university of ghana a critique of the political philosophy

72
UNIVERSITY OF GHANA A CRITIQUE OF THE POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF FELA ANIKULAPO-KUTI BY INUSAH AWUNI (10441817) THIS DISSERTATION IS SUBMITTED TO THE UNIVERSITY OF GHANA, LEGON IN PARTIAL FULFILMENT OF THE REQUIREMENT FOR THE AWARD OF MA AFRICAN STUDIES DEGREE

Upload: others

Post on 28-Dec-2021

5 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

UNIVERSITY OF GHANA

A CRITIQUE OF THE POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF

FELA ANIKULAPO-KUTI

BY

INUSAH AWUNI

(10441817)

THIS DISSERTATION IS SUBMITTED TO THE UNIVERSITY OF

GHANA, LEGON IN PARTIAL FULFILMENT OF THE REQUIREMENT

FOR THE AWARD OF MA AFRICAN STUDIES DEGREE

2014

UNIVERSITY OF GHANA

A CRITIQUE OF THE POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF

FELA ANIKULAPO-KUTI

BY

INUSAH AWUNI

This Dissertation is submitted to the University of Ghana, Legon in Partial

Fulfilment of the Requirement for the Award of MA African Studies Degree

JULY, 2014

ii

DECLARATION

Candidate’s Declaration

I hereby declare that this dissertation is the result of my own original research

and that no part of it has been presented for another degree in this University

or elsewhere.

Candidate’s Signature:………………………… Date:………………………..

Name: Inusah Awuni

Supervisors’ Declaration

We hereby declare that the preparation and presentation of the dissertation

were supervised in accordance with the guidelines on supervision of

dissertation laid down by the University of Ghana.

Principal Supervisor’s Signature:…………………… Date:…………………...

Name: Dr. Osman Alhassan

Co-Supervisor’s Signature:…………………………Date……………………...

Name: Professor Daniel Avorgbedor

iii

ABSTRACT

I have argued that since Plato, the main task of political philosophy is

to prescribe how the ideal state ought to be attained. Several postcolonial

thinkers, activists and theoreticians, notably, Fela Anikulapo-Kuti attempted a

prescription of the ideal state suitable for Africa. Thus Fela’s political

philosophy could be summed up as follows: the realisation of Africa’s cultural

independence, the unification of continental Africa under democratic

governance and Africa’s return to the traditional communalism of its

ancestors. Noble as Fela’s political philosophy may seem, nonetheless, it is

replete with some discrepancies. The central objective of this dissertation was

to elucidate some of the contradictions inherent in Fela’s political philosophy.

First, Fela’s glorification of traditional African communal past was not borne

out of the facts, since such past had been altered by years of acculturation.

Besides, such idealisation of Africa’s past veiled Fela from seeing that as a

result of the Islamic and Euro-Christian imprint, Africa had moved beyond the

communal stage. Again, the political kingdom as advocated by Fela was

necessary but not sufficient for other independences economic and social.

More so, Fela’s denunciation of Islam and Christianity for their role in the

enslavement and colonisation of Africa was emotional rather than logical. The

socio-political divisions among states and empires in what is now

geographically Africa were exploited by the slave masters and colonial

powers. He again presented a simplistic solution to the triple heritage problem

in Africa arising from the Islamic and Euro-Christian influences, since he

failed to realise that such influences had taken root. Last but not the least,

Fela’s contravention of existing morality and the excessive use of marijuana

appeared not to have given him much room and space to coherently develop

an ideology for his political philosophy.

iv

ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS

My deepest appreciation goes to my supervisors, Dr. Osman Alhassan

and Professor Daniel Avorgbedor, for the valuable time they spent in

supervising the dissertation. May they be richly blessed! Special appreciation

goes to Professor Akosua Adomako Ampofo, Professor Atta Britwum,

Professor Peter Kojo Grant, Professor R. N. Osei, Francis Taale, Irene Zaato,

and Mark Anthony Alongya for their enormous help and support in the

development of the dissertation.

v

DEDICATION

Dedicated to Tiswini Jerrilyn Awuni

vi

TABLE OF CONTENTS

Page

DECLARATION ii

ABSTRACT iii

ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS iv

DEDICATION v

CHAPTER ONE

1.0 Background to the Study 1

1.1 Statement of the Problem 12

1.2 Methodology 12

1.3 Objective of the Study 13

1.4 Organisation of the Study 13

CHAPTER TWO

Review of Related Literature 14

2.0 Introduction 14

2.1 Review of Literature on Fela’s Biography 14

2.2 Review of Literature on Fela’s Political Consciousness 16

2.3 Review of Literature on Fela’s Ideological Orientation 21

2.4 Review of Literature on Fela’s Pan Africanism 26

CHAPTER THREE

The Political Philosophy of Fela Anikulapo- Kuti 28

3.0 Overview 28

3.1 The Formation of Fela’s Political Consciousness 29

vii

3.2 The Philosophy behind the Formation of Kalakuta Republic 33

3.3 Fela’s Disillusionment with the Postcolonial African State 35

3.4 Fela’s Critique of Neo-colonialism 38

3.5 Fela’s Suggestion of the Way Forward 41

3.6 The Glorification of African Communal Past 41

3.7 Fela’s Contribution to Pan-Africanism 43

CHAPTER FOUR

A Critique of Fela’s Political Philosophy 45

4.0 Overview 45

4.1 Critique of Fela’s Continentalism 45

4.2 Critique of Fela’s Position on African Communalism 48

4.3 Summary and Conclusions 58

REFERENCES 61

1

CHAPTER ONE

1.0 Background to the Study

Political philosophy as an integral part of philosophy is concerned with the

quest for the truth about political matters. It is the philosophical investigation of

political society as a demand of human nature (Okoro, 2004). All the tools of

philosophical investigation are employed to deal with the existing societal

problems of political nature. Man, says Aristotle, “is a political animal.” As a

social animal, man requires certain basic principles to help him organise and

realise his aim in society. At one time or another, societies are confronted with

specific social and political problems, and the views expressed by philosophers

about these problems are relevant as theoretical guides to such societies in

resolving those problems (Okoro, 2004). The ultimate aim of political philosophy

is to conceive a good society where people can live happily. Although political

philosophy may reflect on the socio-political milieu of an era, society or group of

societies, the ideas generated from such reflections may transcend a historical

epoch or the peculiar circumstances of a society. Political philosophy cannot be

tied down to the political thought of an era or else it will no longer be ethics or

applied ethics. It will lose its value as political philosophy. In this wise political

philosophy becomes universal because it does not merely reflect on societal

structure but also on the socio-psychological and existential necessities of

societies in general (Okoro, 2004).

The ultimate and essential questions that are core to political philosophy

are, ‘why are political societies formed? In other words, why do men come

2

together to form political societies? How best are societies to be organised so that

the purpose for which they are formed could be realised'? (Omoregbe, 1991, p.

50). These fundamental questions lead to another question, which is, how much of

society’s common goods can an individual own without depriving others of their

fair share? (Omoregbe, 1991). It is this basic question that determines what

pattern a society follows, that is, whether capitalist, socialist or the mixed

economic model.

The nature of socio-political matters in our days demands the unity of

theory and praxis. It is this unity and praxis that makes political philosophy

become a model of applied ethics rather than mere arm-chair reflection. Hence,

the central task of political philosophy shifts from mere analysis of concepts and

the practice of criticism to criticism through practice, that is, from the dissolution

of concepts to the dissolution of obsolete social and international institutions

(Ogundowole, 1988).

Like philosophy itself, political philosophy is an all-embracing field,

covering all spheres of social life. As a disciplinary study of social life, the task of

political philosophy includes that of the political scientist, the political sociologist,

the political economist, the political psychologist as well as the politician. The

political scientist as a political scientist, is an analyst who employs empirical

means for the study and analysis of society, just as the politician qua politician, is

merely concerned with the employment of the tools of other fields for achieving

specific goals and ends for the community or the society. Though each of the

fields dealing with socio-political matters overlaps with each other, none is as

3

embracing as political philosophy on matters of human social existence (Okoro,

2004).

As an all-embracing field, political philosophy concerns itself with the

formation of ideological and ethical norms and standards, theories of the state its

function covers the material, physical and moral exertions to bring about the

derived goals that a sociological setup demands (Okoro, 2004). The all-embracing

role of political philosophy was recognised in the history of ancient Greek

philosophy by Plato when he advocated for a philosopher to be the king in his

great work, the Republic. In this book Plato contends that

Until philosophers rule as Kings or those who are now

called Kings and leading men genuinely and adequately

philosophise, that is, until political power and

philosophy entirely coincide, while the many natures

who at present pursue either one exclusively are forcibly

prevented from doing so, cities will have no rest from

evils… nor, I think, will the human race (Republic,

473c-d).

The role of political philosophy in nation building or reconstruction cannot

be overemphasised. For instance, Machiavelli (1999) believes that everyone

deserves a strong and effective government. Hobbes (1996) believes that

everyone deserves peace and security. Bentham (1996) thinks that everyone

deserves happiness, while Marx (1959) believes in the economic equality of

mankind and thus urges, in the interim, the dictatorship of the proletariat. In

4

Africa on the other hand, Nkrumah (1964) and Fanon (1963) believe in the

survival and dignity of the African personality among others.

Some scholars are of the view that the role of the political philosopher is

purely theoretical. They are unaware of the aspect of philosophy which deals with

‘what is,’ 'what ought to be' and ‘what there is.’ Contrary to this view, the role of

the political philosopher, like that of political philosophy and philosophy itself, is

all embracing. It consists of theory and practice, action and reflection. This is so

because as Nkrumah famously observed, “practice without thought is blind,

thought without action is empty” (Nkrumah, 1964, p. 56). Once again, Plato

realised the role of the political philosopher as a theoretician and a politician and

thus advocated that a philosopher should always oversee the affairs of the state. In

the same spirit, after he jointly published the Communist Manifesto with Engels,

Karl Marx participated in the revolt aimed at overthrowing the ‘Kaiser’s regime’

in Germany. Nkrumah went beyond theory to establish an ideological institute at

Winneba, a coastal town in Ghana, the purpose of which was to train politicians in

the art of good governance and at the same time liberate the African Personality

from mental slavery, in order to enable the African recover his lost dignity and

identity.

One of the most essential functions of political philosophy is that it helps

us to establish an ideological direction and orientation. Those who are aware of

this fundamental role of political philosophy readily comprehend and analyse

world socio-political and economic issues be they domestic, regional or

international. In doing this, such political philosophers follow their ideological

5

preferences or direction which mainly consist of ideals, theories, norms and

programmes of action.

Fundamentally, political philosophy could be said to have

four main features:

(i) It is itself a social reality. It is an ideology in terms of which certain

institutions and practices are justified and others rejected. Hence it is a

tool for evaluation.

(ii) It is an ethic. An articulation of ideals which on various levels of

generality and articulation is used in judging man’s events, actions and

decisions and as goals, guidelines and policies.

