      treated

      as  uncontroversial   by

     many   philoso-

    phers  and  scientists  in   antiquity, especially  in the   Hellenistic   period,

    when just about everyone seems to have been committed to an episte-

    mology  that was broadly empiricist in the

     sense

     of taking all knowledge

    to

     be

     based,

     ultimately and in the last analysis, on a grasp of the

     evident.

    The Epicureans seem to have subscribed to an especially strong form of

    this position.  Pronouncements

      of

     theirs

      to the

     effect  that

     all

     knowledge

    either

     consists

      in or

     arises

      out of a

     grasp

     of the

     evident

     are not

     hard

      to

    find

      (e.g.,  Letter  to  Herodotus 38; Diogenes Laertius X , 32). Nonetheless I

    mean to argue that the use Epicureanism made of the common empirical

    tradition led them to

      take

     a position which the

      f ramework

      could not

    accommodate or could accommodate only with very significant

     qualifi-

    cations. One way of putting this —  though this too will require

     qualifi-

    cation

     — is to say

     that

      the

     Epicureans were committed

      to a

     still more

    generous conception  of experience.

    Ill

    W e

      can see this, among other places, in the apparently exhaustive

    scheme for assessing opinions  as true or false proposed  by Epicurus  DL

    X   34;

      Ep

      H dt

      51-2; Sextus

      Empir icus,  M VII

     211-16). Attestation

      and

    non-attestation  Ý ðé ì á ñôýñç óé ò and ïõê Ýðé ì áñôýñçóéò )

     apply

     to

     evident

    matters; contestation

      and

      non-contestation

      Ü íôé ì á ñôýñçóéò  and

      ïõê

    Ü í ô é ì á ñ ô ý ñ ç ó é ò ) to nonevident matters. Falsity arises when an opinion

    is

     either

     not

     attested

     or is

     contested

     by the

     evident, truth when

     it is

     either

    Brought to you by | UNAM

    Authenticated

    Download Date | 2 23 15 10:23 PM

  • 8/9/2019 Allen, James_Experience as a Source and Ground of Theory in Epicureanism_Apeiron, 37, 4_2004!89!106

    6/18

    94  James  llen

    attested or not

     contested

      by the

     evident.

     The

     opinion that that

      is Plato

    over there, for instance, awaits attestation. It can legitim ately be accepted

    as

     true

     if, upon closer inspection, it is attested or rejected as false if, under

    th e

      same conditions,

      it is not

      attested.

      An

     opinion about nonevident

    m atters is contested when it has an observable consequence that obser-

    vation

     shows tobe

     false; not

     contested when

     its

     observable consequences

    are not

      shown

      to be

      false

      by

      observation.

      Why the

      mere absence

      of

    contestation should  confirm  th e truth of an opinion about  the nonevi-

    dent  is a notorious puzzle to which we shall turn in a moment;  the use

    of

     contestation  to eliminate false opinions,  on the other hand,

     seems

     not

    to

     present

      a

     problem. Thus

     the

     false opinion that there

     is no void,

     which

    is the

     contradictory

     of the

     true Epicurean doctrine,

      is

     contested

      by the

    evident  fact  that there is motion, as there would not be if there were  no

    void for bodies to move into — or so the Epicureans maintained

      Ep

      Hdt

    40; Lucretius I 334 .

    But

     suppose

      we

     connect contestation

     and

     non-attestation

     in the way

    that seems most obvious. Then

     a

     false opinion about nonevident matters

    will be contested when one of its observable consequences is not attested

      in

     the

     appropriate

     conditions .

     Sometimes, when

     the

     observable conse-

    quence

     of the

     thesis

     to be

     contested

     is a

     universal negative, e.g., that there

    is no motion, this can be achieved by the attestation of a single counter-

    instance, assuming that

     we

     grant

      the

     unobjectionable principle that

     if P

    is attested then not-P

      is not

      attested.

     One

     observed  episode

     of

      motion

    will banish

     the

     denial o f

     void

     and vindicate its contradictory.

    Matters are not  always so simple, however. Consider,  for example,

    the

     Epicurean argument

     for the

     principle that nothing comes

     to be  from

    nothing.

      If it

     did, then anything could come

     to be

     anywhere

     at any

     time

    without  the proper  seeds, which  is contested because not  attested  by

    observation  E p H d t

     38;

     Lucretius 1159 ff . ) .

     Or the

     argument that atoms

    cannot

     be of any

     size because,

     if

     they were, there would have

     to be

     visible

    atomic

     bodies, which

      is

     likewise

     not

      attested

      E p

     H d t 55-6; Lucretius

     II

    496-9).

    3

     Yet as w e have seen, attestation  and non-attestation appear  to

    establish only contingent matters of fact  or empirical truths. A classical

    3 To be

     sure,

     he adds

     other reasons, e.g., that

     it is not

     possible

      to

     conceive

      how an

    atom could become visible. This may refer to his theory of vision, according to which

    vision  is caused  by the flow of invisible atomic  f i lms

      from

      the object being seen  to

    the eyes. The problem would then be how an atom of this size could interact with

    the organs of

     visual perception.

