zhou tony research essay

Upload: tony-zhou

Post on 02-Jun-2018

219 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/10/2019 Zhou Tony Research Essay

    1/9

    Zhou Yan Kai s4265505

    Why Corrective Justice Kant Explain Everything

    In recent years, Weinrib has strongly pressed the idea that restitutionary remedies (i.e. gain-based monetary

    remedies) are based on a single, foundational aim, namely to do corrective justice between the parties to a

    dispute. The aim of this essay is twofold: firstly, it will examine the merits and weaknesses of Weinribs1

    view as an explanation for the philosophical foundations of unjust enrichment law; and secondly, the author

    will demonstrate an alternative plausible viewpoint as to what the foundations of unjust enrichment law

    might be. Examination of the Weinribian conception of corrective justice (Weinribs Theory) reveals that

    its strength emanates from the formal structural appeal, and its weakness stems largely from the Kantian

    foundations upon which it was framed. The authors alternative model draws upon an Aristotelian notion of

    corrective justice, and the earlier works of Drassinower and Dagan. Despite not being able to fully explore2 3

    the limits of the authors own model, it is hoped that the reader is at least convinced that such an alternative

    demonstrates adequate potential in describing the underpinnings of unjust enrichment.

    I Unjust Enrichment and Corrective Justice

    Before we explore the merits and weaknesses of Weinribs Theory, it might be useful to first give a brief

    account of the theory itself. Corrective justice concerns the relationship between the two parties, the plaintiff

    and defendant. Weinrib emphasised that because corrective justice as a framework is entirely interactional,every element of liability must have an effect on both parties - termed relational liability. Furthermore, the4

    defendants liability should always be intelligible in light of the position of the plaintiff - termed

    correlativity.5

    Weinribs Theory is based on two fundamental theories developed by Aristotle and Kant, and focuses on6

    understanding the immanent rationality of the law, as an autonomous discipline. Aristotles account of

    corrective justice concerned maintaining a notional equality between two parties. An injustice would occur

    when, relative to this baseline, one party realises a gain and another a corresponding loss. The law would7

    then intervene to correct this injustice by making the defendant restore the gain which corresponded to the

    loss. Kants theory of das recht provides Aristotles formal equality with normative substance. According

    to Kant, individuals are self-determining agents, free to do what they like provided they respect an equalstatus in others. Liability to a particular plaintiff arises only when the defendant exercises a choice

    inconsistent with anothers free will such that there is a normativegain by the exercising party and a

    normativeloss by another. As this arises as a result of the defendants free choice, liability is consistent with

    the defendants will.8

    With respect to unjust enrichment, relying on the Hegelian notion of value and exchange, Weinrib

    proposes that there are two obligation-creating conditions. Firstly, the plaintiffs non-donative transfer of9

    of1 9LAWS5215 Unjust Enrichment Research Essay

    The most recent having been Ernest Weinrib, Corrective Justice (Oxford University Press, 1st

    ed., 2012)1

    186-229; for his previous works, see e.g. Ernest Weinrib, The Normative Structure of Unjust Enrichment

    in Charles Rickett and Ross Grantham, Structure & Justification of Private Law (Hart Publishing Ltd., 2008)21; Ernest Weinrib, Correctly Unjust Enrichment in Robert Chambers, Charles Mitchell and James Penner,

    Philosophical Foundations of the law of Unjust Enrichment (Oxford University Press, 2009) 32.

    Abraham Drassinower Unrequested Benefits in the law of Unjust Enrichment (1998) 48(4) Toronto Law2

    Journal 459.

    Hanoch Dagan The Distributive Foundation of Corrective Justice (1999) 98Michigan Law Review138.3

    Ernest Weinrib, The Structure of Unjustness (2012) 92Boston University Law Review 1067, 1068.4

    Ibid.5

    Ernest Weinrib, The Idea of Private Law (Cambridge: HUP, 1995); Ernest Weinrib, Law as a Kantian Idea6

    of Reason (1987) 87 Columbia Law Review 472, 473, 495.That is to say, the parties were the doer and sufferer of the same injustice.7

    One can also describe this gain/loss relationship as consisting of a right and corresponding duty to be

    8

    entitled to and observe the self-determining agency of individuals, and hence Weinribs emphasis on

    relational liability.

