this inscrutable principle of an original organization

37
7/24/2019 This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/this-inscrutable-principle-of-an-original-organization 1/37

Upload: fisfil490

Post on 22-Feb-2018

219 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

7/24/2019 This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/this-inscrutable-principle-of-an-original-organization 1/37

Page 2: This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

7/24/2019 This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/this-inscrutable-principle-of-an-original-organization 2/37

74   J.H. Zammito / Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 34 (2003) 73 – 109

organization, on account of which he calls the faculty in the matter in an organized

body (in distinction from the merely mechanical   formative power   [ Bildungskraft ]

that is present in all matter) a  formative drive [ Bildungstrieb] (standing, as it were,

under the guidance and direction of that former principle).1

One of the most important contributions of Gerd Buchdahl to the history and the

philosophy of science was his argument for a crucial   ‘looseness of  fit’  between the

transcendental and the empirical elements in Kant’s epistemology.2 The issues of 

Buchdahl’s exposition remain at the center of ongoing disputes concerning Kant’sphilosophy of science and indeed Kant’s transcendental method altogether.3 While

Buchdahl and others seek to rescue Kant from what Peter Strawson once dubbed

the ‘non-sequitur  of numbing grossness’ of making natural science  a priori, everyone

who has dealt at all carefully with the Kantian texts is aware of the ambiguities in

the Konigsberger’s formulations and the challenge to coherent interpretation they

pose.4 Buchdahl generously ascribes this to the  ‘thinness’ of the conceptual language

available to Kant for his exposition, and he resists the view that Kant lacked perspi-

cuity regarding the questions at issue.5 That is indeed the high road of historical

reconstruction, which renders Kant most charitably for presentist concerns and by

presentist standards. I must confess to a less sanguine view of the  historical   Kant,

though I enlist wholeheartedly in the endeavor to  ‘naturalize’  Kantian philosophy of 

science for our own purposes.6 The  historical  Kant’s intransigence over the question

of  ‘hylozoism’, I wish to argue, put decisive obstacles before any  naturalistic coher-

ence in his philosophy of science.One way to situate the issue of the historical versus the reconstructed Kantian

philosophy of science—one where the difference  makes  a difference—is to consider

how the scientific community of Kant’s own day construed Kant’s proposals.7 Parti-

cularly salient in this context is the group of life scientists that Timothy Lenoir more

than twenty years ago dubbed the   ‘Gottingen school’.8 In Lenoir’s view, Kant’s

philosophy of science played a major role   ‘in helping to shape the theoretical foun-dations of the life sciences’  led by Johann Friedrich Blumenbach after 1790. Indeed,

‘from the late 1780s to the late 1790s Blumenbach’s ideas on natural history

underwent a thorough revision in light of Kant’s analysis of the conceptual foun-

dations for the construction of a scientific theory of organic form’.9

Blumenbach

1 Kant (1790), AA 5, 424.2 Buchdahl (1965), (1967), (1969), (1971), (1984), (1986).3 Friedman (1986), (1991), (1992a), (1992b); Butts (1991); Allison (1991), (1994); Guyer (1990a),

(1990b); Kitcher (1983), (1986), (1993), (1994).4 The allegation, from Strawson (1966), is discussed in all the texts cited above.5 On   ‘thinness’   of language, see Buchdahl (1967), p. 213.6 In particular, I am very interested in the pragmatist-naturalist reconstructions of philosophers of 

science like Kitcher (1993), (1994), and Rescher (2001).7 See, e.g., Williams (1973); Barnaby (1988); Gregory (1989).8 Lenoir (1980), (1981a), (1981b), (1988).9 Lenoir (1980), p. 77. The fullest acknowledgment of Kant, entailing abandonment of ideas Blumen-

bach had long held, came after 1797.

Page 3: This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

7/24/2019 This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/this-inscrutable-principle-of-an-original-organization 3/37

75 J.H. Zammito / Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 34 (2003) 73 – 109

began serious consideration of the philosophy of Kant in 1786 as a direct conse-

quence of the dispute surrounding Kant’s reviews of Herder’s  Ideen zur Philosophie

der Geschichte der Menschheit , especially Kant’s controversy with Georg Forster.10

But already   five years before, in 1781, Blumenbach proposed the most importantrevision in the eighteenth-century  fields of embryology and physiology with his idea

of the Bildungstrieb and his implied endorsement of epigenesis.11 The period between

1786 and 1797 brought the Gottingen physiologist and the Konigsberg philosopher

into direct communication, and there is clear evidence that Blumenbach assimilated

many aspects of Kantianism into his scientific methodology. There is also evidencein the converse direction, i.e., Kant’s assimilation of Blumenbach’s scientific method-

ology into his own exposition of philosophy of science. What is not so clear is the

ultimate cogency of either of these assimilations.

There are important issues of historical reconstruction that remain to be sorted

out.12 While one could pursue that in the direction of further developments in the

life sciences, as Lenoir and others have done, I will pursue the other direction: the

implications for Kant’s philosophy of science. In taking up Kant’s philosophy of 

science in what one commentator has provocatively titled  ‘the  transcendent  science’of biology these scientists encountered head-on the tensions in Kant’s system of 

empirical entailment, precisely those issues of the   ‘looseness of   fit’   between the

constitutive and the regulative in Kant’s critical epistemology.13

One of the most notable endeavors to assimilate Kantian thought into the practice

of the life sciences at the end of the eighteenth century, and one which has the

distinction of explicit endorsement by  both Kant and Blumenbach, is Christoph Girt-anner’s U ¨ ber das Kantische Prinzip fu r die Naturgeschichte (1796). Girtanner’s work 

offers a very useful starting point for assessing how Kant was being understood by

Blumenbach and the Gottingen school at the decisive moment. Through Girtanner

we can see how the specific issues at stake in Kant’s biological thought open out

onto the deepest issues of his philosophy of science, indeed of his transcendental

philosophy altogether.

1. Girtanner’s   Kantische Prinzip

In   Anthropology from a pragmatic point of view   (1798) Kant specifically cel-

ebrated Christoph Girtanner for the latter’s exposition of the theory of race. Under

the heading   ‘On the Character of Races’  Kant wrote:   ‘As to this subject I can refer

to what Girtanner has stated so beautifully and carefully in explanation and further

development (of my principles)’.14 Kant also referred to Girtanner repeatedly as auth-

10 On the dispute itself see Riedel (1980).11 Blumenbach (1781).12 On this crucial and still not definitively interpreted reception, see Lenoir (1980), pp. 89–98; Sloan

(2001); Bernasconi (2001b).13 Zumbach (1984).14 Kant (1798), AA 7, 320.