    Brought to you by | UNAM

    Authenticated

    Download Date | 2 23 15 10:23 PM

  • 8/9/2019 Allen, James_Experience as a Source and Ground of Theory in Epicureanism_Apeiron, 37, 4_2004!89!106

    7/18

    Experience  as a  ource  95

    empiricist,  a  Humean descendent  of  his,  or   indeed anyone  who   sub-

    scribes to the

     framework

     described above, will patiently explain that the

    fact  that episodes

      of

      random spontaneous generation

      or

      absolutely

    unbreakable

     objects

     have

     not

     been attested

      in our

     experience,

     and

      that

    recorded history contains no  traces  of  them,

     does

     not by

      itself

     entitle us

    to  conclude that  one has not   been overlooked  or   will   not  occur or be

    found

      in ten  seconds, or ten  years or ten  million years. According to  this

    familiar  way of  looking at  things,  no  amount  of  observation or experi-

    ence by

      itself

      can   rule  it out as a  possibility.

    It

     appears that something more

     is

     required

      to

     establish opinions

     of the

    kind that are  candidates for  contestation and  non-contestation. W e  must

    somehow

      be

     able

     to

     tell that what

     is

     implied

      by the

      false

     opinion

      to be

    contested, e.g., the  manifest  episodes of  random spontaneous generation

    that

     are implied  by the  opinion that creation

     ex nihilo

     is  possible  or the

    visible atoms that

     are

     implied

     by the  opinion

     that atoms

     can be of any

    size, are not the  sort or  type or  kind of  thing that can  happen  or  exist.  But

    attestation  and  non-attestation through  or  by means

      of

      the evident do

    not seem to be equal to this task.

    The

      same result appears

      to

      follow

      if we

      approach matters

      from

      a

    different  angle.

     The

     principal candidates

     fo r

     contestation, which

     can be

    rejected   as   false   if  contested  and   accepted  as   true   if not   contested,  are

    theories,

     for example, the theories about meteorological matters that are

    discussed in the  Letter

     to P ythocles

      Ep

     Py th).

      And the

     main source

     of

     these

    is  analogy with the  phenomena with us  (ðáñ

      ÞìÀí)

     or, as  translators  often

    put it,

      in

      our   experience Ep

     H dt

      80). Inevitably  it  often   happens that

    more than one theory about the nonevident causation of a natural

    phenomenon

     suggested

      by

     analogy remains uncontested (cf. Lucretius

    V I

      703

     f f . .

     Yet it

     appears that

     the

     status

     of

     such

      a

     theory

     is not

     like that

    of

     an  opinion about an  evident matter awaiting attestation by  remaining

    epistemically possible, i.e., possible for all we  know or can  say,  as  long

    as it is not

      falsified

      by   observation. Rather, Epicurus seems  to   have

    regarded all the theories compatible with the phenomena as objectively

    possible.

     Indeed,  he

     seems

     to

     have held that they

     are

     true

     in the

     sense

     of

    being realized either a t  some time  in our  world  or in  some other world

    in the

     infinite universe (Lucretius

     V

     526-33).

    Now

      suppose

     that one could somehow be on the moon in the way

    imagined  by  Aristotle in the  Posterior

     Analytics

      and see  which accounts

    of

      eclipses

      or

      waxing

      and

      waning

      do not

      obtain there

      (I 31,  87b39; II

    90a26). Apparently, on the  Epicurean view,  the   fact that these theories

    are not directly attested in these conditions would not show that they

    are

      false

      as  claims about what might be or  what  is  true  in  some world.

    Brought to you by | UNAM

    Authenticated

    Download Date | 2 23 15 10:23 PM

  • 8/9/2019 Allen, James_Experience as a Source and Ground of Theory in Epicureanism_Apeiron, 37, 4_2004!89!106

    8/18

    96

      James

      llen

    Y et  this is not how  Epicurus treated  our

      failures

      to observe episodes of

    random spontaneous generation

      or to  find

      a to ms

     of

      observable size.

    These revealed that certain phen om ena — or

     objects

     or events that would

    have

     to be

     phenomena

      if

     they we re capable

     of

     ex is t ing— are

     not the

     kind

    of

     things

     that can exist at all, and  thereby refute certain theo ries once and

    for

      all.

    4

     Trips  to the  moon  or

      efforts

      to  determine whether that  is , say,

    Plato

     ove r there, by  establishing contingent matters of fact, serve only to

    show that  an opinion  is  false  here  or a  theory  does not  apply  in  this

    cosmos.

    The w ay in which the two pairs — attestation and no n-attestation, on

    the

     one hand, and conte station  and non-contestation, on the other — are

    both said

      to

     take place

      through

     the

     evident

    appears

      to

     conceal

     a gap

    between  two quite dif ferent  ways  of grasping  the evident  and to  leave

    the  relation betwe en them  in the dark  Sextus Em piricus M V II 216). At

    any rate, this  is how someone in sym pathy w ith the frame w ork that I

    outlined above  is likely to  feel.