    Ernest Weinrib, Corrective Justice (Oxford University Press, 1st

    ed., 2012) 197-198.9

  • 8/10/2019 Zhou Tony Research Essay

    2/9

    Zhou Yan Kai s4265505

    value to the defendant; and secondly, the defendants acceptance of the transfer of value on non-donative

    grounds. Importantly, acceptance here is a juridical concept capable of imputation, and hence is

    independentof the state of mind of the defendant. Where both conditions are satisfied, compelling a10

    restoration of the value transferred will be consistent with the parties wills. 11

    II

    The Weinribian Appeal

    From an empirical perspective, by and large, the corrective justice approach is the most closely followed by

    the courts. Private law disputes are decided primarily by way of merit, meaning that external factors like12

    the economic wealth of the parties rarely features as a concern for the courts. This does not mean that judges

    are necessarily insulated from the influence of external factors in coming to their decision, but given the13

    orthodox approach is to consider matters of principle, as opposed to policy, a reasonable conclusion to14

    draw might be that even though judicial outcomes may sometimes, serendipitously, also align with the

    promotion of certain external goals, this is merely the bi-product of doing corrective justice, as opposed to15

    the aim. This general empirical claim is no weaker within the specific context of restitution: for example, if

    one were to examine what makes an enrichment unjust, one would find that courts have regard to very

    specific, defined, legalcategories of injustice, as opposed to the general fairness of the enrichment. 16

    From a theoretical perspective, Weinribs Theory promotes an internally intelligible view of the law. Itencourages a critical approach by asking practitioners to evaluate arguments and principles found within the

    law to the extent they introduce concepts foreign to the framework. This drives the law towards greater

    certainty and articulacy, and directly fosters an attitude for treating like cases alike. As Smith eloquently put

    it, Weinrib has built an intellectual edifice which synthesises centuries of ethical and legal philosophy into a

    coherent system. Within the area of unjust enrichment law, this formal structure facilitates the17

    understanding of unjust enrichment as a unifying legal concept by drawing attention to both why the law

    recognises and whether it shouldrecognise an obligation to make restitution. One might think that such18

    merit is purely academic, but as Priel noted, to the extent the rule of law depends on certainty, opening up

    private law to questions other than corrective justice will imply the demise of private law.19

    Most compellingly, from a descriptive standpoint, the composition of unjust enrichment law mapscomfortably onto the corrective justice framework. The idea of unjust enrichment itself draws undeniable

    parallels with Aristotelian conceptions of correction: there is a notional baseline which is disturbed as a result

    of some unjust enrichment accruing to the defendant, at the plaintiffs expense, the restoration of which

    requires the return of that benefit to the plaintiff. It is this kind of mathematical symmetry that has led to

    of2 9LAWS5215 Unjust Enrichment Research Essay

    Ibid 205.10

    As stated by Weinrib, The correlative situation of the parties is observed through the way that liability11

    works to remedy the lack of justice in transfer. Just as the unjustness of the enrichment lies in normative

    defectiveness of the transfer of value, so the correction of this injustice consists in the retransfer of the value.The retransfer that rectifies the injustice has the same subject matter, the same correlative structure, and the

    same correlatively situated parties as did the defective transfer.: Ibid 228.

    This was also noted by Priel in Dan Priel, The Justice in Unjust Enrichment (2014) 51(3) Osgoode Hall12

    Law Journal 1, 27.

    Indeed, as Hart noted, judges may very well form intuitive decisions, and then go window-shopping for13

    rules: HLA Hart, The Concept of Law (Oxford University Press, 3rd Ed., 2012) 140.

    As strongly advocated by Dworkin: see e.g. Ronald Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously (Harvard University14

    Press, 1st Ed., 1977) 82.

    For example, wealth distribution or economic/commercial efficiency.15

    Indeed, Justice Martland has commented that unjust enrichment would become a free-for-all palm tree of16

    justice without the benefit of any guidelines: Pettkus v Becker [1980] 2 SCR 834, 859.Lionel Smith, Restitution: The Heart of Corrective Justice (2001) 79 Texas Law Review2115, 2121.17

    Pavey & Matthews Pty Ltd v Paul (1987) 162 CLR 221, 256 (per Deane J).18

    Dan Priel, The Justice in Unjust Enrichment (2014) 51(3) Osgoode Hall Law Journal 1, 28.19

  • 8/10/2019 Zhou Tony Research Essay

    3/9

    Zhou Yan Kai s4265505

    remarks such as restitution is the heart of corrective justice. Furthermore, the corrective justice emphasis20

    on relational reasons justifying the imposition of liability is reflected in the types of unjust categories that

    have developed: consider cases of coercion or, more controversially, wrongdoing. In both cases, the

    disturbance of equality brought on by the defendants conduct justifies restoration to the plaintiff because the

    right which the plaintiff has been deprived of is the correlativeof the duty that the defendant failed to

    observe. This congruence between corrective justice and unjust enrichment is embodied by Weinribs

    insistence on corrective justice being unifying, bipolar, and expressive of transactional equality, all21

    characteristics that can be seen to emanate from within a restitutionary claim.

