understanding ``consensus' - the jouini-napp model of ...markus/teaching/eco525/21...n...

136
Introduction and motivation Model and proofs Understanding “Consensus" The Jouini-Napp Model of Belief Aggregation Markus Brunnermeier E. Glen Weyl Department of Economics Princeton University Financial Economics I Fall 2006 Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Upload: others

Post on 04-Oct-2020

0 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

Understanding “Consensus"The Jouini-Napp Model of Belief Aggregation

Markus Brunnermeier E. Glen Weyl

Department of EconomicsPrinceton University

Financial Economics IFall 2006

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 2: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Why study belief aggregation?

Market prices embed consensus set of beliefs amonginvestors?What information do we need to extract beliefs?Standard model assumes“market consensus". What islost?What happens if we us standard model to understandworld with heterogeneous beliefs?False beliefs, pessimism and first-order risk-aversion

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 3: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Why study belief aggregation?

Market prices embed consensus set of beliefs amonginvestors?What information do we need to extract beliefs?Standard model assumes“market consensus". What islost?What happens if we us standard model to understandworld with heterogeneous beliefs?False beliefs, pessimism and first-order risk-aversion

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 4: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Why study belief aggregation?

Market prices embed consensus set of beliefs amonginvestors?What information do we need to extract beliefs?Standard model assumes“market consensus". What islost?What happens if we us standard model to understandworld with heterogeneous beliefs?False beliefs, pessimism and first-order risk-aversion

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 5: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Why study belief aggregation?

Market prices embed consensus set of beliefs amonginvestors?What information do we need to extract beliefs?Standard model assumes“market consensus". What islost?What happens if we us standard model to understandworld with heterogeneous beliefs?False beliefs, pessimism and first-order risk-aversion

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 6: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Why study belief aggregation?

Market prices embed consensus set of beliefs amonginvestors?What information do we need to extract beliefs?Standard model assumes“market consensus". What islost?What happens if we us standard model to understandworld with heterogeneous beliefs?False beliefs, pessimism and first-order risk-aversion

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 7: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

A simple example of belief aggregation

Two-periods, two states of the world ωgood and ωbad in thesecond period.

N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e−wθi , θi is

individual i ’s constant absolute risk-tolerance), nodiscounting.Complete markets (two securities, each paying off 1 unit ofconsumption in each state).Investors have different beliefs; investor i believes the goodstate happens with probability πi 6= πj .Both investors endowed with 2 in the good state, 1 in thebad state and 1.5 today.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 8: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

A simple example of belief aggregation

Two-periods, two states of the world ωgood and ωbad in thesecond period.

N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e−wθi , θi is

individual i ’s constant absolute risk-tolerance), nodiscounting.Complete markets (two securities, each paying off 1 unit ofconsumption in each state).Investors have different beliefs; investor i believes the goodstate happens with probability πi 6= πj .Both investors endowed with 2 in the good state, 1 in thebad state and 1.5 today.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 9: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

A simple example of belief aggregation

Two-periods, two states of the world ωgood and ωbad in thesecond period.

N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e−wθi , θi is

individual i ’s constant absolute risk-tolerance), nodiscounting.Complete markets (two securities, each paying off 1 unit ofconsumption in each state).Investors have different beliefs; investor i believes the goodstate happens with probability πi 6= πj .Both investors endowed with 2 in the good state, 1 in thebad state and 1.5 today.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 10: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

A simple example of belief aggregation

Two-periods, two states of the world ωgood and ωbad in thesecond period.

N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e−wθi , θi is

individual i ’s constant absolute risk-tolerance), nodiscounting.Complete markets (two securities, each paying off 1 unit ofconsumption in each state).Investors have different beliefs; investor i believes the goodstate happens with probability πi 6= πj .Both investors endowed with 2 in the good state, 1 in thebad state and 1.5 today.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 11: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

A simple example of belief aggregation

Two-periods, two states of the world ωgood and ωbad in thesecond period.

N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e−wθi , θi is

individual i ’s constant absolute risk-tolerance), nodiscounting.Complete markets (two securities, each paying off 1 unit ofconsumption in each state).Investors have different beliefs; investor i believes the goodstate happens with probability πi 6= πj .Both investors endowed with 2 in the good state, 1 in thebad state and 1.5 today.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 12: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Solution concept

Solve for equivalent common belief equilibrium (ECBE). ECBEmeans:

1 Investors have a common set of beliefs, as in standardmodel.

2 All prices (i.e. investor marginal valuations andbehavior)same as in the original equilibrium.

3 Trading is the same.4 Aggregate, but not individual, endowment the same.

Heterogeneous beliefs =⇒ heterogeneous endowments.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 13: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Solution concept

Solve for equivalent common belief equilibrium (ECBE). ECBEmeans:

1 Investors have a common set of beliefs, as in standardmodel.

2 All prices (i.e. investor marginal valuations andbehavior)same as in the original equilibrium.

3 Trading is the same.4 Aggregate, but not individual, endowment the same.

Heterogeneous beliefs =⇒ heterogeneous endowments.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 14: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Solution concept

Solve for equivalent common belief equilibrium (ECBE). ECBEmeans:

1 Investors have a common set of beliefs, as in standardmodel.

2 All prices (i.e. investor marginal valuations andbehavior)same as in the original equilibrium.

3 Trading is the same.4 Aggregate, but not individual, endowment the same.

Heterogeneous beliefs =⇒ heterogeneous endowments.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 15: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Solution concept

Solve for equivalent common belief equilibrium (ECBE). ECBEmeans:

1 Investors have a common set of beliefs, as in standardmodel.

2 All prices (i.e. investor marginal valuations andbehavior)same as in the original equilibrium.

3 Trading is the same.4 Aggregate, but not individual, endowment the same.

Heterogeneous beliefs =⇒ heterogeneous endowments.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 16: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Solution concept

Solve for equivalent common belief equilibrium (ECBE). ECBEmeans:

1 Investors have a common set of beliefs, as in standardmodel.

2 All prices (i.e. investor marginal valuations andbehavior)same as in the original equilibrium.

3 Trading is the same.4 Aggregate, but not individual, endowment the same.

Heterogeneous beliefs =⇒ heterogeneous endowments.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 17: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Solution concept

Solve for equivalent common belief equilibrium (ECBE). ECBEmeans:

1 Investors have a common set of beliefs, as in standardmodel.

2 All prices (i.e. investor marginal valuations andbehavior)same as in the original equilibrium.

3 Trading is the same.4 Aggregate, but not individual, endowment the same.

Heterogeneous beliefs =⇒ heterogeneous endowments.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 18: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

The old way to solve

We could solve by brute force:Solve the consumers’ optimization problem given anyprices.Find the prices that clear the market.Find a probability measure leading to a ECBE.Adjust individual endowments to match the equilibrium

BUT tedious! Instead, we use a quicker and simpler method.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 19: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

The old way to solve

We could solve by brute force:Solve the consumers’ optimization problem given anyprices.Find the prices that clear the market.Find a probability measure leading to a ECBE.Adjust individual endowments to match the equilibrium

BUT tedious! Instead, we use a quicker and simpler method.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 20: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

The old way to solve

We could solve by brute force:Solve the consumers’ optimization problem given anyprices.Find the prices that clear the market.Find a probability measure leading to a ECBE.Adjust individual endowments to match the equilibrium

BUT tedious! Instead, we use a quicker and simpler method.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 21: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

The old way to solve

We could solve by brute force:Solve the consumers’ optimization problem given anyprices.Find the prices that clear the market.Find a probability measure leading to a ECBE.Adjust individual endowments to match the equilibrium

BUT tedious! Instead, we use a quicker and simpler method.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 22: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

The old way to solve

We could solve by brute force:Solve the consumers’ optimization problem given anyprices.Find the prices that clear the market.Find a probability measure leading to a ECBE.Adjust individual endowments to match the equilibrium

BUT tedious! Instead, we use a quicker and simpler method.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 23: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

The old way to solve

We could solve by brute force:Solve the consumers’ optimization problem given anyprices.Find the prices that clear the market.Find a probability measure leading to a ECBE.Adjust individual endowments to match the equilibrium

BUT tedious! Instead, we use a quicker and simpler method.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 24: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

An easier way

Directly use condition of consistent marginal valuations.