     

    This suspicion is we ll foun ded, and it receives add itiona l sup po rt  from

    the use

     Epicurus makes

     of analogies

     wi th

     the

     phenomena

      in

     establishing

    theories about

      the

     nonevident. This

     use

     makes

     the

     most sense

     if it

     rests

    on the  assumption that a grasp  of the  evident puts us in

     possession

     of

    truths  not only, as we have seen, about w hat cannot be, but also about

    what , in ve ry robust sense, can be. Near the end of the Letter  to

     Herodotus

    Epicurus says:

      seeing

     in how

     m any ways

      the

     like comes

     to be

     wi th

      us

      ðáñ  Þìúí),

     one

     must theorize about

      the

     causes

      áÀôé ïë ïãçôÝï í )

     o f

     astro-

    4 The

     discussion

     of the

     shapes

     of the  cosmoi in the

      Letter  to

     Pythocles  88

     migh t seem

      to

    count  against this. There

      it is

      said that many shapes

     are

      possible because this

      is

    contested

      by  none  of the  phenomena  in  this cosmos, whose boundary  it is not

    possible  to grasp. This could be

     taken

     to mean

     that

     the m an y possible cosmic shapes

    are not

      contested

      since  we

      cannot grasp

      the

      shape

      of our own cosmos, wi th  the

    implication that ,

     if we

     could,

     all of the shapes apar t

     from

      the one

     that

     belongs to our

    cosmos would be contested. In  this case, the ir non-attestation here wo uld contest

    the

     possibility

     of

     their obtaining an yw here

     at

      all.

     I

     take

     the

     po int rather

     to be

     tha t

    th e

      many possible shapes

      are not

      contested

      by

      phenomena

     wi th in

      this cosmos,

    whose

     own

     boundary,

     like

      the way in

     w hich eclipses

     and

      many

     othe r phenomena

    come

     about i n  it , are,

     as it

     happens, unkno wn .

    Brought to you by | UNAM

    Authenticated

    Download Date | 2 23 15 10:23 PM

  • 8/9/2019 Allen, James_Experience as a Source and Ground of Theory in Epicureanism_Apeiron, 37, 4_2004!89!106

    9/18

    Experience  as a

      ource

      97

    nomical phenomena  ì å ô Ýù ñ á ) and everything  nonevident (80). And in

    th e

      Letter  to

      Pythodes,  he

      offers  multiple explanations  for

      a

      host

      of

    meteorological

      phenomena based

      on

      analogies with

      the

      behavior

     of

    medium sized physical objects that  we can observe

     from

     close  up.

    If  every possibility  is   realized somewhere  or at  some time  in the

    infinite  universe, analogies suggested  by observation of the phenomena

    among

     us

     will suggest theories that stand

     a

     good chance

     of

     being  true

     in

    th e  sense

     that they

     are

     true

     of

     some episodes

      of the

     phenomenon

      to be

    explained at

     some time

     or in

     some cosmos.

     But is

     being suggested

     by the

    phenomena

      sufficient

      to show that  a  theory  is genuinely possible,   and

    therefore  true  in  this

      way?

     Perhaps, despite having  a better chance of

    being true on Epicurean assumptions than it would on other assump-

    tions,

     a

     theory suggested

     by an

     analogy with

     the

     phenomena has,

     so

     far,

    only been  shown  to be epistemically

     possible.

     It

     could still

     happen,  for

    all

     w e know  or can say, that it is not genuinely or  objectively  possible.

    And

     if  this  is so, we  shall  be

     entitled

     to accept  it as a  genuine possibility

    only

     after  it has  survived  th e test of contestation by the phenomena. If it

    does not survive, then it only seemed to be genuinely possible.

    Some of Epicurus language

      suggests

      an interpretation along these

    lines

      or is

      compatible with

      it

      Ep Pyth

      92, 93,

      98-9).

      But

      there

      is

      also

    evidence suggesting that likeness of the right kind to a phenomenal

    analogue

      is

     suff icient

      to

     establish

     a

     theory about nonevident causation

    as  true.  In parts  of the  Letter

      to Pythodes,

     where explanations based  on

    analogies with the phenomena in our experience are discussed,   these

    phenomena

      are

      four times said

     to bid or call

     for

      the

     analogous explana-

    tions

     (87,  94,100,113).  This may be merely suggestive, but in the same

    work,

     after

     remarking that  the  waxing  and waning

     of

     the

     moon  can come

    about in all the ways in which we observe similar phenomena coming

    about in our experience, and noting that the same is true of the way in

    which the moon gets its light and presents a visage to us, Epicurus says

    that someone

     who

     accepts

     one of the

     explanations

     and  rejects the

     others

    will be in

     conflict

      ìÜ÷ç)

     with

     the

     evident (96). And, after  reviewing

     the

    explanations for the varying lengths of nights and days over the course

    of  the year that are suggested by analogous occurrences in our  experi-

    ence, Epicurus insists that

      it is

      necessary

      to

      speak

      of

     meteorological

    mat te r s

     in a

     manner

      that is

     consonant

     or in

     agreement

     (óõìöþíùò)

     with

    the phenomena,

      before

     going  on to say  that those  who accept only one

    explanation are, once again, in

     conflict

     with the phenomena (98).