    From this analysis, it isnt hard to agree with the basic proposition that Weinribs Theory informs the logic of

    unjust enrichment. However, as McInnes pointed out, it would be nothing short of miraculous if the whole22

    of the private law, formulated over centuries by the hands of countless distinct circumstances, would be

    referable to any single principle. For this reason, the following section moves on to critically evaluate the

    corrective justice framework.

    III

    Shortcomings of the Weinribian Approach

    The first criticism can be introduced by reference to Maslows law of the instrument: To the man who only

    has a hammer, everything he encounters begins to look like a nail. Adopting a Dworkinian approach, inorder to understand the law, one must work from the materials and abstract a seamless web of principles

    embedded within them. This may seem familiar since Weinrib considers that corrective justice reflects the

    immanent rationality of private law. However, upon closer examination, the supposed immanence23

    disappears. Weinribs Theory draws upon a formalist understanding of equality, supplemented by an external

    metaphysical truth. This conception of corrective justice colours what unjust enrichment is with what it24

    ought to be because it necessarily dismisses as external, the rich social fabric upon which the law has

    developed - an aspect all too important to the normatively pluralistic area of unjust enrichment law - and25

    ignores the fact that what might presently be considered as some principle internal to the law was once26

    something that had yet to be internalised. As Barker highlighted, Weinribs insistence on perfect27 28

    coherence between the ends and means of the law sets an impossibly high standard, not least because either

    can change over time and because legal doctrine has not been forged in a cast of perfect rationality.

    of3 9LAWS5215 Unjust Enrichment Research Essay

    Lionel Smith, Restitution: The Heart of Corrective Justice (2001) 79 Texas Law Review2115; see also20

    Kingstreet Investments v New Brunswick (Department of Finance)[2007] 1 SCR 3, 32 and Peel (Regional

    Municipality) v Canada[1992] 3 SCR 762, 804.

    Ernest Weinrib, The Idea of Private Law (Cambridge: HUP, 1995) 120.21

    Mitchell McInnes, Resisting Temptations to Justice in Robert Chambers, Charles Mitchell and James22

    Penner, Philosophical Foundations of the law of Unjust Enrichment (Oxford University Press, 2009) 101,111.

    Ernest Weinrib, Corrective Justice (Oxford University Press, 1st

    ed., 2012) 26.23

    The Kantian notion of a self-determining agent.24

    As contended by Dagan in Hanoch Dagan, The Law and Ethics of Restitution (Cambridge University25

    Press, 2004) 16, and as supported by Barker in Kit Barker, Theorising Unjust Enrichment Law: Being

    Realist(ic) (2006) 26(3) Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 609, 612.

    Internal because it just so happened to align with the corrective justice framework.26

    For example, the tort concept of duty of care is now widely accepted as being something that is naturally27

    internal to the law, but prior Lord Atkins statement inDonoghue v Stevenson [1932] AC 562, would it be

    possible to make that same assertion? In fact, at the time, the decision was widely criticised for introducing

    into the law foreign ideas which departed from established doctrines: see e.g. AL Goodhart, The Foundationof Tortious Liability (1938) 2Modern Law Review1, 4.

    Kit Barker, Theorising Unjust Enrichment Law: Being Realist(ic) (2006) 26(3) Oxford Journal of Legal28

    Studies 609, 619.

  • 8/10/2019 Zhou Tony Research Essay

    4/9

    Zhou Yan Kai s4265505

    The second criticism is that Weinribs Theory is both inconsistent and incomplete. To illustrate its

    inconsistency, recall Weinribs two obligation creating conditions. One might first notice that these29

    conditions presuppose the defendants knowledge of the transfer of value. This is an important observation

    because, considered together with the fact that acceptance may be imputed, it can be argued that the30

    defendants knowledge is made so constructive that it no longer serves to explain their liability. Given

    Kantian liability depends upon the defendants exercise of free choice in a manner which deniesthe plaintiff

    their status as a self-determining agent, surely an oblivious defendant could not be so implicated in liability if

    they were unaware of the non-gratuitous nature of the transfer. By extension, that same defendant could not

    have made a choice with respect to accepting something they didnt know was conferred unto them.

