a degree of faith: a case for christianity for the educated skeptic

Upload: joel-mabry

Post on 06-Jul-2018

214 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/16/2019 A Degree of Faith: A Case for Christianity for the Educated Skeptic

    1/193

  • 8/16/2019 A Degree of Faith: A Case for Christianity for the Educated Skeptic

    2/193

    A DEGREE OF FAITH 

    2

    A DEGREE OF FAITH

     A C ASE FOR CHRISTIANITY FOR THE EDUCATED

    SKEPTIC 

    JOEL M ABRY 

  • 8/16/2019 A Degree of Faith: A Case for Christianity for the Educated Skeptic

    3/193

     

    Copyright© 2014 by Joel P. Mabry

     All rights reserved. This book or any portion thereof may not be reproduced or used in any

    manner whatsoever without the express written permission of the publisher except for the use of

    brief quotations in a book review.

    www.logicalapologetics.com 

    http://www.logicalapologetics.com/http://www.logicalapologetics.com/http://www.logicalapologetics.com/

  • 8/16/2019 A Degree of Faith: A Case for Christianity for the Educated Skeptic

    4/193

    A DEGREE OF FAITH 

    4

    To my wife, without whom this book (and podcast) would not have been possible

  • 8/16/2019 A Degree of Faith: A Case for Christianity for the Educated Skeptic

    5/193

     

    5

    Table of Contents

    Preface 6

     Acknowledgements  8

    Introduction 9

    Part I: Worldview and Epistemology  18

    1. Epistemology 19

    2. Postmodernism 33

    3. Naturalism 42

    Part II: The Existence of God 57 

    4. The Kalam Cosmological Argument 61

    5. The Leibnizian Cosmological Argument 69

    6. The Ontological Argument 76

    7. The Argument from Fine-Tuning 82

    8. The Poetical Arguments 92

    9. The Argument from Religious Experience 97

    10. The Argument from Innate Concepts 105

    11. The Argument from Morality 112

    Part III: History & Christianity 120 

    12. Can Miracles Happen? 121

    13. Textual Criticism and Higher Criticism 134

    14. Did Jesus Claim to be God? 145

    15. Did Jesus Rise from the Dead? 157

    Part IV: The Problem of Evil (and Suffering) 165 

    16. The Problem of Evil (and Suffering) 166

     Appendix A: How to Keep Faith in College  184

     Appendix B: Resources 191

  • 8/16/2019 A Degree of Faith: A Case for Christianity for the Educated Skeptic

    6/193

    A DEGREE OF FAITH 

    6

    Preface

     At the age of nineteen I exited the lecture hall one morning convinced that I had no soul. The

    lecture touched on the mind/body problem and ended with the conclusion, for me at least, that

    we were not souls but merely complex arrangements of neurons. This was jarring for me

    because I couldn’t equate that view of humanity with a final judgment at the end of time asdescribed in the bible. How could God judge us for our actions if our very personalities can be

    altered by, say, electrical shocks?

    I did not, though, go to my room and burn my bible. On the contrary, I delved deeper into the

    problem, somehow having the wisdom to go further than the usual college skeptic to doubt even

    my doubts. I didn’t have much time for research, and I wouldn’t have known where to go even if

    I did. So I googled it.

     According to Wikipedia, there were a few notable philosophers that were not materialists. One

    of these, Richard Swinburne, was an Emeritus Professor of Philosophy at Oxford. Upon seeing

    this, I thought that if an Oxford professor can be a dualist, then I can continue to be one until I

    can investigate the matter myself.

    It was not until a couple years later that I was in the library looking around aimlessly and

    stumbled upon the name of that Oxford professor and his book The Evolution of the Soul .

    Despite the sophisticated argumentation and prodigious footnotes and appendices, I devoured

    the book. That started a cascade of reading on the mind/body problem along with other alleged

    problems of Christian belief.

    During these college years, a few people close to me had either lost their faith or were

    seriously doubting it. This compelled me to dig deeper in my research and address theirparticular concerns.

    Then, before I knew it, I graduated from college, moved to another city, got married, and

    started working. My first job involved data-entry or, more accurately, data-extraction. I sat in a

    cubicle eight hours a day and worked my way down a spreadsheet of 27,000 names. For each

    name, I found it in the database, wrote the information onto a physical sheet of paper, placed

    that paper in a certain stack depending on whether this or that criterion was met, marked the

    name off my spreadsheet, and moved to the next name, ad nauseum. And although I was 97%

    sure that what I was doing added no value to the company but was only a solution devised by a

    boss due to an IT-related misunderstanding, I continued to show up each day and do my job

    while listening to eight hours of audio material through my headphones. I listened to a panoply

    of podcasts, sermons, interviews, and lectures.

    I was consuming so much information each day that I needed an outlet to organize my

    thoughts and synthesize my half-baked ideas. The podcast (www.logicalapologetics.com) 

    became that outlet.

    http://www.logicalapologetics.com/http://www.logicalapologetics.com/http://www.logicalapologetics.com/http://www.logicalapologetics.com/

  • 8/16/2019 A Degree of Faith: A Case for Christianity for the Educated Skeptic

    7/193

     

    7

     And while audio is a great tool for propagation, I find books to be much more effective at

    organizing complex ideas, and they are much easier to skim and find particular interesting

    passages. This book is an attempt to do that.

    I have taken much of the material from the podcast, cleaned it up, added new material, and

    organized it into one coherent and concise argument for Christianity.

     As for goals for the book, I have three. First, I hope to provide a resource for others who are

    doubting or know someone who is doubting. Second, I hope this book, like Richard Swinburne’s

    book, shows that there are intelligent people out there that hold dissenting views, and that the

    Christian doesn’t have to be alone. Third, I hope this book works some small part in setting the

    record straight and redeeming Christianity’s popular image from unwarranted disparagement

    and ridicule because of perceived anti-intellectualism.

    Whether I achieve these goals or not is for the reader to decide. I only ask for an open mind.

  • 8/16/2019 A Degree of Faith: A Case for Christianity for the Educated Skeptic

    8/193

    A DEGREE OF FAITH 

    8

    Acknowledgments

    This project of mine would have died in the first episodes of the podcast if it were not for the

    early encouragement and interest of those family and friends closest to me. I thank each of

    them.

     A special thanks goes to Will Webb for figuring out how to start a podcast, sharing that

    knowledge with me, and giving me my first microphone. Without such help, I doubt this would

    have ever gotten off the ground.

    Most of all, I thank Casey for graciously telling me to work on my podcast when anyone else

    would have told me to get a job. I couldn’t ask for a better friend, confidant, and wife. 

  • 8/16/2019 A Degree of Faith: A Case for Christianity for the Educated Skeptic

    9/193

    Introduction: Faith

    Faith or Reason. Conservative or Liberal. Good or Evil. These are three dichotomies that most

    people never question. In their view, you either have faith or you have reason. You are

    conservative or liberal. You are good or bad. You cannot be both.

    Is that the case? Can reality truly be divided so neatly into pat categories? As a preliminary

    test, let’s focus first on the last one: good or evil. And since the difference between the two has

    never seemed more obvious or more important than in World War II, we will use that conflict to

    question whether good and evil can be so sharply divided.

     At first, everything appears to separate neatly into one or the other category. On the side of

    the Axis powers we have Nazi Germany, Fascist Italy, and Imperial Japan. All three are known

    for their opportunistic aggression, horrific war-crimes, and oppressive rule. Sounds evil enough.

    On the side of the Allies we have the United States fighting for democracy and freedom, the

    U.K. fighting for national survival, and... Stalin’s Soviet Union. 

    The Soviet Union wasn’t brought into this conflict with a clear slate. It had teamed with Nazi

    Germany in attacking Poland unprovoked until Germany broke the pact and attacked the Soviet

    Union as well. The Soviet Union was also led by Josef Stalin, a man that killed twenty million of

    his own subjects in peacetime. During the war, the Soviet Union performed war atrocities of

    their own such as the Katyn massacre in which 20,000 Polish officers were secretly executed in

    the forest. Furthermore, we now know that after the war, the Soviet Union held half of Europe

    under a regime as oppressive as the one that had just collapsed in Berlin.

    These facts significantly muddy what, at first, seemed an obvious dichotomy. Were the Alliesgood or evil? Also keep in mind that most of the Allied war power came from the Soviet Union,

    as Michael Bess explains:

    The overwhelming bulk of the killing of Nazis was not done by the citizen soldiers at all,

    but rather by the soldiers of the Red Army: the ratio is about four German soldiers killed

    by the Russians for every one killed by the British and Americans.... The Russian people

    had shown a heroism and self-sacrifice in this war that boggled the mind; but they were

    led by a government whose catalogue of crimes was extraordinarily heinous, even by

    the standards of the twentieth century. We won World War II partly through our own

    courage and self-sacrifice, and partly through the hammerblows struck by our extremely

    powerful, and extremely nasty, ally.1 

    That’s not the only problem with viewing the Allies as wholly good guys. There are also the

    questions that arise from the dropping of two atom bombs on Japan as well as the carpet-

    bombing of civilian populations by the United States and United Kingdom. The firebombing of

    1 Michael Bess, Choices Under Fire: Moral Dimensions of World War II (New York: Vintage Books, 2008),

    167-168. 