Page 4: This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

7/24/2019 This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/this-inscrutable-principle-of-an-original-organization 4/37

76   J.H. Zammito / Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 34 (2003) 73 – 109

oritative in the lecture materials for his   Physical geography, which Rink edited and

published in 1802.15 Now, Kant was remarkably chary of publicly praising other

authors, and rarely did he acknowledge that anyone grasped his thought properly,

much less extended it. But Girtanner’s extension of Kant’s work followed just thevein that Kant himself had indicated his theory of race would require were it to

become a serious scientific research program.16

Rather ungenerously labeled   ‘an outsider and an eccentric’   by one of the few

scholars to have written of him, Christoph Girtanner deserves a bit more consider-

ation than this would imply.17 It is no small thing to have both Immanuel Kant andJohann Friedrich Blumenbach refer to one’s work as the definitive exposition of a

crucial matter in eighteenth-century life science. Girtanner was born in St. Gallen,

Switzerland in 1760.18 He studied  first at Lausanne, then at Strasbourg, and  finally

from 1780 to 1782 at Gottingen, where he completed a medical degree under the

direction of Blumenbach. Girtanner’s studies encompassed botany, chemistry and

mineralogy before culminating in medicine. His dissertation was on limestone and

its organic origins. After a brief stint back home in Switzerland as a physician,

Girtanner began to travel. In 1784 he went to Paris, then on to Edinburgh, in each

locus making crucial intellectual contacts. In Paris, he familiarized himself with

Lavoisier’s   ‘chemical revolution’. In Edinburgh he came into contact with William

Cullen and with the theories of the latter’s maverick student, John Brown.19 Girtanner

became an honorary member of the Royal Medical Society of Edinburgh and a

foreign member of the Royal Society of Science of Edinburgh and proved a crucial

figure in transmitting the thought of the late Scottish Enlightenment to Germany. Assuch a crucial intermediary, Blumenbach recommended him in 1786 to become a

corresponding member of the Gottingen Academy of Science.20 Back in Gottingen

briefly in 1787, Girtanner became a close friend of the other great scientific mind

at that University, Georg Lichtenberg. Then his urge to travel overtook him again

and he went on a grand tour which culminated in his witnessing the events of the

French Revolution in Paris, 1789.21

His  first major publication appeared in French in the  Journal de physique of 1790,

a two-part essay entitled   ‘ Me moires sur l’irritabilite   considere e comme principe de

15 Kant (1802), AA 9, 185, 234, 313–314, 319.16 In a letter responding to the publisher Breitkopf ’s invitation to submit a more extended work on race

in 1778, Kant, declining the invitation, explained:   ‘my frame of reference would need to be widely

expanded and I would need to take fully into consideration the place of race among animal and plant

species, which would occupy me too much and carry me into extensive new reading which in a measure

lies outside my  field, because natural history is not my study but only my game . . .’  (Kant to Breitkopf,

April 1, 1778, AA 10, 227–230). The project of extending consideration of race to animals and plants

took up the bulk of Girtanner’s study.17 Querner (1990), p. 125.18 Wegelin (1957).19 Ibid., pp. 142–143.20 Querner (1990), p. 124.21 Indeed, Girtanner produced a substantial volume of political commentary on the revolution, but that

is another story.

Page 5: This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

7/24/2019 This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/this-inscrutable-principle-of-an-original-organization 5/37

77 J.H. Zammito / Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 34 (2003) 73 – 109

vie dans la nature organise e’.22 The  first part surveyed thought on the crucial ques-

tion of organic form and its medical implications, drawing especially on Haller and—

without acknowledgement—Brown. The second part sought to explain the character

of irritability in terms of Lavoisier’s new chemistry. The  first part drew down uponGirtanner the probably justified charge of plagiarism (of Brown) and the second the

equally justified charge of excessive speculation (on the role of oxygen in

physiology), but the result was to make him a widely known theorist of life science.

Girtanner settled in Gottingen in 1790 as a physician and private scholar. In 1792

he published two major contributions to the propagation of Lavoisier’s anti-phlogisticchemistry in Germany.23 In 1794 he published a major work on the illnesses of 

children which established him as one of the leading clinical writers of the day, a

status confirmed a few years later in a series of massive works on venereal disease

(1798), on John Brown’s medical system (1798) and on the work of Erasmus Darwin

(1799). This extraordinary string of publications made Girtanner one of the most

important authors in medical science in the decade. Still, Girtanner’s study of Kant

did not leap to the public’s attention. Indeed, Girtanner had to write his own review

of the work for the  Go ttingische Anzeigen von gelehrten Sachen.24 His book appeared

in 1796; the acknowledgments from Kant and Blumenbach came only some years

later. By 1800, in any event, it could matter no longer to Girtanner, prematurely

dead of a lung disorder.

It would appear that Girtanner began learning about Kant around the same time

Blumenbach did, and that, like Blumenbach himself, Girtanner was stimulated by

Kant’s controversy with Herder and Forster, which drew the attention of most of the leading life scientists in Germany.25 In 1787 Girtanner corresponded regarding

Kant’s philosophy of science with Karl Reinhold, who had converted from a defender

of Herder into the decisive popularizer of Kant in 1786.26 In 1788, Girtanner formed

a personal acquaintance in Edinburgh with one of Kant’s disciples, Johann Jachmann,

who served as an intermediary between Blumenbach and Kant in the 1790s.27 Once

back in Gottingen from 1790 onward, Girtanner participated in the Blumenbach cir-cle during the years—1795–1797—that Lenoir has contended were decisive for the

assimilation of Kantianism by Blumenbach and his school.28 These were the years

of the composition and reception of Girtanner’s work, which he dedicated to Blumen-

bach as a contribution to that very endeavor.Girtanner presented Kant’s thought as the paradigm for a new research program

in the life sciences under the rubric of  Naturgeschichte, and he exemplified the power

22 I have consulted the English version:   ‘Two Memoirs translated from the French of Dr. Girtanner’,

in Beddoes (1815).23 Girtanner (1791), (1795).24 See Goettingische Anzeigen  171, St. 2, Bd. 24 (October, 1796). The information that Girtanner wrote

his own review is taken from Querner (1990), p. 123 n.25 See the documentation of this controversy in Fambach (1959), pp. 357–397.26 Sloan (1979), p. 138; Lenoir (1980), p. 99.27 Sloan (1979), p. 138. See Jachmann to Kant, October 14, 1790, AA 11, 201–213.28 Lenoir (1980), p. 88.