(iii) It theorises about man’s society and history, the reason and the need of

society and why events and facts are intertwined yet can be

differentiated.

(iv) It designates agencies of action, of the means of reform, revolution and

conservation. It contains strategies and programmes that embody both

ends and means, and designates the historical levers by which ideals

are to be won and maintained after they have been won (Okoro, 2004).

Thus, the basic function of political philosophy is that it tells us how to

find out where we stand and where we may be going. It gives us some answers to

these questions and prepares us for the unknown future. To examine any political

philosophy therefore, one must examine it as an ideology, a statement of ideals,

designation of agency or agencies and as a set of social theories (Okoro, 2004). In

order to illuminate the topic under consideration, it is advisable that we

6

distinguish political philosophy from political theory, political science, and an

ideology, since these political terminologies have some semantic affinity.

In a more general sense, Sabine (1973) thinks that every political theory

could be scrutinised from two angles: as social philosophy and as ideology. As

ideology, theories should be seen as psychological phenomena, which transcend

fact or falsity. Sabine thinks that theories are beliefs, events in people’s minds and

factors in their conduct, so that the task of the political philosopher is to ascertain

the extent to which these theories help in shaping the political community

(Sabine, 1973). In keeping with the above general view, Sabine further observes

that

Political theory is, quite simply, man’s attempts to

consciously understand and solve the problems of his group

life and organisation.... It is the disciplined investigation of

political problems ... not only to show what a political

practice is, but also to show what it means. In showing

what a practice means, or what it ought to mean, political

theory can alter what it is (Sabine, 1973, pp. 3-5).

I infer from the above quotation that political theory, in a historical sense,

has been used to either defend or question existing customs and conventions of a

given society at a given time.

On the other hand, political ideology can be seen as a systematic and all-

embracing principle which attempts to provide a comprehensive and universally

applicable theory of human nature and society, with a detailed programme of

7

attaining it (Ruch & Anyanwu, 1981). Marxism provides a classical example of

ideology which is summed up in Marx’s much quoted contention that

philosophers have only interpreted the world in various ways; the point, however,

is to change it (Marx, 1959). In keeping with this practical perspective of

ideology, Marx defines ideology as a set of beliefs by which people are led to

deceive themselves. These beliefs are imposed on them by the economic

conditions in which they live. They are a form of class consciousness and so they

are particularistic and false ((Ruch & Anyanwu, 1981). Whichever way the

equation is balanced, ideologies are meant to influence the world for better or for

worse. That explains why in a positive and pragmatic sense, ideologies are seen as

rational basis aimed at the ideal state along rational and scientific lines ((Ruch &

Anyanwu, 1981). In a nutshell, ideologies for the most part are propounded by

philosophers and political theoreticians, they are described and marketed by

political scientists and implemented by politicians or statesmen (Okoro, 2004).

This brings us to the distinction between political philosophy and political

science.

Whereas political philosophy is really a discipline setting up norms or

ideal standards for society and government, telling us what ought to be the case or

what we ought to do, political science explains how governments conduct their

affairs and how men behave in their pursuit of actual political objectives, instead

of prescribing what governments ought to do and what ought to be our political

objectives (Popkin & Stroll, 2000). In brief, political philosophy prescribes how

an ideal polity can be attained whereas political science merely describes a

8

particular form of institution. For instance, when Plato suggested in The Republic,

that the philosopher kings should conduct the affairs of the state while the

guardians and auxiliaries subordinate themselves to the philosopher kings and

perform other functions of the state so as to create a harmonious atmosphere in

the state, he was actually prescribing how the ideal polity could be brought about.

Hence Plato was affirming the prescriptive role of political philosophy when he

proposed that the rational element of the soul and the philosopher king for that

matter should control the affairs of the body and the state respectively.

It must however be observed that a given political philosophy is largely

determined by the prevalent circumstances of a given historical epoch. It is

problems of a given period that compel political philosophers to react and then

make efforts to address such problems of their time. Thus, political philosophy

does two things. It reacts to existing problems such as anarchy, corruption and

oppression among others. Secondly, it attempts to provide a theoretical or

philosophical blue print to address such existing problems of a given period. For

instance, writing at a time of political chaos and moral confusion, Italian

unification constituted the fundamental objective of Niccolo Machiavelli.

Macchiavelli (1999) perhaps hoped to redeem Italy from poverty and servitude.

Hence he dreamt of a united, rejuvenated and glorious Italy. In order to achieve

this objective, Macchiavelli thought that the end justified the means. He reasoned

that the defence and preservation of the state should be the main preoccupation of

the “Prince”. Considerations of justice or injustice, humanity or cruelty, as well as

9

glory or shame were immaterial in light of protecting the individual’s life and

liberty (Machiavelli, 1999).

Political philosophy deals with such issues as what ought to be the proper

limits of government over members of society and how an ideal state ought to be

organised. Should members of parliament be allowed to exercise their franchise

according to their conscience, or should they merely reflect the opinions of their

constituents, states or provinces? The central task of political philosophy

therefore, is to prescribe how an ideal state ought to be organised (Popkin &

Stroll, 2000). In general, political philosophy may study the nature of human

communities in order to evaluate their aims and modes of operation. In a more

general way, political philosophy asks the following questions: What is the

relationship between the individual and the state? Can the existence of the state be

justified? What principles should guide the operation of government? And what

form of constitution should be adopted by government? Or what form of

constitution should the ideal state adopt in order that it brings about maximum

amount of happiness for its citizens as against greater unhappiness? Or, is the

individual’s moral quest for maximum happiness best fulfilled in a stateless

society? (Popkin & Stroll, 2000).

In order to answer the above questions, political philosophy derives its

strength from other branches of philosophy namely, metaphysics, logic,

epistemology and ethics. Thus, in order for one to understand the dynamics of

political philosophy, some background knowledge of history of political thought

10

is desirable. Philosophers, before, during and after the era of Plato have been

preoccupied with the idea of attaining a strife-free ideal state.

Fela Anikulapo Kuti was one African musician who was preoccupied with

a political philosophy not only for his country Nigeria, but a political philosophy

for the African continent as a whole. The political philosophy of Fela can be

gleaned from his music, popularly called Afrobeat or to use his own expression

‘African classical music’ (Olorunyomi, 2005, Moore, 2009). Fragments of his

political philosophy can be gleaned from articles he authored in two influential

Nigerian newspapers, namely, The Punch and Daily Times from the late 1969-

1997. This is so because since time and circumstances play an influential role on

the philosophy of a philosopher, one could suggest that Fela’s reaction to the neo-

colonial system in the form of clashing with the Nigerian military authorities as

well as both civilian and military governments in Nigeria did not give him much

time to systematise his political philosophy in a coherent treatise. My objective in

this work is to extract many of the themes of Fela’s political philosophy from his

musical works, newspapers as well as certain published books on him, in order to

construct a comprehensive and coherent political philosophy.

Fela indicates that Africans and for that matter the post-colonial state had

lost its direction. From dress code to governance system, the post–colonial man

was imitating the former colonial powers as if the African could not boast of any

culture prior to colonisation. Thus, songs like ‘Grammartologilisationalism is the

Boss’, ‘Mr. Follow Follow’, and ‘Johnny Just Drop’ as well as ‘Big Blind

Country’ were composed to address this state of cultural alienation and

11

embarrassment that the African found himself. In Fela’s view, beautiful African

cities such as Oyo, and Benin among others were destroyed by the European

colonising powers with the aim that if they (Europeans) wanted to force the

African into slavery and colonise his country, then they had to prevent the African

from seeing that he was not incapable of creating beauty. Against this backdrop

therefore, Fela felt that by copying the culture of the very person who colonised

you, you give the impression that you were a savage who stood in need of

civilisation from the other side. To remedy this cultural estrangement, Fela called

for a return to traditional African communal past. In fact, his call for a return to

our ancestral past becomes comprehensible when measured against his frustration

with the effects of modernisation as well as the effects of scientific and

technological system of production. As he notes: “The right way is the one of our

ancestors: traditional technology, or naturology. That is the only viable way…

Science means pollution! … There is limit to what Europeans call technological

and industrial development. When that limit is achieved, society just crumbles

….” (Moore, 1982, p. 151).

Fela’s call for a return to our ancestral lifestyle makes sense when it is

measured against the undesirable effects associated with the advancement of

science and technology. In other words, such a call for a return to the status quo

ante cannot easily be dismissed as a nostalgic feeling. In fact, industrial-

technology forces contemporary man to revise his relationship with nature. But is

such call for the return to the past worth the salt?

12

1.1 Statement of the Problem

Several academic works by notable scholars like Moore (1982a, 2009b),

Veal (2000a, 2000b), Collins (2009), Jaboro (2012), and Schoonmaker (2003)

among others exist on Fela’s biography, his musical accomplishments, his

counterculture lifestyle, his Pan African views and his ideological ambivalence

among other themes. But an account and critique of the political philosophy of

Fela does not appear to interest the authors of most of the literature that have been

reviewed. The purpose of this dissertation is to construct and critique the political

philosophy of Fela.

1.2 Methodology

The study is largely a library based research. Primary and secondary

scholarly works on Fela were collected. This study involved content analysis of

the major works and compositions of Fela. Authoritative scholarly works done on

Fela’s musical compositions were examined. Content analysis is a technique for

collecting and analysing the content of a given text. The content thus refers to

“words, meanings, pictures, symbols, ideas, themes, or any message that can be

communicated. The text is anything written, visual, or spoken that serves as a

medium for communication. It includes books, newspaper and magazine articles,

advertisements, speeches, official documents, musical lyrics and works of art

among others” (Neuman, 2007, p. 227).

13

1.3 Objectives of the Study

At the end of the study, the researcher hopes to achieve the

following objectives:

i. To comprehend and articulate the political philosophy of Fela.

ii. To interrogate Fela’s strong conviction that political independence is

prerequisite to all other independences

iii. To demonstrate through critical evaluation, the strengths and

weaknesses of Fela’s political philosophy

1.4 Organisation of the Work

The work is organised into four chapters. Chapter one comprises the

background to the study, statement of the problem, methodology and objectives of

the study. Chapter two is comprised of literature review. This chapter reviews

relevant literature such as articles, books and other primary and secondary data

relating to the political philosophy of Fela. Chapter three attempts a

comprehensive and coherent presentation of the political philosophy of Fela.

Chapter four, the final chapter of the work, carries out a critique of the political

philosophy of Fela.

14

CHAPTER TWO: REVIEW OF RELATED LITERATURE

2.0 Introduction

In this chapter, I attempt to review the existing literature on the topic

under consideration. Since the literature on the topic ranges from Fela’s biography

to his Pan African commitments, I delineate the literature review under certain

sub-categories.