  • 8/16/2019 A Degree of Faith: A Case for Christianity for the Educated Skeptic

    10/193

    A DEGREE OF FAITH 

    10

    Dresden alone killed at least 60,000 noncombatants, and in the first seven months of 1945,

    200,000 civilians died in the bombings of sixty-six Japanese cities.2 

    Now these choices, i.e. teaming with Stalin and firebombing civilian populations, may have

    been necessary to prevent a greater evil. Or not. But either way, this demonstrates how a

    complicated reality can be incorrectly simplified as an either/or dichotomy. After examining theevidence, can you honestly say that any contender in World War II was either good or bad

    instead of some of both?

    Likewise, can you say that you must live either by faith or by reason? Are these two categories

    as clear-cut and antagonistic as the media portrays them? Or are they, like the good and evil,

    often intermixed?

    I argue in this book, and specifically in this introduction, that faith and reason are not

    antagonistic but are collaborative. Furthermore, the two work together not only in the lives of

    Christians, but also in the lives or non-Christians. We all live by both faith and reason.

    Tripartite Faith 

    This fact, that everyone relies on both faith and reason, can be demonstrated once we further

    define faith. And since faith is so difficult to define, I have taken the position of Charles

    Spurgeon who divides it into parts: “It is made up of three things—knowledge, belief, and trust.” 3 

    The first part of faith is knowledge, specifically indirect knowledge. Your own direct

    experiences and what you can reason from logic itself are not a part of faith, e.g. seeing your

    cat on the floor, feeling your own headache, figuring through mental math that 15 + 15 = 30. But

    nearly everything else is a part of faith.

    That the earth is round, that the universe is expanding, that your parents are your parents, that

    George Washington existed – these are all matters of indirect knowledge, and thus matters of

    faith. You did not see these things happen. You only know them on the authority of others; you

    know them by faith. In fact, you know most things by faith.

    But just because you know these propositions – that the universe is expanding, that your

    parents are your parents, etc. – does not mean that you believe them which is the second

    portion of faith. Knowing the proposition is different from attaching a truth value to the

    proposition. I know the proposition “LBJ was the nation’s greatest president” but I don’t

    necessarily believe it, that is, I don’t necessarily regard the proposition as true. And in order to

    believe something, you must first have knowledge of the proposition. A child can’t believe in the

    Holocaust unless he has heard of the Holocaust. So first there is knowledge, then there is belief.

    2 Michael Bess, Choices Under Fire: Moral Dimensions of World War II , 98-99. 

    3Charles Spurgeon, All of Grace: An Earnest Word with Those Seeking Salvation by the Lord Jesus

    Christ , chapter 8, accessed December 8, 2014, http://www.spurgeon.org/all_of_g.htm . 

    http://www.spurgeon.org/all_of_g.htmhttp://www.spurgeon.org/all_of_g.htmhttp://www.spurgeon.org/all_of_g.htmhttp://www.spurgeon.org/all_of_g.htm

  • 8/16/2019 A Degree of Faith: A Case for Christianity for the Educated Skeptic

    11/193

    Faith

    11

    These first two portions of faith are widespread. Most of what we believe is on faith: all of

    history, most of science (the experiments you didn’t personally partake in), and too much of our

    financial system. We heard of these things from authorities, and we chose to believe or not

    believe based on the authority.

    What then, is the difference between the faith of a Christian and the faith of a non-Christian?There are two main differences.

    First, Christians believe one additional proposition to be true: Jesus rose from the dead. This

    belief is not based on “blind faith,” or unsubstantiated faith. On the contrary, this is believed with

    the same faith that the non-Christian believes in Caesar’s assassination or the early death of

     Alexander the Great. These are historical questions that are believed because of the authority of

    the witnesses whom we encounter in the form of ancient texts.4 

    Second, Christians have the third part of faith: trust. This portion is what is known as saving

    faith. It means trusting the person of Jesus for your personal salvation. Spurgeon explains it

    beautifully:

    Now, true faith, in its very essence rests in this—a leaning upon Christ. It will not save

    me to know that Christ is a Saviour; but it will save me to trust him to be my Saviour. I

    shall not be delivered from the wrath to come by believing that his atonement is

    sufficient, but I shall be saved by making that atonement my trust, my refuge, and my all.

    The pith, the essence of faith lies in this—a casting one-self on the promise.... To use an

    old and hackneyed illustration: suppose a fire in the upper room of a house, and the

    people gathered in the street. A child is in the upper story: how is he to escape? He

    cannot leap down—that were to be dashed to pieces. A strong man comes beneath, and

    cries, "Drop into my arms." It is a part of faith to know that the man is there; it is anotherpart of faith to believe that the man is strong; but the essence of faith lies in the dropping

    down into the man's arms. That is the proof of faith, and the real pith and essence of it.

    So, sinner, thou art to know that Christ died for sin; thou art also to understand that

    Christ is able to save, and thou art to believe that; but thou art not saved, unless in

    addition to that, thou puttest thy trust in him to be thy Saviour, and to be thine for ever.5 

    So what is faith not ? Faith is not forcing yourself to believe something despite the evidence.

    On the contrary, it is forcing yourself to act on the evidence despite your feelings. C.S. Lewis

    illustrates this finely:

    My reason is is perfectly convinced by good evidence that anaesthetics do not smother

    me and that properly trained surgeons do not start operating until I am unconscious. But

    that does not alter the fact that when they have me down on the table and clap their

    horrible mask over my face, a mere childish panic begins inside me. I start thinking I am

    4 For the reliability of the witnesses, cf. chapter 13.  

    5 Charles Spurgeon, “Faith,” accessed December 8, 2014, http://www.spurgeon.org/sermons/0107.htm. 

    http://www.spurgeon.org/sermons/0107.htmhttp://www.spurgeon.org/sermons/0107.htmhttp://www.spurgeon.org/sermons/0107.htmhttp://www.spurgeon.org/sermons/0107.htm

  • 8/16/2019 A Degree of Faith: A Case for Christianity for the Educated Skeptic

    12/193

    A DEGREE OF FAITH 

    12

    going to choke, and I am afraid they will start cutting me up before I am properly under.

    In other words, I lose my faith in anaesthetics. It is not reason that is taking away my

    faith: on the contrary, my faith is based on reason. It is my imagination and emotions.

    The battle is between faith and reason on one side and emotion and imagination on the

    other.6 

     As you can see, it is often our emotions that keep us from the truth. This book seeks to

    present the truth of Christianity to the reader’s mind, and asks that the reader keep an open

    heart.

    Models of Unbelief  

    If you seek to understand anything, it never hurts to better understand yourself. Below I have

    categorized what I see to be the most common personality profiles of unbelief. I do not mean to

    stereotype; this is merely an exercise in introspection. Look at these types and ask yourself,

    “With which do I most identify?” And, hopefully, once you have identified your type, you will be

    able to notice your own biases. It is not bad to have biases. Everyone has biases, but we should

    be aware of what they are. Mine is the Apologist which is the Christian corollary to the

    Enlightened.

    Let me say again, please don’t be offended. These are only personality profiles.

    1. The Rebel

    The defining feature of the Rebel is that he refuses to place his trust in Jesus even though he is

    more or less convinced of the truth of Christianity.

    Examples include:

    ●  Binx Bolling from Walker Percy’s novel The Moviegoer who states: “The proofs of God’s

    existence may have been true for all I know, but it didn’t make the slightest difference. If

    God himself appeared to me, it would have changed nothing. In fact, I have only to hear

    the word God and a curtain comes down in my head.”7 

    ●  Hazel Motes from Flannery O’Connor’s novel Wise Blood : “‘Do you think I believe in

    Jesus?’ he said, leaning toward her and speaking almost as if he were breathless. ‘Well I

    wouldn’t even if He existed. Even if He was on this train.’”8 

    ●  The demons from James 2:19 (ESV): “You believe that God is one; you do well. Even

    the demons believe—and shudder!” 

    6 C.S. Lewis, The Complete C.S. Lewis Signature Classics (New York: HarperOne, 2002), 116-117. 

    7 Walker Percy, The Moviegoer (New York: Vintage Books, 1989), 145. 

    8 Flannery O’Connor, Wise Blood (New York: Farrar, Straus, and Giroux, 1990), 10. 

  • 8/16/2019 A Degree of Faith: A Case for Christianity for the Educated Skeptic

    13/193

    Faith

    13

    If you evangelize to them... they may get angry.

    When it comes to Truth... they think, “It doesn’t matter what the truth is, I’ll never believe.”  

    Christian Corollary: the Fundamentalist who thinks, “Science could show every part of thebible to be false, and I’d still believe.” 

    How to approach them: Show the ultimate emptiness of whatever they currently place their

    trust in, e.g. career success, sexual freedom, social activism, etc.

    2. The Post-Christian

    The Post-Christian is just not interested in Christianity. He probably has a worldview that

    seems to work well enough for him already and thus shows zero interest in Christianity. You

    might as well try and convert him into an ancient pagan. He is entirely apathetic when it comesto this topic.9 

    Examples include:

    ●  Meursault from Albert Camus’ novel The Stranger : “I said that I didn’t believe in God. He

    wanted to know if I was sure and I said that I didn’t see any reason to ask myself that

    question: it seemed unimportant.... In any case, I may not have been sure about what

    really did interest me, but I was absolutely sure about what didn’t. And it just so 

    happened that what he was talking about didn’t interest me.”10 

    ●  Ira Glass, who said: “I find that I don't seem to have a choice over whether or not Ibelieve in God. I simply find that I do not. And trying to force myself to believe, it would

    be like trying to convince yourself that you're in love with somebody who you're not in

    love with.”11 

    If you evangelize to them... they won’t argue with you. They will probably just politely refuse

    because they aren’t interested. 

