unit 4 utilitarian ethics

15
Ethics, part 1 Unit 4

Upload: aimee-hoover-miller

Post on 01-Nov-2014

8.792 views

Category:

Education


6 download

DESCRIPTION

 

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Unit 4   Utilitarian Ethics

Ethics, part 1

Unit 4

Page 2: Unit 4   Utilitarian Ethics

What is ethics?• Ethics, also known as moral philosophy, seeks to

address questions of morality: right vs. wrong, good vs. bad, etc.

• Seeks to answer questions such as:• What is the Good?• What ought we to do?• Are there absolute moral values, or are said moral values

relative?• We will be looking at several different

philosophical approaches to answering these questions: egoism, hedonism, utilitarianism, and Kant’s deontic ethic

Page 3: Unit 4   Utilitarian Ethics

Consequentialism vs. Non-Consequentialism

• Two types of ethics: consequentialist and non-consequentialist

• Consequentialism says that no act is good or bad in and of itself, rather it is good or bad only in terms of its consequences

• A non-consequentialist theory asserts that the empirical consequences of any given act have nothing to do with the moral worth of the act

» In other words, actions are right or wrong in and of themselves, not because of any consequences that may result from it

• Utilitarianism is consequentialist in nature, while Kant’s ethic is non-consequentialist

Page 4: Unit 4   Utilitarian Ethics

Utilitarianism• Utilitarianism is a theory of moral philosophy that

is based on the principle that an action is morally right if it produces a greater quantity of good or happiness than any other possible action

• It requires us to look at the consequences to determine the morality of an action and claim that the morality of the action depends on the amount of “goodness” that the action produces. In the case of both Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill, good = pleasure

• All utilitarianism involves a moral calculus as follows:

(Amount of Good Produced) – (Amount of Evil Produced) = “Utility” of the Act

Page 5: Unit 4   Utilitarian Ethics

Jeremy Bentham’s Utilitarianism

• Father of Utilitarianism• Later criticized by his

wayward disciple, John Stuart Mill

• Similar to Hedonism, as both center on pleasure as the good

• However, Greek Hedonism is essentially egoist in nature; while Utilitarianism is social in nature

Page 6: Unit 4   Utilitarian Ethics

Bentham’s Calculus of Felicity

• Like Hobbes, Bentham assumes that we humans are all governed by the desire for pleasure and the aversion to pain. He seeks to give advice on how one should pursue the goal of pleasure.

• However unlike Hobbes, he did not rule out the possibility of altruism

• His advice on pursuing pleasure is called the Calculus of Felicity, made up of seven categories intended to provide a rational analysis of pleasure. Whenever one considers performing any action one can analyze its value in terms of the Calculus of Felicity and contrast it with alternatives

Page 7: Unit 4   Utilitarian Ethics

Bentham’s Calculus of Felicity• Bentham claims that there are seven categories

to examine when utilizing the Calculus of Felicity:1. Intensity: How intense is the pleasure?2. Duration: How long does it last?3. Certainty: How sure is the pleasure?4. Propinquity: How soon will it occur?5. Fecundity: How many more?6. Purity: How free from pain is the pleasure?7. Extent: How many people are affected?

» Note: It is this category that makes utilitarianism a form of social hedonism. One must consider the pleasures and pains of other people. This is what allows for the possibility of altruism in utilitarianism.

Page 8: Unit 4   Utilitarian Ethics

Bentham’s Calculus of Felicity• Bentham believed that his Calculus of Felicity was actually

the schematization of something we do semiconsciously anyway

• The 7th category allows for altruism: if an act will bring a great amount of happiness to a great number of people, then I should perform it, regardless of whether or not it brings misery to me.

• In fact, there is even a democratic bias built into it. When it comes to evaluating acts, Bentham subscribes to the “one person, one vote” principle

• To quote Bentham, “Prejudice apart, the game of push-pin is of equal value with the arts and sciences of music and poetry. If the game of push-pin furnishes more pleasure, it is more valuable than either.”

Page 9: Unit 4   Utilitarian Ethics

John Stuart Mill’s Utilitarianism• Wayward disciple of

Bentham• Concerned that a

utilitarian might actually conclude that a game of push-pin really was better than poetry

• He sought to rewrite utilitarianism in such a way that he would be able to demonstrate that Shakespeare outranked push-pin

Page 10: Unit 4   Utilitarian Ethics

J. S. Mill’s Utilitarianism

• Part of the problem, according to Mill, is the Calculus generates a purely quantitative analysis, and pays no attention to the “quality” of the pleasure

• Mill feared that over time, the Calculus of Felicity would gradually erode culture, leaving behind a society of belching, beer-swilling Nascar enthusiasts

• In order to combat this “lowering” of culture, Mill differentiated between “lower desires” and “higher desires”

• Lower desires (food, sleep, etc.) may be dealt with using the Calculus

• Higher desires, on the other hand, may only be discussed in terms of quality – which Mill claimed no calculus could evaluate

Page 11: Unit 4   Utilitarian Ethics

Is Mill’s Utilitarianism Elitist?

• Unlike Bentham’s utilitarianism, which was democratic in nature, Mill’s version is quite oligarchical (elitist; ruled by the few)

• Mill has famously stated, “The uncultivated cannot be competent judges of the cultivated.”

• If one must demonstrate “competence” before one is granted a vote, many issues would only allow a small minority the right to voice an opinion

• Another problem? How does one define “quality?” Can we even come to a universally-agreed upon schema to determine what ranks as a “lower desire” and what is considered a “higher desire?”

Page 12: Unit 4   Utilitarian Ethics

Criticism of Utilitarianism – The Case of Sam

“Sam, a basically normal, rather nondescript but ‘nice’ human being, goes to the hospital to visit his only living relative, his senile, sick aunt. His visit coincides with five medical emergencies at the hospital. One person needs a liver transplant, another a spleen transplant, another a lung transplant, another a new heart, and a fifth a new pineal gland. Each of the five patients is a tremendously important, much-loved person whose death would bring a great deal of grief and actual physical discomfort to a great number of people. Sam’s death, on the other hand, would be mourned by no one (except possibly his aunt in her lucid moments). The top members of the hospital administration, all strict utilitarians, lure Sam into an operating room, remove all his vital organs, and distribute them to the other needy patients, thereby operating (literally) in accordance with the principle of utility: the greatest amount of happiness for the greatest number of people.” Donald Palmer, Does the Center Hold, pg. 270-71

Page 13: Unit 4   Utilitarian Ethics

Criticism, cont’d…

• Utilitarianism doesn’t seem so appealing now, does it?

• The reason this example is so disquieting is that it appears to go against our intuitive sense of justice

• However, since this example is clearly compatible with utilitarianism, either something is wrong with our intuitive sense of justice or something is wrong with utilitarianism.• Which do you think it is?

Page 14: Unit 4   Utilitarian Ethics

Criticism, cont’d…

• Many contemporary utilitarians recognize this problem, and have created a distinction between “act utilitarianism” and “rule utilitarianism”

• Act utilitarianism is the traditional form. It necessitates that one perform the specific act that will produce the greatest amount of happiness for the greatest number of people. In other words, the Calculus of Felicity is utilized to discover what specific acts should be done

Page 15: Unit 4   Utilitarian Ethics

Criticism, cont’d…

• Rule utilitarianism argues that the Calculus of Felicity should be utilized to determine the rules that, if followed would produce the greatest good for the greatest number

• Even if a particular self-serving lie may go undetected (and therefore causes no one unhappiness), it is nevertheless not appropriate because lying and deceiving in general cause more unhappiness than happiness• Utilitarians believe that this distinction answers the

Case of Sam