Page 6: This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

7/24/2019 This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/this-inscrutable-principle-of-an-original-organization 6/37

78   J.H. Zammito / Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 34 (2003) 73 – 109

of this new research program and its proposed  ‘laws of nature’ through its application

to racial variation. In invoking racial variation Girtanner was not taking up a periph-

eral matter in Kant’s thought. Rather, the question of racial variation had assumed

saliency in Kant’s philosophy of science, as evidenced not only by his two essayson race but above all by his controversy with Georg Forster around that issue.29 I

have argued that this saliency was already emergent in the original essay on race of 

1775/77.30 That essay began to set the terms in which the critical Kant understood

himself and wished to be understood as a  Naturforscher .31 Ten years later, provoked

by Herder and then challenged by one of the premier natural scientists of the day,Forster, Kant found himself enunciating key premises of his entire philosophy of 

science in the essay,   ‘Uber den Gebrauch teleologischer Principien in der Philoso-

phie’  (1788). As I have argued extensively elsewhere, these considerations   flowed

directly into the composition of the  Critique of judgment  over the next two years.32

That is, Kant’s theories of the life sciences, embroiled in the question of racial vari-

ation, must be construed as far more central to the problem of his general philosophy

of science than has hitherto been the case.33

The essential point from which Girtanner departed was Kant’s new conception of 

 Naturgeschichte. Hitherto the term   ‘natural history’   in German science had really

only signified natural  description. It was heuristic and classificatory, as exemplified

above all by Linnaeus.34 But Kant, taking up impulses from Buffon, intended to

displace this with a real and genetic conception of the order of living forms

( Naturgattungen   in place of  Schulgattungen), and therewith to make  history   central

to the project of the life sciences.

35

This new research program would ask, in Girtan-ner’s words,   ‘what the primal form of each ancestral species of animals and plants

originally consisted of, and how the species gradually devolved from their ancestral

species’.36 This was a new and specific science which would explore and explain

how environmental changes on the earth—indeed   ‘violent revolutions in nature’—

occasioned dramatic changes in life forms. Yet however dramatic, the point was that

these were not   chaotic   changes; rather, the variation in observed traits in currentspecies emerged always under the guidance of a   ‘natural law’  requiring that   ‘in all

29 Kant (1775/77), (1785b), (1788).30 Zammito (2001b).31 It is extremely important to reflect on the manner in which Kant understood himself  vis a vis science;

the starting point is Adickes (1924).32 Zammito (1992), (1998).33 Thus I strongly resist the position taken by Stephan Korner that Kant’s  ‘conjectures’  that  ‘the growth

of organisms or the af finity between different species, are not susceptible to mechanistic explanation, do

not form part of the critical philosophy’. They are  obiter dicta  expressing his strong interest in the science

of his day and his expectation of its progress’   (Korner, 1955, p. 211). By eliding Kant’s biological

thought—as even so careful a student of Kant as Michael Friedman (1992b), has done by electing to

discuss only the   ‘exact sciences’— just this kind of problem gets concealed.34 E.g., Blumenbach (1779), which Kant owned.35 Sloan (1979), pp. 127–129; Riedel (1980).36 Girtanner (1796), p. 2.

Page 7: This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

7/24/2019 This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/this-inscrutable-principle-of-an-original-organization 7/37

79 J.H. Zammito / Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 34 (2003) 73 – 109

of organic creation, species remain unaltered’.37 Kant’s great achievement, in Girtan-

ner’s eyes, was his conection of this law to a more determinate   ‘natural law’

(proposed by Buffon) to explain this process, namely that   ‘all animals or plants that

produce fertile offspring belong to the same physical [i.e., real] species’, notwith-standing considerable observed variation in traits.38 That is, these organisms   must 

have  ‘derived from one and the same stem [Stamme]’.39 While there could be heredi-

tary variations [ Abartungen]  within the confines of the governing stem, there could

not be  ‘degenerations’  [ Ausartungen], that is, permanently heritable departures from

the fundamental traits of the ancestral stem.40  Races constituted decisive evidence forthis theory, because their crosses always showed perfect proportion in the offspring:

 Halbschlachtigkeit   (half-breeding). To account for these internal variations within

species, Kant offered the view that  ‘the ancestral stem of each species of organic life

contained a quantity of different germs [Keime] and natural potentialities [natu rliche

 Anlagen]’.41 Girtanner followed Kant literally in identifying  Keime  with the source

of changes in the parts (organs) of an organic life form, while   natu rliche Anlagen

occasioned changes only in the size or proportion of such parts.42 Kant used winter

feathers in birds to exemplify the  first, and thickness in the husk of grain to exemplify

the second. Girtanner replicated these examples.

To help explicate the  process of variation, Girtanner turned to his teacher Blumen-

bach. It was   ‘through different directions of the  Bildungstrieb, [that] now these and

now those [germs or natural potentialities] developed, while the others remained

inert’.43 Only climate acting on organisms over extended time could educe such

variation, such shifts in the  ‘

direction of the  Bildungstrieb’, and thus permanentlyalter   ‘the primal forces of organic development and movement’.44 Moreover, once

such shifts in direction took place, once certain germs or natural potentialities trig-

gered into actualization, the rest atrophied and the process proved irreversible.45 This

claim represented one of Kant’s decisive interventions in the theory of race, separat-

ing him sharply from Buffon, for example.46

Girtanner was acutely aware of the way in which Kant’s  ‘natural history’ interpen-etrated with his theory of organic form. Not only did Kant require a specific theory

of generic transmission, but he needed a theory of organic life in which to cast it.

The only form of generation that had been empirically observed, Girtanner noted,

was   generatio homonyma, the persistence of species, though   generatio heteronyma

37 Ibid., p. 6.38 Ibid., p. 4.39 Ibid.40 The term  ‘degeneration’  came to be used in very disparate ways in 18th-century natural science; the

way Girtanner employed it signified mutation of species. It is not clear that Kant was so careful in his

own usage of this term. See Sloan (1973).41 Girtanner (1796), p. 11.42 Despite the considerable departure Blumenbach had by then taken from such terminology.43 Girtanner (1796), 11.44 Ibid., 12.45 Ibid., 27.46 Bernasconi (2001a).