    When it comes to Truth... they agree that the Truth matters. But they aren’t looking for the

    truth because what they have seems to work just fine. 

    Christian Corollary: Cultural Christians who think, “Why would I not believe in God? I’ve

    always believed.” 

    9 Christian belief is not a “live” option for the Post-Christian, cf. chapter 1. 

    10 Albert Camus, The Stranger, trans. Matthew Ward (New York: Vintage Books, 1989), 116. 

    11 Ira Glass, “Faith” This American Life, December 20, 2001, WBEZ Chicago, accessed December 8,

    2014, http://www.thisamericanlife.org/radio-archives/episode/202/transcript . 

    http://www.thisamericanlife.org/radio-archives/episode/202/transcripthttp://www.thisamericanlife.org/radio-archives/episode/202/transcripthttp://www.thisamericanlife.org/radio-archives/episode/202/transcripthttp://www.thisamericanlife.org/radio-archives/episode/202/transcript

  • 8/16/2019 A Degree of Faith: A Case for Christianity for the Educated Skeptic

    14/193

    A DEGREE OF FAITH 

    14

    How to approach them: Inspire wonder and show how mysterious reality truly is. 

    3. The Enlightened

    The Enlightened views himself as too smart for Christianity. Whereas the Post-Christiandoesn’t have any arguments, the Enlightened man knows all the arguments against Christianity.

    He delights in using these arguments to show intellectual superiority to Christians.

    Examples include:

    ●  Thomas Jefferson

    ●  Bart Ehrman

    ●  Most of the new atheists

    If you evangelize to them... they will debate you. You can argue philosophical and historical

    points with the Enlightened.

    When it comes to Truth... they desire it and spend much time searching for it.

    Christian Corollary: The Apologist

    How to approach them: Show the superior arguments for Christianity. Remind them that

    humans do not have the minds of gods.

    4. The Post-Modern

    The Post-Modern believes in Jesus, but also believes in every other religion because all truth ispart of the greater truth that truth is relative. He tends to chose his own philosophy from portions

    of many different religions and based on his core values of tolerance, anti-conflict, and love.

    Examples include:

    ●  John Lennon

    ●  Pi from Yann Martel’s Life of Pi .

    If you evangelize to them... they will just agree with you because all truth is relative. Why

    argue when we are called to love one another?

    When it comes to Truth... they don’t believe in objective Truth. All truth is relative. There is

    something of truth in everything.

    Christian Corollary: The Liberal Christian who seems to use religion only as a vehicle for

    deeper beliefs in tolerance and acceptance.

    How to approach them: Show the deep beauty and visceral reasons for Christianity.

  • 8/16/2019 A Degree of Faith: A Case for Christianity for the Educated Skeptic

    15/193

    Faith

    15

    Each personality profile can also be described by which of the three portions of faith it has.

    Remember that faith is composed of knowledge, belief, and trust.

    Knowledge of

    Doctrines

    Belief Trust

    The Rebel Yes Yes No

    The Post-Christian Yes or Partial No No

    The Enlightened Yes No No

    The Post-Modern Yes, BUT w/ hereticalextras

    Yes, BUT in wrongdoctrine as well

    Yes, BUT notexclusive trust

     As you can see, each personality profile requires a different starting point.

    The Rebel already knows and believes, and therefore it would be useless to tell him doctrines

    or try to convince him of their truth. Instead you must show the futility of trusting in anything

    other than Jesus.

    The Post-Christian needs to be shown the genuine doctrines of Christianity and how strange

    they are first. The wonder of it all must be shown in order to give them new eyes.

    The Enlightened needs to have his arguments defeated or at least subdued first.

    The Post-Modern needs to be first disabused of several notions, such as the relativity of truth.

    Short Outline 

    This book builds a case for Christianity from the ground up. It is designed to show the existence

    of a benevolent creator God and that this same God became the man Jesus who was crucified

    and rose again on the third day. Each section of the book builds upon the former sections.

    However, don’t stop reading if you get stuck. Just jump ahead and there should be small

    summaries of past information where necessary.

    Part I argues that the only workable worldview is one that allows for the supernatural. In this

    part I delve into questions of epistemology that become quite mind-bending.

    Part II argues for the existence of a creator God. This part is valuable for all theists and all

    members of an Abrahamic religion (Judaism, Christianity, and Islam). This part is mostly

    philosophical with small portions of scientific arguments.

  • 8/16/2019 A Degree of Faith: A Case for Christianity for the Educated Skeptic

    16/193

    A DEGREE OF FAITH 

    16

    Part III argues for Christianity in particular. This part uses historical arguments to show that

    Jesus was who he said he was and that he died and rose again.

    This book does not discuss a few topics that, despite their importance, are not necessary for

    the argument this book makes. Some of these topics that are beyond the scope of this book

    include: Darwinism, inerrancy, and accusations that Paul’s letters are pseudepigraphical (similaraccusations against the Gospels, on the other hand, are discussed).

    Finally, I have put some questions in the text to allow the reader to self-evaluate and make the

    book more interactive. I lifted this idea from Walker Percy’s Lost in the Cosmos. I hope you’ll

    make use of them.

  • 8/16/2019 A Degree of Faith: A Case for Christianity for the Educated Skeptic

    17/193

    Faith

    17

    Bibliography

    Bess, Michael. Choices Under Fire: Moral Dimensions of World War II. New York: Vintage Books, 2008.

    Camus, Albert. The Stranger. Translated by Matthew Ward. New York: Vintage Books, 1989. 

    Glass, Ira. “Faith.” This American Life. December 20, 2001, WBEZ Chicago.http://www.thisamericanlife.org/radio-archives/episode/202/transcript . 

    Lewis, C.S. The Complete C.S. Lewis Signature Classics. New York: HarperOne, 2002. 

    O’Connor, Flannery. Wise Blood. New York: Farrar, Straus, and Giroux, 1990. 

    Percy, Walker. The Moviegoer. New York: Vintage Books, 1989.

    Spurgeon, Charles. All of Grace: An Earnest Word with Those Seeking Salvation by the Lord Jesus

    Christ. Chapter 8. http://www.spurgeon.org/all_of_g.htm . 

    Spurgeon, Charles. “Faith.” http://www.spurgeon.org/sermons/0107.htm. 

    http://www.thisamericanlife.org/radio-archives/episode/202/transcripthttp://www.thisamericanlife.org/radio-archives/episode/202/transcripthttp://www.spurgeon.org/all_of_g.htmhttp://www.spurgeon.org/all_of_g.htmhttp://www.spurgeon.org/all_of_g.htmhttp://www.spurgeon.org/sermons/0107.htmhttp://www.spurgeon.org/sermons/0107.htmhttp://www.spurgeon.org/sermons/0107.htmhttp://www.spurgeon.org/sermons/0107.htmhttp://www.spurgeon.org/all_of_g.htmhttp://www.thisamericanlife.org/radio-archives/episode/202/transcript

  • 8/16/2019 A Degree of Faith: A Case for Christianity for the Educated Skeptic

    18/193

    Part I: Worldview and Epistemology

  • 8/16/2019 A Degree of Faith: A Case for Christianity for the Educated Skeptic

    19/193

    Chapter 1: Epistemology

    or

    Is everyone but me a mindless zombie?

    He stretcheth out the north over the empty place, and hangeth the earth upon nothing.

    — Job 26:7 (KJV)

    Thought Experiment: Imagine that you are dreaming. Then, down from the sky, descends a

    radiant person holding a shiny smooth tablet. This effulgent being claims to have the Answer to

    all of life’s mysteries on the tablet. However, before you can receive the Answer, the brilliant

    person must test whether or not you have a belief-system capable of supporting the Answer.

    The dazzling being starts the exam by gauging your reaction to the following statements:

    1. The earth was created roughly ten thousand years ago by an act of divine power.

    2. Humans and chimpanzees evolved from a common ancestor that lived 5 to 8 millionyears ago.

    3. It is wrong to murder.

    4. Water boils at 212 degrees Fahrenheit.

    5. If A and B, then C. Yes, A and B. Therefore, C.

    6. 2 + 2 = 4.

    7. Jesus of Nazareth was crucified circa AD 30.

    8. Jesus of Nazareth rose from the dead on the third day after his crucifixion.

    9. George Washington was the first President of the USA.

    10. I have a self, or soul, that is continuous despite the fact that my body is composed of

    different atoms now than ten years ago.

    11. I have free will, and therefore, am, to some degree, responsible for my decisions andactions.

    12. All truth is relative.

    13. The world outside of my mind is not an illusion.

    14. Other people have minds.

    15. God exists.

    16. My memories are genuine.

    Question: Look at the statements you believe. Why do you believe them?

    ❏Because you’ve seen it (or heard/felt/tasted/smelled it)? 

    ❏ Because it is directly obvious to your mind.

    ❏ Because that’s what people say and you’ve never had any reason to doubt it.  

    ❏ Because it’s given to you on good authority. 