    Therefore, to the extent imputation of acceptance is necessary in justifying restitutionary liability (e.g. in

    mistake cases), the theory denies itself.31

    To illustrate its incompleteness, recall the function of the obligation-creating conditions is not to show that it

    is wrongful, but that, to compel a retransfer of value would not be inconsistent with the parties wills.32

    However, this begs the question: why should there be a retransfer? As is evident with Weinribs Theory, fault

    is a central component. If the defendant has done no wrong by accepting the transfer of value, what then

    does the requisite normative work necessary to justify the defendants liability? It might seem plausible to

    say that retention of the transfer of value after the point of acceptance constitutes the wrong. However, this

    cannot be right as it would require accepting the fact that the defendant, upon their acceptance, alsoaccepted a duty to make restitution, the imposition of which could only be justified by having reference to33

    the breach of that duty. Accordingly, it becomes difficult to maintain that theory is without gaps.34 35

    The third criticism is that Weinribs Theory is unable to explain cases of mistake or cases of contractual

    disgorgement. As discussed above, the very nature of the two obligation-creating conditions prevents an

    adequate explanation of the mistake cases. With respect to disgorgement in response to breach of contract,

    the theory also falls short in explanatory power because the gain which is disgorged from the defendant

    doesn't necessarily correlate with the loss suffered by the plaintiff. Unlike cases of disgorgement in response

    to the commission of proprietary torts, the plaintiff cannot be said to have a rightto the subject matter of36

    the contract. However, the author acknowledges the weight of this criticism is discountable if one37

    considers cases likeAttorney General v Blake as instances of hard cases making bad law.

    38 39

    of4 9LAWS5215 Unjust Enrichment Research Essay

    The first is the plaintiffs non-donative transfer of value to the defendant, and the second is the defendants29

    acceptance of the transfer of value on non-donative grounds.

    Imputation is possible because acceptance is a juridical concept: Weinrib, above n 9, 206-207.30

    This point was expressed in more detail in Matthew Doyle, Corrective Justice and Unjust31

    Enrichment (2012) 62 (2) University of Toronto Law Journal, 229-254.Consistent with Lord Bowens famous dictum in Falcke v Imperial Insurance Co. (1886) 34 Ch D 234,32

    248: liabilities are not to be forced upon people behind their backs.For there can be no wrong without a prior duty.33

    This point was briefly discussed in Dennis Klimchuk, Normative Foundations of Unjust Enrichment in34

    Robert Chambers, Charles Mitchell and James Penner, Philosophical Foundations of the Law of UnjustEnrichment (Oxford University Press, 2009) 82.

    Upon reflection, it would seem that even Weinrib himself was unsettled as to whether restitutionary35

    liability could be fault-independent. Note the inconsistencies in Weinribs initial work: Ernest Weinrib, The

    Idea of Private Law (Cambridge: HUP, 1995) 134, 140, 141.

    Cases of disgorgement involving property was justified in Ernest Weinrib, Restitutionary damages as36

    corrective justice (2000) 1 Theoretical Inquiries in Law 1.Nor could it be said they have a right to the situation that would result from the performance of the37

    contract, or a right to the defendants loyalty: see Ernest Weinrib, Punishment and disgorgement as contract

    remedies (2003) 78 Chicago-Kent Law Review 55, 67.

    [2001] 1 AC 268.38

    This is the authors own position, and is reflected in current Australian authority see e.g.Hospital Products39

    Ltd v US Surgical Corp (1984) 156 CLR 41, 124-125 (per Deane J);Hospitality Group Pty Ltd v Australian

    Rugby Union Ltd [2001] FCA 1040, [159];Brambles Holdings Ltd v Bathurst City Council (2001) 53

    NSWLR 153, 155-156.

  • 8/10/2019 Zhou Tony Research Essay

    5/9

    Zhou Yan Kai s4265505

    The final criticism is that the elements of unjust enrichment lends itself to expression as a strict liability area

    of law, and because of this, cannot be properly accounted for by Weinribs Theory. Liability is strict in three

    senses: (1) the cause of action is complete upon acceptance of the transfer of value, reflected in the fact that

    interest accrues upon the date of receipt; (2) the obligation to make restitution is only ever aprimary40

    obligation, as the courts do not award compensatory damages in response to a defendants failure to make

    restitution; and (3) establishing a prima facie restitutionary claim does not depend upon the proof of41 42

    fault. As has been canvassed before, underlying Weinribs Theory is the notion of relational liability and43

    fault: because of this feature, one cannot conceive of duty as being the mere reflex of a right.