    I t  seems very much  as if a theory s similarity to the  phenomena  is

    sufficient

      to

     ensure that

     it is in

     agreement with them,

     and

     that being

      in

    agreement with

     the

     phenomena guarantees that

     a

     theory

     is

     true,

     in the

    Brought to you by | UNAM

    Authenticated

    Download Date | 2 23 15 10:23 PM

  • 8/9/2019 Allen, James_Experience as a Source and Ground of Theory in Epicureanism_Apeiron, 37, 4_2004!89!106

    10/18

    98

      James

      llen

    sense  of   being possible   and   true somewhere

      or

      at   some time,   for   it is

    implied   that   to   reject   one of the   explan ations based   on   analogy with  a

    phenomenon  is to  deny  the   reality  of the  phenomenon that  it  resembles.

    Perhaps theories undergo a do uble test. W hen put

      forward

      as universal

    explanations

    holding   of all  times   and   places, they  q ual ify   as  true  if  they

    are merely not contested by the

     phenomena

    but w hen reform ulated as

    claims a bo ut possibility, each has a co ntradictory,  viz.,   the proposition

    that

      it is not

      possible, which

      is in

     conflict   with

     the

      phenomenon that

     i t

    resembles and which w as the basis of the ana logy tha t is its sourc e. This

    would mean that theories  —  conc eived   as  c laims abo ut objective possi-

    bility —   follow from   the  phenomena   to  w hich they  a re   analogous.  The

    grounds that

     the

     phenomenon

      on

     which

     an

      analogous theory

      is

     based

    furnish

      for

     accepting

      the

      theory would then complement

      the

      grounds

    furnished

      by the

     fact

      that   the   theory   is not   contested  by the   phenomena

    quite generally.

    Epicurus use of the  vocabulary  o f  signs and   sign-inference  o f   signs

    that

     seem

     to

     signify

     how

     nonevident m atters

     a re by

     being sim ilar

     to

     them

    lends add itiona l support   to  this suggestion   Ep Pyth 97; cf.  104).  To  reject

    some possible explanations while giving a rbitra ry preferenc e

     to one is

    he

      maintains,

      to be

     unable

      to

     grasp

      the

     phenomena

      as

     signs

     and to be

    carried into inconceivability (97). My

     guess

      is   that  the  inconc eivability

    that he   means   is  that  of  denying  that  one   instance   of a  type  of  behavior

    is  possible when other m anifes t instances   of it  show that behavior  of  that

    type

     is

      possible.

    For our present purpo se, w ha t m atters most is that E pic urus wa s able to

    assign such

     an

      impo rtant part

      to

     an alogy because

     he did not

     share

      the

    assumptions about wha t

     can and

     cannot

     fall

     under

     a

     grasp

     of the

     evident

    that are incorporated in the  f ramework   set out above. Ac co rding to  these

    assumptions, on the basis of such a grasp w e know only that things have

    behaved as we  have observed they did. This knowledge will make  an

    empiricist, who relies only on experience, expec t that events will coin-

    cide,  follow

      and

      precede

      one

      another

      as

      they have been observed

      to

    without

      in any way

      justifying

     h is

      expectation.

      But

     Epicurus

     seems  to

    suppose that,  in grasping  the phenomena,  we grasp  how things  can and

    must

     be. I am

     tempted

      to go

     further

     and say

     that, acco rding

      to

     Epicurus

    to

     grasp the pheno m ena is, within limits and in pa rt, to und erstand the

    causes at work by grasping the natures in virtue of which ordinary

    Brought to you by | UNAM

    Authenticated

    Download Date | 2 23 15 10:23 PM

  • 8/9/2019 Allen, James_Experience as a Source and Ground of Theory in Epicureanism_Apeiron, 37, 4_2004!89!106

    11/18

    Experience

      as a

      ource  99

    medium sized

      objects  act and

     behave

     as

     they

      do .

     Understanding

      how

    and why  they behave as  they do,   we  thereby  see how bigger objects

    fur ther

     away that are relevantly like them by sharing  the nature respon-

    sible for

     their behavior must behave.

     The

     same holds

      mutatis mutandis

    for

     smaller

     objects

     whose distance from

      us m ay be

     negligible,

     bu t

     which

    are

     too

     small

     for us to

     perceive.

    Grasping true theories about the nonevident extends and

     deepens

     our

    understanding of the causes which explain and necessitate the behavior

    we

     a re able to observe, but the sharp line which the framework takes to

    separate knowledge  of the phenomena  from   the grasp  of  truths about

    what

      can and  must  be of the  kind  that  f igure  in causal explanations

    appears

      not to be a

     part

     of

     Epicureanism .