    ❏ Because it is derived from other ideas that you deem trustworthy.

    ❏ Because society could not function if it were not true.

    ❏ Because the statement is a necessary precondition for any knowledge to be possible.

    ❏ Because you couldn’t interact with others and find meaning in relationships if it were not

  • 8/16/2019 A Degree of Faith: A Case for Christianity for the Educated Skeptic

    20/193

    A DEGREE OF FAITH 

    20

    true.

    (CHECK ONE OR MORE)

    Question: Look at the statements you don’t believe. Why don’t you believe them? 

    ❏ Because there is no evidence for it.❏ Because it would identify you with a group with which you would rather not associate.

    ❏ Because the evidence is against it.

    ❏ Because it clashes with your other more deeply held beliefs.

    ❏ Because, if it were true, then you would have to make life changes.

    ❏ Because it is the product of pre-Enlightenment superstition.

    ❏ Because it is the product of post-modern “thinking.” 

    ❏ Because you’ve never thought about it. 

    (CHECK ONE OR MORE)

    Why do we believe what we believe?

    The question sounds simple enough, but try to answer it while imagining a petulant child next

    to you. Every time you give an answer, this child will screech a high-pitched “WHYYYY?”

     Answer that , and again the child will ask, “WHYYY?” Repeat ad nauseum.

    Eventually, you will get to something foundational, something so basic and vital to your belief-

    structure that you have never questioned it before. And then the child, once again, annoyingly

    asks why you believe that. At this point, you have unwittingly become embroiled in the

    philosophic debate over epistemology, or how we can know anything. And then you realize, to

    your surprise, that the petulant child has been speaking with a French accent, has luxurious

    black hair and a soul-patch, and is none other than René Descartes, the great 17th

     centuryphilosopher.

    Now, before I address your French friend, let’s look at the epistemological abyss into which

    he’s so helpfully lowered you. By the end of the questioning, you probably had come to a couple

    of dead-end beliefs at which you could go no further, a position known as Classical

    Foundationalism.

    Classical Foundationalism 

    Classical Foundationalism is the epistemological position that all our beliefs should be based on

    either logic or direct observation. Think of these two as the firm stone foundation on which your

    whole belief-structure is built. Why do you believe that 2 + 2 = 4? Because of logic. Why do you

    believe that this book exists? Because you see it. And any other belief you have must be based

    on logic, the senses, or derived from those two.

  • 8/16/2019 A Degree of Faith: A Case for Christianity for the Educated Skeptic

    21/193

    Epistemology

    21

    Therefore, Classical Foundationalism’s answer to the question posed at the beginning of this

    chapter — “Why do we believe what we believe?”— is this: We believe because of the evidence

    of logic and our senses.

    But is this answer sufficient?

    Problems with Classical Foundationalism 

    The first problem with Classical Foundationalism is that it is self-referentially incoherent . In other

    words, Classical Foundationalism fails its own test. It contradicts itself. It is neither (1) proven by

    logic nor (2) proven by the senses. In other words, you could sit outside in the woods for all

    eternity and never once will you see Classical Foundationalism come crashing through the

    bushes. And never once will you reach it through the mere manipulation of thought itself.

    The second problem with Classical Foundationalism is that even if you could  prove it by logic

    or the senses, that might not be enough. For how do we know we can trust logic or the senses?

    Logic’s Weak Link: A Critique of Rationalism 

    This brings us promptly back to René Descartes.

    Descartes is most famous for his skeptical method in which he doubted everything in search of

    a completely stable foundation on which to base his philosophy. He describes it thus:

    I thought . . . that I ought to reject as absolutely false all opinions in regard to

    which I could suppose the least ground for doubt…. Accordingly, seeing that our

    senses sometimes deceive us, I was willing to suppose that there existed nothing reallysuch as they presented to us; and because some men err in reasoning…. I,

    convinced that I was as open to error as any other, rejected as false all the

    reasonings I had hitherto taken for demonstrations; and finally, when I considered

    that the very same thoughts which we experience when awake may also be experienced

    when we are asleep, while there is at that time not one of them true, I supposed that all

    the objects that had ever entered into my mind when awake, had in them no more truth

    than the illusions of my dreams.1 (my emphasis) 

    Descartes points to the fact that people sometimes make logical mistakes as evidence that

    logic is not trustworthy enough as a foundation of knowledge. However, I wouldn’t go that far.The existence of occasional mistakes in DNA replication doesn’t mean that the process isn’t

    reliable on the whole for transferring genetic material.

    1 René Descartes, Discourse on Method (New York: P.F. Collier & Son, 1909), accessed December 2,

    2014, http://www.bartleby.com/34/1/4.html . 

    http://www.bartleby.com/34/1/4.htmlhttp://www.bartleby.com/34/1/4.htmlhttp://www.bartleby.com/34/1/4.htmlhttp://www.bartleby.com/34/1/4.html

  • 8/16/2019 A Degree of Faith: A Case for Christianity for the Educated Skeptic

    22/193

    A DEGREE OF FAITH 

    22

    On the other hand, if there was a systemic  problem, one that casts aspersion on the reliability

    of the logical process as a whole, instead of specific instances of mistakes, then logic might not

    be so reliable after all. Is there such a fundamental flaw in logic?

    I was introduced to this problem in a short piece entitled “What the Tortoise Said to Achilles” 

    written by Lewis Carroll.2

     The scene opens with swift-footed Achilles having overtaken thetortoise in a foot-race,3 and Achilles is sitting on the tortoise’s shell. The tortoise, though, poses

    a question that even mythology’s fastest man won’t be able to catch before it falls into the vortex

    of an infinite regress. The tortoise starts with a simple logical argument. The two premises are

    labeled A and B, and the conclusion is labeled Z.

     A: Things that are equal to the same thing are equal to each other.

    B: Two sides of this triangle are equal to the same thing.

    Therefore, Z: the two sides of this triangle are equal to each other.

    The tortoise states this argument and asks Achilles if he agrees. And Achilles, like many of us,

    finds the truth of this argument to be immediately apparent. He says that, yes, Z follows logically  

    from A and B. But the tortoise disagrees with that statement.

    Now, the tortoise doesn’t doubt that A and B are true, but he does doubt the hypothetical

    proposition— let’s call it C— which says that “if A and B, then Z.” So they write that down in a

    notebook.

    Now they have:

     A: Things that are equal to the same thing are equal to each other.

    B: Two sides of this triangle are equal to the same thing.

    C: If A and B are true, then Z is true.Therefore, Z: the two sides of this triangle are equal to each other.

     Achilles says to the tortoise that he must accept that! But the tortoise asks, “Why?” 

    “Because,” says Achilles, “it follows logically  from them. If A and B and C are true, Z

    must  be true. You can’t dispute that , I imagine?” 

    2

     Lewis Carroll, “What the Tortoise Said to Achilles” Mind  4, No. 14 (1895): 278-280, accessedDecember 2, 2014, http://www.ditext.com/carroll/tortoise.html . 3By his choice of setting and characters, Lewis is referencing one of the paradoxes of Zeno, a rationalist

    pre-Socratic philosopher. Zeno claimed that given a race between Achilles and a tortoise in which thetortoise is given a head start, Achilles will never be able to catch the tortoise. For, in the time it takes Achilles to move forward, the tortoise will invariably have moved forward. And when Achilles movesforward more, the tortoise will still move forward more, ad infinitum. Thus, says Zeno, Achilles can nevercatch the tortoise, and all movement is an illusion. The flaw in Zeno’s argument, though, is that hepresupposes that Achilles and the tortoise move at the same rate even though he presumably pickedthose two characters because one is fast and the other slow.  

    http://www.ditext.com/carroll/tortoise.htmlhttp://www.ditext.com/carroll/tortoise.htmlhttp://www.ditext.com/carroll/tortoise.htmlhttp://www.ditext.com/carroll/tortoise.html

  • 8/16/2019 A Degree of Faith: A Case for Christianity for the Educated Skeptic

    23/193

    Epistemology

    23

    “If A and B and C are true, Z must  be true,” the Tortoise thoughtfully repeated. “That’s

    another  Hypothetical, isn’t it?”4 

    So then they add another proposition, what the tortoise just said, and they call it D: “If A and B

    and C are true, Z must be true.” 

    So they write that one down. But again, the tortoise refuses to accept that the premises

    necessitate the conclusion unless there is another premise which says so. And this continues

    on and on and on with Achilles writing down endless propositions in the notebook forever.

    Now what is this story supposed to show? Well, there have been many debates about that.

    But what I learned from it is the unprovability of logic. It shows that logic’s attempts to prove

    itself just fall into an infinite regress. The truth of logic may be immediately apparent to us, but

    that is its only authority. Logic cannot prove itself, nor can anything else prove it.

    To be clear, I am not saying that the fundamental laws of logic contradict  themselves. But I amsaying that the basics of logic are unprovable and unproven. In other words, even logic, on

    which we base nearly all our beliefs, is not absolutely proven. And given that fact, should we

    rely on it as heavily as we do?

    Perception’s Problems: A Critique of Empiricism 

    Since logic is unproven and unprovable, let’s test empiricism, the other pillar of Classical

    Foundationalism. Empiricism means relying on sense-experience such as sight, hearing, smell,

    taste, and/or touch as the path to knowledge.