    IV Alternative Foundation to Unjust Enrichment?

    Having exposed the weaknesses in Weinribs Theory, one might ask are there any other theories capable of

    more adequately explaining the philosophical foundations of unjust enrichment?. A distributive justice

    approach would be the next best option, but our purpose here is not to examine that framework in any depth,

    suffice to say it would also struggle to adequately encapsulate the philosophical foundations of unjust

    enrichment. How then might this dilemma be resolved? A potential solution emerges once we adopt a44

    more flexible perspective. Up to this point, it has been assumed that only one single theory could be used to

    explain the underpinnings of unjust enrichment, but who is to say that such a basis must be homogenous?Some would in fact advocate against monistic approaches, given the normative pluralism of unjust

    enrichment. Consequently, two options present themselves: (1) to explain as much of unjust enrichment on45

    a corrective justice framework as possible, and then leave the rest to an alternative framework; or (2) to

    develop a hybrid framework with which one can incorporate the whole of unjust enrichment. In light of

    Saprais cautioning against the first option, the author will ambitiously endeavour to pursue the second.46

    As was outlined in Section II, it is clear that although the formal structure promoted by corrective justice is

    something to be desired, the Kantian substance is questionable. Yet, in the absence of some notion to give a

    formalist account of corrective justice any content (i.e. without anything to inform the substance of the

    baseline), the theory is at too high a level of abstraction to be of any use. What then can pull the normative

    weight that would otherwise be borne by the Kantian conception of das recht?

    of5 9LAWS5215 Unjust Enrichment Research Essay

    Sandeman v Wilson(1880) 1 LR (NSW) Eq 1.40

    As distinct from the courts awarding of compensatory damages in cases of wrongdoing as an alternative to41

    restitution.

    This is not to say that it could not be relevant to proof of some unjust factors.42

    On this point, Birks has noted that the court, in making a judgement for restitution, is not attempting to43

    redress the defendants failure to do his duty, but is simply ordering him to do it: Peter Birks, Rights,

    Wrongs and Remedies (2000) 20 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 1, 14-15; see also, Lionel Smith,Restitution: The Heart of Corrective Justice (2001) 79 Texas Law Review2115, 2134; Stephen Smith,

    Justifying the Law of Unjust Enrichment (2001) 79 Texas Law Review 2177, 2181.

    One of the greatest advocates of distributive justice is Dagan, who provides a compelling but not entirely44

    convincing theory in his article, Hanoch Dagan, Restitutions Realism in Robert Chambers, Charles

    Mitchell and James Penner, Philosophical Foundations of the law of Unjust Enrichment (Oxford University

    Press, 2009) 55, 64-70. For a critique on Dagans approach, see e.g. Dennis Klimchuk, Normative

    Foundations of Unjust Enrichment in Robert Chambers, Charles Mitchell and James Penner, Philosophical

    Foundations of the Law of Unjust Enrichment (Oxford University Press, 2009) 82; Kit Barker, Theorising

    Unjust Enrichment Law: Being Realist(ic) (2006) 26(3) Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 609. For a critique

    on the instrumentalist approach generally, see Ernest Weinrib Can Law Survive Legal Education (2007) 60

    Vanderbilt Law Review 401-438.See e.g. Kit Barker and Ross Grantham, Unjust Enrichment(LexisNexis Butterworths, 2008) 62; Peter45

    Cane, Distributive Justice and Tort Law (2001) 4New Zealand Law Review 401-420.

    Prince Saprai, Restitution Without Corrective Justice' (2006) 14Restitution Law Review41, 53-54.46

