1980 - mansbridge - review (pateman) the problem of political obligation

Upload: carolina-ferro

Post on 20-Feb-2018

220 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/24/2019 1980 - Mansbridge - Review (PATEMAN) the Problem of Political Obligation

    1/4

    American Political Science Association and Cambridge University Press are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserveand extend access to The American Political Science Review.

    http://www.jstor.org

    ReviewAuthor(s): Jane MansbridgeReview by: Jane MansbridgeSource: The American Political Science Review, Vol. 74, No. 2 (Jun., 1980), pp. 488-490Published by: American Political Science AssociationStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1960662Accessed: 23-11-2015 18:40 UTC

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of contentin a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship.For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    This content downloaded from 143.106.201.162 on Mon, 23 Nov 2015 18:40:53 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=apsahttp://www.jstor.org/stable/1960662http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/1960662http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=apsahttp://www.jstor.org/
  • 7/24/2019 1980 - Mansbridge - Review (PATEMAN) the Problem of Political Obligation

    2/4

    488

    TheAmerican

    PoliticalScience

    Review

    Vol. 74

    has

    written,

    and

    necessarily

    presuppose

    the

    existence

    of

    such

    criteria,

    which he

    has

    em-

    ployed in

    order

    to resolve

    these

    problems.

    An

    interpretation

    of

    Locke's

    ideas,

    in

    other

    words,

    always

    points

    in

    two

    directions

    in

    its

    assessment of those ideas. It presents,in some

    respect, a

    contextual

    view of

    Locke's

    intellectu-

    al

    surroundings

    n

    terms of which

    the

    meanings

    of his

    statements

    are

    explicated,

    and it

    assumes

    some

    basis for

    the

    recognition

    by

    the

    reader

    of

    the

    relevance

    of these

    views. These

    undertak-

    ings, of

    course, may

    be

    carried

    out

    well

    or

    poorly in

    terms of the

    historical

    evidence

    presented

    and the

    conscious

    attention

    paid to

    the

    interpreter's

    presuppositions.

    Against

    the

    record

    of

    existing

    scholarship

    dealingwith

    the

    history

    of

    political

    theory,

    Parry

    does reason-

    ably well. He recognizes that placingLockean

    ideas in

    their

    historical

    context

    is

    necessary

    if

    readers

    are

    to

    grasp the

    dimensions

    and

    the

    implications attached

    to the

    choices

    they

    face

    with

    respect to

    the

    many

    and

    varied Lockean

    legacies,

    which,

    like the

    ghost of

    Hamlet's

    father,

    appear

    now

    and

    then

    to

    urge

    them

    to

    commit-or

    not

    to

    commit-some

    political ac-

    tion.

    There

    is much

    to be

    said

    for

    both

    the

    relevance

    and the

    historical

    accuracy

    of

    Parry's

    Locke

    who

    opposed authoritarianism

    n

    intel-

    lectual life (p. 2). Certainly,a good deal of

    this

    anti-authoritarian

    erspective,

    especially

    in

    philosophy and

    religion,

    depends

    upon

    and

    reinforces

    the

    development

    of

    individuality

    as

    Parry

    describes

    it.

    Still,

    the

    darker

    shadows

    of this

    enlightenment

    iberalism

    begin

    to

    appear

    when we

    shift

    the

    meaning

    of

    Locke's

    indivi-

    duality towards

    its

    identification

    with

    those

    who are

    industrious,

    or its

    necessary

    connec-

    tion

    with

    private

    property,

    leading to the

    conclusion

    that

    a

    capitalist

    market

    economy is

    undoubtedly that

    which

    is

    most

    congruent

    with

    Lockean civil society (pp. 42-43, 50, 123).

    The

    interpretive

    problems in

    John

    Locke arise

    for

    Parry

    because

    his

    view

    of Locke

    supposes

    that the

    meaning

    of

    express

    consent

    extends

    to all

    individuals and

    therefore

    beyond Mac-

    pherson's

    identification

    of

    that

    term

    with

    a

    defense

    of

    property

    rights,

    although

    Parry

    admits

    that

    he

    has

    no

    textual

    warrantfor

    this

    reading

    (thus,

    he

    judges

    Locke's

    account of

    express

    consent

    to be

    seriously

    inadequate )

    (pp.

    103-08).