Page 8: This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

7/24/2019 This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/this-inscrutable-principle-of-an-original-organization 8/37

80   J.H. Zammito / Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 34 (2003) 73 – 109

[ Ausartung] was not impossible (against reason), but only unheard of (against

experience). The essential point was that these both contrasted with generatio aequiv-

oca   (spontaneous generation).  ‘That by mechanism organized beings should emerge

from unorganized matter . . . contradicts reason as well as experience’.47 That is,  ‘itcontradicts all known laws of experience that matter which is not organized should

have by itself, without the intervention of other, organized matter, organized itself ’.48

 Anti-hylozoism, then, was the essential posit of Kant’s theory of organic form. Girt-

anner stressed this about the idea of organism. Not only was it   ‘not a machine’   in

consequence of the mutuality of cause and effect, of parts and whole, but neitherwas it the   ‘analogue of art’, for   ‘organized Nature organizes itself ’.49

In the terminology of Blumenbach, Kant discriminated between a  Bildungskraft —

‘the   vis plastica   of the ancients, which works merely via mechanism’—and a   Bil-

dungstrieb  which Blumenbach conceived as a  ‘nisus formativus  that worked organi-

cally’.50 Girtanner was clear that Blumenbach’s   Bildungstrieb   was a   Lebenskraft ,

namely   ‘that force by virtue of which the chemical and physical laws are subordi-

nated under the laws of organization’.51 Because life forms showed characteristics—

reproduction, growth through nourishment and assimilation, regeneration of lost

organs and self-healing generally—which could not be assimilated to the mechanistic

model of natural science, they represented anomalies requiring recourse to teleologi-

cal judgment, the analogy of   ‘purposiveness’. This was Kant’s central concern in

the   ‘Critique of teleological judgment’   and, as the epigraph to this essay demon-

strates, Kant felt that Blumenbach had most perspicuously articulated the proper

approach.

2. The unresolved issue of   ‘epigenesis’   in Kant

In terms of the broader methodological issues in Kant’s philosophy of science,

what is the status of the so-called laws of nature which Girtanner ascribed to him?Did Kant’s philosophy of science permit  laws in this domain? More, are these  ‘teleo-

logical’   or   ‘mechanical’   in character, and can there even be   ‘teleological’   laws of 

nature?52 Furthermore, what sorts of entities were  ‘germs’ and ‘natural potentialities’

for Kant? Clark Zumbach observes, for example:   ‘Keime, as part of the generativeforce [ Zeugungskraft ], are postulated . . . as the inner mechanisms for development

in future circumstances . . . [T]hey control the permanence of phenotypic traits and

are   ‘kept back or unfolded’   depending on the situation at hand’.53 Through them

Kant sought to characterize the mysterious   ‘inner possibility’  of organic form in its

47 Girtanner (1796), p. 15.48 Ibid., pp. 14–15.49 Ibid., pp. 17–18.50 Ibid., pp. 16–17 n.51 Ibid., p. 17.52 Butts (1990), p. 12, for one, denies it.53 Zumbach (1984), p. 102.

Page 9: This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

7/24/2019 This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/this-inscrutable-principle-of-an-original-organization 9/37

81 J.H. Zammito / Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 34 (2003) 73 – 109

objective reality or real possibility. What kind of  ‘theoretical terms’  did they consti-

tute, and what sorts of observational evidence could instantiate them? The cognitive

status of these concepts is all the more pressing since the new   ‘natural history’

postulated an   original   or  ancestral   form which, at least in the case of humans andin all likelihood for any other life forms, no longer persisted in the present.54 Without

some  necessary  principle of the derivation of current species from these ancestors,

the whole approach would be less than an art, it would be arrant speculation. 55

In Kantian terms, what made these ‘real possibilities’ and not just wild hypotheses

irreconcilable with   ‘proper Newtonian science?’   Zumbach suggests that   ‘Kant ismaking the broader claim that more than the physicochemical conception is  required 

to explain and understand the epigenetic capacities of living things’.56 Specifically,

‘the difference between the biological point of view and the mechanistic lies in the

fact that there is a concept of causality found in the former which is not present in

the latter’.57 More extensively:

Kant holds both that (i) the conceptual materials available to the mechanical point

of view are insuf ficient for the construction of our concept of a living system,

thus leaving living phenomena inexplicable in terms of the mechanism of nature,

and (ii) the basis of this deficiency lies in the fact that the mechanical conception

of nature lacks this idea of a free cause. That Kant holds   both   (i) and (ii) is one

of the most closely guarded secrets of the Critical Philosophy. Kant maintains

that  all  living processes  involve   the causality of reason, that is,  final causes. And

final causes are free causes. Thus to assert that something is a natural purposeentails the view that its internal processes contain events which do not occur with

the necessity that is the mark of inorganic occurrences.58

Yet this leads, in Zumbach’s view, all too far towards   ‘vitalism’. And, he asserts,

‘to fall back on a vital entity to explain the generative, and the rest of . . . the  ‘epigen-

etic’ capacities of living things, is to fall back on that which science cannot pursue’.59

Two observations seem appropriate. First, this repudiation is very much in the

spirit of the  prescriptive  character of Kantian philosophy of science. Kant could only

view the assertion of an empirically actual formative force as  hylozoism, and there

was nothing toward which he felt a stronger metaphysical animus, even though hisown struggle with organic form accentuated that possibility. Kant wrote:

54 ‘Indeed, if we depart from this principle, we cannot know with certainty whether several parts of 

the form which is now apparent in a species have not a contingent and unpurposive origin; and the

principle of teleology: to judge nothing in an organized being as unpurposive which maintains it in its

propagation, would be very unreliable in its application and would be reliable solely for the original stock 

(of which we have no further knowledge)’   (Kant, 1790, AA 5, 420).55 Here I am invoking Kant’s language from the Preface to 1786, AA 4, 467–469, a matter to which

I will return.56 Zumbach (1984), p. 83.57 Ibid., p. 94.58 Ibid., p. 99.59 Ibid., p. 85.

Page 10: This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

7/24/2019 This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/this-inscrutable-principle-of-an-original-organization 10/37

82   J.H. Zammito / Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 34 (2003) 73 – 109

We perhaps approach nearer to this inscrutable property if we describe it as an

analogue of life, but then we must either endow matter, as mere matter, with a

property that contradicts its very being (hylozoism) or associate it with a foreign

principle  standing in communion  with it (a soul) . . .60

Neither seemed acceptable. Thus, Kant did denounce   ‘vitalism’, especially as he

construed it in Herder, but he also—and ironically enough  with the same breath—

repudiated  ‘materialism’.61 Yet, second, against the grain of both Zumbach and Kant,

everything hinges on what exactly vitalism signifies. Zumbach presumes that vitalismmust mean animism. But this is profoundly to misunderstand the scientific thought

of the eighteenth century, whose essential endeavor was to discard animism and  find

a new approach to vitalism—a   vital materialism.62 That was the essence of  epigen-

esis. In contemporary terms, what they were striving after was a theory of  emergence

as immanent in nature.