  • 8/10/2019 Zhou Tony Research Essay

    6/9

    Zhou Yan Kai s4265505

    The author proposes the following: drawing upon the earlier works of Drassinower and Dagan, the47 48

    baseline is to be informed by the principle that each individual is entitled to the security of autonomous use,

    and from this, the freedom of exchange regarding their resources. Therefore, cases in which restitutionary

    causes of action are available can be explained by reference to a departure from this baseline. In response49

    to this departure, the question as to the availability and form of remedy that could be afforded naturally

    emerges. Respecting the fact the law doesnt operate in a vacuum, the appropriate remedy will depend upon

    the degree of security and freedom of exchange attributed to the exact resource, which itself is representative

    of the prevailing background ethos of society, and its conceptions of self. The more closely a particular

    resource is attached to the holders identity, the more important the protection of baseline entitlements

    associated with that resource (e.g. emphasising negative liberty) and accordingly, the greater the protections

    afforded at law.50

    This model can be seen as an instantiation of the concept of freedom of self, and is essentially dual-tiered: at

    the higher level of abstraction is the principle that informs the baseline, and at the lower level of abstraction,

    societys background ethos attributes varying dimensions of weight to the protection of that principle. From

    this brief account presented above, the model appears to overcome the difficulties with cases of mistake and

    the general fault requirement inherent in Kantian liability by shifting the focus of inquiry from the requisite

    wrongdoing necessary to implicate liability, to the denial of another individuals security of autonomous use

    and freedom of exchange of what is theirs. The model also manages to rationalise the availability and awardof different remedies in response to different kinds of unjust enrichments by reference to the web of social

    morality within which the law is inexorably entangled.

    However, despite the models face-value appeal, three criticisms could be levelled against it. These will now

    be addressed in turn. Firstly, one might argue that a hybrid account is untenable because corrective justice

    and distributive justice are mutually irreducible theories, and hence, cannot be combined without51

    threatening the integrity of the other. However, this criticism fails to appreciate the fact that corrective

    justice and distributive justice answer different theoretical questions: Aristotelian corrective justice

    (employed by the author as theformalisticbasis of the alternative model) addresses the question of the

    justificatory internal structure of claims, whereas distributive justice addresses the external social context of

    that structure. Only by combining these approaches can one hope to paint a complete picture of the law.

    52

    Secondly, one might argue that a hybrid account fails to observe sufficient correlativity necessary to justify

    the imposition of liability onto the defendant. An initial response could be to concede that correlativity

    serves a function in the place of private law, but only insofar as correlativity requires the defendants liability

    and remedy correspond to the plaintiffs entitlement. Beyond that, it is both unhelpful - in obscuring social53

    of6 9LAWS5215 Unjust Enrichment Research Essay

    Abraham Drassinower Unrequested Benefits in the law of Unjust Enrichment (1998) 48(4) Toronto Law47

    Journal 459.

    Hanoch Dagan The Distributive Foundation of Corrective Justice (1999) 98Michigan Law Review138.48

    For example, where person A is coerced into giving person B a benefit, person A has lost their security of49

    autonomous use and freedom to exchange their resources. Similarly, where there has been a failure of basis,the freedom to exchange resources will have been undermined.

    For example, unjust enrichment involving infringements of property rights typically result in a remedy of50

    account of profits (e.g. in cases of conversion: Colbeam Palmer v Stock Affiliates Pty Ltd (1968) 122 CLR

    25) or a reasonable license fee (e.g. in cases of trespass: Strand Electric Engineering v Brisford

    Entertainments[1952] 2 QB 246) whereas unjust enrichment involving taking the benefit of money not

    intended to be transferred typically result in a money had and received type remedy (see e.g. Kleinwort

    Benson Ltd v Lincoln City Council[1999] 2 AC 349).

    The distributive justice aspect of the authors model emanates from the prevailing background social ethos.51

    A potential second ground might be that since Weinribs model depended, in part, on the Hegelian52

    concepts of value and exchange, distributive factors have already been incorporated (since value

    presupposes a market within which a thing is valuable, and exchange presupposes social and moral notionsof fairness and equality).

    It is one thing to recognise that law is an autonomous discipline and that coherence is desired, but another53

    entirely to suggest autonomy and coherence is the be-all-end-all.

  • 8/10/2019 Zhou Tony Research Essay

    7/9

    Zhou Yan Kai s4265505

    values - and unnecessary - because the need for relational reasons ignores the convergences of justification

    for restitutionary liability. However, a more persuasive response would highlight that the notion of security54

    of autonomous use and freedom of exchange is necessarily relational. Neither party can claim to have an

    interest in those values without also recognising that the other party also has a right to those values being

    respected. As a result, within the bipolar structure of unjust enrichment, the defendants obligation to make

    restitution when there has been a departure from the baseline is as much an obligation he owes to the plaintiff

    as it is an obligation he owes to himself. 55

    The third, and potentially most damaging criticism is that this model doesnt adequately encompass cases of

    restitution for services. In a classic sense, resources represent something tangible. From this perspective,

    resources can be substituted for wealth. Clearly the concept of a service does not fall within the traditional

    concept of wealth. But in a modern market that facilitates for the exchanges of wealth for services, it56 57

    would be ill-considered to refuse to classify services as a resource. This position finds support in the way

    unjust enrichment identifies benefits - conferral of a benefit is not limited to the granting of wealth, but

    extends to services and the discharge of debts. Consequently, the author considers that, consistent with the58

    values informing the baseline, anything that has a market forexchangecan be classified as a resource. 59

    It is acknowledges that the account of the model presented here could only be considered cursory at best.