2.1 Review of Literature on Fela’s Biography

Moore (1982a) graphically chronicles the life history of Fela. He examines

the circumstances surrounding Fela’s birth, his achievements and his sojourn in

the USA in the 1960s, his introduction to the Black Power Movement which

invariably raised the political consciousness of Fela. Issues covered in this

authorised biography include Fela’s unconventional behaviour such as his

excessive love of women, his marriage to 27 ladies in 1978, the destruction of

Fela’s communal enclave, the Kalakuta Republic in 1977, his contradictory

relationship with his numerous wives on one hand and girlfriends on the other

hand, his hedonistic lifestyle as well as Fela’s traditional convictions on one hand,

and his metaphysical and epistemological views on the other hand. Fela’s political

views do not even constitute a chapter in Moore’s book. However, with hindsight,

fragments of political philosophy and bits of Fela’s views on Pan Africanism can

be gleaned from some few pages in this authorised biographical work. Thus, Fela,

Fela:This Bitch of a Life provides a rudimentary insight into the topic under

consideration.

15

Moore (2009b) in Fela: This Bitch of a Life attempts to revise his 1982

publication of Fela’s authorised biography. The difference between this book and

the earlier publication is that, Moore devotes the opening chapter of this work to

discuss Fela’s position on Africa unification. Among other themes, Moore

recounts the response of the Nigerian military to Fela’s counterculture lifestyle,

Fela’s excessive smoking of Indian hemp, and his direct condemnation of

Nigerian military regimes, particularly, in his1976 hit song “ ombie” a track that

directly insults the intelligence of the military who only obey before they could

complain (Moore, 2009). hile conceding that Fela was a contradiction in several

respects, the accusation of Fela being a polygyny and a misogyny his conception

of women as mattresses appears to have been carried out of context (Moore,

2009). Like Frantz Fanon before him, Fela, in Moore’s opinion obviously

identified the ills afflicting post-independent Africa as neo-colonialism and

predicted that relatively, the first generation of African leaders would fail to

emancipate Africa from colonialism and neo-colonialism.

In ‘Colonial Mentality’ and ‘Teacher Don’t Teach me no Nonsense’ for

example, Fela accused the new elite as follows: “You don be slave from before.

Dem don release you now. But you never release yourself” (Moore, 2009, p.13).

On the whole, an attempt by Moore to further interrogate Fela’s political

convictions and attempt to situate them within a political philosophy is lacking in

this revised edition.

Jaboro (2012) examines Fela’s belief in ancient Egyptian mystery system,

especially after 1979 when Fela was introduced to the Ghanaian magician, Kwaku

16

Addae, Fela’s nostalgic feeling for traditional African communal life, and Fela’s

rise to legendary status that got cut by HIV/AIDS infection in 1997. He

particularly discusses certain sections of Fela’s music in which Fela mounts an

attack on neo-colonialism and African leaders who were agents of this system.

Thus songs like ‘International Thief Thief’ and ‘Authourity Stealing’ directly

attack multinationals like CFAO, UAC, BP, Total, Mobil etc. of not developing

African economies (Jaboro, 2012). Jaboro further reinforces passionately Fela’s

lamentation of poverty, disease, hunger, oppression and confusion in Africa as

direct consequences of the operation of the above multinationals in Africa. This

book thus recounts Fela’s disillusionment with the post-colonial African state and

its leaders. This is exactly one function of political philosophy, namely, discontent

with ‘what is’ and a proposition of ‘what ought to be’. However, ‘what ought to

be’ with regard to Fela’s political philosophy is not given much attention in this

work.

2.2 Review of Literature on the Evolution of Fela’s Political Consciousness

Veal (2000a) points out that the life and history of Fela gives us an

opportunity to comprehend the exceptional and unprecedented way Fela used art

as a medium of creating socio-political, cultural and revolutionary consciousness

in order to contribute to the intellectual debate on Pan-Africanism. Veal (2000a)

wonders whether Fela’s life story should be examined as a comedy, tragedy,

tragic hero or better still, a character in a literary piece who achieves greatness

and lost that greatness due to hamartia. In spite of the difficulty in classifying

Fela’s political significance, Veal regards Fela’s Afrobeat style of music as a

17

particular version of hybrid music which holds a transformed significance not

only for a particular nation-state in post-independent Africa but the entire African

continent as a whole. Thus, in the opinion of Veal, the two most fundamental

objectives of Fela’s art could be summarised in two phrases, namely, a search for

the remedy to the problems of the nation-state in post-independent Africa and the

realisation of a Pan-African state to serve as a haven for all marginalised and

dispossessed Africans the world over.

Veal (2000b) further traces the formation of Fela’s social awakening and

political consciousness to his childhood exposure to traditional social functions in

Abeokuta as well as the influence of his mother’s Marxist and Leninist influences

on him and urges that “… in order to understand the ideological underpinning of

Fela’s social mission, his symbolic deconstruction of his elite status, his deviation

from the traditional function of the African creative artist, and the varying

reception of his message by different sectors of the Nigerian society,” then we

must look critically at the issue of the social strata of post-independent Nigeria in

which Fela was born.

Though Veal’s insight into Fela’s struggle in post-colonial Nigeria relies

more on empirical evidence, nevertheless such a consideration of the life of Fela,

especially Fela’s analysis of post-independent Africa and his Pan-African

orientations will afford us an opportunity to examine the political philosophy of

Fela Anikulapo-Kuti.

In “Politics of omanhood,” Nzegwu (2003) critiques Fela’s perception of

an ideal African woman as encapsulated in one of Fela’s hit songs ‘Lady’.

18

Nzegwu builts his critique of Fela’s perception of the traditional African woman

by comparing the independent roles women played as hardworking domestic

servants during the Victorian era in 19th century Europe on one hand and the role

Christianity assign to women on the other. While the former stresses economic

independence in women, the latter encourages subservience and economic

dependency. Nzegwu thinks that Fela’s insistence of an African woman to be

submissive to her husband, cook for him and do everything the husband demands,

neither reflects the character and role of traditional African woman nor her

indigenous nature. Since traditional African women aspire to social and economic

independence, Fela’s perception of them as being dependent on their husbands for

everything misses the point.

Though Nzegwu’s critique of Fela’s perception of African women is not

directly linked to Fela’s political philosophy, nonetheless, his exposure of Fela’s

inadequate comprehension of the real role(s) of an indigenous African woman

helps us to situate the place of women in his political philosophy. This will help

enrich our critique of the political philosophy of Fela.

In “No Agreement Today, No Agreement Tomorrow: Fela Anikulapo-

Kuti and Human Rights Activism in Nigeria,” Alimi and Opeyemi (2013) explore

the socio-economic problems which characterised postcolonial Nigeria and situate

the role Fela Anikulapo-Kuti played as a campaigner against the abuse of human

rights in this epoch. The above authors examine the factors which shaped Fela’s

radicalism and uncompromising attacks of the ruling elite in postcolonial Nigeria

in particular and Africa in general. Alimi and Opeyemi (2013) identify these

19

factors as the strict discipline nature of Fela’s parents, Fela’s parents anti-colonial

stance and Fela’s association with a radical newspaper known as The Planless

Times (Alimi & Opeyemi, 2013). Particularly, Fela’s affinity to his mother who

took him to several anti-colonial rallies will later play a fundamental role in Fela’s

denunciation of anything colonialism and imperialism.

Apart from these above domestic forces which had a profound influence

on Fela’s political consciousness, Alimi and Opeyemi (2013) also identify certain

external forces which aided in shaping the human rights activism of Fela. Among

these include his exposure to the literature of certain American civil rights activist

such as Malcolm X and his introduction to the Black Panthers Group in America.

Alimi and Opeyemi (2013) urges that just as Kwame Nkrumah in Neo-

colonialism: Last Stage of Imperialism (1965) blames colonialism and

imperialism for most of the problems Africa faced after the departure of the

colonising powers, Fela attributes the socio-economic and political problems

facing African people to colonialism and slavery.

Like Veal (1995), Alimi and Opeyemi (2013), offer us a useful medium by

which we could easily interpret the message inherent in Fela’s songs. In fact, their

insight into the multiple forces which shaped Fela’s human rights activism and

social commentary is useful to our study.

In “Fela’s Resistance of Domination”, Durotoye (2003) observes the

strategies Fela employed in his resistance against domination in postcolonial

Nigeria in particular and Africa in general. Durotoye (2003) further examines

Fela’s resistance against the dominant forces of postcolonial Nigeria by alluding

20

to Antonio Gramsci’s two pillars of hegemony, namely, “coercion” and

“intellectual and moral leadership”(Schoonmaker, 2003). That while coercion

demands compliance by applying force, intellectual and moral leadership secures

the consent of the dominated by a resort to persuasion (Schoonmaker, 2003).

Durotoye (2003) puts Fela’s resistance to domination in postcolonial

Nigeria into two perspectives. According to Durotype, the period 1960-1973

could best be described as Fela’s “apolitical” years, where Fela’s political

consciousness had not taken shape yet. Durotoye (2003) regards 1974-1997 as a

period which marked Fela’s intense political struggle against domination in

Nigeria, culminating in his withdrawal and death. In Durotoye’s view, from the

1960s to the early 1970s, Fela was more preoccupied with the idea of playing jazz

like any other musician before him. Hence it was after his sojourn in the USA

which exercised a profound influence in Fela’s thought when he incorporated

political music into his Afrobeat. This partly explains why Fela’s first two songs

in the 1970s, namely, “Black Man’s Cry” and “ hy Black Man Dey Suffer” were

less popular with the Nigerian masses because in these songs, Fela laid the blame

of Africa’s backwardness and underdevelopment on slavery and colonialism

(Schoonmaker, 2003).

Concomitantly, Durotoye observes that from 1974 onwards, Fela’s

building of Kalakuta Republic which was declared independent of the Nigerian

Federation and other songs which critiqued domination in postcolonial Nigeria

were indication that Fela had become politically conscious and had acquired the

capacity to resist domination and in fact, songs like “Alagbon Close” (1974),

21

“Expensive Shit” (1975), “Kalakuta Show” (1975), “ ombie” (1976), “Sorrow,

Tears and Blood” (1977) and “Unknown Soldier” (1979) are all couched and

lyricized in politics of resistances against the coercive forces of the Nigerian

State. This strategy of resistance, according to Durotoye (2003), continued until

Fela withdrew from public life and eventually gave out the ghost from Aids

related complications in August 1997.

Durotoye’s insight into Fela’s use of politics of resistance as a weapon in his

Afrobeat music adds to our understanding of the overall political agenda of Fela.

Indeed, Durotoye’s analysis of Fela’s politics of resistance further sharpens what

we set out to achieve, namely, a critique of Fela’s political philosophy. Though

Durotoye’s focus on Fela’s politics of resistance in the postcolony constitutes but

one of the aspect of our topic under consideration, it is particularly useful in

construction and deconstruction of Fela’s political philosophy.