    At

    the same

    time,

    Parryargues

    for the

    importance of a

    moral

    dimension

    to

    Locke's linkage of private property with the

    development

    of

    individuality

    (p.

    50).

    Yet

    when later

    liberals

    (e.g.,

    T.

    H.

    Green)

    used

    this

    aspect

    of

    Lockean

    liberalism

    n defense

    of

    the

    view

    that

    society ought

    to

    redistribute

    its

    resources

    to

    place the

    deprived

    n a

    position to

    cultivate their

    individuality,

    they

    are

    accused

    by

    Parry

    of

    having

    taken

    the

    wrong

    historical

    turn

    (p.

    157).

    It

    is

    true

    that

    Locke

    did

    not

    assignthis

    task

    to civil

    society,

    but

    it

    is

    far

    from

    self-evident that

    it does more violence

    to

    his

    intentions than the attempt to use his defini-

    tion

    of

    private

    property (in its

    moral dimen-

    sion?) in defense of the

    social and

    economic

    power

    of

    IBM,

    StandardOil,

    or General

    Motors.

    Throughout John

    Locke,

    Parry is con-

    cerned-almost

    obsessed-with

    arguing hat

    civil

    society

    has

    no right

    to

    redistribute

    private

    property in

    order

    to

    lessen

    social

    inequalities

    (pp.

    120,

    153-56).

    This is

    a

    bit

    odd,

    since

    no

    one has

    attributed

    such

    a view to

    Locke. At the

    same

    time,

    Parry enlists the

    support

    of

    Hayek,

    Banfield, and

    Friedman in their

    criticisms

    of

    the ends and achievements of welfare state

    liberalism.

    There

    is

    nothing

    wrong with

    this,

    but to

    conclude, as

    Parry

    does, that

    the

    remedy

    for the

    political

    problems of

    con-

    temporarysociety

    must

    be to turn

    the

    state's

    activities

    back to

    something

    akin to

    those

    of

    Locke's civil

    government

    p. 158),

    assumes he

    construction

    of a bridge

    over

    troubled

    waters

    for which

    all the

    necessary materials

    are

    not

    provided

    n

    John

    Locke.

    RICHARD

    ASHCRAFT

    Universityof California,LosAngeles

    The

    Problem of Political

    Obligation:A

    Critical

    Analysis

    of

    Liberal

    Theory.

    By

    Carole

    Pate-

    man.

    (New York:

    John

    Wiley,

    1979.

    Pp.xi +

    205.

    $21.95.)

    Subtle insight, originality, and the dogged

    pursuit of

    an idea

    markCarole

    Pateman'snew

    book on

    political

    obligation.

    Obligation

    for

    Pateman can

    only mean

    self-assumed' bliga-

    tion (pp.

    12-13). This

    assumption

    leads her

    to

    conclude

    that only a

    fully

    participatory

    democracy-where each citizen

    either wills

    each

    law

    or actively

    consents to a

    majority

    willing

    that

    law-can create

    genuine

    political

    obliga-

    tion.

    oPateman's

    onsideration

    of different

    versions

    of

    the

    competing

    liberal

    heory

    of

    obligation

    and the analogyshe developsbetween political

    obligation and

    the

    social

    practice

    of

    promising

    form

    the

    strongest

    parts

    of

    the

    book.

    Hypo-

    thetical,

    or

    tacit,

    consent cannot

    produce

    politi-

    cal

    obligation, she

    argues,

    because

    'consent'

    is

    meaningless

    if

    people

    do not

    know

    that

    t6'

    This content downloaded from 143.106.201.162 on Mon, 23 Nov 2015 18:40:53 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/24/2019 1980 - Mansbridge - Review (PATEMAN) the Problem of Political Obligation

    3/4

    1980

    Book Reviews:

    Political

    Theory

    and

    Methodology

    489

    perform

    a certain act is

    to consent (p. 73).

    Neither

    can

    non-acts

    like electoral

    abstention

    count as acts

    of authorization

    that

    create

    obligation.

    Nor,

    if one adds the criteria of

    relatively

    free or

    consciousaction,

    can voting

    in

    a polity

    in which the government

    significantly

    manipulates public

    opinion,

    or in

    which

    the

    policy consequences

    of voting are difficult

    to

    decipher,

    be

    said to

    imply consent.