I submit that Kant’s language of  Keime and  natu rliche Anlagen and his acceptance

of the idea of a  Lebenskraft  as exemplified by Blumenbach’s  Bildungstrieb  commit-

ted him to a conception of life science entailing the  objective reality  of forces which

could not be reduced to those he admitted in the Newtonian order of physics. And,

in fact, there is considerable evidence that, against the grain of his high  ‘Newtonian’

rigor, Kant tacitly admitted the objective actuality of   forces   throughout physical

science.63 That was certainly where he ended up in the  Opus postumum, though most

Kantians seem inclined to see that work as detached from the   ‘critical’   philosophy

and hence not necessarily to be taken seriously.

64

To give more weight to my claim, I propose to examine more closely Kant ’s

conception of  epigenesis. What did Kant understand by an epigenetic theory of gener-

ation? That Kant found it appropriate to draw an analogy of his own transcendental

method in philosophy to epigenesis in embryology suggests that something very

central was involved for him in this issue in the life sciences.65 Indeed, spontaneity

and systematicity, two crucial ideas in Kant’s theory of reason,  find their empiricalanalogs in the idea of epigenesis in nature. But we must be sensitive to the uses of 

analogy which Kant was prepared to acknowledge, as Hans Ingensiep has argued.66

Ingensiep suggests that Kant did not intend by analogy to extend his formal argu-

ment for transcendental philosophy, nor was analogy serving here as a heuristic toenable further discoveries (as in the Kuhnian sense of paradigm); rather, it was only

for   ‘intuitive illustration’   [anschaulichen Verdeutlichung].67 At most, Kant gestured

60 Kant (1790), AA 5, 374–375.61 Kant (1785a), AA 8, 48.62 Lenoir (1980), (1981a); Reill (1989), (1992), (1998).63 Okruhlik (1983).64 See Tuschling (1991).65 Kant (1781/1787), B167. See Wubnig (1968); Genova (1974); Zoller (1988); Ingensiep (1994);

Sloan (2002).66 Ingensiep (1994).67 Ibid., p. 385.

Page 11: This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

7/24/2019 This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/this-inscrutable-principle-of-an-original-organization 11/37

83 J.H. Zammito / Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 34 (2003) 73 – 109

to  ‘structural similarities’, and  ‘accordingly in no way can it be construed as a claim

for any compelling ontological connection between the respective philosophical and

biological positions’.68 There remains, even for Ingensiep, however, a clear struc-

tural correlation:

As, according to the epigenesis theory, unformed inorganic matter gets transfor-

med under the direction of a  ‘purposive endowment’  into something entirely new

via the  Bildungstrieb  and an organism is produced, so via the categories and the

raw material of sensibility empirical knowledge is   ‘produced’. The organizingproductivity, however, lies entirely on the side of categorizing understanding. As,

via the requisites of the epigenesis theory, from something unformed and unpur-

posive gradually something specially formed, purposive (according to the most

inward interfusion of generative  fluids) gets produced, so, similarly, one can con-

ceive the unifying ordering of the manifold by the categories.69

But this does not yet clarify the tension between the concepts of epigenesis and

preformation as they featured in Kant’s thinking.

The debate between preformation and epigenesis in the late eighteenth century is

well-known to have occasioned both metaphysical and methodological controversies

over the relation of mechanism to vitalism.70 From the beginning, Kant was acutely

sensitive to this whole constellation of concerns in both its methodological and its

metaphysical aspects. Already in his  One possible basis for a demonstration of the

existence of  God (1763), Kant showed his awareness of the new twist toward epigen-esis introduced by Maupertuis and Buffon, along with the strong rebuttal to it

developed by the leading German life scientist of the day, Albrecht von Haller.71

Indeed, there is strong reason to believe that Kant followed Haller’s view very closely

in his own thinking, adopting eagerly the latter’s modified preformation theory both

because it seemed more methodologically viable and also—perhaps even more—

because it reasserted with full rigor the metaphysical objection against hylozoism.72

The specific form of  preformation that Kant endorsed was the sophisticated version

developed by Bonnet and Haller in the early 1760s in response to the challenge  first

of Maupertuis and Buffon and then, more fundamentally, of Caspar Friedrich

Wolff.73

As Gunter Zoller characterizes this form,   ‘preformationism is primarily atheory concerning the generation of distinct parts (organs) in the growing embryo.

It maintains that growth is  quantitative growth of preexisting parts . . . no qualitative

embryological growth or formation of new parts’. In that light the term  Anlagen  had

68 Ibid.69 Ibid., p. 387.70 Roe (1979); Gaissinovich (1968); Bodemer (1964); Breidenbach (1995); Rheinberger (1981), (1986);

Mocek (1995); Muller-Sievers (1993), (1997); Dawson (1991); Duchesneau (1985); Haigh (1976); Zam-

mito (2001).71 Kant (1763), AA 2, 114–115.72 Sloan’s work (2001, and 2002) has made this perfectly clear.73 Roe (1979).

Page 12: This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

7/24/2019 This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/this-inscrutable-principle-of-an-original-organization 12/37

84   J.H. Zammito / Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 34 (2003) 73 – 109

a quite specific application, just as Kant articulated it in his   first essay on race,

namely to   ‘‘conditions of a certain development . . . in so far as the latter only

concerns the size and the   relation   of parts’   . . . [as] opposed to   germs   (‘Keime’),

which are conditions for the development of new parts’.74 That is, the role of  Anlagencould be construed in a quasi-mechanistic fashion; the essential  metaphysical   prin-

ciple guaranteeing species difference (and persistence) was assigned to  Keime. When

Kant turned to questions of life science in his  first essay on race, 1775/77, he clearly

employed a Hallerian approach to preformation, but he also believed that he could

advance the argument, both in the formulation of the  mechanism   of adaptation andvariation—the great weakness of earlier preformation theories—and also in his gen-

eral methodological idea of   ‘natural history’, which Haller and the incipient Got-

tingen school acknowledged in principle but could not bring themselves to accept

in its Buffonian formulation.75

Thus, by the time he published the  first Critique  in 1781, Kant considered himself 

suf ficiently adept in the theory of generation to offer a telling analogy to his theory

of knowledge.

I understand under the  ‘Analytic of concepts’ . . . the still little investigated dissec-

tion of the capacity of the understanding itself, in order thereby that we search

into the possibility of   a priori  concepts, seeking them out in the understanding

alone,  as their source of birth  . . . We will therefore   follow the pure concepts up

to their   first germs and capacities [Keimen und Anlagen] in the human under-

standing, in which they lie predisposed, until they   finally, on the occasion of experience, develop  and through exactly the same understanding are displayed in

their purity, freed from their attending empirical conditions.76

This analogy of 1781, as Phillip Sloan has established, is crucial to any assessment

of the more famous analogy of 1787 to epigenesis.77 First, the 1781 language is

unequivocally a preformationist  analogy. The concepts lie ‘predisposed’ in the under-standing; they are not produced, they are occasioned. As Sloan argues, in terms of 

the philosophical debate about Kant’s relation to innate ideas, this is clearly as  ‘nativ-

ist’   a Kant as one can   find.78 Moreover, Kant meant to suggest an element in the

analogy which would be central to his thinking throughout, namely that just as  Keimeand   Anlagen   were inaccessible to ultimate derivation, so too the concepts of the

understanding were simply givens behind which we could not seek. The clearest

formulation is in the revised version (1787) of the  first  Critique:

This peculiarity of our understanding, that it can produce a priori unity of apper-

ception solely by means of the categories, and only such and so many, is as little

74 Zoller (1988), p. 79.75 Sloan (1979), pp. 122–3; Lenoir (1981a), pp. 120–123.76 Kant (1781/1787), A66, my italics.77 Sloan (2002).78 Ibid. On Kant’s   ‘nativism’  see Zoller (1989).

Page 13: This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

7/24/2019 This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/this-inscrutable-principle-of-an-original-organization 13/37

85 J.H. Zammito / Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 34 (2003) 73 – 109

capable of further explanation as why we have just these and no other functions

of judgment, or why space and time are the only forms of our possible intuition. 79

But it was fully entailed in the earlier version, with its speculative gesture to acommon but unknown root of sensibility and understanding.80 The critical point is

that Kant wished to see an analogy between  preformation  and transcendental philo-

sophy, and not between the latter and  epigenesis. Indeed, there was no af firmation

of epigenesis in any of Kant’s writings before 1787.81

In his dispute with Herder and Forster from 1784 through 1788, i.e. up throughthe time of his revision of the   first   Critique, Kant remained committed to prefor-

mation. Indeed, the insistence upon   Keime   as   fixtures limiting adaptive change in

organisms was the decisive point in Kant’s critique of Herder’s representation of 

generation theory.   ‘The author bases his argument not on germs but on an organic

force . . . The  animal soul   is the sum of all the forces at work in an organism, and

instinct is not a particular natural force but the direction given by nature to all of 

these forces by virtue of their overall combination’.82 Kant interjected with contempt:

‘But what are we to think of the whole hypothesis of invisible forces which give

rise to organisation, and hence of the author’s attempt to explain  what is not under-

stood   in terms of   what is understood even less?’83 He became more specific in the

second installment of his review:

As the reviewer understands it, the sense in which the author uses this expression

[i.e.,   genetische Kraft ] is as follows. He wishes to reject the system of evolutionon the one hand, but also the purely mechanical influence of external causes on

the other, as worthless explanations. He assumes that the cause of such differences

is the vital principle [ Lebensprinzip] which modifies  itself  from within in accord-

ance with variations in external circumstances, and in a manner appropriate to

these. The reviewer is fully in agreement with him here, but with this reservation:

if the cause which organises   from within   were limited by its nature to only acertain number and degree of differences in the development of the creature which

it organises (so that, once these differences were exhausted, it would no longer

be free to work from another archetype [Typus] under altered circumstances), one

could well describe this natural development of formative nature in terms of germs[Keime] or original dispositions [ Anlagen], without thereby regarding the differ-

ences in question as originally implanted and only occasionally activated mech-

anisms or buds [Knospen] (as in the system of evolution); on the contrary, such

differences should be regarded simply as limitations imposed on a self-determining

79 Kant (1781/1787), B145–146.80 See Kant (1783), AA 4, 319.81 Zoller (1988), pp. 80–84, discusses uses of epigenesis in Kant’s lectures and Reflexionen but there

is no reason to suspect any of these date significantly before 1786.82 Kant (1785a), AA 8, 48.83 Ibid., 53–54.

Page 14: This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

7/24/2019 This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/this-inscrutable-principle-of-an-original-organization 14/37

86   J.H. Zammito / Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 34 (2003) 73 – 109

power, limitations which are inexplicable as the power itself is incapable of being

explained or rendered comprehensible.84

Clearly, Kant was invoking   Keime   in the sense of Haller’s sophisticated prefor-mationism   against   what he saw as an insupportable  hylozoism   in Herder. Yet this

hylozoism is simply  epigenesis as Herder wished it understood! Gunter Zoller is one

of the few commentators to have grasped correctly what Herder was arguing in the

crucial passage on epigenesis in his   Ideen zur Philosophie der Geschichte der 

 Menschheit   which Kant was here critiquing.85 But Zoller himself is not carefulenough about the concept.   ‘ De facto, Herder’s concept of formation corresponds

to Wolff ’s and Blumenbach’s concepts of epigenesis’, Zoller writes, yet of course

Blumenbach argued extensively for the difference of his concept from that of Wolff.86

There is remarkably little consensus about exactly what   epigenesis   signified in

eighteenth-century discourse generally, not just in Kant.87 Modern usage set out from

William Harvey’s 1651 text,  On generation, in which he characterized as epigenesis

the characteristic of an organism that   ‘all its parts are not fashioned simultaneously,

but emerge in their due succession and order . . . For the formative faculty . . .

acquires and prepares its own material for itself ’.88 First, Harvey’s concept stressed

sequential emergence, and second, it stressed  self-organization. Spontaneity and sys-

tematicity were thus central features. What is ambiguous in this formulation is the

nature of the ‘formative faculty’. Is it a causal force or a teleological principle? What

ontological status does it have? When does it emerge? What preconditions in the

material or in the wider environment are suf fi

cient or necessary? Can such anapproach be assimilated to materialist and to mechanist models of science or is it

irreducibly vitalist, indeed animist? Crucially, Harvey and his early eighteenth-cen-

tury successors, Maupertuis and Buffon, believed that epigenesis could be assimilated

to a materialist approach to science and that it utilized mechanisms, even if it could

not be reduced to mechanism. Buffon’s   moule inte rieure   was a reformulation of 

Harvey’s formative faculty, a principle of design which was an emergent and whichthen set in motion determinate mechanisms of organic development.89 Buffon

invoked an analogy between his  ‘microforce’ and Newton’s characterization of grav-

ity.90 That became a consistent practice among all subsequent theorists of epigenesis.

Ironically enough, Haller’s pathbreaking work on irritability and sensibility rep-resented further elaborations of the very methodology which he found unacceptable

when called upon in support of epigenesis.91 In 1764 Caspar Friedrich Wolff, in

84 Ibid., 62–63.85 Herder (1887), and Zoller (1988), p. 81. See Zammito (2001a).86 Zoller (1988), p. 81. Blumenbach’s criticism of Wolff is recognized by all the major commentators

on his work. See, e.g., McLaughlin (1982); Jahn (1995).87 Roe (1979), p. 3 n.; Muller-Sievers (1993), (1997); Zammito (2001a).88 Harvey (1943), p. 366.89 Sloan (1979), p. 118.90 Lenoir (1981a), p. 123.91 Ibid., p. 135.

Page 15: This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

7/24/2019 This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/this-inscrutable-principle-of-an-original-organization 15/37

87 J.H. Zammito / Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 34 (2003) 73 – 109

what is taken to be the most important reformulation of epigenesis in the mid-eight-

eenth century, elaborated on all these elements. His   vis essentialis  was conceived as

a Newtonian force which induced through certain chemical processes the production

of organic matter out of inorganic matter in accordance with regular and empiricallydemonstrable patterns.92 Herder was drawing directly upon Wolff ’s work in articulat-

ing his idea of epigenesis in 1784, though he may have been aware as well of Blu-

menbach’s work on the  Bildungstrieb. It is important to note that in the 1780–1781

versions dealing with that concept, Blumenbach avoided the term   epigenesis, and

that he consistently sought to discriminate his idea from that of Wolff.93

A. C. Genova identifies three crucial elements in the concept of epigenesis in its

full-fledged form in the eighteenth century:   autonomy,   community   and   re fl exivity.94

In my terms, I would stress the radicality of emergence by replacing autonomy with

spontaneity. By   community   Genova signifies the mutuality of cause and effect and

of parts and whole which is central to the notion of organic form, especially as

Kant articulated it.  Re fl exivity,  finally, has to do with the self-regulating, self-forming

dimension as a persistent feature of life-forms, over and above the question of their

emergence  de novo. Each of these elements poses decisive challenges, methodolog-

ically and metaphysically, to a physical science on the sort of Newtonian foundations

Kant preferred. At the metaphysical end of this spectrum lie the problems of  radical

novelty   in a model that stresses systematic causal determination and, as well, of the

determinacy  of specific life forms: why there is so much regularity in a context of 

apparently radical freedom.95 At the methodological end of the spectrum lie the ques-

tions of empirical verifi

cation and of the degree and nature of mechanical executionof the self-organizing principle in the life forms. Blumenbach found Wolff problem-

atic as much—or more—for the metaphysical quandaries as for the methodological

ones. There is a high level of ambivalence and ambiguity in his critique of Wolff 

and in his assimilation of Kantian principles over the 1780s and early 1790s, such

that his own position has occasioned widely divergent reconstructions.96 There is

good reason to question whether his ultimate version of epigenesis diverged thatsubstantially from Wolff ’s, despite all his efforts to uphold a difference.97

That professed difference, nonetheless, proved central to Kant’s adoption of epi-

92 Wolff (1966); Roe (1979); Gaissinovich (1968); Aulie (1961); Duchesneau (1979); McLaughlin

(1982); Mocek (1995); Jahn (1995).93 Sloan (2002) notes Blumenbach’s aversion to the term epigenesis in his early texts on the   Bil-

dungstrieb  (Blumenbach, 1781, 1792).94 Genova (1974), p. 269.95 In his influential challenge to C. F. Wolff, Haller hit upon this:  ‘why does this  ‘vis essentialis’, which

is one only, form always and in the same places the parts of an animal which are so different, and always

upon the same model, if inorganic matter is susceptible of changes and is capable of taking all sorts of 

forms?’   (cited in Aulie (1961), p. 140).96 Thus different interpreters see Blumenbach moving towards vitalism or away from it, as achieving

the clear distinctions between constitutive and regulative that Kant required and as dissolving these, e.g.,

McLaughlin vs Lenoir on the  first, Lenoir vs Larson on the second (Larson, 1979, 1994).97 Most commentators are hard-pressed to uphold, though they clearly try to articulate what Blumenbach

thought distinguished himself from Wolff. For a good discussion, see McLaughlin (1982), pp. 365–367.

Page 16: This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

7/24/2019 This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/this-inscrutable-principle-of-an-original-organization 16/37

88   J.H. Zammito / Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 34 (2003) 73 – 109

genesis. But that is to leap ahead. First, we have to ask how it was that Kant could

even come to his new and now more famous analogy of transcendental philosophy

to  epigenesis  at B167 of the  first  Critique. What drew Kant to epigenesis at all? The

first answer is that Kant appropriated the term from Herder.98 He found it in a formthat was too radical for his taste, yet he believed that he could seize it from Herder

and make it stand precisely for his own position. All that required was a two-step

process. First, Kant had to insist that even epigenesis implied preformation: at the

origin there had to be some inexplicable (transcendent) endowment, and with it, in

his view, some determinate restriction in species variation. Thereafter, the organizedprinciples within the natural world could proceed on adaptive lines. This made  epi-

genesis  over into Kant’s variant of  preformation. Even so, this seemed to postulate

the objective   actuality   of these forces for natural science. Hence Kant faced the

ultimate need for a second step: to transpose the whole matter from the constitutive

to the regulative order. In his  Metaphysics lectures, Kant made the point succinctly:

‘The system of epigenesis does not explain the origin of the human body, but says

far more that we don’t know a thing about it’.99 This would be the position that

Kant would assume in the third Critique. But that came only in 1790. Let us consider

the famous passage at B167 in the 1787 version of the  first  Critique.