2.3 Review of Literature on Fela’s Ideological Orientation

Palombit (1981) captures Fela’s stance on politics in general, Fela’s Pan-

African views, Fela’s revulsion of communism, militarism, capitalism,

multinational companies operating in Africa, military rule in Africa as well as the

implantation of Islam and Christianity in Africa. Palombit thinks that in Fela’s

opinion socio-political and religious forces constitute an obstacle to the overall

progress of Africa’s socio-political and economic development. According to

Palombit (1981) Fela sees capitalism and communism as two incompatible

ideologies that regard Africa as a “… milking cow and territory to settle their

differences” (Palombit, 1981, p. 2). Though Pamlobit’s article gives us an insight

22

into Fela’s reception of Pan- Africanism and denunciation of western ideologies

such as capitalism among others, and at the same time positions us to construct

Fela’s political philosophy, nonetheless, Palombit’s article, comprising only two

pages, does not exhaust the topic under consideration.

In his “Fela Kuti and the oppositional Lyrical Power” Sithole (2012),

bemoans the lack of a consistent ideological expression in Fela’s political thought

which he expressed in his political music with the aim of opposing corruption in

the postcolonial African state. This, according to Sithole, appears to constitute a

weakness in Fela’s political philosophy. Sithole further laments that the failure of

the postcolonial African state, especially Nigeria in particular, to genuinely

embark on progressive national reconstruction provided a fertile ground for

Fela’s political music to sprout and attempt to address those failures.

Sithole (2012) urges that though Fela often blamed colonialism for some

of Africa’s problems, nevertheless, with respect to who should take the ultimate

blame for the failure of the postcolonial state in Africa, Fela places the blame on

the doorstep of the first and second generation of African leaders such as Obafemi

Awolowo, Sani Abacha, Mobutu Seseko, and Thomas Sankara among others.

Indeed, the failure of the African postcolonial state has been painstakingly

discussed in Claude Ake’s book, Democracy and Development in Africa where

among other factors, Ake (2000) identifies corruption, oppression, incompetent

leadership, and lack of political liberties as factors that made development in

postcolonial Africa an illusion.

23

Sithole (2012) also devotes space to examine the rationale behind the

formation of Fela’s commune which was later named Kalakuta Republic. As to

whether the formation of this commune by Fela was imaginary or real, Sithole

avoids taking sides and argues that Kalakuta Republic, which was seen by Fela as

a state within the Nigerian state, demonstrates some form of defiance against the

oppressive and corrupt Nigerian state which managed to cow “… its subjects into

objectified submission and legitimised itself even … [when it was deemed as

‘illegitimate’]” (Sithole, 2012, p.4).

Sithole (2012) concludes his article and suggests that though Fela’s

political music, which was vitriolic in character and in content attempts to check

the abuse of state’s power, corruption and oppression in postcolonial Africa, such

political struggle lacked a key and consistent ideology in order to mobilise the

masses against oppression and marginalisation.

Sithole’s critical stance on Fela’s lack of a consistent ideology in the

political struggle against repressive forces in postcolonial Africa is refreshing. In

fact, such a critical approach in scholarship helps us to sharpen our critique of

Fela’s political philosophy.

Olaniyan (2001) admits that Fela’s “extramusical”, “extrasonic” and by

extension his unconventional lifestyle often appear to dominate that of his musical

aspect. Olaniyan further suggests that a more beneficial or rewarding study of

Fela’s musical practice is best undertaken by examining the contradictions

inherent in such music. Following Howe (1997), Olaniyan argues that there

appear to be contradictions in every aspect of Fela’s life. Olaniyan thinks, for

24

instance, that though at the level of personal life Fela spoke against tyranny and

the restriction of fundamental human and civil liberties, he “… ran a strictly

hierarchical household…” at his commune, the Kalakuta Republic.

Olaniyan finds it difficult to interpret Fela’ ideological orientation within

a philosophical spectrum. Particularly, the difficulty lies in reconciling Fela’s

belief in cultural nationalism with his idolisation of two leftist intellectuals,

namely, Kwame Nkrumah and Walter Rodney (Olaniyan, 1997). This

contradiction in Fela’s thought perhaps compelled Howe (1997) to remark that

“… Fela had no interest in perfect philosophical correctness and that

contradictions of a sometimes painful sort were apparent in Fela’s own life and

household”(Olaniyan, 1997, p.77). Olaniyan particularly explores Fela’s

insistence that the only way forward for postcolonial Africa is to return to its

precolonial past and wonders whether such an approach could provide effective

remedy to the myriad of problems facing postcolonial Africa. Thus, what, in

Olaniyan’s opinion, spurred Fela’s nativist attitude to development include factors

such as “tyrannical leadership, political instability, flagrant disregard for rules,

economic…malformation, epochal inequalities between the few and the many,

impossible cities, recurrent devastating interethnic wars, anti-state rebellions and

attendant heart-breaking dispersal of populations…”(Olaniyan, 1997, p.7)

Olaniyan (1997) traces the origin of Fela’s cultural nationalism to he

(Fela’s) association with the Black Power group in 1969 during his sojourn in the

United States. That association with the group raised Fela’s social awareness and

political consciousness which later became useful in his struggle against the

25

postcolonial state, especially in the 1970s and 80s. According to Olaniyan (1997),

though Fela lacks a consistent ideology in his political theorising, Fela’s bold

exertion had the advantage of taming “modernity, that historical aggressive

estern imposition on other lands…” (Olaniyan, 1997, p.83)

Though Olaniyan’s study provides useful suggestions and tools to help

advance our examination of Fela’s political philosophy, especially its

identification of antinomies or contradictions inherent in Fela’s thought,

Olaniyan’s over concentration of Fela’s contradictions veils him from seeing that

consistent contradictions, if maintained consistently, becomes a coherent theory

of knowledge. Besides, Olaniyan’s exposure of some contradictions in Fela’s

thought will help enrich our critique of Fela’s political philosophy.

In “Rebel with a Cause”, Stein (2013) narrates the circumstances which

led to his friendship with Fela in London in the 1970s. To Stein, this friendship

with Fela gradually led to his appointment as a co-manager of Fela’s music.

Indeed, Stein graphically chronicled his tour with Fela’s musical group and the

accomplishment they chalked during such time he spent with the group. Stein

describes Fela as an accomplished human right activist whose message was not,

and still not, for Africa in particular but for the world at large. Though fragments

of Stein’s work touches on the political agenda of Fela, his work is basically a

polemical narration of Fela’s sojourn in London, the United States and beyond.

Nonetheless, Stein’s capture of Fela’s fight for human rights in postcolonial

Nigeria helps us in constructing and critiquing Fela’s political philosophy.

26

2.4 Review of Literature on Fela’s Pan Africanism

Awuni (2011) in “The Contribution of The Afrobeat Legend, Fela

Anikulapo-Kuti to Pan-Africanism”, narrates a brief history of Fela from his

Abeokuta childhood up-bringing to stardom as a master of classical African

music. Awuni (2011) particularly pays attention to how the traditional culture of

the Yoruba played an influential role in shaping how Fela fashioned his cultural

nationalism and pan- Africanism. Also discussed in this article is how the

advancement in science and technology and their negative consequences,

especially the destructive tendencies of nuclear weapons, wars and pollution of

the environment ultimately compelled Fela to admonish Africans to return to their

precolonial past as a solution to the postcolonial problems (Awuni, 2011).

Though Awuni’s study is not devoted to discussing the political

philosophy of Fela, it is useful to the current study since such exposure of Fela’s

stance on the ideal solution to postcolonial African problems will aid sharpen our

critique of Fela’s political philosophy.

Though Veal’s (1995) “Jazz Music Influences on the ork of Fela

Anikulapo-Kuti” is devoted to examining the specific elements of jazz element in

Fela’s music, how Fela embraced the jazz element in his music and the extent to

which Afrobeat can be called jazz, Veal devotes space in his work to examine the

historical and contextual underpinning of most of Fela’s tracks. This gives the

reader the advantage to easily discern the message Fela tries to portray in most of

his compositions or songs. Thus, from Veal’s study, songs like ‘Movement

Against Second Slavery’ (MASS), ‘Big Blind Country’ (BBC), ‘Customs Check

27

Point’ (CCP), and ‘Beast of No Nation’ (BONN) among other songs of Fela can

easily be discerned and their philosophical usefulness ascertained.

28

CHAPTER THREE

THE POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF FELA ANIKULAPO-KUTI

3.0 Overview

As already argued out in chapter two, political philosophy is that branch of

philosophy which prescribes how the ideal state ought to be organised or attained.

In its bid to prescribe the ideal state, political philosophy considers existing

political arrangement(s) as being inadequate in addressing existing socio-political

and economic challenges. For instance, in The Republic, Plato's attempt to

prescribe an ideal society for the Athenian state was premised on the political and

civil instability that characterised Greece after the Peloponnesian War. Similarly,

the political philosophy of Fela Anikulapo-Kuti is linked up with the social,

political, economic, religious and cultural problems confronting postcolonial

Africa when political independence came. I aver that while it is true that most of

the issues Fela raised in his political philosophy largely reflected the problems of

postcolonial Africa, Fela equally blamed certain precolonial factors such as

slavery and racism as historical hangover hindering the material and cultural

progress of Africa. Even so, Fela's political philosophy could best be described in

the words of Veal (2000) as cultural Pan-Africanism. That is, Fela was convinced

that Africans had been uprooted culturally as a result of slavery and colonisation

and so the continent needed a cultural re-orientation to fix such cultural

estrangement. Though an examination of Fela's political philosophy reveals

glaring contradictions and complexities, it is fair to say that it was basically such

antinomies in his philosophy which help to make his philosophy exciting.

29

More so, some scholars such as Omoregbe (1991), Stroll and Popkin

(2000), aver that no philosophy can arise out of vacuum. That a given philosophy

is to a large extent influenced by the socio- political and economic environment in

which the philosopher emerged. Thus such a given philosophy attempts to

respond to the problems and challenges of such time and place. Just as African

freedom fighters such as Kwame Nkrumah (1964), Julius Nyerere (1968), and

Leopold Senghor (1964) constructed their philosophies in the form of

Consciencism, Ujamaa and Negritude to address the challenges arising from

Africa's slave and colonial past, Fela's Afrobeat, in which he expressed his

political philosophy in a form of social criticism, vitriolic attacks of the state and

a recommendation for Africans to turn to their ancestral past can be seen in the

same light as the solutions put forward by the first generation of African leaders

that I have mentioned. Thus, Fela's music, after 1973 was purely political. It was a

form of political music that attempted to fix complexities and contradictions of

post-colonial Nigeria in particular and Africa in general. What then account for

the evolution of politics in Fela’s music? I now turn to address how his political

consciousness evolved.

3.1 The Formation of Fela's Political Consciousness

Born in 1938 to a middle class family in Abeokuta, Fela had a taste of

colonial life since Nigeria was still under the colonial authority of Britain. Since

Fela's father, Rev. Israel Ransome Kuti and mother, Funmilayo Ransome Kuti

were both influential personalities and Anglicans, they were determined to bring

up all their four children, including Fela, the Christian way of life (Moore, 1982).

30

At the age of 16 at Abeokuta Grammar School, Fela's first evidence of

political consciousness started when he formed a club called The Planless Society,

whose aim was to disobey all school rules and regulations. Subsequently, Fela

founded and edited a radical newspaper called The Planless Times which was

swiftly proscribed by the Abeokuta Grammar School because its publications had

incited riots in the school (Moore 1982).