    5

     For

     adherents

     of the

      f rame-

    work, anything that smacks

     of

     knowledge

     o f

     natures,

     the

     necessities they

    impose  and the possibilities they

     open

     up is knowledge  of the nonevi-

    dent,  to be had, if it can be had at all, by inference or by means o f another

    exercise of a  special

     rational

      faculty

     distinct from

     experience. But as we

    have seen, this

     is not so

     for Epicurus

     and the

     Epicureans:

     the

     grasp

     of the

    evident, which precedes  and  secures all knowledge of the  nonevident,

    must

      itself

     already be a grasp, however  partial, of how

      things

      can and

    must be.

    Should we then say that the Epicureans were committed to a concep-

    tion of experience still more generous and richer than  the one  enshrined

    in the   f ramework  — the suggestion that I put forward fo r consideration

    above?

    6

     Perhaps, bu t there are reasons  to hesitate, most notably the  fact

    that  this  is not something  any Epicurean ever says  or I suspect,   ever

    would say.

      The

      framework takes experience

      to be

      coordinate with

    evident matters or phenomena. They are accessible to experience, and

    the

     knowledge

     o ne has of

     them

     is

     experience.

     A

     better

     way of

     describing

    the

     distinctive character

     of the

     Epicurean

     position, I

     shall suggest, would

    be to say that this coordination does not obtain in Epicureanism.

    5  Perhaps  this is what Epicurus is saying  in a passage  of the  Letter to

     Pythocles

    where

    he

     notes that

      signs

     about celestial matters

     are

     furnished

      by

     certain phenomena

     m

    ou r

     experience concerning which

      it

     is

     seen

     how they are

     unlike celestial phenom-

    ena  themselves 87; c f.  Ep  Hdl  80).

     N.B.

    however, that  this reading  is  based  on an

    emendation.

    6

      This

     is

     something

      I

     have

     said

     elsewhere.

      See

     Allen, 2001,196,236-9.

    rought to you by | UNAM

    Authenticated

    Download Date | 2 23 15 10:23 PM

  • 8/9/2019 Allen, James_Experience as a Source and Ground of Theory in Epicureanism_Apeiron, 37, 4_2004!89!106

    12/18

    100

      James

      llen

    This becomes clear when   we try to see  wh at Epicurus  and his  follow -

    ers though t abo ut ancient form s of em piricism. To jud ge by the available

    evidence it is not a

     subject that Epicu rus himself took m uc h

     of an

     interest

    in .

    7

     Philodemus

      is a

     different

      matter, however.

     On  Signs and

      Sign-infer-

    ences (henceforward  On Signs) defends  the so  called m ethod  of  similarity,

    which would allow

      us to

      infer, e.g.,   that

      all

     hu m an beings everywhere

    are mortal

      from

      the

      fact

      that

     those

      amon g us are or that  atoms  behave

    mutatis  mutandis  in the way visible bodies do   from   th e   fact   that visible

    bodies behave   in   that wa y.  The   work   is  full   of  terms   and   notions  from

    empiricism, which retain   th e

     meanings

      they have   in it,   e.g.,

      peira

      and

    historia.

      And

      Philodemus directly confronts

      the

      problem that arises

    already in  Epicurus, nam ely  how  observation   of  a  finite

     sample

    however

    large of, say, hum an beings,   can   entitle   us to   conclude that   all   human

    beings everywhere are

     m ortal.

     The

     occasion for

     the

     work

     is the

      challenge

    presented   by   unnamed opponents   w ho  raise precisely this problem .  Yet

    Philodemus  does not  credit

     peira,

     the  activity, w ith  any  more  powers or

    take

      the

      knowledge

      we

      have

      as a

      result

      of it to

      extend

      any

      further

      or

    penetrate   any more deeply   than em piricism  does.

    8

    Consider, how ever, Letter to H erodotus, 79 ,

     where  Epicurus  rem arks that

     w h a t

     comes

    under history

     (É ó ô ï ñ ß á )

     about

     th e  risings,

     settings , eclipses

     and   like

     matters

     does not

    contribute to

      blessedness because

      it

     leaves untouc hed  fears

      that  can

     block

      the way

    to

      happiness.

      H is

      point

      is

      that   it is

      possible

      to   have   a   great

      deal

     of

      astronomical

    knowledge

      of

     this kind while rema ining vulnerable

     to

     superst it ion, which

      can be

    banished   only   by a

     grasp

      of the

     natures

      ( ö ý ó å éò )  and   principal

      causes

      ( íõ ñ é þ ô á ô ï é

    á ú ô ß á é underlying

     the

      phenomena.

      É ó ô ï ñ ß á ,

     though

      not the

     exclus ive property

     of

    Empiricists,

      was a key   term   of   theirs,   and   this   passage reads very much

      like

      a

    rejection   of

      merely empirical astronomy in

      favor

      of a

      version

      that

      satisfies

      the

    rationalists demand

     for  explanation by way of

     natures

     and

     causes, albeit

     fo r

     reasons

    peculiar

     to  E picureanism.