    First, let’s look back at that same Descartes quote: 

    I thought . . . that I ought to reject as absolutely false all opinions in regard to

    which I could suppose the least ground for doubt…. Accordingly, seeing that our

    senses sometimes deceive us, I was willing to suppose that there existed nothing

    really such as they presented to us; and because some men err in reasoning…. I,

    convinced that I was as open to error as any other, rejected as false all the reasonings I

    had hitherto taken for demonstrations; and finally, when I considered that the very

    same thoughts which we experience when awake may also be experienced when

    we are asleep, while there is at that time not one of them true, I supposed that all

    the objects that had ever entered into my mind when awake, had in them no moretruth than the illusions of my dreams.5 (my emphasis) 

    Have you ever wondered if your life were just a dream? Or if you were actually just a brain in a

    vat that’s being electrically stimulated to have experiences like a person in the Matrix? These

    4 Carroll, “What the Tortoise Said to Achilles.” 5 Descartes, Discourse on Method.

  • 8/16/2019 A Degree of Faith: A Case for Christianity for the Educated Skeptic

    24/193

    A DEGREE OF FAITH 

    24

    are the doubts to which Descartes is referring. Sure, we see this or that, but how do we know

    that these things really exist? Descartes understood that just because these images and

    sensations are in our minds, it doesn’t necessarily follow that they actually exist outside of our

    minds, especially given the possibility that we are dreaming, being deceived by some evil

    demon, or having our brains electrically stimulated by our machine overlords. If it is even

     possible that we are being deceived about our sensations, then empiricism is no more proventhan logic.

    Second, even supposing that our perceptions correspond to a reality outside of our minds,

    empiricism still has a problem providing us with knowledge. This problem is called the problem

    of induction.

    Induction means observing several instances of a phenomenon and then making a general

    rule about how it all works. For example, if every time you drop an apple it falls to the floor, then

    you can induce that all apples naturally fall to the floor. Then through other experiences, you

    notice that everything falls to the floor. From these many particular experiences, you induce a

    law of gravity that says everything falls to the floor unless otherwise supported.

    The problem of induction, then, can be illustrated as a dialogue between an empiricist and a

    skeptic:

    SKEPTIC: Why do you think that if I drop this apple it will fall to the ground?

    EMPIRICIST: Because we have done millions of trials and apples always fall to the

    ground when we let go of them.

    SKEPTIC: So we are assuming that the future will be like the past? In the past, the applefell to the ground, so in the future it also will?

    EMPIRICIST: Yes, that’s what we are doing. We are inducing laws of nature by finding

    patterns in our past observations.

    SKEPTIC: Okay, we are finding rules derived from past observations. But how do you

    know that the future will be like the past?

    EMPIRICIST: I know because induction has always worked in the past.

    SKEPTIC: Yes, but how do you know that the future will be like the past?

    EMPIRICIST: Because the future has always been like the past. Therefore, I induce a

    general law that the future works like the past.

    SKEPTIC: Hold on, aren’t you using induction to prove that induction is reliable? Isn’t

    that a circular argument? You only believe this apple will fall because it always has in the

  • 8/16/2019 A Degree of Faith: A Case for Christianity for the Educated Skeptic

    25/193

    Epistemology

    25

    past. But you only believe that the future will be like the past because it always has been

    like the past.

    Do you see what happened there? The empiricist can only induce things because the future is

    like the past, but he only knows the future is like the past because the future has always been

    like the past, and he only knows that , i.e. that the future has always been like the past, becausethe future has always been like the past, and so on and so on ad infinitum.

    Here we find that empiricism is in the same boat as logic, that is, in the boat forever swirling

    into an infinite Charybdis of self-justification, never to reach the bottom.

    Parable: A man lived with his young son at the top of a tower that pierced the clouds. One day,

    his son came to him trembling and asked, “Father, we live above the clouds. How is it that we

    have not fallen through the floor to our doom?” So his father brought him a piece of sturdy

    material and said, “Our tower is made of this material which is too sturdy to fail us.” The child

    was satisfied and went away glad.

    The next day, the child returned to his father and asked with a quivering voice, “Father, we live

    above the clouds. How is it that our tower has not been blown over by the wind, dooming us?”

    So his father brought him to the architect that designed their tower. And the architect said to the

    child, “Be not afraid. I designed this building to withstand any possible wind by anchoring it with

    beams deep underground.” At this answer the child was satisfied and went away glad.

     A few days later, the child ran to his father with tears in his eyes and said, “Father, we live

    above the clouds. How is it that our tower has not fallen through the earth, dooming us?” So the

    father took him to the ground outside and said, “Jump up and down. Feel how sturdy the earth

    is. Nothing can shake it. Nothing can fall through it.” At this, the child was satisfied and went

    away glad.

    Meanwhile, the Earth soars through space at 67,000 miles per hour, a spinning speck of dust

    in a vast galaxy of fire and debris.

    Reductio ad Absurdum 

    So far, not only have I shown that Classical Foundationalism contradicts itself (since it isn’t itself

    derived from logic or empiricism), I have also shown that logic and induction cannot be proven

    without infinite regress.

    Now, I will list some propositions that I think true and necessary, and yet Classical

    Foundationalism denies. From this, we can conclude that Classical Foundationalism is

    insufficient as an epistemological basis, and we’ll need to find something else.

    G.K. Chesterton lists some of these necessary truths in his essay “Philosophy for the

    Schoolroom” and notes that these propositions are accepted by all sane people and yet are

  • 8/16/2019 A Degree of Faith: A Case for Christianity for the Educated Skeptic

    26/193

    A DEGREE OF FAITH 

    26

    unproven and unprovable: 6 

    1. Every sane man believes that the world around him and the people in it are real, and not

    his own delusion or dream. No man starts burning London in the belief that his servant

    will soon wake him for breakfast. But that I, at any given moment, am not in a dream, is

    unproved and unprovable. That anything exists except myself is unproved andunprovable.

    2. All sane men believe that this world not only exists, but matters. Every man believes

    there is a sort of obligation on us to interest ourselves in this vision or panorama of life.

    He would think a man wrong who said, “I did not ask for this farce and it bores me. I am

    aware that an old lady is being murdered down-stairs, but I am going to sleep.”  That

    there is any such duty to improve the things we did not make is a thing unproved and

    unprovable.

    3. All sane men believe that there is such a thing as a self, or ego, which is continuous.

    There is no inch of my brain matter the same as it was ten years ago. But if I have saved

    a man in battle ten years ago, I am proud; if I have run away, I am ashamed. That there

    is such a paramount “I”  is unproved and unprovable. But it is more than unproved and

    unprovable; it is definitely disputed by many metaphysicians.

    4. Lastly, most sane men believe, and all sane men in practice assume, that they have a

    power of choice and responsibility for action.

    In summary, Chesterton says these propositions are unproven and unprovable: 1) that the

    world exists, and other minds exist; (2) that events matter, and we have moral obligations; (3)

    that there is continuity of personhood/identity; and (4) that we have free will. Additionally, we

    can add logic and induction to this list, making six necessary and unprovable foundational

    beliefs.

    So now the question is this: Given that none of these important beliefs are supported by

    evidence, what do we believe in the absence of evidence?

    Belief in the Absence of Evidence: Three Models 

    I would not want to jettison a single one of these unprovable propositions, but Classical

    Foundationalism would have you reject all of them, or at least the four that Chesterton mentions.

    In the absence of evidence, Classical Foundationalism abides by W.K. Clifford’s maxim: “It is

    wrong always, everywhere, and for anyone, to believe anything upon insufficient evidence.”7 

     And while this may seem prudent at first, remember that this is setting the burden of proof very

    high— so high, in fact, that many of our most important beliefs don’t qualify! 

    6 G.K. Chesterton, “Philosophy for the Schoolroom” Daily News, June 22, 1907, accessed December 2,

    2014, http://www.chesterton.org/philosophy-for-the-schoolroom/ . 7 W.K. Clifford, “The Ethics of Belief” Contemporary Review , 1877, accessed December 2, 2014,

    http://people.uwec.edu/beachea/clifford.html . 

    http://www.chesterton.org/philosophy-for-the-schoolroom/http://www.chesterton.org/philosophy-for-the-schoolroom/http://www.chesterton.org/philosophy-for-the-schoolroom/http://people.uwec.edu/beachea/clifford.htmlhttp://people.uwec.edu/beachea/clifford.htmlhttp://people.uwec.edu/beachea/clifford.htmlhttp://www.chesterton.org/philosophy-for-the-schoolroom/

  • 8/16/2019 A Degree of Faith: A Case for Christianity for the Educated Skeptic

    27/193

    Epistemology

    27

    The downside to such a position is aptly explained by William James in his lecture, “The Will to

    Believe”: 

    Believe truth! Shun error!—  these, we see, are two materially different laws; and by

    choosing between them we may end up by coloring differently our whole intellectual life.

    We may regard the chase for truth as paramount, and the avoidance of error assecondary; or we may, on the other hand, treat the avoidance of error as more

    imperative, and let truth take its chance. Clifford, in the instructive passage which I have

    quoted, exhorts us to the latter course. Believe nothing, he tells us, keep your mind in

    suspense forever, rather than by closing it on insufficient evidence incur the awful risk of

    believing lies. You, on the other hand, may think that the risk of being in error is a very

    small matter when compared with the blessings of real knowledge, and be ready to be

    duped many times in your investigation rather than postpone indefinitely the chance of

    guessing true. I myself find it impossible to go with Clifford. 8 

    If we, likewise, find it impossible to go with Clifford, then what are our options?