    Finally,

    Pateman

    considers the claim

    that political

    obligation

    is a spuriousproblem

    risingfrom

    the

    individualist's

    nability

    to understand what it

    means to be a

    member of a policy,

    and

    concludes that this conceptual

    view says

    nothing about specific

    rules or forms of social

    institutions (p.

    107).

    What

    of the claim that we

    are politically

    obligated to obey just laws because they are

    just? Patemandistinguishes

    between actions

    we

    4 ought

    to

    perform

    because

    those actions

    are

    generally

    right and morally

    worthy to per-

    form and actions

    we are

    obliged

    to

    perform

    because we

    have

    voluntarily

    assumed that obli-

    gation.

    In the first

    case, she argues,the citizen

    simply accepts

    or

    recognizes

    an

    already

    existing

    duty;

    only

    in the

    second

    case is there a

    freely

    created,

    public, obligation (pp.

    28-29). This

    distinction

    between

    what

    we

    ought

    to do and

    the

    obligations

    we

    have

    voluntarily

    assumed is

    useful. But Pateman does not convinceme that

    it

    is useful to

    restrict

    the

    term

    obligation

    to

    that

    which we have

    voluntarily

    assumed.

    It

    would

    be more

    plausible

    to

    argue

    that

    when

    one's

    voluntary assumption of

    obligation

    coin-

    cides with one's

    sense of

    justice,

    one's obliga-

    tion is

    clear;

    when the two

    conflict,

    one's

    obligation

    s unclear.

    Pateman does

    not claim to

    have

    developed

    a

    full theory

    of political obligation.

    She claims

    only

    that the

    problem

    of

    political obligation

    can be solved only through the

    developmentof

    the theory and practice of participatory or

    self-managing democracy (p.

    1).

    Yet in the

    context

    of

    her

    interpretation

    of

    Rousseau,

    she

    puts forth

    the

    first

    tendrils of what she

    pre-

    sumably believes

    to be a valid theory

    of

    political obligation.

    This is

    the

    weakest section

    of the book.

    For Pateman

    (or

    Pateman-Rousseau),poli-

    tical

    obligation,

    though

    self-assumed,

    is not

    purely

    procedural p. 92).

    The mere

    agreement

    of

    citizens does

    not

    (ever?)

    create

    political

    obligation. Rather,

    political

    obligation presup-

    poses substantiveprinciplesof politicalmorali-

    ty,

    like

    the

    principle

    (the only

    one Pateman

    spells

    out)

    that

    each

    law must benefit

    or

    burden all

    citizens

    equally

    (p. 152).

    If

    genuine

    political obligation

    s

    to

    be created,

    each

    citizen

    at the

    moment of

    the

    social

    contract must

    actively

    will some

    or all of

    the

    principles

    of

    political morality.

    Citizens

    come

    to will the

    principles

    of political

    morality whenever

    their

    previous experience

    of political participation

    (presumably

    under either

    the liberal social

    contract or some

    other imperfect

    regime) has

    had a

    sufficient educative

    effect for them to

    see the

    light (p. 156).

    Whole

    polities

    can revoke

    the

    principle(s)

    of political morality

    (p.

    154),

    althoughperhaps

    ndividualscannot

    (p.

    82).

    Individuals

    are, however,

    remarkably

    ree

    in

    this participatory

    polity.

    Even

    within the social

    contract, not

    every individual

    is obliged to

    conform

    to

    the

    mandate

    of

    every

    law.

    In

    analogy with

    the social practice of promising,

    citizens

    incur political obligation

    only by know-

    ingly

    committing

    themselves

    to

    their fellow

    citizens through their votes on specific issues

    (citizens

    must

    understand that to

    vote .. . is

    to commit oneself [p.

    1611 ). Citizens who do

    not themselves

    vote on a specific

    law

    (e.g., by

    referendum) remain

    uncommitted.

    The

    mi-

    nority who

    vote against

    a

    winningproposal

    also

    remain uncommitted

    unless they judge

    indi-

    vidually

    either

    (1)

    that the majority

    in

    voting

    followed the

    principles

    of

    political

    morality

    or

    (2)

    that at

    least the

    majority

    acted

    in

    good

    faith, thinking

    t was following

    the

    principlesof

    political

    morality.

    In short, the only polity that could bind its

    citizens

    would be both based

    on the

    principle(s)

    of

    political

    morality

    and

    a

    truly

    voluntary

    association

    (p.