    However, given the breadth of the law of unjust enrichment, an in-depth critique is simply beyond the scopeof what could be achieved by this brief essay. Hopefully, the reader is at least content that an alternative

    philosophical foundation to unjust enrichment has been demonstrated to be prima facie plausible.

    V Conclusion

    Any attempt to determine the philosophical underpinnings of an area of law will be challenging, and the

    journey taken thus far has not proven to the contrary. This essay aimed to analyse the merits and weaknesses

    of Weinribs Theory as an explanation for the philosophical foundations of unjust enrichment law, and then

    proceeded to offer an alternative explanatory model. Undeniably, Weinribs Theory has its merits, as

    examined in Part II: indeed, one of Weinribs greatest contributions in recent years has been to promote an

    understanding of unjust enrichment and restitution as restoring normative entitlements. However, Part IIIwent on to expose that the greatest strength of Weinribs Theory was also one of the features to which

    attracted the most criticism. Following the critique, Part IV presented an alternative justificatory model

    which drew upon the merits of corrective justice but looked elsewhere for the normative content necessary to

    help it function as a useful theory. Despite not being able to examine the alternative model in great detail,

    taken at face-value, the weaknesses of Weinribs Theory which it manages to overcome and the criticisms it

    is capable of standing up to reflects that it is at least a step in the right direction.

    of7 9LAWS5215 Unjust Enrichment Research Essay

    This point was strongly put by Dagan in Hanoch Dagan, Restitutions Realism in Robert Chambers,54

    Charles Mitchell and James Penner, Philosophical Foundations of the law of Unjust Enrichment (Oxford

    University Press, 2009) 55, 69-70.

    This may seem to unnecessarily burden the defendant, but if, colloquially put, the shoe was on the other55

    foot, the plaintiff would be equally obliged to do the same.

    See Jack Beatson, Benefit, Reliance and the Structure of Unjust Enrichment (1987) 40 Current Legal56

    Problems71, 74.

    For example, a building contractor and developer can enter into a contract whereby the contractor provides57

    the man-power necessary to build the design envisaged by the developer, and in return, the developer pays

    the contractor a sum of money for the provision of their service. To both the contractor and the developer,

    there has been an exchange (otherwise, neither would want to contract in the first place). Logically, this

    means that both ends obtained something of the same nature, hence why tangible and intangible things can

    both be considered resources.

    See e.g. Peel (Regional Municipality) v Canada [1992] 3 SCR 762, 790;Brenner v First Artists58

    Management Pty Ltd [1993] 2 VR 221, 257-258.Put another way, anything which is capable of conferring a benefit to an individual when applied to them59

    is capable of being considered a resource in the hands of the plaintiff. Whether or not that resource has a

    precise translatable monetary value is another question entirely.

  • 8/10/2019 Zhou Tony Research Essay

    8/9

    Zhou Yan Kai s4265505

    Word Count: 3272

    Bibliography

    A Articles/Books/Reports

    Barker, Kit, Theorising Unjust Enrichment Law: Being Realist(ic) (2006) 26(3) Oxford Journal of Legal

    Studies 609

    Barker, Kit, and Ross Grantham, Unjust Enrichment(LexisNexis Butterworths, 2008)

    Beatson, Jack, Benefit, Reliance and the Structure of Unjust Enrichment (1987) 40 Current Legal Problems

    71

    Birks, Peter, Rights, Wrongs and Remedies (2000) 20 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 1

    Burrows, Andrew, The Law of Restitution (LexisNexis Butterworths, 2nd ed., 2002)

    Cane, Peter, Distributive Justice and Tort Law (2001) 4New Zealand Law Review 401

    Dagan, Hanoch, Restitutions Realism in Robert Chambers, Charles Mitchell and James Penner,

    Philosophical Foundations of the law of Unjust Enrichment (Oxford University Press, 2009) 55