    One option is Reformed Epistemology which holds that our beliefs are justified, or have

    warrant, if they are (1) produced by properly functioning cognitive faculties that (2) were

    designed to attain truth (3) in an environment for which they were designed. If those three

    conditions are met, then a belief is properly basic, that is, it doesn’t need logical or empirical

    support.9 

    For example, you have warrant for believing that you truly resemble your reflection in the

    mirror because (1) you are awake and not under the influence of hallucinogens, (2) your eyes

    were designed (by God, presumably) to accurately convey visual information to your brain, and

    (3) the mirror is not a trick-mirror or a life size photo.

    The consequences of Reformed Epistemology are profound. Under this model, you can

    provide warrant for logic and induction, belief in other minds, belief in morality, belief in the

    continuity of personhood, and belief in free will. Furthermore, a belief in the existence of God

    can be warranted without logical or empirical evidence so long as the individual has the sensus

    divinitatis, or an ingrained belief in the divine.

    Whereas Classical Foundationalism says to reject beliefs until you have reason to accept

    them, Reformed Epistemology says to accept beliefs until you have reason to reject them,

    provided that you have an inner conviction about such beliefs. This is a much more naturalmodus operandi  and produces better results. To be clear, I’ll repeat that Reformed

    Epistemology does not uncritically accept all beliefs, it just believes them until it has a reason

    not to, and only those beliefs held by inner conviction such as a sensus divinitatis or the

    attestation of the Holy Spirit or some such mechanism. Such a method is expressed by C.S.

    8 William James, The Will to Believe and Other Essays in Popular Philosophy (New York: Longmans,

    Green, and Co., 1912), Kindle edition. 9 Alvin Plantinga, Warranted Christian Belief  (New York: Oxford University Press, 2000). 

  • 8/16/2019 A Degree of Faith: A Case for Christianity for the Educated Skeptic

    28/193

    A DEGREE OF FAITH 

    28

    Pierce: “A person may, it is true, find reason to doubt what he began by believing; but in that

    case he doubts because he has a positive reason for it, and not on account of the Cartesian

    maxim. Let us not pretend to doubt in philosophy what we do not doubt in our hearts.” 10 

     A second alternative to Classical Foundationalism, or really an addendum to it, is expressed

    by William James:

    The thesis I defend is, briefly stated, this: Our passional nature not only lawfully may, but

    must, decide an option between propositions, whenever it is a genuine option that

    cannot by its nature be decided on intellectual grounds; for to say, under such

    circumstances, “Do not decide, but leave the question open,” is itself a passional

    decision— just like deciding yes or no— and is attended with the same risk of losing the

    truth.11 

    The meaning of this quote is not immediately apparent unless you are familiar with what

    James means by a “genuine” option. But first you must understand the three characteristics of

    an option. An option is either (1) live or dead, (2) fixed or open, and (3) momentous or trivial.

     An option is live if there is a real possibility of you choosing to believe or not believe. For

    example, choosing whether or not to believe in God, for many of us, is a live option. On the

    other hand, an option is dead if one of the choices is practically unbelievable. For example, it is

    impossible for me to believe in the Flying Spaghetti Monster or the Great Pumpkin. Even if I

    tried to believe, my other beliefs and general worldview would not let me. Such beliefs are so

    ridiculous to me that they are not even possible beliefs. Thus, the option to believe or not

    believe in the Great Pumpkin is a dead option.

     An option is fixed if deciding not to choose is tantamount to choosing. Examples of fixedoptions include: golfing or not golfing, believing or not believing that a plane is safe for travel,

    and placing or not placing one’s trust in Jesus for personal salvation. An option is open, on the

    other hand, if there are other choices, such as the choice to not choose. For example, the option

    between believing that the U.S. will win the most gold medals at the Olympics or that Germany

    will win the most gold medals is open because you could pick a third option by saying that

    Russia will win the most gold medals. You could even refuse to choose between the U.S. and

    Germany. Refusing to choose in a fixed option, though, such as trusting or not trusting an

    airplane to be safe, is tantamount to choosing. If you decide not to ride the plane because you

    can’t decide, then you have practically chosen that it is not safe.

    Lastly, an option is momentous or trivial. It is momentous if it is of great importance and trivial

    if it is not. For example, your choice of religion is momentous because it affects you drastically

    on every level of your life and possibly in the next life. On the other hand, your choice of

    10 C.S. Pierce, “Some Consequences of Four Incapacities” Journal of Speculative Philosophy  2 (1868):

    140-157, accessed December 2, 2014, http://www.peirce.org/writings/p27.html . 11

     James, The Will to Believe and Other Essays in Popular Philosophy.  

    http://www.peirce.org/writings/p27.htmlhttp://www.peirce.org/writings/p27.htmlhttp://www.peirce.org/writings/p27.htmlhttp://www.peirce.org/writings/p27.html

  • 8/16/2019 A Degree of Faith: A Case for Christianity for the Educated Skeptic

    29/193

    Epistemology

    29

    hypotheses in a science experiment designed to test the effects of methane on clown fish is

    trivial because you could delay judgment indefinitely without affecting your life.

     A genuine option, then, is one that is live, fixed, and momentous. And now that we know the

    basic vocabulary, we can better understand James’ thesis: In the case of a genuine option that

    cannot be decided through evidence, we not only may, but must  choose what to believe.

    I prefer James’ addendum to Classical Foundationalism more than Reformed Epistemology

    because it provides clearer criteria for when to believe something in the absence of evidence.

    Reformed Epistemology is often criticized because of all the ridiculous propositions that it could

     justify. According to Reformed Epistemology, its critics assert, someone could believe

    something as silly as the Great Pumpkin without any proof. However, that is not strictly true

    because they would need a sensus pumpkinitus that provides an inner conviction that the Great

    Pumpkin exists. If such a sensus pumpkinitus exists, then that person would be justified in

    believing in it, according to Reformed Epistemology. But is that such a flaw, especially in view of

    the many flaws of Classical Foundationalism? How many people do you know that have aninner conviction that the Great Pumpkin exists?

    In this way, the sensus divinitatis or its equivalent acts in a similar way to James’ requirement

    that a choice be a live option. James’ criteria, though, seems clearer and less liable to

    misinterpretation and confusion. According to James, if the Great Pumpkin is a live option for

    you (and both fixed and momentous), then you are justified in choosing to believe in it. But for

    the rest of us who find such a belief ridiculous, we are justified in not believing it without positive

    evidence.

    The complement, though, is that if the Great Pumpkin, or God, for that matter, is a live option

    for you, then you must choose. The option is live, the choice is momentous, and the option isfixed. Remaining agnostic is tantamount to not believing:

    We see, first, that religion offers itself as a momentous option. We are supposed to gain,

    even now, by our belief, and to lose by our non-belief, a certain vital good. Secondly,

    religion is a forced option, so far as that good goes. We cannot escape the issue by

    remaining 29eighbor29 and waiting for more light, because, although we do avoid error

    in that way if religion be untrue, we lose the good, if it be true, just as certainly as if we

    positively chose to disbelieve. It is as if a man should hesitate indefinitely to ask a certain

    woman to marry him because he was not perfectly sure that she would prove an angel

    after he brought her home. Would he not cut himself off from that particular angel-possibility as decisively as if he went and married some one else? Scepticism, then, is

    not avoidance of option; it is option of a certain particular kind of risk. Better risk loss of

    truth than chance of error —  that is your faith-vetoer’s exact position. He is actively

    playing his stake as much as the believer is; he is backing the field against the religious

    hypothesis, just as the believer is backing the religious hypothesis against the field. To

    preach 29eighbor29m to us as a duty until “sufficient evidence” for religion be found, is

    tantamount therefore to telling us, when in presence of the religious hypothesis, that to

  • 8/16/2019 A Degree of Faith: A Case for Christianity for the Educated Skeptic

    30/193

    A DEGREE OF FAITH 

    30

    yield to our fear of its being error is wiser and better than to yield to our hope that it may

    be true. It is not intellect against all passions, then; it is only intellect with one passion

    laying down its law.12 

    Thought Experiment: Imagine you are in a prison cell and hooked up to several electrodes.

    There is only one window in the cell, and through it you see someone hooked up to electrodesas you are. On the wall of your cell are two buttons. The first button unlocks the door and frees

    you, but condemns the person in the other room to a severe electric shock every hour for the

    next ten years. The second button frees the other person but condemns you to a severe electric

    shock every hour for the next ten years. And as long as you don’t push any button, both of you

    receive a severe electric shock every hour. What do you do?

    ❏ You reason that there is no such thing as morality, and therefore it’s not wrong for you to

    free yourself at the cost of another’s suffering. Push the first button. 

    ❏ You reason that while you are certain of your own capacity for pain, you aren’t sure that

    the person in the other room has a mental life similar to yours with the capacity to feel

    pain, feel pleasure, desire freedom, etc. Now that you think of it, you don’t have any

    proof at all that the person is anything more than a life-like robot without a

    consciousness, and it would be silly for you to believe something without any proof.

    Push the first button.

    ❏ You think that perhaps you are dreaming. If that is the case, then the person in the other

    room isn’t real. Push the first button. 