    And

      in his wo rk

     On rhetoric,

     using lang uag e

     that

     would

     not

     hav e been

      out of

     place

    in   a   Platonist

      inspired

      by the   Gorgias,  he   maintains

      that

      practices grounded

      in

    observation  and   history,  ð á ñ á ô Þ ñ ç ó é ò  and

      É ó ô ï ñ ß á ,  which

     he  calls  ô ñ é â á ß ,  are not

     arts

    properly speaking

      Rhet

      I I X X X 1 9   f f ;  but cf.  X X X V I I I 2   f f .

    rought to you by | UNAM

    Authenticated

    Download Date | 2 23 15 10:23 PM

  • 8/9/2019 Allen, James_Experience as a Source and Ground of Theory in Epicureanism_Apeiron, 37, 4_2004!89!106

    13/18

    Experience

      as a Source  101

    VI

    How, then, are

     we

     able

     to

      infer

     conclusions about

     the

     nonevident

      from

    the phenomena?  A crucial part  in the Epicurean account appears  to be

    played

     by

      epilogismos,

     which, or at least the term for which, was, as we

    noted, also used

     by the

     medical

     Empiricists.

     They stressed

      two

     features:

    that

      epilogismos

      is concerned exclusively with evident matters, unlike

    analogismos, the  form   of reasoning that is employed by the Rationalists

    and

     which allows them

     to

     deduce nonevident conclusions;

     and

     that

     it is

    the kind of

     reasoning employed

     by

     ordinary human beings

     in

     everyday

    life.

     They

     use it, for

     instance,

      of

     inferring

     one

     evident matter, which

      is

    temporarily

     nonevident,

     from

     another, which they

     call

     commemorative

    signification  elsewhere,

      e.g.,

      since

      there  is  smoke, there  is

      fire Sect

    ingred

     10 23-4;

      11,

     9-10).

    As I noted above, however, this is not how the Epicureans used   the

    term.

     An earlier tendency to render it as

      empirical inference

    has been

    much criticized. Though Philodemus speaks frequently of the

      epilogismos

    of  the phenomena,  and even, in one especially badly preserved passage,

    of

     the

     application

      of

      epilogismos

      to

     what

     has

     been grasped

     by

     experience

     peira)  (fr.  4), a survey of Epicurean usage shows  that it is

     often

      applied

    to items that are not obviously empirical. Epicurus himself speaks of the

    epilogismos  of the end or  telos,  and one of  Philodemus authorities,

    Demetrius of Laconia, speaks intriguingly  of his

     opponents failure

      to

    apply

     ep ilogismos  to

     their

     own

     method

     of

     inference  (XXVII I13  ff.).  What

    is

     more,

     it is not

     obvious that

     the

     rational activity designated

     by  epilo-

    gismos is a matter

     of

     inference. Viewed in isolation, a few

     passages

     seem

    to suggest that

      epilogismos

     is the inference of the nonevident conclusion

    from  evident  signs  (XX II37  ff.),  but it is plain  from  a

     fuller

     survey of the

    evidence that

      epilogismos

      belongs to a preliminary phase prior to the

    inference

      of a  nonevident conclusion,  for which  the  terms

      sign-infer-

    ence

    (óçìåßùóéò)

     or  reasoning (óõëëïãßæåóèáé) are reserved.

    9

     Philode-

    mus speaks of advancing or making a transition to a nonevident

    conclusion through

     or by

     means

     of epilogismos

     because

     epilogismos  is an

    indispensable precondition

     for the

     inference,

     not the

     inference proper.

    The

      noun

      Ýðéëïãéóìüò   and the

      verb

      Ýðéëïãßæåóèáé

      occur

      in

      several

    different  constructions.

     We  find   the

     verb used with

     a

     direct

      object   and

    9 Cf. Barnes,

     1988,130-1,

     Sedley,  1978,  27-34, and  especially   Schofield,  1996.

    rought to you by | UNAM

    Authenticated

    Download Date | 2 23 15 10:23 PM

  • 8/9/2019 Allen, James_Experience as a Source and Ground of Theory in Epicureanism_Apeiron, 37, 4_2004!89!106

    14/18

    102   James  llen

    the noun taking  an objective genitive,  e.g., the epilogismo s of the end or

    of  the phenomena which have already been mentioned.

    10

     The verb can

    be

     used

      to

     introduce

     a

     subordinate clause  that with which

     we

     seem

      to

    come closest  to  reasoning  as

      inference

      or

      deduction.

    11

      And   there   are

    constructions

      in

     which

      the

     verb takes

     a

     direct

     object

     and introduces

      a

    subordinate clause — the

      consider

     the  lilies,  how

      they grow

    construc-

    tion especially

     fam iliar

     in Greek verbs

      to

     know ,  where  the

     subordinate

    clause unpacks

     in

     propositional  form what

     it is one

     knows

     o/an

     item

     in

    knowing it  (Philodemus,

     On  Signs

      XXVIII15-25;

     cf. Epicurus,

     Men

     133,

    where

     the

     construction

     is

     implicit).

    Though

      the

      last construction

      is rare,   the

      fact  tha t

     it is

     possible

     may

    help

     us.