Let y ji be the wealth that i buys in state j in the original

equilibrium.Let y j

i be the wealth she buys in the ECBE.Also, let π represent the common belief of the probability ofthe good state.

=⇒

∀i : πiu′i

(ygood

i

)= πu′

i

(ygood

i

)∀i : (1− πi)u′

i

(ybad

i

)= (1− π)u′

i

(ybad

i

)

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 25: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

An easier way

Directly use condition of consistent marginal valuations.

Let y ji be the wealth that i buys in state j in the original

equilibrium.Let y j

i be the wealth she buys in the ECBE.Also, let π represent the common belief of the probability ofthe good state.

=⇒

∀i : πiu′i

(ygood

i

)= πu′

i

(ygood

i

)∀i : (1− πi)u′

i

(ybad

i

)= (1− π)u′

i

(ybad

i

)

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 26: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

An easier way

Directly use condition of consistent marginal valuations.

Let y ji be the wealth that i buys in state j in the original

equilibrium.Let y j

i be the wealth she buys in the ECBE.Also, let π represent the common belief of the probability ofthe good state.

=⇒

∀i : πiu′i

(ygood

i

)= πu′

i

(ygood

i

)∀i : (1− πi)u′

i

(ybad

i

)= (1− π)u′

i

(ybad

i

)

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 27: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

An easier way

Directly use condition of consistent marginal valuations.

Let y ji be the wealth that i buys in state j in the original

equilibrium.Let y j

i be the wealth she buys in the ECBE.Also, let π represent the common belief of the probability ofthe good state.

=⇒

∀i : πiu′i

(ygood

i

)= πu′

i

(ygood

i

)∀i : (1− πi)u′

i

(ybad

i

)= (1− π)u′

i

(ybad

i

)

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 28: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

An easier way

Directly use condition of consistent marginal valuations.

Let y ji be the wealth that i buys in state j in the original

equilibrium.Let y j

i be the wealth she buys in the ECBE.Also, let π represent the common belief of the probability ofthe good state.

=⇒

∀i : πiu′i

(ygood

i

)= πu′

i

(ygood

i

)∀i : (1− πi)u′

i

(ybad

i

)= (1− π)u′

i

(ybad

i

)

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 29: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

An easier way

Directly use condition of consistent marginal valuations.

Let y ji be the wealth that i buys in state j in the original

equilibrium.Let y j

i be the wealth she buys in the ECBE.Also, let π represent the common belief of the probability ofthe good state.

=⇒

∀i : πiu′i

(ygood

i

)= πu′

i

(ygood

i

)∀i : (1− πi)u′

i

(ybad

i

)= (1− π)u′

i

(ybad

i

)

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 30: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Solving

By simple differentiation we have that u′i (x) = e

− xθi

θi. Property 4

=⇒ aggregate endowment the same. We exploit this:Define θ ≡

∑i θi .

We raise the equations for individual i to the power θiθ

toput the argument of their marginal utility in “commoncurrency". We obtain:

∀i , πθiθ

i e−ygoodi

θ = πθiθ e−

ygoodiθ

Corresponding equation for bad state.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 31: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Solving

By simple differentiation we have that u′i (x) = e

− xθi

θi. Property 4

=⇒ aggregate endowment the same. We exploit this:Define θ ≡

∑i θi .

We raise the equations for individual i to the power θiθ

toput the argument of their marginal utility in “commoncurrency". We obtain:

∀i , πθiθ

i e−ygoodi

θ = πθiθ e−

ygoodiθ

Corresponding equation for bad state.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 32: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Solving

By simple differentiation we have that u′i (x) = e

− xθi

θi. Property 4

=⇒ aggregate endowment the same. We exploit this:Define θ ≡

∑i θi .

We raise the equations for individual i to the power θiθ

toput the argument of their marginal utility in “commoncurrency". We obtain:

∀i , πθiθ

i e−ygoodi

θ = πθiθ e−

ygoodiθ

Corresponding equation for bad state.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 33: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Solving continued...

Multiplying:

πθ1θ

1 πθ2θ

2 e−ygood1 +ygood

2θ = πe−

ygood1 +ygood

But aggregate endowments the same:

π =∏

i πθiθ

i

A corresponding formula 1− π =∏

i(1− πi)θiθ applies to the

bad state.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 34: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Solving continued...

Multiplying:

πθ1θ

1 πθ2θ

2 e−ygood1 +ygood

2θ = πe−

ygood1 +ygood

But aggregate endowments the same:

π =∏

i πθiθ

i

A corresponding formula 1− π =∏

i(1− πi)θiθ applies to the

bad state.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 35: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Solving continued...

Multiplying:

πθ1θ

1 πθ2θ

2 e−ygood1 +ygood

2θ = πe−

ygood1 +ygood

But aggregate endowments the same:

π =∏

i πθiθ

i

A corresponding formula 1− π =∏

i(1− πi)θiθ applies to the

bad state.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 36: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Solving continued...

Multiplying:

πθ1θ

1 πθ2θ

2 e−ygood1 +ygood

2θ = πe−

ygood1 +ygood

But aggregate endowments the same:

π =∏

i πθiθ

i

A corresponding formula 1− π =∏

i(1− πi)θiθ applies to the

bad state.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 37: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Interpreting the solution

Note:pi is not a probability measure. Suppose that there are justtwo investors, θ1 = θ2 = 1 and π1 = 1− π2 = .9. Thenpi = 1− pi = .18 .5. Not clear how we should interpretthese “common beliefs".Effect on common belief proportional to fraction of totalrisk-bearing; those willing to bet more on their beliefsshape market beliefs more.Common belief is weighted geometric mean of theindividual beliefs.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 38: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Interpreting the solution

Note:pi is not a probability measure. Suppose that there are justtwo investors, θ1 = θ2 = 1 and π1 = 1− π2 = .9. Thenpi = 1− pi = .18 .5. Not clear how we should interpretthese “common beliefs".Effect on common belief proportional to fraction of totalrisk-bearing; those willing to bet more on their beliefsshape market beliefs more.Common belief is weighted geometric mean of theindividual beliefs.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 39: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Interpreting the solution

Note:pi is not a probability measure. Suppose that there are justtwo investors, θ1 = θ2 = 1 and π1 = 1− π2 = .9. Thenpi = 1− pi = .18 .5. Not clear how we should interpretthese “common beliefs".Effect on common belief proportional to fraction of totalrisk-bearing; those willing to bet more on their beliefsshape market beliefs more.Common belief is weighted geometric mean of theindividual beliefs.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 40: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Interpreting the solution

Note:pi is not a probability measure. Suppose that there are justtwo investors, θ1 = θ2 = 1 and π1 = 1− π2 = .9. Thenpi = 1− pi = .18 .5. Not clear how we should interpretthese “common beliefs".Effect on common belief proportional to fraction of totalrisk-bearing; those willing to bet more on their beliefsshape market beliefs more.Common belief is weighted geometric mean of theindividual beliefs.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 41: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

What about endowments?