    155),

    or

    on

    the

    largest

    scale,

    a

    political

    association of

    a

    multiplicity

    of

    politi-

    cal

    associations

    (p. 174).

    Unfortunately,

    such

    a

    polity

    could not act

    when

    individual nterests

    came

    in

    conflict. It

    could

    only act,

    as Rousseau

    said a

    polity

    should only act,

    when

    there was

    an

    overriding

    common

    good

    on

    a

    given

    issue.

    Indeed,

    if citizens

    were

    to

    take seriously

    the

    principle

    of equal benefit,

    their polity

    could

    seldom act even when there was a common

    good,

    because

    laws can seldom

    avoid

    producing

    more

    benefit

    for

    some

    than

    for

    others.

    Thus

    it

    seems

    unlikely

    that

    a

    polity

    based on the

    principles

    Pateman

    begins

    to sketch out here

    could

    survive.

    Its

    low

    degree

    of practicalapplicability

    may

    lead

    readers to dismiss

    Pateman's fledgling

    conception

    of

    political

    obligation.

    So

    may

    her

    occasional

    overstatement or careless

    wording.

    Such a dismissal

    would

    be a

    mistake.

    Her

    attempt

    to

    push

    the

    analogy

    with

    promising

    as

    far as it can go, while not resulting in a

    convincing theory

    of

    political

    obligation, does

    permit

    a successful

    challenge

    to many of

    the

    shibboleths of

    the liberal

    tradition,

    and lends

    itself to

    intriguing interpretations

    of

    Hobbes,

    Locke, Hegel, Godwin,

    and others. It

    poses

    This content downloaded from 143.106.201.162 on Mon, 23 Nov 2015 18:40:53 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/24/2019 1980 - Mansbridge - Review (PATEMAN) the Problem of Political Obligation

    4/4

    490

    The American

    Political

    Science

    Review

    Vol.

    74

    starkly

    problems

    that are

    central

    to

    developing

    a

    coherent

    theory of

    democracy.

    JANE

    MANSBRIDGE

    Universityof

    Chicago

    Emile

    or

    On

    Education.

    By

    Jean-JacquesRous-

    seau.

    Translated

    by

    Allan

    Bloom.

    (New

    York:

    Basic

    Books, 1979.

    Pp. ix

    +

    501.

    $18.50,

    cloth;

    $7.95,

    paper.)

    Unlike

    his

    Plato's

    Republic,

    Bloom

    here

    reserves

    extended

    commentary

    to

    another

    pro-

    ject,

    adding

    only

    a

    25-page

    ntroductionand 14pages of notes

    indicating

    Rousseau's

    sources

    and

    translating

    Latinisms,

    etc.,

    inconveniently

    left

    standing

    n

    the

    text.

    Adherence

    to

    Leo

    Strauss'

    goals of

    literal-

    ness

    and

    consistency

    strengthens this

    transla-

    tion.

    Its

    superiority

    is

    obvious

    to

    anyone

    who

    has

    crowded

    the

    margins

    of the

    1911

    Foxley

    translation

    with

    corrections.

    Apart

    from

    omit-

    ting

    at

    least

    one

    paragraph

    which

    Bloom

    re-

    stores

    (his

    p.

    272),

    Foxley

    loosely

    phrased

    even

    the

    famous

    opening

    of

    Book

    1.

    Above

    all,

    Bloom

    avoids

    Foxley's exasperatingly incon-

    sistent

    renditions

    of

    central

    terms.

    Rousseau's

    generic

    term

    for

    preoccupation

    with

    one's

    standing in

    the

    eyes

    of

    others is

    wisely left

    untranslated

    as

    amour-propren

    Bloom

    but

    was

    obscured

    by

    a

    half-dozen

    English

    substitutes

    n

    Foxley.

    Joining

    sound

    translationsof

    the

    politi-

    cal

    writings,

    Bloom's

    version

    of

    Rousseau's

    masterpiece

    diminishes

    handicaps

    for

    students

    with little

    or no

    French.

    Strauss'

    influence

    weakens

    Bloom's

    intro-

    duction, which

    works

    the

    familiar

    pattern

    of

    magnifying contrasts of Ancients and Moderns

    by

    exaggerating

    consensus

    within each

    group.