    ❏ What is ten years of electric shocks compared to a reward in heaven? Push the second

    button.

    ❏ You refuse to push either button and take an electric shock every hour as you

    contemplate the nature of live, fixed, and momentous choices.

    (CHECK ONE)

    Summary 

     Although we tout logic and induction as the prime means of attaining knowledge, relying wholly

    on them is dangerous. For one, neither logic nor induction can be proven. Second, the

    epistemological position of Classical Foundationalism which emphasizes logic and induction is

    self-contradictory. Third, Classical Foundationalism exhorts us not to believe many necessary

    and fundamental beliefs such as the belief in other minds, the belief in an external reality, the

    belief that memory is generally true, the belief in morality, the belief in the continuity of

    personhood, etc.

    Because of these problems, a different epistemology should be chosen, either Reformed

    Epistemology or William James’ addendum to Classical Foundationalism. Under this new

    epistemology, the aforesaid integral beliefs can be maintained. Furthermore, a belief in God is

    one of the integral beliefs that is justified outside of evidence. It is also, for most readers, a belief

    12 William James, The Will to Believe and Other Essays in Popular Philosophy.  

  • 8/16/2019 A Degree of Faith: A Case for Christianity for the Educated Skeptic

    31/193

    Epistemology

    31

    that requires a choice because to not choose in such a situation is, itself, a choice against belief.

    Evaluation 

    Rate this chapter ’s argument from 1 to 7.

    1. “I am sure this argument is wrong.” 

    2. “I think this argument is wrong, but I have minor reservations.”  

    3. “I think this argument is wrong but with some reservations.”  

    4. “I am equally convinced by both sides of this argument.” 

    5. “I think this argument is right, but with some reservations.” 

    6. “I think this argument is right, but I have minor reservations.”  

    7. “I am sure this argument is right.” 

  • 8/16/2019 A Degree of Faith: A Case for Christianity for the Educated Skeptic

    32/193

    A DEGREE OF FAITH 

    32

    Bibliography

    Carroll, Lewis. “What the Tortoise Said to Achilles.” Mind 4, No. 14 (1895): 278-280,http://www.ditext.com/carroll/tortoise.html . 

    Chesterton, G.K. “Philosophy for the Schoolroom.” Daily News, June 22, 1907.http://www.chesterton.org/philosophy-for-the-schoolroom/ . 

    Clifford, W.K. “The Ethics of Belief.” Contemporary Review , 1877.http://people.uwec.edu/beachea/clifford.html . 

    Descartes, René. Discourse on Method. New York: P.F. Collier & Son, 1909.http://www.bartleby.com/34/1/4.html . 

    James, William. The Will to Believe and Other Essays in Popular Philosophy. New York:Longmans, Green, and Co., 1912. Kindle edition.

    Pierce, C.S. “Some Consequences of Four Incapacities.” Journal of Speculative Philosophy  2(1868): 140-157. http://www.peirce.org/writings/p27.html . 

    Plantinga, Alvin. Warranted Christian Belief. New York: Oxford University Press, 2000.

    http://www.ditext.com/carroll/tortoise.htmlhttp://www.ditext.com/carroll/tortoise.htmlhttp://www.chesterton.org/philosophy-for-the-schoolroom/http://www.chesterton.org/philosophy-for-the-schoolroom/http://people.uwec.edu/beachea/clifford.htmlhttp://people.uwec.edu/beachea/clifford.htmlhttp://www.bartleby.com/34/1/4.htmlhttp://www.bartleby.com/34/1/4.htmlhttp://www.peirce.org/writings/p27.htmlhttp://www.peirce.org/writings/p27.htmlhttp://www.peirce.org/writings/p27.htmlhttp://www.peirce.org/writings/p27.htmlhttp://www.bartleby.com/34/1/4.htmlhttp://people.uwec.edu/beachea/clifford.htmlhttp://www.chesterton.org/philosophy-for-the-schoolroom/http://www.ditext.com/carroll/tortoise.html

  • 8/16/2019 A Degree of Faith: A Case for Christianity for the Educated Skeptic

    33/193

    Chapter 2: Postmodernism

    or

    Will someone stop those blind men from harassing that elephant?

    Question: How would you describe human history?

    ❏ The story of humanity is one of progress and growth. Man began as a primitive life-form,

    nothing more than an animal. Life was difficult, nasty, brutish, and short: women were

    oppressed and died in childbirth, men worked long hours in the fields doing body-

    breaking manual labor, life-spans were short, feces was ubiquitous, disease was

    rampant, war and subsequent rape and death were constant, rulers viciously subjugated

    their citizens, and most people were ignorant and superstitious. But then came science.

    Through science and technology, we have drastically increased our lifespans,

    exponentially increased our food production, eliminated most disease, given everyone

    an equal voice in government, accelerated commerce, created marvels of

    communication and transportation, propagated learning and literacy, and freed man fromthe brutal enslavement of ignorance and superstition. Mankind will continue to prosper

    as technology advances.

    ❏ The story of humanity is a depressing, morbid tale of disappointment, cruelty, and death.

    Man began as an animal and continues to be an animal. He enslaves, rapes, kills, and

    plunders his fellow man. With every advance in technology has only come an advance in

    man’s ability to do these deplorable acts. In fact, beneficial technology, for the most part,

    is merely an accidental by-product of the search for ways to better kill each other. First

    we hit each other with hard, sharp objects, then we propelled little pieces of metal at

    each other with the help of explosive powder, now we send robots flying through the air

    to rain fire and death on all below. We are now equipped with enough explosives to

    make our whole planet uninhabitable. And while there are periods of ostensibleprogress, every advance in prosperity and comfort only comes through exploitation of

    others. The West lives at ease because it colonized and exploited the rest of the world

    and continues to do so through financial institutions. Most of the rest of the world,

    though, continues to live a dirty, miserable existence that proves the idea of modern

    progress is nothing more than an oppressive lie.

    (CHECK ONE OR MORE)

    In the last chapter, we questioned how we could know anything. But we never questioned

    whether there was anything to know. We assumed that there was a Truth: we just didn’t know

    how to get to it. In other words, we started with modern presuppositions. In this chapter, though,we will question these assumptions by examining postmodernism which, as the name suggests,

    is a reaction to modernism.

    Understanding Postmodernism as a Reaction to Modernism 

    There are at least two ways to approach postmodernism. First, you could approach it in the way

    it was developed, as a reaction against modernism.

  • 8/16/2019 A Degree of Faith: A Case for Christianity for the Educated Skeptic

    34/193

    A DEGREE OF FAITH 

    34

    Below are some examples of modern thought contrasted with postmodern thought that I’ve

    paraphrased and supplemented from an Encyclopaedia Britannica article:1 

    Modernism Postmodernism 

    There is an objective reality that isindependent of observation.

     All reality is merely a social construct.

    The statements of historians and scientists,in principle, are either true or false. That eventhough we’ll never know if Herodotus wastelling the truth, there were events in the pastthat actually  happened and are trueregardless of whether we can find or expressthem.

    There is no such thing as Truth.

    Humanity, as a result of science andenlightenment, is becoming smarter, moreprosperous, more humane, and history is astory of progress. 

    Our technological achievements are not

     progress. If anything, our technologies are a

    regress. Technology only enables us to better

    torture and kill and oppress as demonstrated

    in the horrific conflict of WWII and the

    hundreds of smaller conflicts since then.

    Logic applies universally. Logic is a social construct with nometaphysical authority.

    There is a thing called human nature thatwe have in common with even ancientpeoples and can learn about through thestudy of the Greek and Roman Classics.

    Human nature is entirely determined by thesocial environment, and therefore, there areno human nature insights that can be derivedfrom reading about cultures as distant as theGreeks or Romans.

    Language reflects reality. Words only have meaning in relation toother words, and these words only havemeaning in relation to the intellectual andcultural values of the readers, and, therefore,even if there were Truth, there would be noway to express it.

    Understanding Postmodernism through its Definition 

    1 Brian Duignan, “Postmodernism and Relativism” Encyclopædia Britannica Online, s. v.

    "postmodernism", accessed December 02, 2014,http://www.britannica.com/EBchecked/topic/1077292/postmodernism/282559/Postmodernism-and-relativism. 

    http://www.britannica.com/EBchecked/topic/1077292/postmodernism/282559/Postmodernism-and-relativismhttp://www.britannica.com/EBchecked/topic/1077292/postmodernism/282559/Postmodernism-and-relativismhttp://www.britannica.com/EBchecked/topic/1077292/postmodernism/282559/Postmodernism-and-relativismhttp://www.britannica.com/EBchecked/topic/1077292/postmodernism/282559/Postmodernism-and-relativismhttp://www.britannica.com/EBchecked/topic/1077292/postmodernism/282559/Postmodernism-and-relativism

  • 8/16/2019 A Degree of Faith: A Case for Christianity for the Educated Skeptic

    35/193

    Postmodernism

    35

    The second way to approach postmodernism is to define it. So what definition of postmodernism

    do its adherents give? None. Postmodernists refuse to define postmodernism. They say it can’t

    be defined. They rail against the very idea of defining something because that presupposes

    Truth.