     Suppose

     we

     distinguish between

     the

     materials

     to

     which reason-

    ing is  applied   and its  upshot   or  result.  I  hesitate   to say

      conclusion

    because I do not  want  to prejudge  the question of whether  the reasoning

    at

      issue   is a  fo rm of deduction   or inference, though  the premises of an

    inference may perhaps be  viewed  as one kind of material and its conclu-

    sion  as one   kind   of  upshot

      or

      result.  The  distinguishing feature  of

    epilogistic reasoning, signaled by the prefix

      epi-

    would then be  that  the

    materials to which  one  applies it and  that about which  one knows,   or

    knows better,  as a result  are the same.

    12

     Passages in which   epilogismos/epi-

    logizesthai takes a direct  object  or objective  genitive, signifying  the mate-

    rial  to which epilogistic reasoning is applied, and passages in which

    epilogismos/epilogizesthai  introduces  a subordinate clause, signifying the

    upshot or conclusion of the  reasoning, would then  be incomplete speci-

    fications

     of part  of a whole instance  of  epilogistic reasoning.

    Whether every

     use of

      epilogismos

    can be

     made

     to fit

     this pattern,

     I

    do not

      know.

     But if

     this

     is the

     basic idea,

     it

     might explain

     some

     things

    about

     both  the  Epicurean and Empiricist  uses of the  term.  For instance,

    though it is far f rom clear that this distinction is marked  in Epicureanism,

    according  to the  Empiricists, what distinguishes  epilogismos

      f rom

      the

    analogismos of the  rationalists is that it  never departs f rom  the  phenom-

    10 W ith a direct object· E picuru s, E p H dt  72

    Letter

      to  M enoeceus 133,

     Principal Do ctrines

    XXII,

     Philodemus,  O n  Signs  XIII

     32. W ith an

      objective

      genitive-

     Epicurus,

     Principle

    Doctrines

     XX;

      hilodemus, O n  Signs XXII37 ,

     XXVII 23.

    11  Epicurus,

      Vatican Sayings

     35,

     Ep Hdt

      73; Phi lodemus,

     On

      Signs

      XXVIII16

    12

      For these

     ideas

     ab o u t  epilogismos an d  analogismos see

     Schofield,  1996, nn.

     8 which

    contains

     suggestions of David

     Sedley)

     and 12

    Brought to you by | UNAM

    Authenticated

    Download Date | 2 23 15 10:23 PM

  • 8/9/2019 Allen, James_Experience as a Source and Ground of Theory in Epicureanism_Apeiron, 37, 4_2004!89!106

    15/18

  • 8/9/2019 Allen, James_Experience as a Source and Ground of Theory in Epicureanism_Apeiron, 37, 4_2004!89!106

    16/18

    104

      James

      llen

    one another in  certain pattern s and   w ith certain re lat ive frequencies. O n

    the   basis  of  this knowledge he

      can

    in a  manner  of  speakin g reason

    about

      the

      phenomena

      and   form

      reasonable expectations abo ut unob-

    served  observables

     or

     phenomena

      to be. A s a

     resul t

     o f his

     ep ilogismos

    on

    the other hand the Epicurean has a grasp h ow eve r  incomplete and

    partial of the  natures  and   powers  of the   i tems he is s tudying .  And on

    this basis he is able to

     infer

     that unobserved and even

     unobservable

     item s

    m ust be the same or similar.

    V II

      the

     Epicureans had

    as I put it

     earlier

    a

     still m ore gene rous conception

    of

      experience than that admitted

      by the   f ramework

    then

      it is not one

    they described

      in

     terms draw n   from

      the

     standard em pirical v ocabulary.

    The

     activities that w ent  under

     the

     head

     o f

     experience

    remained capable

    only  of grasping   facts  that

    devoid

      of necessity   and   explanatory power.

     

    you  will Epicurean epistemology

      depends

     on a more than em pirical

    grasp o r comprehension of the phenom ena or the ev iden t. It is pretty

    clear that

      epilogismos to

      which Epicurus

      had

      a lready

      appealed,   w as

    enlisted  by  Philodemus

    Epicurean authorities

     to

      close

      a gap

      between

    the  deliverances  of experience   and the   grasp  of the  phenomena that  is

    necessary  if  sign-inferences  to the  nonevident are  to be  possible.  It is also

    a

     fair

     guess that their opp onents responded

      by

     tak ing epilogistic reason-

    ing to be a  matter of inference  or ded uction . H av ing elicited   the  admis-

    sion tha t experience

     b y

     itself  tells

     us

     no thing about

     how

     things must

     be

    they could then proceed

      by

     demanding

      to

     know

     how an

     inference

      from

    the

      data

      of

     experience

     can

      yield

      a

      grasp

      of the

      phenomena which

      is at

    once   the  upshot  o r result  of epilogismos  and a sufficient  basis  for sign-in-

    ferences

      to the

      nonevident.

    Thus if the   f ramework  cannot accom mo date Epicurean views it is

    not

      because

      the

      Epicureans  explicitly  disavow

      the

      assumptions that

    compose it.

     Indeed such evidence

     as w e

     hav e suggests they might hav e

    been w illing to endorse claims ab ou t the limits of experience strictly so

    called.