We can also determine how endowments differ in the ECBE:

πie−

ygoodiθi =

∏j

π

θjθ

j e−ygood

iθi

Taking the logarithm, arithmetic yield:

ygoodi − ygood

i = θi∑j 6=i

θj

θ

[log(πj)− log(πi)

]Property 3, =⇒ :

ei − ei = θi∑

j 6=iθj

θ

[log(πj)− log(πi)

]= θi

[log(π)− log(πi)

]Thus, heterogeneous beliefs =⇒ heterogeneousendowments.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 42: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

What about endowments?

We can also determine how endowments differ in the ECBE:

πie−

ygoodiθi =

∏j

π

θjθ

j e−ygood

iθi

Taking the logarithm, arithmetic yield:

ygoodi − ygood

i = θi∑j 6=i

θj

θ

[log(πj)− log(πi)

]Property 3, =⇒ :

ei − ei = θi∑

j 6=iθj

θ

[log(πj)− log(πi)

]= θi

[log(π)− log(πi)

]Thus, heterogeneous beliefs =⇒ heterogeneousendowments.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 43: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

What about endowments?

We can also determine how endowments differ in the ECBE:

πie−

ygoodiθi =

∏j

π

θjθ

j e−ygood

iθi

Taking the logarithm, arithmetic yield:

ygoodi − ygood

i = θi∑j 6=i

θj

θ

[log(πj)− log(πi)

]Property 3, =⇒ :

ei − ei = θi∑

j 6=iθj

θ

[log(πj)− log(πi)

]= θi

[log(π)− log(πi)

]Thus, heterogeneous beliefs =⇒ heterogeneousendowments.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 44: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

What about endowments?

We can also determine how endowments differ in the ECBE:

πie−

ygoodiθi =

∏j

π

θjθ

j e−ygood

iθi

Taking the logarithm, arithmetic yield:

ygoodi − ygood

i = θi∑j 6=i

θj

θ

[log(πj)− log(πi)

]Property 3, =⇒ :

ei − ei = θi∑

j 6=iθj

θ

[log(πj)− log(πi)

]= θi

[log(π)− log(πi)

]Thus, heterogeneous beliefs =⇒ heterogeneousendowments.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 45: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

What about endowments?

We can also determine how endowments differ in the ECBE:

πie−

ygoodiθi =

∏j

π

θjθ

j e−ygood

iθi

Taking the logarithm, arithmetic yield:

ygoodi − ygood

i = θi∑j 6=i

θj

θ

[log(πj)− log(πi)

]Property 3, =⇒ :

ei − ei = θi∑

j 6=iθj

θ

[log(πj)− log(πi)

]= θi

[log(π)− log(πi)

]Thus, heterogeneous beliefs =⇒ heterogeneousendowments.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 46: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

What about endowments?

We can also determine how endowments differ in the ECBE:

πie−

ygoodiθi =

∏j

π

θjθ

j e−ygood

iθi

Taking the logarithm, arithmetic yield:

ygoodi − ygood

i = θi∑j 6=i

θj

θ

[log(πj)− log(πi)

]Property 3, =⇒ :

ei − ei = θi∑

j 6=iθj

θ

[log(πj)− log(πi)

]= θi

[log(π)− log(πi)

]Thus, heterogeneous beliefs =⇒ heterogeneousendowments.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 47: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Interpreting endowment shift

Change in belief proportional to: difference fromconsensus and risk-tolerance.If individual has higher probability on a state than thecommon belief, she tends to trade towards this state.Rationalized by individual having a lower endowment inthis state(hedging an idiosyncratic risk).Thus standard model will interpret trading due toheterogeneous beliefs as resulting from idiosyncratic risks.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 48: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Interpreting endowment shift

Change in belief proportional to: difference fromconsensus and risk-tolerance.If individual has higher probability on a state than thecommon belief, she tends to trade towards this state.Rationalized by individual having a lower endowment inthis state(hedging an idiosyncratic risk).Thus standard model will interpret trading due toheterogeneous beliefs as resulting from idiosyncratic risks.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 49: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Interpreting endowment shift

Change in belief proportional to: difference fromconsensus and risk-tolerance.If individual has higher probability on a state than thecommon belief, she tends to trade towards this state.Rationalized by individual having a lower endowment inthis state(hedging an idiosyncratic risk).Thus standard model will interpret trading due toheterogeneous beliefs as resulting from idiosyncratic risks.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 50: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Interpreting endowment shift

Change in belief proportional to: difference fromconsensus and risk-tolerance.If individual has higher probability on a state than thecommon belief, she tends to trade towards this state.Rationalized by individual having a lower endowment inthis state(hedging an idiosyncratic risk).Thus standard model will interpret trading due toheterogeneous beliefs as resulting from idiosyncratic risks.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 51: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Endowments continued...

Adjustment also proportional to risk tolerance.Those with large risk tolerance will bet a lot on beliefs:large endowment adjustment necessary to rationalizeStandard model: risk-tolerant person with idiosyncraticbeliefs trading because of large idiosyncratic risks

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 52: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Endowments continued...

Adjustment also proportional to risk tolerance.Those with large risk tolerance will bet a lot on beliefs:large endowment adjustment necessary to rationalizeStandard model: risk-tolerant person with idiosyncraticbeliefs trading because of large idiosyncratic risks

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 53: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Endowments continued...

Adjustment also proportional to risk tolerance.Those with large risk tolerance will bet a lot on beliefs:large endowment adjustment necessary to rationalizeStandard model: risk-tolerant person with idiosyncraticbeliefs trading because of large idiosyncratic risks

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 54: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

A motivating example of pessimism

Can beliefs generate first-order risk-aversion?Would you consider risk-averse someone who was afraid to fly?This cannot be (economic) “risk-aversion"

If arrives earns uIf he drives he earns disutility from inconvenience vIf he crashes he earns utility 0Two people, both with the same inconvenience from notflying and value to flying but one chooses not to fly, whilethe other chooses to fly.Is this plausible? It seems to happen a lot.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 55: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

A motivating example of pessimism

Can beliefs generate first-order risk-aversion?Would you consider risk-averse someone who was afraid to fly?This cannot be (economic) “risk-aversion"

If arrives earns uIf he drives he earns disutility from inconvenience vIf he crashes he earns utility 0Two people, both with the same inconvenience from notflying and value to flying but one chooses not to fly, whilethe other chooses to fly.Is this plausible? It seems to happen a lot.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 56: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

A motivating example of pessimism

Can beliefs generate first-order risk-aversion?Would you consider risk-averse someone who was afraid to fly?This cannot be (economic) “risk-aversion"