    Fortunately, I’m not completely postmodern, and therefore I have no compunction aboutdefining things. And since its adherents won’t supply a definition, we will use the one given by

    the aforementioned article in the Encyclopaedia Britannica. Postmodernism is:

    a late 20th-century movement characterized by broad skepticism, subjectivism, or

    relativism; a general suspicion of reason; and an acute sensitivity to the role of

    ideology in asserting and maintaining political and economic power.2  (my

    emphasis)

    That’s a huge definition. And it probably doesn’t even cover much of what is described as

    postmodern. But let’s use it to get a better picture of this philosophy and some of its pro’s and

    con’s. 

    Skepticism, Subjectivism, Relativism and Self-Defeating Statements in General 

    The first part of our definition of postmodernism is skepticism. Now, postmodern skepticism is

    different from some other branches of skepticism. But basically, skeptics say that we can never

    know truth. And I think postmodernists would agree with that. But they would also add that there

    is no such thing as Truth. This means that postmodern skepticism is self-referentially absurd, or

    self-defeating. Because the claim “there is no truth” is itself  a truth. You’ll see this happen again

    and again with postmodernism.

    The second part of our definition of postmodernism is subjectivism. Subjectivism is the idea

    that all knowledge and truth is subjective. In other words, what is true for you is not true for me,

    therefore there is no objective Truth, only subjective truths. This, also, is self-defeating because

    the claim “all truth is subjective” would itself  have to be subjective and thus not binding on all

    truths.

    To be fair, though, there is some merit to postmodernism ’s emphasis on the role of the reader

    in interpretation. It rightly points out that every reader comes to a text with a different framework

    and set of background knowledge. Therefore, each text could mean something slightly different

    to each reader, and perfect communication is impossible. But nobody has ever claimed to have

     perfect communication. Postmodernism makes its mistake by taking the same data to mean that

    all communication is impossible due to the subjective role of the reader in interpretation. There

    is no need to besmirch all communication just because perfect communication is impossible.

    The third part of the definition of postmodernism is relativism. Relativism is the idea that all

    2 Brian Duignan. “Postmodernism and Relativism.” 

  • 8/16/2019 A Degree of Faith: A Case for Christianity for the Educated Skeptic

    36/193

    A DEGREE OF FAITH 

    36

    truth is relative to cultural context. Of course, this, too, is self-defeating because the claim “all

    truth is relative” claims to be culturally independent and absolute while simultaneously holding

    that all truth is relative to cultural context.

    Question: Does Truth exist?

    ❏  As some Roman once said, “What is Truth?” There is no such thing as Truth with acapital t. There are only truths. What is true for you may not be true for me. In fact, any

    capital t Truth is no more than a power play designed to exploit others.

    ❏ Truth exists, and one day we will find it through continual application of the scientific

    method. We just haven’t gotten there yet.

    ❏ The Truth is out there, man, it’s like a great cosmic principle that guides all our actions

    and says, “Go for it, dude. Spread the love.” But it’s also, like, inside of you too. You just

    have to reach in and harness it. You are the Truth, man.

    ❏ Truth is a person, the second person of the Trinity.

    ❏ What do I care? I’ll leave that question for the philosophers.

    (CHECK ONE)

    In short, the first three aspects of postmodernism—skepticism, subjectivism, and relativism—

    are all self-defeating. In other words, if these tenets of postmodernism are true then they are

    also false. And for something to be both true and false simultaneously is a contradiction which

    violates the most basic law of logic: the law of noncontradiction. For example, if the claim “This

    statement is false” is true, then it is also false, which is a contradiction. In the same boat are the

    statements “There is no truth,” “All truth is subjective,” and “All truth is relative.” 

    To be clear, this differs from being a circular argument. In the last chapter, I demonstrated that

    both logic and induction are circular —that is, they rely on themselves to prove themselves. But

    a contradiction, a self-defeating  statement, is the opposite. If it relies on itself, it collapses.

    For a person who believes in logic, it is much worse to believe in a statement that is self-

    defeating than merely self-proving. However, if you are a postmodernist, then it, theoretically  

    shouldn’t bother you that the tenets of postmodernism are logically self -defeating. Because

    logic, to a postmodernist, is just a social construct with no metaphysical backing. In that sense,

    postmodernism is anti-intellectual and illogical despite its large adherence among the highly

    educated.

    Postmodernism in Academia 

    Why is it that postmodernism is heavily concentrated among intellectuals, especially those inthe humanities and literature departments? Perhaps it is because postmodernism relies soheavily on arguments about language.

    Berkeley philosopher John Searle, however, in his article “The Case for a Traditional LiberalEducation” gives a different explanation. He says postmodernism took hold in literaturedepartments because “during the 1960’s a fairly sizable number of leftist intellectuals became

  • 8/16/2019 A Degree of Faith: A Case for Christianity for the Educated Skeptic

    37/193

    Postmodernism

    37

    convinced that the best arena of social change was culture, that high culture in general anduniversity departments of literature in particular could become important weapons in thestruggle to overcome racism, imperialism, et cetera. We are now witnessing some of theconsequences of this migration.”3 

    If John Searle is correct, then there has always been a conscious political motive forteaching postmodernism in literature departments, and it is not taught merely for academicpurposes such as literary criticism.

    Political Cynicism 

    The last part of the definition of postmodernism is political cynicism. At heart, postmodernism is

    a reaction to colonialism, exploitation, and oppression.The desire for justice seems to be the

    motive of postmodernism, and I admire that. As with most cynical perspectives, this one too

    masks a more compassionate interior. So at the very least, I must admit that postmodernism

    usually has its heart in the right place.

    But regardless of its motive, does postmodernism accurately describe reality with its cynical

    view? Is postmodernism correct in criticizing modernism’s optimism?

    I side with postmodernism in this case. For me, today’s problems are too large and

    complicated for us to be as optimistic about our future as the modernists. The modernist

    believes that science and technology will transform our world into a utopia. All we need is more

    science. Postmodernism, on the other hand, rightly points out the silliness of the modernist ’s

    childlike faith in science. Has the modern Man seen the newsreels of WWII, the pictures of the

    near-starved Holocaust survivors, or heard accounts of the Allied firebombing of Germany and

    Japan? These examples and the almost unlimited number of similar events all prove thatgreater technology does not necessarily lead to greater happiness. The modern man makes the

    simple mistake of equating greater knowledge with greater love and compassion. The latter are

    what we need for a utopian society, not more knowledge.

    But the postmodernist hardly does more than critique modernism. At best, the postmodernist

    merely proposes progressive political reforms as if the systems of oppression are the sole

    problem. Whereas modernism views the problem as a lack of knowledge to be remedied by

    more science and technology, postmodernism views the problem as systems of oppression to

    be remedied by progressive political reforms. But both views ignore the underlying problem: the

    nature of humanity. Postmodernism does not wonder how and why systems of oppression were

    formed in the first place.

    Christianity, at this point, must step in where postmodernism left off and complete the picture.

     According to Christianity, humanity is a fallen race with a sin nature that manifests itself in war,

    enslavement, systems of oppression and exploitation, etc. The problem is not so much

    3 John Searle, “The Case for a Traditional Liberal Education,” The Journal of Blacks in Higher Education,

    no. 13 (Autumn 1996): 91-98. 

  • 8/16/2019 A Degree of Faith: A Case for Christianity for the Educated Skeptic

    38/193

    A DEGREE OF FAITH 

    38

    impersonal institutions as it is us. Humanity is the problem. And more science doesn’t remedy

    that, and neither does more tolerance and postmodern theory. Humans only function properly

    when they are in the proper relationship with their Creator.

    Truth Claims as Power Plays

    Postmodernists would never accept the Christian answer, mainly, due to the fact that it is an

    answer. An answer presupposes that there is a truth. And postmodernism knows that any truth

    claim is a power play. The reasoning goes like this: if I have the truth, then I have something

    you don’t have. And that makes me special. You might could say that I am more important than

    you since I have the truth. This gives me a cognitive excuse for alienating you, oppressing you,

    killing you. Therefore, every religion or philosophy, as a source of truth, has the seed of

    oppression built into it. Any Truth or dogma, by its very nature, causes separation, alienation,

    and oppression, if only between those who know the Truth and those who do not.

    Postmodernism attempts to obviate these unfortunate side effects by denying that Truth exists.

    If there is no right answer, if there is no dogma, then there can be nothing to fight about.

    The Parable of the Three Blind Men, the Elephant, and the Omniscient Narrator  

    If the postmodernist solution, that there is no Truth, seems difficult to grasp at first, then the

    postmodernist will probably explain it with a simple illustration: There were three blind men

    wandering around and they came upon this elephant. And the first man touched the elephant’s

    ear and said, “Ah, the elephant is soft and flat like a blanket.” And the second man touched the

    elephant’s leg and said, “No, the elephant is thick and hard like a tree trunk.” And the third man

    touched the elephant’s nose and said, “You are both wrong. The elephant is muscular and

    bendy like a snake.”

     And then the postmodernist storyteller sighs and says with a patronizing smile, “This is what

    religions and dogmas are like! Christianity sees one aspect of God, Islam sees another,

    Buddhism another, etc. But they are all just incomplete pictures of the same thing! Therefore, all

    dogmas are equally true!” 

    This story and the moral it espouses, that there is no objective Truth, seems reasonable,

    tolerant, and uncontroversial at first. But there is one major flaw  in the story—the narrator. The

    narrator can only describe the three blind men and their humor