     Y et the

     fact

      that they

     do not

     take experience

     to be

     coordinate w ith

    the  phenomena and as I put it  earlier permit  a  more than empirical

    grasp

     or

     comprehension

      of the

     phenom ena m ean s that this tells

     us less

    abo ut Epicureanism than it otherw ise m ight. This is not the com prehen-

    sion

      of the

     phenomena that

     w e

     have when

      w e

     view them

      in the

      light

     of

    first

      principles  or as  effects  of  their underlying causes because  it is an

    essential precondition

      for

     aetiology. A ccord ing

     to

     orthodo x  adherents

     to

    Brought to you by | UNAM

    Authenticated

    Download Date | 2 23 15 10:23 PM

  • 8/9/2019 Allen, James_Experience as a Source and Ground of Theory in Epicureanism_Apeiron, 37, 4_2004!89!106

    17/18

    Experience  as a

      ource

      105

    th e

      f ramework,  experience plays this

      part ,

      whereas

      for

      Epicureans,

    experience

     merely prepares  the wa y

      for

      the more than empirical grasp

    of   th e phenomena that in turn supports rational insights about nonevi-

    dent matters.

      If

      experience

    were simply

      the

      name

      for the

      grasp

      or

    comprehension

      of the

      phenomena that precedes aetiology, then

      the

    Epicureans

      would disavow  th e  restrictions  on   empirical knowledge

    imposed

      by the

      f ramework.

      suggest that  we  look  at  matters  in   this way. Sometimes, when

    philosophers like Plato

      and

      Aristotle defended

      one

     position

      and op-

    posed another, they were

     not

     taking

     a

     familiar position

      in a

     dispute

      that

    was

      already  being  conducted along

      wel l

      defined lines

      so

      much

      as

    creating

      a new way of

      understanding

      th e

      issues.

      When

      th e

     medical

    Empiricists

     defend

      th e

     claim that experience

      can by   itself

      give rise

      to

    artistic knowledge,  it is an  impoverished

      form

      of experience, experience

    as conceived  and   marked o ff  from   reason by  Plato and  Aristotle. But it

    is doubtful that earlier figures

     w ho

     made large claims

      for

     experience

    drew

      the

      lines quite

      so

     sharply. Rather,

     from   the

     point

      of

     view

     of

     Plato

    and

     Aristotle,

      it was

     probably

      fairer   to say

     that they

      failed   to see

     that

    knowledge  of the  kind which they

      assumed

      could  be  explained  by

    experience

      and

      perception alone actually requires

      a

      separate rational

    faculty with distinctive powers  of its own.  In  this respect,  as in  others,

    Epicurus  is  something  o f a  throwback.

    14

    Bibliography

    Allen,

     James.

     2001.

     Inf erence

      from Signs:

     Ancient

     Debates

     about

      th e

     Nature

      o f

      Evidence.

     Oxford:

    Oxford University Press.

    Annas,  J. and   Grimm,

      R.H.,

      eds. 1988.

      O x f o r d

      Studies   in   Ancient   Philosophy suppl. vol.

    Oxford:

     Oxford

     University

     Press.

    Barnes, Jonathan. 1988.  Epicurean

     Signs ,

     in  Annas and   Gr imm, eds. 91-134

    De Lacy, P.H. and   H.A., eds. 2nd  edn. 1978. Philodemus:   On   Methods

      of

      n f e r e n c e  Naples:

    Bibliopolis.

    14  I am   grateful

      fo r

      comments  and criticism to the

     participants

     in the  conference,  to the

    speakers

     and  audience at Philoso phy in Assos, Ju ly  2004, where I

     delivered

     a  paper

    related to this one,  and to the   participants   in the

      Pi t tsburgh/Athens Symposium,

    October

      2000,

     where

     I   first

      presented some

      of

      these ideas

      as a

     commentator

     on

    Michael Frede's paper,

      Experience

     in the ancient Empiricists

    rought to you by | UNAM

    Authenticated

    Download Date | 2 23 15 10:23 PM

  • 8/9/2019 Allen, James_Experience as a Source and Ground of Theory in Epicureanism_Apeiron, 37, 4_2004!89!106

    18/18

    106  James  Allen

    Deichgräber,   Kar l ,   ed 2nd edn   1965   D ie

     g riechische

      Empinkerschule

      Sammlung  der

      Frag

    mente

     und

      Darste l lung

     der

     Lehre  Ber li n W ei dm a n n

    Everson,

      S. ed.

      1990.  Companions to

     Ancient

     Thought

     

    Epistenwlogy.  Ca m br i dge : Ca m bridge

    Universi ty Press.

    Frede, M. 1990.  An  empiricist view of know ledge: m em orism ,  in   Evers on , ed 225-50.

    Frede,

     M. and Striker, G ., eds. 1996.   Rationality

      in

     Creek

      Thought .

     Oxford: Oxford Univers ity

    Press.

    Schofield,  M .   1996. Epilogismos:   An  Appraisal ,   in  Frede   and   Striker,  eds   221-37.

    Sedley,

      D.

     1973.

      Epicurus o n

      Nature Book

     X V I I I .

      Cronache

     ercolanesi  3:

     5-83

    Brought to you by | UNAM