    Dagan, Hanoch The Distributive Foundation of Corrective Justice (1999) 98Michigan Law Review138

    Dagan, Hanoch, The Law and Ethics of Restitution (Cambridge University Press, 2004)

    Doyle, Matthew, Corrective Justice and Unjust Enrichment (2012) 62 (2) University of Toronto Law

    Journal, 229

    Drassinower, Abraham, Unrequested Benefits in the law of Unjust Enrichment (1998) 48(4) Toronto Law

    Journal 459

    Dworkin, Ronald, Taking Rights Seriously (Harvard University Press, 1st Ed., 1977)

    Edelman, James, and Elise Bant, Unjust Enrichment in Australia (Oxford University Press, 2006)

    Friedmann, Daniel, Restitution of Benefits Obtained through the commission of a Wrong (1980) 80(3)

    Columbia Law Review 504

    Goodhart, AL, The Foundation of Tortious Liability (1938) 2Modern Law Review1

    Hart, HLA, The Concept of Law (Oxford University Press, 3rd Ed., 2012)

    Klimchuk, Dennis, Normative Foundations of Unjust Enrichment in Robert Chambers, Charles Mitchell

    and James Penner, Philosophical Foundations of the Law of Unjust Enrichment (Oxford University Press,

    2009) 82

    McInnes, Mitchell, Resisting Temptations to Justice in Robert Chambers, Charles Mitchell and James

    Penner, Philosophical Foundations of the law of Unjust Enrichment (Oxford University Press, 2009) 101

    Priel, Dan The Justice in Unjust Enrichment (2014) 51(3) Osgoode Hall Law Journal 1

    Saprai, Prince, Restitution Without Corrective Justice' (2006) 14Restitution Law Review41

    of8 9LAWS5215 Unjust Enrichment Research Essay

  • 8/10/2019 Zhou Tony Research Essay

    9/9

    Zhou Yan Kai s4265505

    Smith, Lionel, Restitution: The Heart of Corrective Justice (2001) 79 Texas Law Review2115

    Smith, Stephen, Justifying the Law of Unjust Enrichment (2001) 79 Texas Law Review 2177

    Weinrib, Ernest, Can Law Survive Legal Education (2007) 60 Vanderbilt Law Review 401

    Weinrib, Ernest, Corrective Justice (Oxford University Press, 1st ed., 2012)

    Weinrib, Ernest, Correctively Unjust Enrichment in Robert Chambers, Charles Mitchell and James Penner,

    Philosophical Foundations of the law of Unjust Enrichment (Oxford University Press, 2009) 32

    Weinrib, Ernest, Law as a Kantian Idea of Reason (1987) 87 Columbia Law Review 472

    Weinrib, Ernest, Punishment and disgorgement as contract remedies (2003) 78 Chicago-Kent Law Review

    55

    Weinrib, Ernest, Restitutionary damages as corrective justice (2000) 1 Theoretical Inquiries in Law 1

    Weinrib, Ernest, The Idea of Private Law (Cambridge: HUP, 1995)

    Weinrib, Ernest, The Normative Structure of Unjust Enrichment in Charles Rickett and Ross Grantham,

    Structure & Justification of Private Law (Hart Publishing Ltd., 2008) 21

    Weinrib, Ernest, The Structure of Unjustness (2012) 92Boston University Law Review 1067.

    B Cases

    Brambles Holdings Ltd v Bathurst City Council (2001) 53 NSWLR 153

    Colbeam Palmer v Stock Affiliates Pty Ltd (1968) 122 CLR 25

    Donoghue v Stevenson [1932] AC 562

    Falcke v Imperial Insurance Co. (1886) 34 Ch D 234

    Hospital Products Ltd v US Surgical Corp (1984) 156 CLR 41

    Hospitality Group Pty Ltd v Australian Rugby Union Ltd [2001] FCA 1040

    Kingstreet Investments v New Brunswick (Department of Finance)[2007] 1 SCR 3

    Kleinwort Benson Ltd v Lincoln City Council[1999] 2 AC 349

    Pavey & Matthews Pty Ltd v Paul (1987) 162 CLR 221

    Peel (Regional Municipality) v Canada[1992] 3 SCR 762

    Pettkus v Becker [1980] 2 SCR 834

    Sandeman v Wilson(1880) 1 LR (NSW) Eq 1

    Strand Electric Engineering v Brisford Entertainments[1952] 2 QB 246

    of9 9LAWS5215 Unjust Enrichment Research Essay