However, the single most important factor which tremendously influenced

the political views of Fela was his mother, Funmilayo Ransom Kuti. As a

president of Nigeria's women's union, an anti-colonial activist, a recipient of

Lenin peace prize in the early 1960s, a first Nigerian woman to drive a car and to

successfully tour the iron curtain countries such as the USSR, China, Poland,

Yugoslavia and East Berlin, Fela's mother exercised a tremendous influence on

him (Moore, 1982, Veal, 2000).

Two incidents however deserve emphasis concerning the formation of

Fela's political consciousness. As a youth, Fela recalls with excitement and deep

admiration for his mother for leading a delegation of women in Abeokuta to

successfully dethrone the chief, Ladapo Ademola II, for the latter’s complicity in

harassing small scale traders on matters of tax payment. It appears pretty clear

that such admiration for his mother's courage and tenacity will prepare Fela to

withstand harsh military attacks and reprisals, including the dumping of his

mother’s mock coffin at Dodan Barracks, the official seat of government, as a

protest against an attack by the military in 1977 in which his mother later died

from injuries (Moore, 1982).

31

More so, Fela equally recalls in Fela, Fela: This Bitch of a life that as a

youth his mother took him to several anti-colonial rallies. Since such rallies

absorbed her mother's time from domestic work including disciplinary actions

including flogging, Fela admits that "... when she was running around doing

politics she didn't have time to flog me. The more she got into politics, the less

time she had to beat me. So I too began liking politics” (Moore, 1982, p.42).

Indeed, Fela's mother's leftist and Marxist leanings and bravery so

impressed Kwame Nkrumah that the latter arranged to see her when he visited

Lagos in 1958. Again, Fela met Nkrumah with his mother. Fela's admiration for

the Ghana’s premier on their first meeting speaks for itself. “Man, he was so cool.

My mother thought a lot of him ... Nkrumah! Man, I will never forget his face”

(Moore, 1982, p. 47). There is no doubt that Fela's embrace of Nkrumahism and

Pan-African views dates back to his youthful days even before he was mature

enough to read and digest Nkrumah’s written works. In later years, Fela will not

only espouse the political agenda of Kwame Nkrumah, who called for continental

unification of Africa, but will worship Nkrumah as a Pan-African hero at his

Afrika Shrine, a club in which he entertained visitors with live performances.

Apart from the above domestic factors which played a major role in

shaping the political philosophy of Fela, an external factor which equally played a

key role in the formation of Fela's political consciousness cannot be ignored. Fela

admits that up to his American sojourn in 1969, he was largely ignorant of politics

and African history. However, coming into contact with his American friend,

Sandra Izsadore, Fela was introduced to the activities of the Black Panther

32

Movement and the Autobiography of Malcom X. This development convinced

Fela that Africa had a history to tell the world and the earlier Africa started

conscientising other people about its rich cultural and historical heritage, the

better it will be for Africa. Fela frankly admits his ignorance of African history

prior to his sojourn in America as follows: "Sandra gave me the education I

wanted to know. She was the one who opened my eyes. She is the one who spoke

to me about Africa! For the first time I heard things I’d never heard before about

Africa! She talked to me about politics, history. She taught me what she knew and

what she knew was enough for me to start on” (Moore, 1982, p.85).

It will be correct for one to conclude from the above quote that in spite of

some domestic factors which exercised profound influence on his political views,

Fela discovered Africa, at least intellectually, from America. Through his

association with Sandra Izsadore, through his leanings with the Black Panther

Movement and through his acquaintance with history and political literature on

Africa, Fela's intellectual consciousness was indeed awakened in America. It was

this intellectual awakening which will guide him to make an attempt to liberate

Africa from cultural alienation and neo-colonialism. Thus, realising that Africa

was in theory politically free but economically, culturally and religiously ruled

from the Metropolitan countries of the former European colonial powers, Fela

would make an attempt to establish an independent commune which he called

Kalakuta Republic, the only Republic in Africa which was truly independent in

symbolic terms.

33

3.2 The Philosophy behind the Formation of Kalakuta Republic

It must be made clear that several writers have dismissed Fela's communal

compound, Kalakuta Republic, as a deviant enclave which promoted the use of

hard drugs like heroine and Indian hemp. Such an interpretation misses the point

because granted that Kalakuta Republic gained notoriety for drugs including the

open and excessive use of marijuana, such a labeling should rather be seen as a

consequence of the real philosophy and intention behind the formation of

Kalakuta Republic.

After his return from America in 1975, and especially having been

heavily influenced by Sandra Izsadore and made to believe in the glorious history

of Africa, Fela decided to de-Anglicise every English name around him. To this

end, he changed his name from Fela Ransome Kuti to Fela Anikulapo-Kuti.

Anikulapo means one who carries death in his pouch. Thus, his full name could

be interpreted as follows: ‘He who emanates greatness, carries death in his porch

and cannot die’ (Jaboro, 2012, Moore, 1982a, 2009b & Veal, 2000). Fela's mother

followed her son and changed her name from Funmilayo Ransome Kuti to

Funmilayo Anikulapo-Kuti, demonstrating some sort of solidarity for her son.

In the same year, that is 1975, having been arrested and beaten by the

military for using marijuana, Fela decided to name his communal enclave

Kalakuta Republic as a defiance against established state authority. According to

Veal (2000) “Fela ... named his communal compound 'Kalakuta Republic'

proclaiming it as autonomous zone free from the laws and jurisdiction of Nigeria

and opened to people of African descent worldwide especially to the persecuted

34

Africans" (Veal, 2000, p.143 ). Similarly, Fela admits in an interview with Moore,

that in view of the dispersion of Africans owing to the inglorious trade in human

cargo, “All African countries should open their doors to Africans from

everywhere especially those in the Americas" (Moore, 1982, p.109). Thus we

learn from Moore (1982) that Kalakuta was meant to be a sanctuary for every

African who was escaping persecution. Indeed, it was meant to reflect the

communal lifestyle of Africans prior to the advent of colonisation when Africans

regarded themselves as an inseparable integral whole. Fela expresses his reason

for the formation of Kalakuta Republic as follows:

It was when I was in the police cell at the C.I.D (Central

Intelligence Division) headquarters in Lagos; the cell I was in

was named “The Kalakuta Republic” by the prisoners. I found

out when I went to East Africa that “Kalakuta" is a Swahili

word that means "rascal". So, if rascality is going to get us what

we want, we will use it; because we are dealing with corrupt

people, we have to be rascally with them (Collins, 1985, p.

120).

In spite of the seemingly frank admission of the real reasons behind the

formation of Kalakuta Republic, Veal (2000) insists that the declaration of

Kalakuta's autonomy was symbolic, designed to express dissent against the

complexities of post-colonial Nigeria and Africa as a whole. Veal intimates that

the independence of Kalakuta should be seen as unrealistic. In spite of Veal's

query, we are of view that the philosophy behind the formation of Kalakuta is

35

very much missed in Veal's interpretation. The reason is that Fela was very much

obsessed by the supposedly glorious and ideal nature of African precolonial past.

He had experienced little of that in colonial Nigeria and as well as in racial

America in the 1960s. Besides, Fela had learnt about the communal lifestyle of

Africans in the literature which was available to him in America. He had met

Kwame Nkrumah and had by 1974/75 acquainted himself with Nkrumah's

continental unity argument. It was therefore natural that Fela would attempt to

create the nucleus from which the united African dream could draw inspiration. In

other words, Africa as a continent and a race was being reinvented and re-

imagined in this communal enclave that Fela established. Kalakuta may appear

ambitious, all the same, it had its own laws and time (Kalakuta Meridian Time

(KMT)) that get obeyed and followed respectively.

From Kalakuta and from his Afrika Shrine as well as a column under

which Fela bought a space and regularly featured articles under the name ‘The

Chief Priest Say', he will subject both military and civilian leaders of Africa to

criticisms and other forms of vitriolic attacks. These criticisms of African

leadership arose from Fela's disillusionment with the failure of African leaders to

develop the continent in spite of the availability of resources both natural and

human. This is often referred to in post-independent African literature as the

paradox of abundance.

3.3 Fela's Disillusionment with the Post-colonial African State

Born in 1938 and died in 1997, it is fair to say that Fela's life story cannot

be reasonably examined without reference to the problems of postcolonial Africa.

36

In other words, Fela's “personal story is inextricably intertwined with the history

of post-colonial Nigeria" in particular, and Africa in general (Veal 2000, p.19).

The continent as a whole had so much hope for material, cultural, political and

economic progress when many African states, with the exception of Apartheid

South Africa, Portuguese Guinea Bissau, Southern Rhodesia, had gained their

independence in the 1960s. In fact, this era has been described by some

postcolonial scholars as a decade of hope. Since colonialism had ended, at least

politically, the continent had been settled for development. Thus, Africans in

general became disillusioned when they realised that this era, which had been

christened the decade of hope, presented them with hopelessness and a grim

future.

Ake (2000) summed up the state of Africa in post-colonial era much

clearer.

Three decades of preoccupation with development in

Africa have yielded meager returns. Africa economies have

been stagnating or regressing. For most Africans real

incomes are lower than they were two decades ago. Health

prospects are poorer, malnourishment is widespread and

infrastructure is breaking down as are some social

institutions (Ake, 2000, p.1).

Indeed, these were some of the many factors that caught the attention of

Fela in which he used his Afrobeat music to address.

37

On the exploration of oil in South-eastern Nigeria without due regard for

the pollution of the environment for instance, Fela composed a track called

"Government of Crooks" with the view of addressing "... government’s

complicity in the despoliation of south-eastern Ogoniland by foreign oil

companies, a state of affairs that had recently culminated in the state execution of

Ogoni activist... Ken Saro iwa” (Veal, 2000, p.4)

More so, tracks like “Chop and Clean Mouth like Nothing Happened, Na

New Name for Stealing" comprehensively addresses the sequential and colossal

rape of Nigeria's economy by successive governments be they military or

civilian. In this track also, Fela equally bemoans the hardships that were visited

on the African masses as a result of unwitting African leader's adoption of

Structural Adjustment Programmes (SAPS). Besides, "Country of Pain" is

paradoxically composed to bemoan hardships and suffering in the midst of

abundance of oil in Nigeria. "Big Blind Country" for instance, addresses a wide

range of issues issues that range from the need for indigenous African medicine

to the use of African languages as means of true liberation. In the track he sings;

The man wey them say go steal for market, im go stand for court go dey look o,

the only thing for im go understand for there, now them tell am to go for jail o. In

much the same way "Akunakuna, Senior brother of parambulator" launches a

devastating critique of government’s oppression of small scale traders and "other

participants of the country's informal economy" ( Veal, 2000, p. 4)

In a nutshell, the above cited tracks that speak to the problems of

postcolonial Africa will suffice. However, Fela's enigma was why African leaders

38

could callously continue to betray their continent in the manner in which they did.

Thus after so many years of social vilification of the leaders of postcolonial

Africa for corruption, plunder of African resources, continuing enslavement of the

African masses and complicity with multi-national companies for the degradation

of the African environment, Fela became convinced that the true liberators of

Africa would not be the leaders of his time. In an interview with Moore (2009)

when he had withdrawn from public life and was spending so much time in

spiritual contemplation in his room at Kalakuta, Fela could not hide his

disillusionment with the failure of the postcolonial state to transform. As he puts it

"why even bother? I have said everything. It's all been said. It’s all been done"

(Moore, 2009, p. 283).

3.4 Fela's Critique of Neo-Colonialism

Neo-colonialism is a popular terminology in ant-imperialist literature.

Following Lenin's book, Capitalism: The Highest Stage of Imperialism, Nkrumah

followed suit with his 1965 publication, Neo-colonialism: The Last Stage of

Imperialism. Whether Nkrumah's book was a deliberate echo of Lenin's work or

not as Mazrui (1966) wants us to note, both books appear to carry a compressive

examination of the operations of the capitalist mode of production championed by

America and Europe. Nkrumah (1965) thinks that “The essence of neo-

colonialism is that the State which is subject to it is, in theory, independent and

has all the outward trappings of international sovereignty. In reality its economic

system and thus, its political policy is directed from outside” (Nkrumah, 1965, p.

ix). In Nkrumah's view, the operation of neo-colonialism does not differ from the

39

colonial system of direct exploitation, except that direct colonialism cannot, like

the proverbial camel, return to Africa hump and lump (Nkrumah, 1965).

Indeed, neo-colonialism in Africa almost immediately started when

political independence came. Hence, such neo-colonial elements like Structural

Adjustment Programmes (SAPS), other conditionalities of the World Bank and

the complicity between international organisations such as multi-national

companies and comprador African bourgeoisie for the purpose of plundering

African resources did not escape Fela's social criticism, which were inherent in

his compositions, sang at the Afrika Shrine.

Fela questions Africa's claim of being independent from slavery and

colonialism when behaviour of Africans cannot be said to be different from the

colonial era. As he wonders, how could Africans be free when they continue to

exhibit the identities of those who colonised and enslaved them? Thus, the

Europeanisation and Christianisation as well as the Arabisation and Islamisation

of Africans in the wake of political independence were enough proof that Africa

was still being ruled by the invisible government (neo-colonialism). To quote him

regarding a track titled "Upside Down" which he had recorded in the 1970s, it

(the track) dealt with all the confusion and corruption of the Gowon-Obasanjo

period. “All the shit man! The chaos! the foolishness of those Africans who look

down on the names of their ancestors and take European names" ( Moore, 1982,

p.131). As a cultural Pan-Africanist who led by example, Fela puts it this way:

“Me, myself, I had just changed my own name...” (Moore, 1982, p. 131).

40

But more importantly, Fela questioned the adoption of colonialist

language(s) by governments in a continent that was said to have emancipated

itself from the colonising European powers. In one of his songs, he says: Instead

of Nigeria, Onyibo language we speak, Government style be say, Onyibo thing

one better past.

In fact Fela’s query is sensible to the extent that analogically, just as you

cannot expect illiterate and poor third world parents to respond favourably to

‘birth control’ appeals when more children constitute their only ‘welfare

insurance’ against the instabilities of old-age, you cannot expect Africans to

reflect and intellectualise in a colonialist language that does not exhaust the

ontological problems, especially the vital forces and cultural values of the

African. Thus for the continent to progress educationally, politically,

economically and socially and to conscientise other cultures about the richness of

its language, we need to reflect, articulate and examine the African problems in

indigenous African languages ‘for the unexamined life isn’t worth living’. In fact,

the Kenyan foremost literary artist, Ngugi Wa Thiongo is embarking on this

journey.

In the field of culture, Fela indicates that Africans and for that matter the

postcolonial state had lost its direction. From dress code to governance system,

the postcolonial man was imitating the former colonial powers as if the African

could not boast of his culture prior to colonisation. Thus, songs like

‘Grammartologilisationalism is the Boss’, ‘Mr. Follow Follow’, and ‘Johny Just

Drop’ as well as ‘Big Blind Country’ were composed to address this state of

41

cultural alienation and embarrassment that the African found himself. In Fela’s

view, beautiful African cities such as Oyo, and Benin among others were

destroyed by the European colonising powers with the aim that if they

(Europeans) wanted to force the African into slavery and colonise his country,

then they had to prevent the African from seeing that he could be creative.

Against this backdrop therefore, Fela felt that by copying the culture of the very

person who colonised you, you give the impression that you were a savage who

stood in need of civilisation from the other side.

3.5 Fela’s Suggestion of the Way Forward

In view of the cultural estrangement that the African had found himself in

the wake of political independence, Fela put up certain propositions to help in the

reconstruction of the African identity. These propositions could be summed up in

three terms, namely, the glorification of African communal past, the adoration of

the black race, and the continental unification of Africa.

3.6 The Glorification of African Communal Past

To remedy this cultural estrangement that the African had found himself

in postcolonial Africa arising from what Mazrui (2002) and Nkrumah (1964) had

referred to us the Triple Heritage, Fela called for a return to traditional African

communal past. In fact, his call for a return to our ancestral past becomes

comprehensible when measured against his frustration with the effects of

modernisation as well as the effects of scientific and technological system of

production. As he writes: “The right way is the one of our ancestors: traditional

technology, or naturology. That is the only viable way… Science means

42

pollution! … There is limit to what Europeans call technological and industrial

development. When that limit is achieved, society just crumbles ….” (Moore,

1982, p. 151). Fela’s call for a return to our ancestral lifestyle makes sense when

it is measured against the undesirable effects associated with the advancement of

science and technology. In other words, such a clarion call for a return to the

status quo ante cannot easily be dismissed as a nostalgic feeling. In fact,

industrial-technology forces contemporary man to revise his relationship with

nature. Since the ‘home’ of modern man is where his world of work is, the

industrial concentration of labour, capital, communication systems, administrative

institutions, etcetera, in vast single localities compels the transformation of natural

vegetation into cities. As the city grows in terms of spatial expansion, over-

population, and pressure on housing, transportation and other public facilities, it

produces a decaying inner city of slum and ghetto dwellings, unemployed and

unemployable persons, vagrants and criminals, muggings, rape, armed robbery

among others (Aidoo, 1990). The attempt by descent people to escape this cancer

of industrialism leads, inevitably, to suburban life. This, in turn, brings in the bull-

dozer that wipes out areas that were once rich in cultivable land; natural resource

and wildlife. Instead of yesterday’s clover, there is today’s concrete (Aidoo,

1990).

In other words, the Hiroshima and Nagasaki experience during World War

II, the 1986 Chernobyl Nuclear Plant’ explosion in the Soviet Union and the

recent Fukushima nuclear leakage in Japan are certainly experiences that threaten

43

man’s safety on planet earth which in the long ran validates Fela’s call for a return

to the African communal past.

3.7 Fela’s Contribution to Pan-Africanism

In the field of politics, Fela’s contribution to Pan-Africanism stands out

clearly. In fact, he realised that the cultural revolution he so much desired could

not be attained without political independence. This is marked by his formation of

a political party, Movement of the People (MOP) to contest Nigeria’s presidential

elections in 1978 and 1984. Fela realised that the boundaries that separated one

African country from the other were so arbitrarily drawn at the Berlin Colloquium

that those boundaries needed to be erased or redrawn through continental political

union and planning. As he puts it “The Africans should not limit their purview to

the small enclaves cut out for them at the Berlin Conference. While the Europeans

take care of their interest, the Africans just go about copying foreign values …

which permanently endear them to the whole world as certified slaves” (Moore,

1982, p. 150).

In Fela’s opinion, sound continental and economic planning could only be

attained in Africa if the whole of the continent were united under one federal

democratic country. Thus his formation of MOP, a party he would use to capture

political power in Nigeria with which he would sacrifice Nigeria’s sovereignty for

an African continental union government is reminiscent of Nkrumah’s Ghana’s

independence being meaningless unless it was linked up with the total liberation

of Africa (Nkrumah, 1963).

44

In the field of ideology, Fela condemned the deliberate plundering of

Africa’s wealth by multi-national companies from the West. He recounts this

situation in ‘ITT’, ‘Amen Amen Amen’, in which he accuses corrupt African

leaders such as Olusegun Obasanjo, Sani Abacha, General Abiola, Mobutu

Seseko, and Blaise Campaore among others of enhancing global international

capitalism by delivering the natural resources of Africa to the West and at the

same time selling the continent without conscience. To this end, Fela denounced

the capitalist system of production as a system that is too exploitative of human

labour to be reconciled with traditional African communalism, which manifests

the qualities of humanism, classlessness and egalitarianism. Fela’s attack of the

capitalist system did not favourably dispose him to socialism. As he puts it,

“There are many ideologies in Africa that don’t belong there. The capitalist and

the communist systems have always regarded Africa as a milking cow and a

territory to settle their own conflicts” (Palombit, 1981, p. 2).

45

CHAPTER FOUR

A CRITIQUE OF FELA’S POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY

4.0 Overview

I continue to emphasise that the fundamental concern of political

philosophy is the prescription of how the ideal state suitable for a given people

ought to be attained. We further argue that in an attempt to prescribe how the

ideal state could be attained, the political philosopher implicitly also describes the

ideal state, in which case political philosophy may appear to encroach on the

domain of political science. Apart from Fela’s critical stance on corruption,

mismanagement of Africa’s resources by the continent leaders, widespread

military dictatorship which characterised the continent in the second and third

decades after independence, the plunder of Africa’s resources through the

conspiracy of western interests and African comprador bourgeoisie, what I regard

as Fela’s political philosophy is an uncritical love of all that is qualified black

(African), his embrace of cultural Pan-Africanism as a pre-requisite to combatting

the innumerable problems and challenges that faced postcolonial Africa as well as

his glorification or idealisation of the African communal past. I thus devote this

chapter to elucidating the contradictions inherent in Fela’s political philosophy.

4.1 Critique of Fela’s Continentalism

There is no doubt that Fela’s version of Pan-Africanism oscillates around

continental unity of Africa as the surest way to socio-political and economic

progress. Thus, songs like ‘Chop and Clean Mouth’, ‘Movement Against Second

Slavery’, ‘Underground System’, and ‘Authority Stealing’ among others urge

46

Africans to unite in order to move forward. Fela was amazed that while other

continents such as Europe and America were united and had moved forward,

Africa was still geographically balkanised, prone to the manipulation of

neocolonialism and imperialism. As he puts it, “we should not limit our area of

belonging to that small enclave cut out for us by the Berlin Conference of 1884-5.

Africa has to open her doors to every black man in the world. Until Africa sees it

that way, she won’t have made it yet, man! White people … have a sense of

belonging. They have even gone as far as electing a European parliament to take

care of their interest” (Moore, 1982, p. 150).

Noble as Fela’s vision of African unity may appear, the two

methodologies that he relied upon for the realisation of African unity were not

only incompatible, but contradictory and therefore yielded no results. Thus Fela

can be faulted on methodological bankruptcy as far as his quest for African unity

was concerned. First, the first methodology Fela relied upon for the unification of

Africa was cultural revolution. Thus songs like ‘Mr Follow Follow’ (MFF),

‘Johnny Just Drop’ (JJD), ‘Big Blind Country’ (BBC), were composed to criticise

Africans who looked down upon their own culture and were copying European

values and ideals.

Realising that European and Islamic influences had altered the behaviour

of Africans arising from their combined presence with African traditional culture,

a phenomenon which had been examined by Nkrumah (1964) and Mazrui (1966,

2002), Fela abandoned the cultural approach (method) and switched to another

equally problematic method, namely, the political method.

47

Fela realised that the African cultural revolution he so much desired could

not be attained without political independence. Hence, he formed a political party,

Movement of the People (MOP) to contest the Nigeria elections of 1978 and

1984. Let us remind ourselves that Kwame Nkrumah, the first premier of

independent Ghana, had placed more emphasis on the political kingdom as the

surest way for the attainment of all other independences economic and cultural.

As he said, ‘seek ye first the political kingdom and all others would be added unto

you’ (Mazrui, 1966).

To be sure, political independence is certainly a path to control state

capital within which all aspects of the state’s life could be organised. It must

however be observed that merely seeking the political kingdom as an end in itself

rather than as a means to an end is immaterial to economic and any other

independence(s) (Mazrui, 1966). In other words, what most advocates of the

political kingdom school of thought, including Fela, overlooked is the distinction

in the art of critical thinking or logic (Mazrui, 1966). The flaw inherent in the

logic of proponents of the political kingdom, including Fela, is their inability to

make a distinction between necessary and sufficient conditions. Hence, the

political kingdom as canvassed by Fela was a necessary condition for Africa to

attain the other independences. However, political independence was not a

sufficient condition for all other independences (Mazrui, 1966). This critique is

even reinforced by an empirical fact that most countries in Africa are politically

independent, yet, economic independence is still a mirage.

48

We thus observe that what seems to unite most advocates of the political

kingdom argument is their strong conviction that the political kingdom is the key

to all other independences cultural, social, religious and economic among others.

Even so, Fela was born in 1938, made to meet Kwame Nkrumah as a

youth and grew to espouse Nkrumahism among other ideologies. One would have

expected that he would have adopted a critical stance toward Nkrumahism, at

least, intellectually. But he failed to consider certain weaknesses inherent in

Nkrumah’s political literature. For historical purpose, Nkrumah had earlier been

criticized for advocating a return to the African communal past. Critics argued

that such a return to the communal past portrays the African as being fit only for

jungle life. Nkrumah was therefore compelled to abandon this thesis that he

constructed in Consciencism. Thus, for adopting a dogmatic attitude towards

Nkrumahism, Fela exposed himself to those criticisms which had been raised

against Nkrumahism. One may therefore be compelled to conclude that either

Fela did not understand Nkrumahism or espoused Nkrumahism religiously.

4.2 Critique of Fela’s Position on African Communalism

In response to the crisis of cultural identity which the African had found

himself in the postcolonial era, Fela admonished Africans to return to the

traditional communal past of their ancestors. Though this call for a return to the

status quo ante cannot be easily dismissed as a nostalgic feeling, nonetheless, one

could still argue that

To advocate a return to the rock from which we were

hewn is a charming thought. This is so because we are

49

faced with contemporary problems arising from

colonisation, political subjugation, economic exploitation,

educational and social backwardness, increases in

population, familiarity with the methods and products of

industrialisation as well as modern agricultural techniques.

These–as well as a host of other complexities–can be

resolved by no mere communalistic society, however

sophisticated, and anyone who so advocates must be caught

in insoluble dilemma of the most excruciating kind. In fact,

all available evidence from socio-political history discloses

that such a return to the status quo ante is quite

unexampled in the evolution of societies (Nkrumah, 1967,

p. 205).

The above quotation unambiguously demonstrates that Nkrumah

had emancipated himself from the idyllic conception of traditional African

society which was supposedly glorious, perfect and devoid of any social

hierarchy or classes so much that it got altered only with the colonial

imprint. Yet, Fela, who openly admitted of being Nkrumahist, still clung

to the erroneous conception of traditional Africa as unsullied.

Moreover, it must be observed that having been amazed by the

colossal scale, technological and scientific advancement of American

culture during his sojourn in the 1960s and 1970s, one would have

expected that Fela would have been moved by such experience of

50

America’s achievements to either prescribe for Africa, a communitarian

society which would at least, embrace some positive contributions of

western culture. Thus such a consistent insistence that Africans should

return to their ancestral lifestyle was not only impossible but cast a bad

picture on the African as a being who is fit only for jungle life, backward

and not innovative. In other words, one possible problem for Fela’s

position is that the African is incapable of scientific and technological

thought.

In the field of ideology, a critic can say that Fela demonstrated

gross ambivalence in his ideological orientation. Though Fela dismissed

capitalism and socialism as being too incompatible to be reconciled with

traditional African communalism, he never made any effort to propose an

ideology of his own which will guide postcolonial Africa in its quest for

nation building. He often appeared to vacillate between capitalism and

socialism, not knowing whether to express his preference for one over the

other. Though Fela could be spoken of in some circles as a cultural

nationalist, nevertheless, Howe (1997) points out the contradiction

inherent in Fela’s political philosophy with respect to his (Fela’s)

ideological stance. As Howe notes, “Fela had no interest in perfect

philosophical correctness” (Howe, 1997, p. 130). Similarly, Veal (2000)

observes, “in most generous terms, he has been described as ideologically

inconsistent, more frequently as a reactionary traditionalist, and at worst

an unrepentant sexist” (Veal, 2000, p. 105).

51

It is significant to note that the observations made by Howe and

Veal are not necessarily accidental. In fact, the above observations do

coincide and mutually reinforce each other. Such observations aid us to

explain why Fela was seldom successful in his political ambition to rule

Nigeria. Such an absence of ideology in the political philosophy of Fela

only helps to explain his motives of being reactionary and could not

therefore be trusted with the responsibility of state’s power by most urban

elite. While it may be true that ideologies may not be completely

successful in their application in a given scenario, ironically, the complete

absence of an ideology produces what Fela himself describes as an aimless

economic and political wandering, which in the long ran, disorients the

people. Fela satirises this phenomenon in one of his songs as

‘perambulation’ and labelled most African leaders as perambulators. as

Fela self-critiquing himself in this song? Whatever the case, we see this

development as self-criticism of an unconscious kind.

Another observation of contradiction in Fela’s thought was his

dismissal of Christianity and Islam in Africa. While he denounced

Christianity for its complicity in the colonisation of Africa, he dismissed

Islam and Arabs in particular, for their role in the acquisition of slaves in

Africa. Even so, Fela was “equally suspicious of organised religion in its

organised form, which he viewed as irreversibly corrupted by colonialism”

(Veal, 2000, p. 244).

52

I agree with Fela that by accident of Arabic enslavement and

European colonisation of Africa, post-independent Africa habours two

main strands of patriarchal monotheism, namely, Islam and Christianity

(Okoro, 2010). I further agree that these two brands of monotheism are not

only ontologically hostile to each other, but equally irreconcilable with

traditional African weltanschauung.

Though these religions cannot be exonerated as they spearheaded

the campaign for the enslavement, disbandment and subsequent

colonisation of Africa, Fela lost sight of the fact that prior to the European

and Arabic advent, “Africans were prepared to sell, often for not more

than thirty pieces of silver, fellow tribesmen and even members of the

same extended family and clan” (Nkrumah, 1967, p. 202). I further agree

with Nkrumah (1967) that “… colonialism deserved to be blamed for

many evils in Africa, but surely, it was not preceded by an African Golden

Age or paradise” (Nkrumah, 1967, p. 203).

The point being made here is that long before the European and

Arabic advent in Africa, however vicious such experience might appear,

recorded history of inter and intra-tribal and state wars abound. And such

divisions among states, tribes and empires in Africa were easily exploited

by the colonialists to their own advantage. Rather than blame the forces of

Islam and Christianity for the African condition, Fela should have noted

that the internal strife in what is now geographically referred to as Africa,

53

accelerated rather than decelerated the enslavement and colonisation of the

continent. As Veal (2000) aptly observes,

… the lyrics of ‘Gentleman’ and ‘ hy Black Man Dey

Suffer’ present an idyllic image of pure, ‘original’ Africa that

remained harmonious and unsullied until the arrival of the

Europeans. Such a conception fails to account for the pre-

existing social and political divisions the colonialists were so

able to exploit, as well as the continuous process of change

and outside influence that inform all cultures (Veal, 2000, p.

246).

It is therefore a wonder as to how Fela clung to the African past

which was not exactly the picture he attempted to paint nor could be

reconstructed in its unsullied form. One other way of forging ahead was

not for Fela to dismiss the above religions for playing a historical role in

Africa’s colonisation and enslavement, but to attempt to domesticate

them as experiences that had come to stay. Better still, one could attempt

to forge a combined harmony for them to co-exist with traditional

African culture harmoniously as Nkrumah did in Consciencism.

Nkrumah is thus worthy to quote:

With true independence regained, however, a new

harmony needs to be forged, a harmony that will allow the

combined presence of traditional Africa, Islamic Africa

and Euro-Christian Africa, so that this presence is in tune

54

with the original humanist principles underlying African

society. Our society is not the old society, but a new

society enlarged by Islamic and Euro-Christian influences.

A new emergent society is therefore required (Nkrumah,

1964, p. 70).

In the above quotation, Nkrumah demonstrates the difficulty, if not

the impossibility, of purging Africa of the Islamic and Euro-Christian

influences. It remains valid therefore to suggest that a converging point be

found in order to allow traditional Africa, Euro-Christian and Islamic

Africa to converge and co-exist harmoniously. Thus, by insisting on a

return to traditional African communal past, Fela appears to have exhibited

his gross ignorance of Nkrumah’s political literature, given that the latter

had made far-reaching revision of some of his theses.

In addition, Olorunyomi (2005) points out that three of

Nkrumah’s intellectual works, namely, Consciencism, Africa Must Unite

and Neo-Colonialism:The Last Stage of Imperialism, played a profound

role in the development of Fela’s construction of an African identity. He

could not therefore fathom why Nkrumah had revised his own ideas on

matters of communalism, yet, wonders why Fela failed to make any

intellectual advancement about the true picture of communal Africa,

when those he professed to be furthering their arguments, had updated

their political ideas.

55

More so, the general perception of Fela as a social deviant had

certain ramifications for his political agenda and own credibility. At

worst, Fela’s unconventional behaviour negatively impacted his

ambition to assume political leadership in postcolonial Nigeria much

against his desire. Among other contraventions of existing norms, here

was a man who collectively married twenty seven women in the

immediate aftermath of the siege of Kalakuta Republic in 1978; here

was a man who openly smoked marijuana in a state which had outlawed

the use of such drug, and here was a man who openly confessed of being

a hedonist –a philosophical theory which posits that the ultimate purpose

of human life is to seek pleasure. These qualities of Fela had the

tendency of portraying him in the eyes of the general public as an

irresponsible reactionist who was obsessed with winning political power.

He could not therefore be trusted with any public position of which

exemplar was expected from such leader. As Veal points out, “the anti-

Fela position most frequently voiced holds that he was a complete

nuisance who had no respect for the rule of law or anybody else,

including himself. He contributed a lot to the current state of absolute

moral decadence among the youths (sic) in Nigeria’s urban centres”

(Veal, 2000, p. 250).

It is also significant to note that such unconventional behaviour

easily aided his enemies, who were opposed to his leadership bid, to

campaign against his candidature at the opportune time. Though the time

56

was slow in coming, all the same it came. It came in 1978 and 1984,

when his political party was banned from participating in those

elections.

In essence, Fela was mainly seen within the lens of the urban and

semi-urban elite of postcolonial Nigeria as lacking credibility and could

not therefore be trusted with state’s leadership. Such contraventions of

existing norms by Fela did much to damage his image as a political

activist and a social critic than he imagined. While Veal (2000) sums up

the consequences of Fela’s unconventional behaviour by alluding to a

Yoruba traditional aphorism which maintains that “one is not fit to rule a

nation if one’s own home is not in order”, Denzer (2003) holds that “on

occasion, journalists reported that he came directly from his bedroom,

semen dripping from his underpants, for interviews. This brazen, public

celebration of his sexuality and preferences offended many, especially

the educated Christian elite…” (Veal, 2000, p. 250 & Denzer, 2003, p.

112).

Veal (2000) painstakingly shows that while Fela’s excessive use

of marijuana could be advantageous in terms of creating room for

innovation and at the same time economically empower the

underprivileged or marginalised, its excessive use by Fela carried certain

consequences for his political ambition. In the first place, Veal thinks

that the abuse of marijuana by Fela was inconsistent with the coherent

reflection needed to construct a systematic political philosophy.

57

Secondly, the excessive use of marijuana appeared to have undermined

the credibility of Fela as a social commentator and a political critic. And

thirdly, the open use of marijuana by Fela was not only illegal but

pitched the Nigerian military against him, which used the least

opportunity to physically harass him at the slightest provocation. I

conclude that the political philosophy of Fela, however its merit, was not

taken seriously because of his contravention of existing laws at the time.

One could therefore speculate that many sympathisers who could have

joined him in fighting the system were perhaps discouraged “… by the

intensifying performative contradictions, belligerence and absurdities of

his lyrical compositions, of his onstage comportment, antics and

grotesqueries….” (Durotoye, 2003, p. 191).

58

4.3 Summary and Conclusions

The dissertation contends that since the Golden Age of Greece,

and much especially since the era of Plato, the primary preoccupation of

political philosophy has been how the ideal state ought to be organised.

Thus an attempt to prescribe the ideal state suitable for the reconstruction

of postcolonial Africa did not escape the intellectual curiosity of Fela

Anikulapo-Kuti, who consciously and for the most part, expressed his

political philosophy in his music, popularly known as Afrobeat. Thus

Fela saw the prevalent political economy of postcolonial Africa as a

phenomenon which could not lead Africa out of its colonial past. Indeed,

corruption, oppression, mismanagement of Africa’s resources by the

continent’s leaders, neo-colonialism in Africa, the despoliation of

Africa’s environment in oil producing areas in Africa and the African

cultural crisis, were all phenomena Fela attempted to address in his

musical compositions and attempted to propose a way out of this morass.

He proposed that the solution to Africa’s problems is for Africans

to embark on continental unification under democratic governance, a

return to the communal ways of their ancestors as well as purging

themselves and of the continent, of Euro-Christian and Islamic

influences. I therefore dedicated chapter one of the dissertation to

examining and elucidating the subject matter of political philosophy. I

then proceeded to tease out the political philosophy of Fela in some of his

musical compositions and written works.

59

Chapter two of the dissertation discusses the related literature on

the topic under consideration. I found out that not much intellectual

efforts have been made to systematise Fela’s political views or thought

into a coherent political philosophy. I therefore moved on to examine the

political views of Fela with the purpose of ascertaining what uniquely

constitutes Fela’s political philosophy which is worthy of intellectual

attention. I argued that his political philosophy could be summed up as

follows: his quest for continental unification of Africa under democracy,

his insistence that Africans return to communal methods of production

and the abolition of certain religions he considered foreign to Africa.

Based on the above factors, I proceeded to comprehensively carry

out an expose of Fela’s political philosophy in chapter three. I thus

systematised the major themes in Fela’s political philosophy with the aim

of sieving the weaknesses and contradictions in such philosophy. Thus

the weaknesses of Fela’s political philosophy constituted the forms of our

critique in our last chapter, namely, chapter four.

I realised among other weaknesses that apart from the

methodological bankruptcy Fela committed in his quest for continental

unification, his view that political independence is key to all other

independences is problematic since it is replete with logical problems.

More so, the solution he proposed to the African identity crisis or triple

heritage problem is equally unconvincing since the dismissal of such

cultures is too simplistic to remedy the problem. Again, Fela’s

60

construction of the African communal past misses the point since his

idealisation of such past veiled him from seeing that such past was not

exactly the picture he was trying to paint. Even so, his insistence that

Africa return to the communal past of its ancestors appears to strengthen

the perception that the African is not dynamic and is fit only for jungle

life. Such a return to the communal past has also been demonstrated to be

impossible. In a nutshell, Fela’s contravention of societal norms through

his extreme and brazen display of his hyper sexuality and the excessive

use of cannabis distracted him from putting forward a coherent and

consistent ideology required of political philosophy.

61

REFERENCES

Aidoo, J.T.(1990). “Of Knowledge and its Social Abuses”. Oguaa

Social Science Journal, 1(1), 54-66.

Ake, C. (2000). Democracy and Development in Africa. Washington

D.C.:The Brookings Institution.

Alimi, S. and Opeyemi, I. A. (2013). “No Agreement Today, No

Agreement Tomorrow: Fela Anikulapo-Kuti and

Human Rights Activism in Nigeria”. The Journal of

Pan African Studies, 6(4), 74-94.

Anyanwu, K. C. & Ruch, E. A. (1981). African Philosophy. Rome:

Catholic Book Agency.

Awuni, I. (2011). “The Contribution of Fela Anikulapo-Kuti to Pan

Africanism”. Unpublished Manuscript.

Bentham, J. (1996). An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation.

Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Collins, J. (1985). Music Makers of West Africa. Washington D.C.:

Three Continents Press.

Collins, J. (2009) Fela: Kalakuta Notes. London: KIT.

Denzer, L. (2003). “Fela, omen, ives”. In Schoonmaker,T.

(Ed.), Fela: From West Africa to West Broadway

(111-134). New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

62

Durotoye, Y. (2003). “Fela’s Resistance of Domination”. In Schoonmaker, T.

(Ed.), Fela: From West Africa to West Broadway (172-194). New York:

Palgrave Macmillan.

Fanon, F. (1963). The Wretched of the Earth. New York: Grove Press.

Hobbes, T. (1996). Leviathan. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Howe, J. (1997). “Fela Anikulapo-Kuti: An Honest Man”. New Left

Review, 225(1997), 127-133.

Jaboro, M. (2009). The Ikoyi Prison Narratives: The Spiritualism and

Political Philosophy of Fela Kuti. Maryland: Lulu Press.

Machiavelli, N. (1999). The Prince. New York: Penguin Books.

Marx, K. (1959). Basic Writings on Politics and Philosophy. New York:

Doubleday.

Mazrui, A. (1966), “Nkrumah: The Leninist Czar”. Transition, 26(1),

8-17.

Mazrui, A. (2002). Nkrumah’s legacy and Africa’s triple heritage.

Accra: Ghana University Press.

Moore, C. (1982a) Fela Fela: This Bitch of a Life. Allison & Busby:

Lawrence Hill Books

Moore, C. (2009b) Fela: This Bitch of a Life. Allison & Busby:

Lawrence Hill Books.

Neuman, W. L. (2007). Basics of social research: Qualitative & quantitative

approaches. Boston, MA: Pearson Education, Inc.

Nkrumah, K. (1963). Africa must unite. London: Panaf.

63

Nkrumah, K. (1964). Consciencism London: Panaf.

Nkrumah, K. (1965). Neo-Colonialism: The Last Stage of

Imperialism. London: Panaf.

Nkrumah, K. (1967). ''African socialism revisited''. African Forum,

1(1), 200-208.

Nyerere, J. (1968). Ujamaa: The Basis of African Socialism. Dare-Salaam:

Oxford University Press,

Nzegwu, N. (2003). “The Politics of omanhood”. In Schoonmaker,

T. (Ed.), Fela: From West Africa to West Broadway

(135-148). New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

Ogundowole, E.K. (1988): Self-reliancism of a new order. Ikeja: John

West Publications.

Okoro, C. (2004). Self-Reliancism and the National Question. (An Unpublished

MA Dissertation). University of Lagos, Lagos.

Okoro, C. (2010). "Communalistic democracy and the traditional African

Society". An unpublished paper presented at the University of

Lagos, Lagos.

Olaniyan, T. (2001). “The Cosmopolitan Nativist: Fela Anikulapo-

Kuti and the Antinomies of Postcolonial Modernism”.

Research in African Literatures, 32(2), 76-89.

Olorunyomi, S. (2005). Afrobeat: Fela and the Imagined Continent.

Ibadan: IFRA

64

Omoregbe, J. I. (1991). Knowing Philosophy. Lagos: Joja Educational

Publishers.

Palombit, R. (1981). “I am a Natural Man”. OOR Music Magazine,

2(1), 1-10.

Plato (1974). The Republic. Trans. by G. M. A. Grube. Indianapolis: Hackett.

Popkin, R. H and Stroll, A. (1996) Philosophy Made Simple. California:

Doubleday.

Sabine, G. H. (1973). History of political theory. ( 4th ed.). New Delhi:

Oxford University Press.

Schoonmaker, T. (2003). Fela: From West Africa to West Broadway (Ed).

New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

Senghor, L. S. (1964). Essays on African Socialism. London: Pall Mall Press.

Sithole, T. (2012). “Fela Kuti and the Oppositional Lyrical Power”.

Muziki, 9(1), 1-6

Stein, R. (2013). “Rebel ith a Cause”. New African, 6(6), 44-47.

Veal, M. (1995). “Jazz Music Influences on the ork of Fela”.

Glendora Review, 1(1), 8-13

Veal, M. (2000). “And After a Continentalist”. African Quarterly on

the Arts, 2(2), 1-6.

Veal, M. (2000). Fela: The Life and Times of an African Musical

Icon. Philadelphia: Temple University Press