If arrives earns uIf he drives he earns disutility from inconvenience vIf he crashes he earns utility 0Two people, both with the same inconvenience from notflying and value to flying but one chooses not to fly, whilethe other chooses to fly.Is this plausible? It seems to happen a lot.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 57: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

A motivating example of pessimism

Can beliefs generate first-order risk-aversion?Would you consider risk-averse someone who was afraid to fly?This cannot be (economic) “risk-aversion"

If arrives earns uIf he drives he earns disutility from inconvenience vIf he crashes he earns utility 0Two people, both with the same inconvenience from notflying and value to flying but one chooses not to fly, whilethe other chooses to fly.Is this plausible? It seems to happen a lot.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 58: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

A motivating example of pessimism

Can beliefs generate first-order risk-aversion?Would you consider risk-averse someone who was afraid to fly?This cannot be (economic) “risk-aversion"

If arrives earns uIf he drives he earns disutility from inconvenience vIf he crashes he earns utility 0Two people, both with the same inconvenience from notflying and value to flying but one chooses not to fly, whilethe other chooses to fly.Is this plausible? It seems to happen a lot.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 59: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

A motivating example of pessimism

Can beliefs generate first-order risk-aversion?Would you consider risk-averse someone who was afraid to fly?This cannot be (economic) “risk-aversion"

If arrives earns uIf he drives he earns disutility from inconvenience vIf he crashes he earns utility 0Two people, both with the same inconvenience from notflying and value to flying but one chooses not to fly, whilethe other chooses to fly.Is this plausible? It seems to happen a lot.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 60: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

A motivating example of pessimism

Can beliefs generate first-order risk-aversion?Would you consider risk-averse someone who was afraid to fly?This cannot be (economic) “risk-aversion"

If arrives earns uIf he drives he earns disutility from inconvenience vIf he crashes he earns utility 0Two people, both with the same inconvenience from notflying and value to flying but one chooses not to fly, whilethe other chooses to fly.Is this plausible? It seems to happen a lot.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 61: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

A motivating example of pessimism

Can beliefs generate first-order risk-aversion?Would you consider risk-averse someone who was afraid to fly?This cannot be (economic) “risk-aversion"

If arrives earns uIf he drives he earns disutility from inconvenience vIf he crashes he earns utility 0Two people, both with the same inconvenience from notflying and value to flying but one chooses not to fly, whilethe other chooses to fly.Is this plausible? It seems to happen a lot.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 62: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Pessimism example explained

Risk-aversion is a property of utility functions.Parameters equal between the two, economic risk-aversioncannot do it. What is?First individual thinks that crashing is more likely, assigningprobability q, second assigns p < qThen if qu − v > 0, but pu − v < 0 the “risk-averse"individual chooses not to fly, but the “risk-seeking"individual chooses to fly.Thus “risk-aversion" in standard parlance is about beliefs,not utility. It is a sort of pessimism.“Luck is out to get me" or “nothing ever goes my way."Can we incorporate into finance?

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 63: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Pessimism example explained

Risk-aversion is a property of utility functions.Parameters equal between the two, economic risk-aversioncannot do it. What is?First individual thinks that crashing is more likely, assigningprobability q, second assigns p < qThen if qu − v > 0, but pu − v < 0 the “risk-averse"individual chooses not to fly, but the “risk-seeking"individual chooses to fly.Thus “risk-aversion" in standard parlance is about beliefs,not utility. It is a sort of pessimism.“Luck is out to get me" or “nothing ever goes my way."Can we incorporate into finance?

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 64: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Pessimism example explained

Risk-aversion is a property of utility functions.Parameters equal between the two, economic risk-aversioncannot do it. What is?First individual thinks that crashing is more likely, assigningprobability q, second assigns p < qThen if qu − v > 0, but pu − v < 0 the “risk-averse"individual chooses not to fly, but the “risk-seeking"individual chooses to fly.Thus “risk-aversion" in standard parlance is about beliefs,not utility. It is a sort of pessimism.“Luck is out to get me" or “nothing ever goes my way."Can we incorporate into finance?

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 65: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Pessimism example explained

Risk-aversion is a property of utility functions.Parameters equal between the two, economic risk-aversioncannot do it. What is?First individual thinks that crashing is more likely, assigningprobability q, second assigns p < qThen if qu − v > 0, but pu − v < 0 the “risk-averse"individual chooses not to fly, but the “risk-seeking"individual chooses to fly.Thus “risk-aversion" in standard parlance is about beliefs,not utility. It is a sort of pessimism.“Luck is out to get me" or “nothing ever goes my way."Can we incorporate into finance?

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 66: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Pessimism example explained

Risk-aversion is a property of utility functions.Parameters equal between the two, economic risk-aversioncannot do it. What is?First individual thinks that crashing is more likely, assigningprobability q, second assigns p < qThen if qu − v > 0, but pu − v < 0 the “risk-averse"individual chooses not to fly, but the “risk-seeking"individual chooses to fly.Thus “risk-aversion" in standard parlance is about beliefs,not utility. It is a sort of pessimism.“Luck is out to get me" or “nothing ever goes my way."Can we incorporate into finance?

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 67: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Pessimism example explained

Risk-aversion is a property of utility functions.Parameters equal between the two, economic risk-aversioncannot do it. What is?First individual thinks that crashing is more likely, assigningprobability q, second assigns p < qThen if qu − v > 0, but pu − v < 0 the “risk-averse"individual chooses not to fly, but the “risk-seeking"individual chooses to fly.Thus “risk-aversion" in standard parlance is about beliefs,not utility. It is a sort of pessimism.“Luck is out to get me" or “nothing ever goes my way."Can we incorporate into finance?

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 68: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Pessimism example explained

Risk-aversion is a property of utility functions.Parameters equal between the two, economic risk-aversioncannot do it. What is?First individual thinks that crashing is more likely, assigningprobability q, second assigns p < qThen if qu − v > 0, but pu − v < 0 the “risk-averse"individual chooses not to fly, but the “risk-seeking"individual chooses to fly.Thus “risk-aversion" in standard parlance is about beliefs,not utility. It is a sort of pessimism.“Luck is out to get me" or “nothing ever goes my way."Can we incorporate into finance?

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 69: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Pessimism in the model

A try:Suppose objective probability π? of the good stateoccurring.Individual i “first-order pessimistic" if πi < π?. Thisdefinition quite obvious here, but more general later.Does pessimism affect the risk-free rate in the same wayas risk-aversion? Market price of risk?

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 70: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Pessimism in the model

A try:Suppose objective probability π? of the good stateoccurring.Individual i “first-order pessimistic" if πi < π?. Thisdefinition quite obvious here, but more general later.Does pessimism affect the risk-free rate in the same wayas risk-aversion? Market price of risk?

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 71: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Pessimism in the model

A try:Suppose objective probability π? of the good stateoccurring.Individual i “first-order pessimistic" if πi < π?. Thisdefinition quite obvious here, but more general later.Does pessimism affect the risk-free rate in the same wayas risk-aversion? Market price of risk?

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 72: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Pessimism in the model

A try:Suppose objective probability π? of the good stateoccurring.Individual i “first-order pessimistic" if πi < π?. Thisdefinition quite obvious here, but more general later.Does pessimism affect the risk-free rate in the same wayas risk-aversion? Market price of risk?

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 73: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Solving the model with pessimism

Sssume there only one investor.Risk-bearing capacity θ and belief about the probability ofthe good state π.

Marginal utility of consumption today is e−3

θ .

Expected marginal utility tomorrow is πe−2θ +(1−π)e−

θ .Thus the risk free rate:

πe−2θ +(1−π)e−

e−3

− 1

e−2θ < e−

1θ , so risk free rate is clearly decreasing in π.

If π < π? then the risk-free rate is higher than if beliefs arecorrect.Thus pessimism increases risk-free rate.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 74: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Solving the model with pessimism

Sssume there only one investor.Risk-bearing capacity θ and belief about the probability ofthe good state π.

Marginal utility of consumption today is e−3

θ .

Expected marginal utility tomorrow is πe−2θ +(1−π)e−

θ .Thus the risk free rate:

πe−2θ +(1−π)e−

e−3

− 1

e−2θ < e−

1θ , so risk free rate is clearly decreasing in π.

If π < π? then the risk-free rate is higher than if beliefs arecorrect.Thus pessimism increases risk-free rate.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 75: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Solving the model with pessimism

Sssume there only one investor.Risk-bearing capacity θ and belief about the probability ofthe good state π.

Marginal utility of consumption today is e−3

θ .

Expected marginal utility tomorrow is πe−2θ +(1−π)e−

θ .Thus the risk free rate:

πe−2θ +(1−π)e−

e−3

− 1

e−2θ < e−

1θ , so risk free rate is clearly decreasing in π.

If π < π? then the risk-free rate is higher than if beliefs arecorrect.Thus pessimism increases risk-free rate.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 76: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Solving the model with pessimism

Sssume there only one investor.Risk-bearing capacity θ and belief about the probability ofthe good state π.

Marginal utility of consumption today is e−3

θ .

Expected marginal utility tomorrow is πe−2θ +(1−π)e−

θ .Thus the risk free rate:

πe−2θ +(1−π)e−

e−3

− 1

e−2θ < e−

1θ , so risk free rate is clearly decreasing in π.

If π < π? then the risk-free rate is higher than if beliefs arecorrect.Thus pessimism increases risk-free rate.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 77: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Solving the model with pessimism

Sssume there only one investor.Risk-bearing capacity θ and belief about the probability ofthe good state π.

Marginal utility of consumption today is e−3

θ .

Expected marginal utility tomorrow is πe−2θ +(1−π)e−

θ .Thus the risk free rate:

πe−2θ +(1−π)e−

e−3

− 1

e−2θ < e−

1θ , so risk free rate is clearly decreasing in π.

If π < π? then the risk-free rate is higher than if beliefs arecorrect.Thus pessimism increases risk-free rate.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 78: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Solving the model with pessimism

Sssume there only one investor.Risk-bearing capacity θ and belief about the probability ofthe good state π.

Marginal utility of consumption today is e−3

θ .

Expected marginal utility tomorrow is πe−2θ +(1−π)e−

θ .Thus the risk free rate:

πe−2θ +(1−π)e−

e−3

− 1

e−2θ < e−

1θ , so risk free rate is clearly decreasing in π.

If π < π? then the risk-free rate is higher than if beliefs arecorrect.Thus pessimism increases risk-free rate.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 79: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Solving the model with pessimism

Sssume there only one investor.Risk-bearing capacity θ and belief about the probability ofthe good state π.

Marginal utility of consumption today is e−3

θ .

Expected marginal utility tomorrow is πe−2θ +(1−π)e−

θ .Thus the risk free rate:

πe−2θ +(1−π)e−

e−3

− 1

e−2θ < e−

1θ , so risk free rate is clearly decreasing in π.

If π < π? then the risk-free rate is higher than if beliefs arecorrect.Thus pessimism increases risk-free rate.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 80: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Solving the model with pessimism

Sssume there only one investor.Risk-bearing capacity θ and belief about the probability ofthe good state π.

Marginal utility of consumption today is e−3

θ .

Expected marginal utility tomorrow is πe−2θ +(1−π)e−

θ .Thus the risk free rate:

πe−2θ +(1−π)e−

e−3

− 1

e−2θ < e−

1θ , so risk free rate is clearly decreasing in π.

If π < π? then the risk-free rate is higher than if beliefs arecorrect.Thus pessimism increases risk-free rate.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 81: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Solving the model with pessimism

Sssume there only one investor.Risk-bearing capacity θ and belief about the probability ofthe good state π.

Marginal utility of consumption today is e−3

θ .

Expected marginal utility tomorrow is πe−2θ +(1−π)e−

θ .Thus the risk free rate:

πe−2θ +(1−π)e−

e−3

− 1

e−2θ < e−

1θ , so risk free rate is clearly decreasing in π.

If π < π? then the risk-free rate is higher than if beliefs arecorrect.Thus pessimism increases risk-free rate.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 82: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

More on pessimism

What effect does pessimism have on the pricing kernel underobjective measure? The value (objective) value of the pricingkernel in the good state is:

πe−2θ

π?e−3

And in the bad state:

(1− π)e−1θ

(1− π?)e−3

Kernel in good state increasing in π.Kernel in bad state is decreasing.Pessimism decreases the kernel in the good state,increases it in the bad state.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 83: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

More on pessimism

What effect does pessimism have on the pricing kernel underobjective measure? The value (objective) value of the pricingkernel in the good state is:

πe−2θ

π?e−3

And in the bad state:

(1− π)e−1θ

(1− π?)e−3

Kernel in good state increasing in π.Kernel in bad state is decreasing.Pessimism decreases the kernel in the good state,increases it in the bad state.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 84: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

More on pessimism

What effect does pessimism have on the pricing kernel underobjective measure? The value (objective) value of the pricingkernel in the good state is:

πe−2θ

π?e−3

And in the bad state:

(1− π)e−1θ

(1− π?)e−3

Kernel in good state increasing in π.Kernel in bad state is decreasing.Pessimism decreases the kernel in the good state,increases it in the bad state.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 85: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

More on pessimism

What effect does pessimism have on the pricing kernel underobjective measure? The value (objective) value of the pricingkernel in the good state is:

πe−2θ

π?e−3

And in the bad state:

(1− π)e−1θ

(1− π?)e−3

Kernel in good state increasing in π.Kernel in bad state is decreasing.Pessimism decreases the kernel in the good state,increases it in the bad state.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 86: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

More on pessimism

What effect does pessimism have on the pricing kernel underobjective measure? The value (objective) value of the pricingkernel in the good state is:

πe−2θ

π?e−3

And in the bad state:

(1− π)e−1θ

(1− π?)e−3

Kernel in good state increasing in π.Kernel in bad state is decreasing.Pessimism decreases the kernel in the good state,increases it in the bad state.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 87: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

More on pessimism

What effect does pessimism have on the pricing kernel underobjective measure? The value (objective) value of the pricingkernel in the good state is:

πe−2θ

π?e−3

And in the bad state:

(1− π)e−1θ

(1− π?)e−3

Kernel in good state increasing in π.Kernel in bad state is decreasing.Pessimism decreases the kernel in the good state,increases it in the bad state.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 88: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

More on pessimism

What effect does pessimism have on the pricing kernel underobjective measure? The value (objective) value of the pricingkernel in the good state is:

πe−2θ

π?e−3

And in the bad state:

(1− π)e−1θ

(1− π?)e−3

Kernel in good state increasing in π.Kernel in bad state is decreasing.Pessimism decreases the kernel in the good state,increases it in the bad state.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 89: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Interpreting pessimism

Leads to a greater “separation" of the price kernel for thetwo states. This is an increase in the “risk-premium", Thus,similar effect on market prices to risk aversion.Optimism has opposite effect; in fact, enough optimism canlead the good state kernel to be higher than the low-statekernel, i.e. risk-seeking.Are there differences?

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 90: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Interpreting pessimism

Leads to a greater “separation" of the price kernel for thetwo states. This is an increase in the “risk-premium", Thus,similar effect on market prices to risk aversion.Optimism has opposite effect; in fact, enough optimism canlead the good state kernel to be higher than the low-statekernel, i.e. risk-seeking.Are there differences?

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 91: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Interpreting pessimism

Leads to a greater “separation" of the price kernel for thetwo states. This is an increase in the “risk-premium", Thus,similar effect on market prices to risk aversion.Optimism has opposite effect; in fact, enough optimism canlead the good state kernel to be higher than the low-statekernel, i.e. risk-seeking.Are there differences?

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 92: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

A problem with pessimism

Suppose two individualsEach has utility u(c) = log cIf coin comes up heads, first endowed with 18, second with2If tails, first endowed with 9, second with 1.Suppose fair coin. Person 1 knows this; person 2 isdrastically pessimistic: believes that probability is .9 thatcomes up tails.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 93: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

A problem with pessimism

Suppose two individualsEach has utility u(c) = log cIf coin comes up heads, first endowed with 18, second with2If tails, first endowed with 9, second with 1.Suppose fair coin. Person 1 knows this; person 2 isdrastically pessimistic: believes that probability is .9 thatcomes up tails.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 94: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

A problem with pessimism

Suppose two individualsEach has utility u(c) = log cIf coin comes up heads, first endowed with 18, second with2If tails, first endowed with 9, second with 1.Suppose fair coin. Person 1 knows this; person 2 isdrastically pessimistic: believes that probability is .9 thatcomes up tails.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 95: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

A problem with pessimism

Suppose two individualsEach has utility u(c) = log cIf coin comes up heads, first endowed with 18, second with2If tails, first endowed with 9, second with 1.Suppose fair coin. Person 1 knows this; person 2 isdrastically pessimistic: believes that probability is .9 thatcomes up tails.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 96: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Solving the problematic pessimism example

Normalize price of consumption in good state to 1.First individual spends 1

2 of his wealth on consumption ingood state; has 9

10 of total perfectly correlated wealth.

Second spends 110 and has 1

10 .Let w ≡ 20 + 10p2, where ptails is price of consumption inthe tails state.Market clearing implies

(9

20 + 1100

)w = 20.

w = 100023 = 20 + 10p2 =⇒ p2 = 54

23

Investor 2 buys c12 = 100

207 ≈12 and c2

2 = 53 = 10

3 c12 .

Investor 1 buys c11 = 450

23 ≈ 1912 and c2

1 = 612 > 3

10c11

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 97: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Solving the problematic pessimism example

Normalize price of consumption in good state to 1.First individual spends 1

2 of his wealth on consumption ingood state; has 9

10 of total perfectly correlated wealth.

Second spends 110 and has 1

10 .Let w ≡ 20 + 10p2, where ptails is price of consumption inthe tails state.Market clearing implies

(9

20 + 1100

)w = 20.

w = 100023 = 20 + 10p2 =⇒ p2 = 54

23

Investor 2 buys c12 = 100

207 ≈12 and c2

2 = 53 = 10

3 c12 .

Investor 1 buys c11 = 450

23 ≈ 1912 and c2

1 = 612 > 3

10c11

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 98: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Solving the problematic pessimism example

Normalize price of consumption in good state to 1.First individual spends 1

2 of his wealth on consumption ingood state; has 9

10 of total perfectly correlated wealth.

Second spends 110 and has 1

10 .Let w ≡ 20 + 10p2, where ptails is price of consumption inthe tails state.Market clearing implies

(9

20 + 1100

)w = 20.

w = 100023 = 20 + 10p2 =⇒ p2 = 54

23

Investor 2 buys c12 = 100

207 ≈12 and c2

2 = 53 = 10

3 c12 .

Investor 1 buys c11 = 450

23 ≈ 1912 and c2

1 = 612 > 3

10c11

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 99: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Solving the problematic pessimism example

Normalize price of consumption in good state to 1.First individual spends 1

2 of his wealth on consumption ingood state; has 9

10 of total perfectly correlated wealth.

Second spends 110 and has 1

10 .Let w ≡ 20 + 10p2, where ptails is price of consumption inthe tails state.Market clearing implies

(9

20 + 1100

)w = 20.

w = 100023 = 20 + 10p2 =⇒ p2 = 54

23

Investor 2 buys c12 = 100

207 ≈12 and c2

2 = 53 = 10

3 c12 .

Investor 1 buys c11 = 450

23 ≈ 1912 and c2

1 = 612 > 3

10c11

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 100: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Solving the problematic pessimism example

Normalize price of consumption in good state to 1.First individual spends 1

2 of his wealth on consumption ingood state; has 9

10 of total perfectly correlated wealth.

Second spends 110 and has 1

10 .Let w ≡ 20 + 10p2, where ptails is price of consumption inthe tails state.Market clearing implies

(9

20 + 1100

)w = 20.

w = 100023 = 20 + 10p2 =⇒ p2 = 54

23

Investor 2 buys c12 = 100

207 ≈12 and c2

2 = 53 = 10

3 c12 .

Investor 1 buys c11 = 450

23 ≈ 1912 and c2

1 = 612 > 3

10c11

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 101: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Solving the problematic pessimism example

Normalize price of consumption in good state to 1.First individual spends 1

2 of his wealth on consumption ingood state; has 9

10 of total perfectly correlated wealth.

Second spends 110 and has 1

10 .Let w ≡ 20 + 10p2, where ptails is price of consumption inthe tails state.Market clearing implies

(9

20 + 1100

)w = 20.

w = 100023 = 20 + 10p2 =⇒ p2 = 54

23

Investor 2 buys c12 = 100

207 ≈12 and c2

2 = 53 = 10

3 c12 .

Investor 1 buys c11 = 450

23 ≈ 1912 and c2

1 = 612 > 3

10c11

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 102: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Solving the problematic pessimism example

Normalize price of consumption in good state to 1.First individual spends 1

2 of his wealth on consumption ingood state; has 9

10 of total perfectly correlated wealth.

Second spends 110 and has 1

10 .Let w ≡ 20 + 10p2, where ptails is price of consumption inthe tails state.Market clearing implies

(9

20 + 1100

)w = 20.

w = 100023 = 20 + 10p2 =⇒ p2 = 54

23

Investor 2 buys c12 = 100

207 ≈12 and c2

2 = 53 = 10

3 c12 .

Investor 1 buys c11 = 450

23 ≈ 1912 and c2

1 = 612 > 3

10c11

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 103: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

Solving the problematic pessimism example

Normalize price of consumption in good state to 1.First individual spends 1

2 of his wealth on consumption ingood state; has 9

10 of total perfectly correlated wealth.

Second spends 110 and has 1

10 .Let w ≡ 20 + 10p2, where ptails is price of consumption inthe tails state.Market clearing implies

(9

20 + 1100

)w = 20.

w = 100023 = 20 + 10p2 =⇒ p2 = 54

23

Investor 2 buys c12 = 100

207 ≈12 and c2

2 = 53 = 10

3 c12 .

Investor 1 buys c11 = 450

23 ≈ 1912 and c2

1 = 612 > 3

10c11

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 104: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

What does this show us about pessimism?

Thus pessimistic individual has less balanced portfolio!Very different from risk aversion...bets on bad outcomes.Is this interesting?Alternatively, could have individuals that believe things goagainst them. Might generate behavior more like riskaversion, but like non-expected utility.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 105: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

What does this show us about pessimism?

Thus pessimistic individual has less balanced portfolio!Very different from risk aversion...bets on bad outcomes.Is this interesting?Alternatively, could have individuals that believe things goagainst them. Might generate behavior more like riskaversion, but like non-expected utility.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 106: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

What does this show us about pessimism?

Thus pessimistic individual has less balanced portfolio!Very different from risk aversion...bets on bad outcomes.Is this interesting?Alternatively, could have individuals that believe things goagainst them. Might generate behavior more like riskaversion, but like non-expected utility.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 107: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

What does this show us about pessimism?

Thus pessimistic individual has less balanced portfolio!Very different from risk aversion...bets on bad outcomes.Is this interesting?Alternatively, could have individuals that believe things goagainst them. Might generate behavior more like riskaversion, but like non-expected utility.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 108: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

QuestionsFirst examplePessimism and risk-aversion

How does it generalize?

These were nice toy examples. But how do the insightsgeneralize? How do we define concepts in a fully generalrigorous manner?

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 109: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

Belief aggregationCCAPM

Assumptions of model

N agents, T periodsDifferentiable, concave, increasing utilityEndowments ei

t bounded below w.p.1 and aboveIndividual probability Qi

Complete markets: optimal individual consumption y?i

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 110: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

Belief aggregationCCAPM

Assumptions of model

N agents, T periodsDifferentiable, concave, increasing utilityEndowments ei

t bounded below w.p.1 and aboveIndividual probability Qi

Complete markets: optimal individual consumption y?i

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 111: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

Belief aggregationCCAPM

Assumptions of model

N agents, T periodsDifferentiable, concave, increasing utilityEndowments ei

t bounded below w.p.1 and aboveIndividual probability Qi

Complete markets: optimal individual consumption y?i

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 112: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

Belief aggregationCCAPM

Assumptions of model

N agents, T periodsDifferentiable, concave, increasing utilityEndowments ei

t bounded below w.p.1 and aboveIndividual probability Qi

Complete markets: optimal individual consumption y?i

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 113: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

Belief aggregationCCAPM

Assumptions of model

N agents, T periodsDifferentiable, concave, increasing utilityEndowments ei

t bounded below w.p.1 and aboveIndividual probability Qi

Complete markets: optimal individual consumption y?i

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 114: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

Belief aggregationCCAPM

Assumptions of model

N agents, T periodsDifferentiable, concave, increasing utilityEndowments ei

t bounded below w.p.1 and aboveIndividual probability Qi

Complete markets: optimal individual consumption y?i

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 115: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

Belief aggregationCCAPM

We look for ECBE with common “characteristic" M,endowments ei and consumption y i such that:

1 Qtu′i (t , y i) = Qi

tu′i (t , y?i

) ∀t , i2 y?i − ei = y i − ei ∀i

Can be shown that this always exists and is unique.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 116: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

Belief aggregationCCAPM

We look for ECBE with common “characteristic" M,endowments ei and consumption y i such that:

1 Qtu′i (t , y i) = Qi

tu′i (t , y?i

) ∀t , i2 y?i − ei = y i − ei ∀i

Can be shown that this always exists and is unique.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 117: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

Belief aggregationCCAPM

We look for ECBE with common “characteristic" M,endowments ei and consumption y i such that:

1 Qtu′i (t , y i) = Qi

tu′i (t , y?i

) ∀t , i2 y?i − ei = y i − ei ∀i

Can be shown that this always exists and is unique.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 118: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

Belief aggregationCCAPM

We look for ECBE with common “characteristic" M,endowments ei and consumption y i such that:

1 Qtu′i (t , y i) = Qi

tu′i (t , y?i

) ∀t , i2 y?i − ei = y i − ei ∀i

Can be shown that this always exists and is unique.

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 119: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

Belief aggregationCCAPM

Some formulae

Already derived formula with exponential utility. Ageneralization:

Suppose utility HARA with common slope:fracu′u′′ = θi + ηxLet λi be the lagrange multiplier in i ’s max

Let γi ≡λ−η

iPj λ−η

j

Then Q is given by:

Q =[ ∑

i γi(Qi)η] 1

η

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 120: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

Belief aggregationCCAPM

Some formulae

Already derived formula with exponential utility. Ageneralization:

Suppose utility HARA with common slope:fracu′u′′ = θi + ηxLet λi be the lagrange multiplier in i ’s max

Let γi ≡λ−η

iPj λ−η

j

Then Q is given by:

Q =[ ∑

i γi(Qi)η] 1

η

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 121: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

Belief aggregationCCAPM

Some formulae

Already derived formula with exponential utility. Ageneralization:

Suppose utility HARA with common slope:fracu′u′′ = θi + ηxLet λi be the lagrange multiplier in i ’s max

Let γi ≡λ−η

iPj λ−η

j

Then Q is given by:

Q =[ ∑

i γi(Qi)η] 1

η

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 122: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

Belief aggregationCCAPM

Some formulae

Already derived formula with exponential utility. Ageneralization:

Suppose utility HARA with common slope:fracu′u′′ = θi + ηxLet λi be the lagrange multiplier in i ’s max

Let γi ≡λ−η

iPj λ−η

j

Then Q is given by:

Q =[ ∑

i γi(Qi)η] 1

η

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 123: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

Belief aggregationCCAPM

Some formulae

Already derived formula with exponential utility. Ageneralization:

Suppose utility HARA with common slope:fracu′u′′ = θi + ηxLet λi be the lagrange multiplier in i ’s max

Let γi ≡λ−η

iPj λ−η

j

Then Q is given by:

Q =[ ∑

i γi(Qi)η] 1

η

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 124: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

Belief aggregationCCAPM

Some formulae

Already derived formula with exponential utility. Ageneralization:

Suppose utility HARA with common slope:fracu′u′′ = θi + ηxLet λi be the lagrange multiplier in i ’s max

Let γi ≡λ−η

iPj λ−η

j

Then Q is given by:

Q =[ ∑

i γi(Qi)η] 1

η

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 125: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

Belief aggregationCCAPM

Interpretation

Weighted “mean" of beliefsWeight proportional to wealth (λ−η) as this determines riskbearingCloser to geometric mean as η → 0 (exponential case),arithmetic mean if η = 1, “superarithmetic" if η > 1Therefore η < 1 =⇒ Q(Ω) < 1, η = 1 =⇒ Q(Ω = 1),η > 1 =⇒ Q(Ω) > 1This is aggregation “bias", cumulates over time

Define Bt by B0 = 1, Bt = Bt−1Et−1[Qt ]

Qt−1; then B is a sort of

deflatorThen Q ≡ Q

B is a belief

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 126: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

Belief aggregationCCAPM

Interpretation

Weighted “mean" of beliefsWeight proportional to wealth (λ−η) as this determines riskbearingCloser to geometric mean as η → 0 (exponential case),arithmetic mean if η = 1, “superarithmetic" if η > 1Therefore η < 1 =⇒ Q(Ω) < 1, η = 1 =⇒ Q(Ω = 1),η > 1 =⇒ Q(Ω) > 1This is aggregation “bias", cumulates over time

Define Bt by B0 = 1, Bt = Bt−1Et−1[Qt ]

Qt−1; then B is a sort of

deflatorThen Q ≡ Q

B is a belief

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 127: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

Belief aggregationCCAPM

Interpretation

Weighted “mean" of beliefsWeight proportional to wealth (λ−η) as this determines riskbearingCloser to geometric mean as η → 0 (exponential case),arithmetic mean if η = 1, “superarithmetic" if η > 1Therefore η < 1 =⇒ Q(Ω) < 1, η = 1 =⇒ Q(Ω = 1),η > 1 =⇒ Q(Ω) > 1This is aggregation “bias", cumulates over time

Define Bt by B0 = 1, Bt = Bt−1Et−1[Qt ]

Qt−1; then B is a sort of

deflatorThen Q ≡ Q

B is a belief

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 128: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

Belief aggregationCCAPM

Interpretation

Weighted “mean" of beliefsWeight proportional to wealth (λ−η) as this determines riskbearingCloser to geometric mean as η → 0 (exponential case),arithmetic mean if η = 1, “superarithmetic" if η > 1Therefore η < 1 =⇒ Q(Ω) < 1, η = 1 =⇒ Q(Ω = 1),η > 1 =⇒ Q(Ω) > 1This is aggregation “bias", cumulates over time

Define Bt by B0 = 1, Bt = Bt−1Et−1[Qt ]

Qt−1; then B is a sort of

deflatorThen Q ≡ Q

B is a belief

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 129: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

Belief aggregationCCAPM

Interpretation

Weighted “mean" of beliefsWeight proportional to wealth (λ−η) as this determines riskbearingCloser to geometric mean as η → 0 (exponential case),arithmetic mean if η = 1, “superarithmetic" if η > 1Therefore η < 1 =⇒ Q(Ω) < 1, η = 1 =⇒ Q(Ω = 1),η > 1 =⇒ Q(Ω) > 1This is aggregation “bias", cumulates over time

Define Bt by B0 = 1, Bt = Bt−1Et−1[Qt ]

Qt−1; then B is a sort of

deflatorThen Q ≡ Q

B is a belief

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 130: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

Belief aggregationCCAPM

Interpretation

Weighted “mean" of beliefsWeight proportional to wealth (λ−η) as this determines riskbearingCloser to geometric mean as η → 0 (exponential case),arithmetic mean if η = 1, “superarithmetic" if η > 1Therefore η < 1 =⇒ Q(Ω) < 1, η = 1 =⇒ Q(Ω = 1),η > 1 =⇒ Q(Ω) > 1This is aggregation “bias", cumulates over time

Define Bt by B0 = 1, Bt = Bt−1Et−1[Qt ]

Qt−1; then B is a sort of

deflatorThen Q ≡ Q

B is a belief

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 131: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

Belief aggregationCCAPM

Interpretation

Weighted “mean" of beliefsWeight proportional to wealth (λ−η) as this determines riskbearingCloser to geometric mean as η → 0 (exponential case),arithmetic mean if η = 1, “superarithmetic" if η > 1Therefore η < 1 =⇒ Q(Ω) < 1, η = 1 =⇒ Q(Ω = 1),η > 1 =⇒ Q(Ω) > 1This is aggregation “bias", cumulates over time

Define Bt by B0 = 1, Bt = Bt−1Et−1[Qt ]

Qt−1; then B is a sort of

deflatorThen Q ≡ Q

B is a belief

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 132: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

Belief aggregationCCAPM

Setting up the CCAPM

Only skimmed over asset pricing in our example. Let’s solve itgenerally here:

Objective measure P

Riskless asset S0 with rate r ft+1 ≡

S0t+1S0

t− 1 and risky assets

with prices Sit and return R i

t+1 ≡Si

t+1Si

t− 1

If π? is equilibrium price deflator process (under P) thenπ?S is martingale

Thus EPt [Rt+1]− r f

t+1 = −covPt

[π?

t+1EP

t [π?t+1]

, Rt+1

]

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 133: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

Belief aggregationCCAPM

Setting up the CCAPM

Only skimmed over asset pricing in our example. Let’s solve itgenerally here:

Objective measure P

Riskless asset S0 with rate r ft+1 ≡

S0t+1S0

t− 1 and risky assets

with prices Sit and return R i

t+1 ≡Si

t+1Si

t− 1

If π? is equilibrium price deflator process (under P) thenπ?S is martingale

Thus EPt [Rt+1]− r f

t+1 = −covPt

[π?

t+1EP

t [π?t+1]

, Rt+1

]

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 134: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

Belief aggregationCCAPM

Setting up the CCAPM

Only skimmed over asset pricing in our example. Let’s solve itgenerally here:

Objective measure P

Riskless asset S0 with rate r ft+1 ≡

S0t+1S0

t− 1 and risky assets

with prices Sit and return R i

t+1 ≡Si

t+1Si

t− 1

If π? is equilibrium price deflator process (under P) thenπ?S is martingale

Thus EPt [Rt+1]− r f

t+1 = −covPt

[π?

t+1EP

t [π?t+1]

, Rt+1

]

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 135: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

Belief aggregationCCAPM

Setting up the CCAPM

Only skimmed over asset pricing in our example. Let’s solve itgenerally here:

Objective measure P

Riskless asset S0 with rate r ft+1 ≡

S0t+1S0

t− 1 and risky assets

with prices Sit and return R i

t+1 ≡Si

t+1Si

t− 1

If π? is equilibrium price deflator process (under P) thenπ?S is martingale

Thus EPt [Rt+1]− r f

t+1 = −covPt

[π?

t+1EP

t [π?t+1]

, Rt+1

]

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp

Page 136: Understanding ``Consensus' - The Jouini-Napp Model of ...markus/teaching/Eco525/21...N investors with CRRA utility (i.e. ui(w) = −e −w θi, θi is individual i’s constant absolute

Introduction and motivationModel and proofs

Belief aggregationCCAPM

Setting up the CCAPM

Only skimmed over asset pricing in our example. Let’s solve itgenerally here:

Objective measure P

Riskless asset S0 with rate r ft+1 ≡

S0t+1S0

t− 1 and risky assets

with prices Sit and return R i

t+1 ≡Si

t+1Si

t− 1

If π? is equilibrium price deflator process (under P) thenπ?S is martingale

Thus EPt [Rt+1]− r f

t+1 = −covPt

[π?

t+1EP

t [π?t+1]

, Rt+1

]

Jouini and Napp (2006) Brunnermeier Slides on Jouini-Napp