    Rather

    than

    training

    rational

    souls

    to

    master

    bodily

    passions,

    the

    Moderns

    engineer

    environ-

    ments

    to

    control

    results

    of

    passions

    which

    inevitably master

    reason,

    neutralizing

    what

    is

    nasty

    in

    the

    passions

    and

    anointing

    what

    is

    nice

    (these

    ground

    rights

    and

    derivative

    duties).

    Like

    Strauss

    and

    Roger

    Masters,

    Bloom

    thinks

    Rous-

    seau's

    dualism

    of

    matter/body

    and

    spirit/soul is

    dubious

    or

    detachable.

    Objection:

    Dualism

    is

    necessary

    for

    the

    coherence of

    Rousseau's

    otherwisecontradictoryusagesof natural. As

    merely

    physical

    beings

    we

    naturally

    tend to

    subordinate

    general

    interests to

    the

    particular

    and

    exempt

    ourselves

    from

    general

    rules,

    but

    as

    spiritual

    beings we

    naturally

    ought

    to

    subor-

    dinate the

    particular o the

    general, sometimes

    even

    sacrificing our

    lives.

    But the

    soul's

    reason

    is

    motivationally barren

    and

    conscience

    is

    weak

    unless

    bodily

    passions

    of

    (sublimated)

    sexuality

    and

    (redirected)

    amour-propre

    become

    allies

    rather

    than

    antagonists

    of

    compassionate

    rea-

    son.

    Bloom

    perversely

    views

    compassion

    as

    a

    selfish

    passion

    (p.

    18),

    claiming that

    Rous-

    seau

    merely derives

    duties from

    different

    pas-

    sions

    than

    Hobbes' fear

    of

    death,

    which

    is

    beyond

    experience

    before

    conceptualized.

    Bloom

    should

    say

    that the

    intensity

    rather

    than

    the

    existence

    of

    self-preservation

    motivation is

    held

    unnatural

    (cf.

    pp.

    9,

    82).

    Bloom

    accents

    discontinuities

    more

    than

    continuities

    between

    a favored

    Plato and

    the

    democratizing

    Rous-

    seau, but if

    Plato's

    sexual

    equality was

    ironical

    we expect Bloom to warm to Rousseau when

    clearly

    sexist

    (pp.

    23-24).

    Bloom

    complains

    that

    Rousseau

    invented the

    disadvantaged

    by

    assessing claims on

    society

    by

    negative

    lacks

    rather

    than

    positive

    contributions

    (p.

    18).

    His

    sexism

    aside, Rousseau

    could

    respond:

    the

    capacity to

    give to a

    society

    is a

    consequence

    of

    what

    one has

    got

    from it.

    TERRENCE

    E.

    COOK

    Washington State

    University

    Marx's

    Method:

    Ideology,

    Science

    and

    Critique

    in

    Capital. By

    Derek

    Sayer.

    (Atlantic

    High-

    lands,

    N.J.:

    Humanities

    Press,

    1979.

    Pp.xi

    +

    197.

    $20.00.)

    Derek

    Sayer's

    intent was

    to write

    a

    clear

    book

    that

    would

    be

    accessible

    to more

    than

    a

    specialist

    audience

    (p. x).

    Though

    a

    detailed

    knowledge of Marx is not a prerequisiteof

    what

    follows,

    nonetheless

    Sayer

    concedes

    that

    some

    readers

    might

    prefer

    to

    pass

    over

    some

    of

    the

    more

    technical

    discussions

    first

    time

    around

    (p.

    x).

    Midway

    through

    chapter

    2,

    the

    Language

    of

    Commodities, the

    reader

    is

    confronted

    with

    the

    Marxist

    concept

    of

    the

    value

    of

    commodity

    expressed

    as

    (p.

    27): Z

    com

    A

    =

    u com

    B

    =

    v

    com

    C

    =

    w

    com

    D

    =

    x

    com E

    ...

    etc.

    Unfortunately,

    there are

    some

    other

    instances

    (pp.

    116,

    168)

    of

    Marxist

    hierograms hat

    contradict

    the

    author's

    stated

    purpose of writinga clearbook.

    To

    compound the

    problem,

    the

    writing is

    rather obscure

    and

    jargon-laden.

    magine

    what

    would have

    become

    of

    Christianity

    f

    Jeremy

    Bentham

    had

    written the

    parables.

    One

    can

    sense

    the

    result

    by

    reading

    Sayer's

    book.

    The

    This content downloaded from 143.106.201.162 on Mon, 23 Nov 2015 18:40:53 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp