wray, k. b. rethinking scientific specialization. social studies of science, vol. 35, no. 1 (feb.,...

Upload: roberto

Post on 07-Jul-2018

220 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/18/2019 Wray, K. B. Rethinking Scientific Specialization. Social Studies of Science, Vol. 35, No. 1 (Feb., 2005), Pp. 151-164

    1/15

    Rethinking Scientific SpecializationAuthor(s): K. Brad WraySource: Social Studies of Science, Vol. 35, No. 1 (Feb., 2005), pp. 151-164Published by: Sage Publications, Ltd.Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/25046633 .Accessed: 21/06/2013 19:30

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    .JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new formsof scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    .

    Sage Publications, Ltd. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Social Studies of Science.

    http://www.jstor.org

    This content downloaded from 14 3.106.201.11 on Fri, 21 Jun 20 13 19:30:10 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=sageltdhttp://www.jstor.org/stable/25046633?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/25046633?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=sageltd

  • 8/18/2019 Wray, K. B. Rethinking Scientific Specialization. Social Studies of Science, Vol. 35, No. 1 (Feb., 2005), Pp. 151-164

    2/15

    sss

    RESEARCH NOTE

    ABSTRACT My aim in this paper is to re-examine specialization in science. I arguethat we need to acknowledge the role that conceptual changes can play in the

    creation of new specialties. Whereas earlier sociological accounts focus on social and

    instrumentalchanges

    as the cause of the creation of newspecialties,

    I argue that

    conceptual changes play an important role in the creation of some scientific

    specialties. Specifically, I argue that conceptual developments played an importantrole in the creation of both endocrinology and virology.

    Keywords conceptual change, Kuhn, scientific change, scientific specialization,

    specialties

    Rethinking Scientific SpecializationK. Brad Wray

    One of the most striking forms of scientific change is the rapid and

    seemingly endless growth of new scientific specialties. Philosophers of

    science seldom discuss this dimension of scientific change. Sociologistsand historians, on the other hand, once studied

    specializationwith intense

    interest. As Harriet Zuckerman (1988) notes, the sociological study of

    scientific specialization was itself, for a time, a sociological specialty (1988:

    535). Interest in specialization, though, has since passed. This, I believe is

    unfortunate.

    My aim in this paper is to re-examine specialization in science. In

    addition to reviewing the important insights of earlier studies, I want to

    emphasize the need to study the role that conceptual changes can play in

    the creation of new specialties. Whereas earlier accounts focus on social

    changes as the cause of the creation of new specialties, I argue that

    conceptual changes have played an important role in the creation of some

    scientific specialties.1 The account of the role of conceptual developmentsin the creation of new specialties that I develop and defend here is deeplyindebted to Thomas Kuhn's (2000 [1987], 2000 [1991], 2000 [1993])later writings. Unfortunately, this work has been largely neglected by the

    science studies research community.

    Social Studies of Science 35/l(February 2005) 151-164? SSS and SAGE Publications (London, Thousand Oaks CA, New Delhi)ISSN 0306-3127 DOI: 10.1177/0306312705045811

    www. sagepublications. com

    This content downloaded from 14 3.106.201.11 on Fri, 21 Jun 20 13 19:30:10 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/18/2019 Wray, K. B. Rethinking Scientific Specialization. Social Studies of Science, Vol. 35, No. 1 (Feb., 2005), Pp. 151-164

    3/15

    152 Social Studies of Science 35/1

    Sociological and Historical Studies of Scientific Specialization

    In this section I examine a variety of sociological and historical studies ofscientific specialization. I begin by examining two pioneering studies. I

    argue that both of these pioneering studies treat the development of a new

    specialty as essentially a change in the social organization of science, andthus treat conceptual changes as derivative. Further, both of these studies

    imply that there is one cause of the creation of new specialties. I then brieflyreview the sociological studies of specialization that followed these pioneering studies. These second-generation studies challenge the assumption thatthe same type of cause is responsible for the creation of all scientific

    specialties. But I argue that, like the pioneering studies, these studiescontinue to treat the conceptual, epistemic, or cognitive changes associated

    with scientific specialties as secondary to the social and instrumental

    changes associated with the process.Let us begin with the pioneering accounts. According to Joseph Ben

    David and Randall Collins (1966 [1991]: 50), the creation of a new

    scientific specialty is a consequence of scientists carving out a new professional niche in an effort to create a new social role. When an existing

    field shows little promise for career advancement, ambitious and ableyoung scientists will seek means to create a new discipline, field, or

    specialty. Ben-David and Collins support their account with a case study of

    the creation in the late 1800s of experimental psychology as a discipline in

    Germany. As they note, before experimental psychology became a distinct

    discipline, 'the subject matter of psychology was divided between speculative philosophy and physiology' (1966 [1991]: 53). In the mid-1800s,

    physiology underwent a period of rapid expansion (1966 [1991]: 63). In a

    relatively short period of time, between 1850 and 1864, many of theuniversity positions in physiology were filled by young men. As a result,there was little opportunity for career advancement for the upcoming

    generation of physiologists (1966 [1991]: 63). Positions were blocked bythe recently appointed generation of men who still had full careers ahead ofthem. This led a number of promising young scientists trained in physiology to create new career opportunities for themselves by applying the

    methods of physiology to problems in psychology.Ben-David and Collins suggest that the

    developmentof

    psychologyis a

    typical case of the process by which a new specialty is created. Crowding inan existing field leads young scientists to develop a new specialty in an

    effort to secure rewarding employment. Importantly, they insist that con

    ceptual developments in the study of the human mind were not responsiblefor the creation of experimental psychology as a discipline (1966 [1991]:50). In fact, Ben-David and Collins believe that, generally, 'the ideas

    necessary for the creation of a new discipline are usually available over a

    relatively prolonged period of time and in several places' (1966 [1991]:50). They suggest that if ideas were sufficient for the creation of a new

    discipline, we should have expected psychology to develop as a disciplinefirst in either France or the UK (1966 [1991]: 67-69).

    This content downloaded from 14 3.106.201.11 on Fri, 21 Jun 20 13 19:30:10 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/18/2019 Wray, K. B. Rethinking Scientific Specialization. Social Studies of Science, Vol. 35, No. 1 (Feb., 2005), Pp. 151-164

    4/15

    Wray: Rethinking Scientific Specialization 153

    Let us now consider the second pioneering account of specialization.Derek de Sol?a Price (1986 [1963]) suggests that the chief factor that leads

    to the creation of a new specialty is the demand to make effective researchpossible. Scientific research is done by humans, and our limited cognitivecapacities place significant constraints on the organization of science.

    Because there is a limit to how much people can read, each scientist can

    only attend to a finite and rather small portion of the continuously growing

    body of scientific literature. As more and more people get involved in

    science, and more and more journals publish more and more papers, eachnew generation of scientists confronts a larger body of scientific literature.

    In fact, Price estimates that by the early 1960s there were already more

    than 10,000,000 published scientific papers. And the number of publications was doubling every 15 years. Price believes that the various sub-fields

    in science are a consequence of scientists carving out manageable bodies of

    literature. He hypothesizes that the optimal size for a scientific research

    community is between 100 and 200 publishing scientists. Such a commu

    nity could keep abreast of the literature they produce (1986 [1963]: 65).There are three features that these pioneering accounts have in com

    mon. First, both accounts are premised on the assumption that conceptual

    developments in science are not what lead scientists to create new specialties. Hence, both of these pioneering studies privilege social changes in the

    creation of a new specialty, and treat conceptual changes as derivative.

    Second, both accounts are premised on the assumption that crowding in

    an existing field leads to the creation of a new specialty. Price assigns

    crowding a different function than that hypothesized by Ben-David and

    Collins. Rather than driving young scientists in search of new career

    opportunities, Price believes that crowding leads communities of scientists

    to narrow their area of research in an effort to prevent themselves frombeing overwhelmed by the growing body of research. Only by narrowingtheir area of research, and thus creating a new specialty, are scientists able

    to effectively manage the continuously growing literature. Third, both

    accounts are premised on the assumption that there is one type of cause

    that leads to the creation of new scientific specialties.The 1970s marked a period of extensive growth in the sociology of

    science in general (see Cole & Zuckerman, 1975: 146-48, 165), and in

    sociologicalstudies of scientific

    specializationin

    particular (Zuckerman,1988). The most important of these studies were Nicholas Mullins' (1972)'The Development of a Scientific Specialty', David Edge and Michael

    Mulkay's (1976) Astronomy Transformed, Daryl Chubin's (1976) 'The Con

    ceptualization of Scientific Specialties', and an anthology edited byLemaine et al. (1976b), Perspectives on the Emergence of Scientific Disciplines.Rather than provide a synthesis of second-generation studies, I want to

    draw attention to two ways these studies differed from the pioneeringstudies.

    First, a number of second-generation sociological studies examine the

    impact that new instruments and the development of instrumentation playin the creation of new specialties. For example, Edge & Mulkay (1976)

    This content downloaded from 14 3.106.201.11 on Fri, 21 Jun 20 13 19:30:10 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/18/2019 Wray, K. B. Rethinking Scientific Specialization. Social Studies of Science, Vol. 35, No. 1 (Feb., 2005), Pp. 151-164

    5/15

    154 Social Studies of Science 35/1

    provide a detailed account of the ways in which new instruments shapedradio astronomy. Similarly, John Law (1976) argues that developments in

    instrumentation played a significant role in the creation of X-ray crystallography. These studies thus suggest a need to broaden the range of causes ofnew scientific specialties. But they assume that developments in instru

    mentation are distinct from conceptual developments (see Law, 1976:

    123).

    Second, a number of second-generation sociological studies acknowl

    edge the complexity of the process by which a new specialty is created

    (Lemaine et al., 1976a). In particular, they begin to recognize that the

    development of a new specialty involves both social changes, the focus of

    the pioneering studies, and conceptual or cognitive changes (Edge &

    Mulkay, 1976: 364; Lemaine et al., 1976a: 1;Mulkay & Edge, 1976: 153;

    Worboys, 1976: 77). This led some sociologists to question the derivative

    role that epistemic developments were assigned in the pioneering studies.

    Sociological studies of scientific specialization seemed to privilege the

    social dimension of the process to such an extent that it is impossible to

    conceive how developments in the content of science could lead to the

    creation of a new specialty. As Chubin (1976: 449) explains, sociologicalstudies of scientific specialization take 'social structure as an antecedent of

    specialties', which 'seemingly denies the possibility that intellectual events

    and the relations they engender give rise to a social structure that we treat

    as a specialty.' Becher &Trowler (2001) suggest that Chubin himself was

    unable to adequately address this concern.

    Unfortunately, the interests and attention of sociologists of science

    shifted away from the study of scientific specialization before this concern

    was adequately addressed. As Zuckerman (1988: 535) notes, 'with the shift

    in research attention to the microsociology of scientific knowledge, thestudy of specialties ... declined markedly amongst sociologists.' I believe

    that the study of specialization ended prematurely. Indeed, as Zuckerman

    (1988: 535) noted in the late 1980s, 'the reasons that led sociologists of

    science to study the development of specialties in the first place still appearto be valid.' In particular, we have yet to develop an adequate under

    standing of the role that conceptual changes can play in the creation of new

    scientific specialties.

    Scientific Specialization and Conceptual Change

    In this section, I want to examine an account of the creation of new

    specialties that focuses on the epistemic dimension of the change. Thomas

    Kuhn discusses specialization in various essays collected together in The

    Road Since Structure (2000). Unfortunately, he never wrote a paper de

    voted exclusively to the topic. As a result, there has been remarkably little

    uptake or response to what he said on the topic. My aim is to synthesize his

    remarks into a coherent account of specialization. I believe that Kuhn

    provides insight into understanding how conceptual changes can lead to

    the creation of new specialties.

    This content downloaded from 14 3.106.201.11 on Fri, 21 Jun 20 13 19:30:10 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/18/2019 Wray, K. B. Rethinking Scientific Specialization. Social Studies of Science, Vol. 35, No. 1 (Feb., 2005), Pp. 151-164

    6/15

    Wray: Rethinking Scientific Specialization 155

    According to Kuhn (2000 [1991]: 97), a new scientific specialty is

    sometimes created as a consequence of a scientific revolution. To expressthe

    pointin the familiar

    thoughoften misunderstood idiom of The Structure

    of Scientific Revolutions (Kuhn, 1996 [1962]), when scientists in a field

    encounter persistent anomalies and they are unable to resolve the crisis

    with the resources provided by the prevailing paradigm, a new paradigmwill inevitably be developed. The new paradigm is designed to resolve the

    outstanding anomalies. But sometimes the new paradigm will not be able

    to serve the purposes of all those working in the field. As a consequence,

    part of the field as it was conceived before the revolution becomes a new

    field or specialty. Thus, old paradigms are not necessarily discarded.

    Sometimes they come to be employed in a more restricted domain.

    As Kuhn developed his account of scientific change in response to

    criticism, he modified his view of the nature of scientific revolutions in

    subtle but important ways that have important implications for under

    standing the process by which a new scientific specialty is created. Let us

    begin by examining how he reconceived the notion of a scientific

    revolution.

    A scientific revolution involves a taxonomic change. For example, in

    the Copernican revolution astronomers replaced a lexicon in which

    'planet' denotes a satellite of the earth with a lexicon in which 'planet'denotes a satellite of the sun (2000 [1987]: 15). Kuhn believes that 'the

    transition to a new lexical structure, to a revised set of kinds, permits the

    resolution of problems with which the previous structure was unable to

    deal' (2000 [1993]: 250). For example, the new lexicon introduced duringthe Copernican revolution enabled astronomers to explain retrograde

    motion. Thus, in Kuhn's developed account of scientific revolutions, the

    notion of a taxonomic change replaces the earlier problematic notion of aparadigm change.2

    It is worth comparing revolutionary changes with the more common

    place discoveries of normal science. In normal science, advances do not

    require modifications to existing taxonomies. Rather, as Kuhn (2000

    [1987]: 14) explains, discoveries in normal science 'simply [add] to the

    way ... antecedently understood variables behave.' Boyle's discovery 'that,

    for a given gas sample, the product of pressure and volume was a constant

    at constant temperature', is a typical example of a normal non-revolu

    tionary scientific discovery.3

    According to Kuhn, sometimes the taxonomic changes that are a

    consequence of a scientific revolution affect only a subset of a scientific

    research community. And, 'what lies outside of [the new taxonomy]becomes the domain of another scientific specialty, a specialty in which an

    evolving form of the old kind terms remain in use' (2000 [1993]: 250).

    Hence, a new specialty is created when a taxonomic change affects only

    part of a research community, and the old taxonomy is still employed

    effectively in a restricted domain. Not every revolutionary change permitsthis. For example, Copernicus' proposed taxonomic change could not be

    adopted without replacing the pre-Copernican lexicon. In such cases, there

    This content downloaded from 14 3.106.201.11 on Fri, 21 Jun 20 13 19:30:10 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/18/2019 Wray, K. B. Rethinking Scientific Specialization. Social Studies of Science, Vol. 35, No. 1 (Feb., 2005), Pp. 151-164

    7/15

    156 Social Studies of Science 35/1

    is no need to create a new specialty, for the whole of the existing research

    community adopts the proposed change.4

    On this Kuhnian account, specialization involves both epistemic andsocial changes. On the social dimension, scientists who once had regularcontact with each other often have less in common to bring them together.

    They may no longer attend the same conferences. They may even beginpublishing in different journals. They may also find communication with

    each other more difficult (Kuhn, 1996 [1962]: 177). But, the process of

    specialization that Kuhn describes is essentially epistemic in nature. It is an

    epistemic shortcoming, the inability of a community of scientists to ade

    quately model the domain of their field with the existing taxonomy, whichleads the community to divide and thus create a new specialty. As Kuhn

    explains, 'specialization and the narrowing of the range of expertise [are]... the necessary price of increasingly powerful cognitive tools' (2000

    [1991]: 98). Confined to the conceptual resources available in the existingscientific taxonomies, the resolution of some outstanding problems may

    have been impossible. Certain phenomena may evade our detection unlessa revolutionary change is made to an existing taxonomy. Thus, sometimes

    scientists must be prepared to relinquish part of their current domain of

    study to those who are willing to employ a new modified taxonomy bettersuited to the study of the recalcitrant phenomena.5

    Support for the Kuhnian Account

    Kuhn's account of specialization provides us with a means to explain how

    conceptual developments in science can contribute to the creation of new

    specialties. Though Kuhn does not provide examples from the history of

    science tosupport

    hisaccount,

    I believe there are cases that do in fact

    support it. In an effort to defend Kuhn's account, I want to examine twocase studies.

    The creation of endocrinology provides a clear illustration of the

    process Kuhn describes. As R.A. Gregory (1977: 105) explains:

    [T]he discovery in 1902 by Bayliss and Starling ... of the duodenalhormone secretin was ... a signal event in the history of physiology. A

    simple experiment ... revealed that the functions of the body were

    normallycoordinated not

    only bythe nervous

    system,but also

    bythe

    mediation of specific chemical agents formed in, and transmitted from,one organ to others by way of circulation, conveying a message intelligible

    only to those cells equipped to capture the 'chemical messenger' and

    decipher the encoded instructions for modification of their activity. By the

    discovery of what came to be called 'hormones' there was opened a new

    era of physiology, the beginning of endocrinology as we know it today.

    Before Bayliss and Starling made their discovery, physiologists generallyassumed that the functions of the body were coordinated by the nervous

    system, and the taxonomy physiologists worked with reflected this. Conse

    quently, in making their discovery, Bayliss and Starling needed to invoke a

    new concept, 'hormone' or 'chemical messenger'.

    This content downloaded from 14 3.106.201.11 on Fri, 21 Jun 20 13 19:30:10 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/18/2019 Wray, K. B. Rethinking Scientific Specialization. Social Studies of Science, Vol. 35, No. 1 (Feb., 2005), Pp. 151-164

    8/15

    Wray: Rethinking Scientific Specialization 157

    Bayliss and Starling's discovery significantly altered the field of physi

    ology. Part of the field as it was conceived before the discovery was

    relinquishedto

    scientists preparedto

    studythe effects of hormones on the

    body. 'Hormone' became a key concept in this new field of study, endocri

    nology. But the traditional study of physiology was, to a large degree, left

    very much intact as it was before the discovery. Many of the functions of

    the body are in fact coordinated by the nervous system, as physiologistsassumed, and physiologists could continue to study various functions of

    the body working with that assumption. One significant change that the

    discovery brought to physiology was a narrowing of the traditional domain

    of the field. The revolutionary discovery of hormones reduced the range of

    phenomena that physiologists were expected to explain in terms of the

    nervous system. Investigating the various functions of the body that are

    coordinated by 'chemical messengers' requires different cognitive tools

    than those that were available to physiologists. In fact, the study of these

    functions is sufficiently different from that of phenomena that are coordi

    nated by the nervous system as to warrant the attention of specialists.Rather than modify the existing taxonomy to accommodate the con

    cept 'hormone', physiologists could have tried to explain the observed

    phenomena in terms of the then-operative lexicon. Had they tried to dothis, though, it is likely that an accurate understanding would have eluded

    them. The existing taxonomy, built on the assumption that the functions of

    the body are coordinated by the nervous system, was not fit to explain the

    phenomena under consideration.

    This example nicely illustrates Kuhn's view. A revolutionary discovery

    required significant changes to the taxonomy of a field, with the result that

    a new field was born and the domain of the original field was subsequently

    truncated. The cognitive tools that were designed for one set of purposes,the study of the nervous system in the functioning of the body, are

    discovered to be inadequate for the range of phenomena to which theywere assumed to apply.

    There are other episodes in the history of science that follow a similar

    path of development, including, for example, the creation of virology as a

    separate field of study. In the late 19th century and first half of the 20th

    century what we now call viruses were often studied as anomalous phenomena

    by bacteriologists, pathologists,and biochemists (Waterson &

    Wilkinson, 1978). Some scientists attempted to understand viruses as

    microbes. Working with the conceptual and experimental resources of

    bacteriology, they were perplexed with the problem of growing viruses in

    artificial media. Other scientists attempted to understand viruses as non

    organic entities. Working with the conceptual and experimental resources

    of chemistry, they were concerned with understanding how a toxic non

    living substance could replicate (Hughes, 1977: 79-84, 90). But, in the

    1950s 'a fundamental conceptual change occurred with the recognitionthat all viruses share a common structure despite observed differences in

    morphology, host specificity and pathological activity' (Hughes, 1977:

    100). It was then realized that viruses were a distinct kind of phenomenon,

    This content downloaded from 14 3.106.201.11 on Fri, 21 Jun 20 13 19:30:10 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/18/2019 Wray, K. B. Rethinking Scientific Specialization. Social Studies of Science, Vol. 35, No. 1 (Feb., 2005), Pp. 151-164

    9/15

    158 Social Studies of Science 35/1

    and could not be adequately conceptualized either as an organism or as a

    toxin. Thus, a new taxonomy had to be constructed to accommodate

    'virus'as a

    kind.The taxonomy bacteriologists used before the discovery of viruses

    remained essentially the same after the discovery. Subsequent research in

    bacteriology was thus more or less continuous with the practice before the

    discovery of viruses. Bacteriologists, though, were able to relinquish re

    sponsibility for explaining certain phenomena that they had previously

    regarded as their responsibility, phenomena that had, until then, remained

    anomalous. A similar situation occurred in pathology and biochemistry,the other specialties in which scientists investigated the phenomena thatcame to be recognized as viruses.

    These two episodes in the history of science illustrate the importantrole that conceptual changes can play in the creation of a new scientific

    specialty. Sometimes a new specialty is created as a result of a revolu

    tionary discovery. Such a discovery sometimes leads a community of

    scientists to split the domain of their field and form two separate research

    communities, each pursuing their research with a taxonomy suited to their

    needs and interests. The creation of a new specialty is thus one means bywhich scientists are able to develop an understanding of the world. Some

    phenomena elude our understanding until scientists make changes to an

    existing taxonomy. Such changes allow scientists to approach the study of

    recalcitrant phenomena with new conceptual tools. And when a taxonomic

    change gives rise to a new specialty, scientists in the parent specialty realize

    the limits of their model, and thus relinquish responsibility for explaining

    phenomena they are ill-equipped to explain.

    Anticipating Criticism

    In light of the sociological studies of specialization discussed earlier, I

    anticipate two criticisms. Similar criticisms could be raised against either of

    the case studies discussed in the previous section, but I will present the

    criticisms as they apply to the case of virology. My aim in this section is to

    address the criticisms and thus defend the Kuhnian account of specialization that I have developed earlier.

    Let us consider the criticisms.First,

    onemight argue

    that the in

    troduction of new instruments and techniques was responsible for the

    creation of virology. In support of this view one might cite the fact that the

    discovery of viruses depended upon a series of developments made in

    filtering, a process that played an integral role in enhancing scientists'

    understanding of viruses. One might also cite the fact that the electron

    microscope also played an indispensable role in the discovery of viruses

    (Hughes, 1977: 96, 98;Waterson &Wilkinson, 1978: 105-06).

    Second, one might argue that virology was created, not as the result of

    conceptual changes, but rather as a result of crowding in existing fields. In

    support of this view, one might cite the fact that even before 1900,Martinus Beijerinck had developed a concept of a non-cellular life form to

    This content downloaded from 14 3.106.201.11 on Fri, 21 Jun 20 13 19:30:10 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/18/2019 Wray, K. B. Rethinking Scientific Specialization. Social Studies of Science, Vol. 35, No. 1 (Feb., 2005), Pp. 151-164

    10/15

    Wray: Rethinking Scientific Specialization 159

    account for 'the agent of tobacco mosaic disease' (Hughes, 1977: 48-51).

    Thus, the required conceptual developments seem to have been available

    longbefore the creation of

    virologyas a

    specialtyin the 1950s. Conse

    quently, it seems that the creation of virology as a specialty in the 1950s

    depended, ultimately, on the migration of physicists into the biologicalsciences. Like the young physiologists who created experimental psychology, these physicists were seeking new career opportunities, and created

    them by applying the methods of physics to biological phenomena

    (Hughes, 1977: 91).In the remainder of this section, I want to address these criticisms,

    beginning with the first. It is undeniable that technological developments

    played an important role in the discovery of viruses, but I believe it is a

    mistake to regard the technological developments as the ultimate cause of

    the creation of virology as a specialty. There are two considerations that

    lead me to believe this. First, rather than being an epistemic asset, at times

    the reliance on techniques was an impediment to the discovery of viruses.

    Before scientists developed the modern concept 'virus', techniquedetermined characteristics, like filterability and microscopic invisibility,were often used to identify substances as viruses. But, as Sally Hughes

    (1977: 87) notes, such 'technique-determined physical characteristics ...were inadequate criteria by which to differentiate viruses from all other

    types of infectious agents.' That is, these characteristics do not distinguishviruses from other superficially similar but unrelated phenomena. What

    scientists lacked was 'information about [the] intrinsic biological properties [of viruses]' (Hughes, 1977: 87). Consequently, I believe it is amistaketo attribute the creation of virology entirely to developments in

    instrumentation.

    Second, contrary to what is implied by this criticism, I believe that it isa mistake to contrast technological developments with epistemic develop

    ments. Earlier sociological studies that emphasized the role that developments in instrumentation played in the creation of new specialties seem to

    assume that these are distinct types of developments. This assumption is

    most evident in Law's study of X-ray protein crystallography. In fact, Law

    (1976: 123) proposes distinguishing between ' technique , theory , and

    subject matter specialties', thus implying that the techniques employedin X-ray

    crystallographycould have been

    developed independentof ac

    companying theoretical developments. Contrary to what Law implies, I

    believe that developments in instrumentation are often tied to conceptual

    developments. That is, developments in instrumentation often either: (1)

    depend upon conceptual developments; or (2) occur simultaneous with

    conceptual developments. For example, in order to develop the technologyto detect X-rays, R?ntgen had to simultaneously discover X-rays (see

    Kuhn, 1996 [1962]: 56-57). Thus, making a sharp distinction between

    developments in instrumentation and conceptual developments, as some

    of the earlier sociological studies did, ismisleading.6Let us now consider the second criticism. I have three replies to this

    criticism. First, I believe that the criticism is based on aWhig reading of

    This content downloaded from 14 3.106.201.11 on Fri, 21 Jun 20 13 19:30:10 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/18/2019 Wray, K. B. Rethinking Scientific Specialization. Social Studies of Science, Vol. 35, No. 1 (Feb., 2005), Pp. 151-164

    11/15

    160 Social Studies of Science 35/1

    history. It is only with hindsight, with the knowledge that viruses form a

    distinct kind of entity, that we identify all the various investigations that led

    to the discovery of viruses as contributions to virology.7 Scientists involvedin these investigations saw things quite differently. Before the 1950s, when

    scientists used the term 'virus', it was applied indiscriminately to a varietyof phenomena, many of which have subsequently been identified as bac

    teria (Hughes, 1977: 92-95).

    Second, though there were earlier anticipations of the modern con

    cept, like Beijerinck's proposal which 'agrees to some extent with the

    modern definition of the virus' (Hughes, 1977: 57), it is a mistake to saythat he discovered the same thing that was discovered in the 1950s. The

    vague understanding that Beijerinck had was, at the time, in conflict with

    widely accepted background assumptions, criticized by others, and not

    well supported by the then-available data (Hughes, 1977: 57-58; Waterson

    & Wilkinson, 1978: 27-30).8Third, many of the scientists who were ultimately responsible for the

    creation of virology as a specialty were not looking for new career opportunities. Many of them were well-established researchers, with secure

    positions, and actively involved in research in a number of specialties.Hence, the pioneers in virology lacked the incentives to create a new socialniche that had motivated the early founders of experimental psychology.

    Consequently, a comprehensive explanation for why virology came to

    be created as a new specialty in the 1950s requires reference to both: (1)

    conceptual developments in our understanding of viruses; and (2) the

    accompanying taxonomic changes required to articulate an adequate un

    derstanding of the phenomena.

    Concluding Remarks

    My analysis emphasizes the epistemic benefits of specialization. It is worth

    briefly mentioning the epistemic costs involved. With the creation of a new

    scientific specialty the expertise of individual scientists narrows. As a

    consequence, scientists are increasingly required to depend upon and trust

    the findings of those who work in other specialties.9 This increasing

    dependence that characterizes contemporary science is one of the principalcosts of

    specializationin science. As new

    specialtiesare

    created,barriers

    are created and these can sometimes be an impediment to the developmentof science. Indeed, some important discoveries have depended uponscientists transcending the barriers created by specialization. For example,

    PaulThagard (1999: 84-85, 181) notes that the discovery of the bacterial

    theory of ulcers required knowledge from two different medical specialties,

    pathology and gastroenterology. Much of the knowledge needed to make

    the discovery was available for some time before the discovery was made.

    But it was only when two scientists from different specialties worked

    collaboratively that the discovery was made.10

    In summary, I have developed and defended an account of how

    conceptual developments in science can contribute to the creation of a new

    This content downloaded from 14 3.106.201.11 on Fri, 21 Jun 20 13 19:30:10 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/18/2019 Wray, K. B. Rethinking Scientific Specialization. Social Studies of Science, Vol. 35, No. 1 (Feb., 2005), Pp. 151-164

    12/15

    Wray: Rethinking Scientific Specialization 161

    scientific specialty. In developing this account, I have addressed a key

    question left unanswered by earlier sociological studies of specialization:

    how can conceptual or epistemic developments in science contribute to thedevelopment of a new scientific specialty? I argued that scientific discov

    eries will sometimes lead a research community to split into two commu

    nities, each subsequently working with a taxonomy suited to its needs and

    interests. Further, I argued that this is what led to the creation of both

    endocrinology in the early 1900s and virology in the 1950s.

    Although my aim has been to account for the role that conceptual

    developments can play in the creation of a new specialty, we should be

    mindful of an importantinsight

    of thesecond-generation sociologicalstudies discussed earlier. The creation of a new specialty is a complex

    process, often involving both cognitive and social changes. Even a social

    factor like crowding in a field could play an important role in leading to thesorts of conceptual developments that would lead to the creation of a new

    specialty. For example, as an existing field gets crowded there may be more

    intense competition, which can lead to a significant discovery. But, a

    thorough examination of the interaction between social and epistemicfactors in the process of specialization is a topic that goes beyond the scopeof this paper.

    Notes

    I thank audiences at the following, to whom I presented earlier drafts: the Science and

    Humanities Circle at the University of Alberta; the annual meeting of the Canadian Societyfor History and Philosophy of Science; the Philosophy Department Colloquium at the State

    University of New York, Oswego; the Pacific Division meeting of the American

    Philosophical Association; and the 12th International Congress of Logic, Methodology, and

    Philosophy of Science. I also thank the following individuals for their constructive feedback:

    Lori Nash, Randall Collins, Kristina Rolin, Paul Teller, David Hull, Lisa Gannett, Leslie

    Cormack, Robert Smith, Patrick McGivern, Robert Wilson, and Alex Reuger. In addition, I

    thank the two anonymous referees for Social Studies of Science who provided insightfulcomments that improved the paper. Harold Kincaid and David Vampola also provided

    insight and encouragement as I worked on the project. Finally, I thank the Dean of the

    College of Arts and Sciences and the Office of International Studies at SUNY-Oswego for

    their financial support to cover travel costs to two of the conferences listed earlier.

    1. The important distinction here is not between 'externar and 'internal' factors. Indeed,as Hull et al. (1978) argue, it is often difficult to determine whether or not a factor is

    to count as external. For example, scientists have frequently been influenced by'extrascientific beliefs', including metaphysical principles, and socioeconomic and

    religious beliefs (1978: 717). From our perspective today, what clearly looks like an

    external factor was often regarded as internal by those influenced by it. The distinction

    that ismy concern here is between social factors and epistemic factors.

    2. Kuhn borrowed the term 'paradigm' from 'the standard examples employed in

    language teaching' (1977a: xix; 1996 [1962]: 23). But, as he explains, 'paradigms took

    on a life of their own .... Having begun simply as exemplary problem solutions, they

    expanded their empire to include, first, the classical books in which these accepted

    examples initially appeared and, finally, the entire global set of commitments shared by

    the members of a particular scientific community' (1977a: xix). Steven Weinberg(1998) notes that James Conant had raised concerns about Kuhn's use of the term

    paradigm even before the publication of Structure. Paradigms still have an importantrole to play in Kuhn's final statement on scientific change. As widely accepted

    This content downloaded from 14 3.106.201.11 on Fri, 21 Jun 20 13 19:30:10 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/18/2019 Wray, K. B. Rethinking Scientific Specialization. Social Studies of Science, Vol. 35, No. 1 (Feb., 2005), Pp. 151-164

    13/15

    162 Social Studies of Science 35/1

    exemplars that guide a community of scientists in solving unresolved problems, they are

    the locus of consensus. It is in this respect that Kuhn's view differs most from the

    positivists. The positivists assumed that scientists were united by either an agreed upon

    method, or a set of sentences that constitute the accepted theory.

    3. Kuhn's amended account of scientific revolutions alleviates some of his critics' worries.

    For example, criticizing Kuhn's earlier paradigm-related account of scientific

    revolutions, Edge & Mulkay (1976: 392) argue that 'it is far from easy to state

    unambiguously what kinds of changes should, from Kuhn's perspective, entail the

    occurrence of a revolution.' Given Kuhn's developed account of scientific revolutions,

    all and only those changes that require taxonomic changes will count as revolutionary.4. Mulkay (1975: 512) describes Kuhn's paradigm-related account of scientific

    development as a closed model, for it stresses 'the existence of scientific orthodoxies.'

    Mulkay (1975: 513) believes that such accounts are ultimately unacceptable for they'make scientific innovation highly problematic'. Instead he recommends a branching

    model of scientific development, according to which 'new problem areas are regularlycreated and associated social networks formed' (1975: 520). The Kuhnian account of

    specialization presented here is more aptly described as a branching model.

    5. Abbott (2001) has recently developed an account of the dynamics of scientific fields

    that attributes an important role to conceptual changes. But unlike the Kuhnian

    account presented here, Abbott's account applies to social sciences only, and it is

    principally concerned with the dynamics within a field, rather than the dynamics that

    lead to the creation of new fields.

    6. I thank one of the referees for Social Studies of Science for advice on developing a

    response to this first criticism, and in particular for suggesting the second response.

    7. Brannigan (1981) makes a similar point with respect to Mendel's alleged contributions

    to genetics.8. As Waterson & Wilkinson (1978: 27) note, a number of Beijerinck's contemporaries

    wh^were researching the tobacco mosaic disease, including C.J. Koning, K.G.E.

    Heintzel, Friedrich Hunger, and Adolf Mayer, did not even understand 'Beijerinck's

    flight of thought'. Others, including Emile Roux, Dmitri Ivanovski, and Eugenio

    Centanni, were critical of Beijerinck's conceptual innovation (Waterson & Wilkinson,

    1978: 27-28).9. On the role of trust in science, see Steven Shapin's (1994) A Social History of Truth.

    10. Thagard believes that it is unlikely that either scientist would have made the discovery

    working alone. Recognizing the predicament that is created by specialization, Swanson

    & Smalheiser (1997) have developed computer software to identify connections

    between bodies of scientific literature from different fields that might lead to scientific

    discoveries.

    References

    Abbott, Andrew (2001) Chaos of Disciplines (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press).

    Becher, Tony & Paul R. Trowler (2001) Academic Tribes and Territories (Buckingham, Bucks.:The Society for Research Into Higher Education and Open University Press).

    Ben-David, Joseph & Randall Collins (1966 [1991]) 'Social Factors in the Origins of a New

    Science: The Case of Psychology', in J. Ben-David (ed.), Scientific Growth: Essays on

    the Social Organization and Ethos of Science (Berkeley, CA: University of California

    Press): 49-70.

    Brannigan, Augustine (1981) The Social Basis of Scientific Discovery (Cambridge: Cambridge

    University Press).

    Chubin, Daryl E. (1976) 'The Conceptualization of Scientific Specialties', The Sociological

    Quarterly 17: 448-76.

    Cole, Jonathan R. & Harriet Zuckerman (1975) 'The Emergence of a Scientific Specialty:The Self-Exemplifying Case of the Sociology of Science', in L.A. Coser (ed.), The Idea

    of Social Structure: Papers inHonor of Robert K Merton (NewYork: Harcourt Brace

    Jovanovich): 139-74.

    This content downloaded from 14 3.106.201.11 on Fri, 21 Jun 20 13 19:30:10 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/18/2019 Wray, K. B. Rethinking Scientific Specialization. Social Studies of Science, Vol. 35, No. 1 (Feb., 2005), Pp. 151-164

    14/15

    Wray: Rethinking Scientific Specialization 163

    Edge, David O. & Michael J. Mulkay (1976) Astronomy Transformed: The Emergence of Radio

    Astronomy in Britain (New York: John Wiley and Sons).

    Gregory, R.A. (1977) 'The Gastrointestinal Hormones: A Historical Review', in A.L.

    Hodgkin, A.F. Huxley, W Feldberg, W.A.H. Rushton, R.A. Gregory & R.A. McCance

    (eds). The Pursuit of Nature: Informal Essays on the History of Physiology (Cambridge:

    Cambridge University Press): 105-32.

    Hughes, Sally Smith (1977) The Virus: A History of the Concept (New York: Science History

    Publications).

    Hull, David L., Peter D. Tessner & Arthur M. Diamond (1978) 'Planck's Principle', Science

    202 (17 November): 717-23.

    Kuhn, Thomas S. (1977a) 'Preface', inT.S. Kuhn, The Essential Tension: Selected Studies in

    Scientific Tradition and Change (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press): ix-xxiii.

    Kuhn, Thomas S. (1977b) The Essential Tension: Selected Studies inScientific

    Tradition and

    Change (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press).

    Kuhn, Thomas S. (1996 [1962]) The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 3rd edn (Chicago,IL: University of Chicago Press).

    Kuhn,Thomas, S. (2000 [1987]) 'What are Scientific Revolutions?', inT.S. Kuhn, The

    Road Since Structure: Philosophical Essays, 1970-1993, with an Autobiographical

    Interview, edited by J. Conant & J. Haugeland (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago

    Press): 13-32.

    Kuhn,Thomas S. (2000 [1991]) 'The Road Since Structure1, inT.S. Kuhn, The Road Since

    Structure: Philosophical Essays, 1970-1993, with an Autobiographical Interview, edited by

    J.Conant &

    J. Haugeland (Chicago,IL:

    Universityof

    Chicago Press): 90-104.Kuhn, Thomas S. (2000 [1993]) 'Afterwords', inT.S. Kuhn, The Road Since Structure:

    Philosophical Essays, 1970-1993, with an Autobiographical Interview, edited by J. Conant

    & J. Haugeland (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press): 224-52.

    Kuhn, Thomas S. (2000) The Road Since Structure: Philosophical Essays, 1970-1993, with an

    Autobiographical Interview, edited by J. Conant & J. Haugeland (Chicago, IL:

    University of Chicago Press).

    Law, John (1976) 'The Development of Specialties in Science: The Case of X-Ray Protein

    Crystallography', in Gerard Lemaine, Roy MacLeod, Michael Mulkay & Peter

    Weingart (eds), Perspectives on the Emergence of Scientific Disciplines (Chicago, IL: Aldine

    Publishing Company): 123-52.Lemaine, Gerard, Roy MacLeod, Michael Mulkay & Peter Weingart (1976a) 'Problems in

    the Emergence of New Disciplines', in Gerard Lemaine, Roy MacLeod, Michael

    Mulkay & Peter Weingart (eds), Perspectives on the Emergence of Scientific Disciplines

    (Chicago, IL: Aldine Publishing Company): 1-23.

    Lemaine, Gerard, Roy MacLeod, Michael Mulkay & Peter Weingart (eds) (1976b)

    Perspectives on the Emergence of Scientific Disciplines (Chicago, IL: Aldine Publishing

    Company).

    Mulkay, M.J. (1975) 'Three Models of Scientific Development', Sociological Review 23:

    509-26.

    Mulkay, M.J. & D.O. Edge (1976) 'Cognitive, Technical and Social Factors in the Growthof Radio Astronomy', in Gerard Lemaine, Roy MacLeod, Michael Mulkay & Peter

    Weingart (eds), Perspectives on the Emergence of Scientific Disciplines (Chicago, IL: Aldine

    Publishing Company): 153-86.

    Mullins, Nicholas C. (1972) 'The Development of a Scientific Specialty: The Phage Groupand the Origins of Molecular Biology', Minerva: Review of Science, Learning and Policy

    X: 1, 51-82.

    Price, Derek de Sol?a (1986 [1963]) Little Science, Big Science ... and Beyond (New York:

    Columbia University Press).

    Shapin, Steven (1994) A Social History of Truth: Civility and Science in Seventeenth Century

    England (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press).

    Swanson, Don R. & Neil R. Smalheiser (1997) 'An Interactive System for Finding

    Complementary Literatures: A Stimulus to Scientific Discovery', Artificial Intelligence91: 183-203.

    This content downloaded from 14 3.106.201.11 on Fri, 21 Jun 20 13 19:30:10 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/18/2019 Wray, K. B. Rethinking Scientific Specialization. Social Studies of Science, Vol. 35, No. 1 (Feb., 2005), Pp. 151-164

    15/15

    164 Social Studies of Science 35/1

    Thagard, Paul (1999) How Scientists Explain Disease (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University

    Press).

    Waterson, A.P. & L. Wilkinson (1978) An Introduction to the History of Virology (Cambridge:

    Cambridge University Press).

    Weinberg, Steven (1998) 'The Revolution that Didn't Happen', The NewYork Review ofBooks XLV (8 October): 15, 48-52.

    Worboys, Michael (1976) 'The Emergence of Tropical Medicine: A Study in the

    Establishment of a Scientific Specialty', in Gerard Lemaine, Roy MacLeod, Michael

    Mulkay & Peter Weingart (eds), Perspectives on the Emergence of Scientific Disciplines

    (Chicago, IL: Aldine Publishing Company): 75-98.

    Zuckerman, Harriet (1988) 'The Sociology of Science', in N.J. Smelser (ed.), The Handbook

    of Sociology (London: SAGE Publications): 511-74.

    K. Brad Wray isAssistant Professor in the Department of Philosophy at theState University of New York, Oswego. His research addresses the followingissues: the interaction between epistemic and social factors in science; therole of collaborative research in science; invisible hand explanations for thesuccess of science; the relationship between age and scientific productivity;and the viability of functional explanations of social phenomena.

    Address: Department of Philosophy, State University of New York, Oswego,128 Piez Hall, Oswego, NY 13126, USA; email: [email protected]