The argument of   §27 of the transcendental deduction in B (which includes the

passage at B167) is an elaboration of the argument of   §36 of the Prolegomena

(1783).100 In both arguments there was a purported disjunctive judgment: either

experience generates the categories or the categories generate experience. In both,

Kant stipulated that we  already know that the categories must be  a priori. Therefore,we must conclude that only the second option is really available. In the  Prolegomena

Kant called the   first simply   ‘self-contradictory’. In the B deduction, however, he

introduced the analogy to generatio aequivoca—spontaneous generation—which was

already an exploded idea in the natural science of the day.101 Zoller suggests that

the introduction of the analogy to biological theories was Kant’s response to criticism

98 Zoller (1988), p. 81.99 Kant,  Vorlesungen, AA 29, 761.

100 ‘[A] necessary agreement of the principles of possible experience with the laws of the possibility of 

nature can only proceed from one of two reasons: either these laws are drawn from nature by means of experience, or conversely nature is derived from the possibility of experience in general and is quite the

same as the mere universal conformity to law of the latter. The former is self-contradictory, for the

universal laws of nature can and must be cognized   a priori   (that is, independent of all experience) and

must be the foundation of all empirical use of the understanding; the latter alternative therefore alone

remains’   (Kant, 1783, AA 4, 319).   ‘There are only two ways in which we can account for a  necessary

agreement of experience with the concepts of its objects: either experience makes these concepts possible

or these concepts make experience possible. The former supposition does not hold in respect of the

categories (nor of pure sensible intuition); for since they are a priori concepts, and therefore independent

of experience, the ascription to them of an empirical origin would be a sort of  generatio aequivoca. There

remains, therefore, only the second supposition –  a system, as it were, of the  epigenesis  of pure reason  –

namely, that the categories contain, on the side of the understanding, the grounds of the possibility of 

experience in general’  (Kant, 1781/1787, B166–167).101 ‘Indeed, it might be argued that, had not epigenesis become popularly linked with espousal of spon-

taneous generation, it would have claimed majority support several decades earlier’  (Bodemer, 1964, 28).

Page 17: This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

7/24/2019 This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/this-inscrutable-principle-of-an-original-organization 17/37

89 J.H. Zammito / Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 34 (2003) 73 – 109

of the  first version of his deduction and an effort to make it more intuitively access-

ible by an empirical corollary.102

I wish to propose an alternative—or at least a supplementary—gloss. The clue to

the recourse to a biological analogy may well lie in the dramatic elaboration of whatwas simply an appendage to the original  Prolegomena  formulation. There, Kant had

added a footnote to the passage in   §36:   ‘Crusius alone thought of a compromise:

that a spirit who can neither err nor deceive implanted these laws in us originally’.103

In the B deduction, this afterthought was elaborated at length and in the main text

(but without mentioning Crusius):

A middle course may be proposed between the two above mentioned, namely, that

the categories are neither self-thought  first principles a priori of our knowledge nor

derived from experience, but subjective dispositions [ Anlagen] of thought,

implanted in us from the   first moment of our existence, and so ordered by our

Creator that their employment is in complete harmony with the laws of nature in

accordance with which experience proceeds—a kind of   preformation-system   of 

pure reason.104

What I want to highlight  first is Kant’s use of the term  preformation  with a clearly

negative   connotation.

The fundamental analogy structure at B167 invokes the disjunction:  either spon-

taneous generation or epigenesis; preformation is introduced in connection with the

misguided endeavor to insert a third, intermediate position. If the whole analogy wasto make Kant’s way of thinking more accessible to readers who were baf fled or put

off by his original formulation, this strategy seems strange. All the more so since

Kant did not explain   any  of his biological phrases; he simply presented them as if 

his readers would understand them unequivocally. That, however, is implausible both

for his contemporaries and for us. Granting that we all might share a general sense

of the impropriety of   ‘spontaneous generation’, the terms   epigenesis   and   prefor-

mation   were hardly transparent in the epoch and they have continued to mystify

commentators through this day.

An inadequate grasp of these terms has marred all treatment of Kant’s passage at

B167 until Phillip Sloan, even Zoller’s.105

The latter does, however, advance ourunderstanding of the particular usage of  preformation  at B167, by drawing attention

to the footnote in the  Prolegomena  and suggesting that it is not at all obvious that

Kant meant to invoke Leibniz or his doctrine of   ‘pre-established harmony’   at

B167.106 While I think his conclusion is false, what set Zoller on his course is con-

vincing. That is, Kant was quite clearly criticizing Crusius in the two passages. What

Zoller wishes to argue is that Crusius had articulated a position quite distinct from

102 Zoller (1988), p. 75.103 Kant (1783), AA 4, 319n.104 Kant (1781/1787), B167–168.105 Wubnig (1968/1969); Genova (1974); Zoller (1988); Ingensiep (1994); Sloan (2002).106 Zoller (1988), pp. 78–79.

Page 18: This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

7/24/2019 This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/this-inscrutable-principle-of-an-original-organization 18/37

90   J.H. Zammito / Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 34 (2003) 73 – 109

that of Leibniz, and hence it is misguided to think Kant was addressing himself to

Leibniz as well. While there are indeed differences between what Crusius argued

and Leibniz’s doctrine of   ‘pre-established harmony’, there are still very important

parallels. For readers of the day, the Leibnizian connection would have been inescap-able, Crusius (and Zoller) notwithstanding. More, as I will argue when we turn to

it, Kant’s formulation of preformation in the third  Critique  demonstrated a far more

explicitly Leibnizian orientation, which suggests we should stress—even in the earl-

ier text—the parallels for Kant between Leibniz and Crusius, and not the differences.

First of all, Leibniz personally subscribed to the old preformationism of encapsul-ation and saw it, moreover, as a striking confirmation of his general theory of pre-

established harmony.107 Second, Kant’s characterization of the Crusius view stressed

that the functioning of the categories implanted by God ran in perfect parallel to the

course of phenomena in the world of experience without any   real  interaction, thus

the intellectual order and the phenomenal order were in perfect   harmony. This is

Leibnizian to its core. What Kant harped on was the   subjective   twist that Crusius

gave to all this. The only warrant Crusius offered for the whole scheme was the

faith that God should have been so benign as to arrange all this for us. But, Kant

asserted, we could easily be mistaken, and furthermore, it was a dangerous precedent

to start down this path, because we could use analogues of this   ‘faith’   to obviate

any and all problems that might arise concerning cognitive validity. Kant’s whole

point against the intermediate position of Crusius was that we need a stronger bond

between the categories and experience if we are to take seriously the necessity that

is the essence of transcendental grounding. That bond could only be achieved if itwere  self-formed , not endowed, even by God. That is why he italicized the strange

term   self-thought   [selbstgedacht ]. That is why Kant suddenly invoked the idea of 

epigenesis. But that still does not resolve the problem.

In his   Metaphysics lectures  Kant left us some crucial evidence regarding how he

conceived the juxtaposition of  preformation  and  epigenesis.

In chemistry one distinguishes between matter   tanquam  eductum   (e.g., oxidized

potassium [Potassche Aschensalz] is an educt)—what was there before has only

taken on a new form, [and] tanquam productum, of which there was nothing there

before . . . The systems of human generation are 1)   involutionis   (encapsulation[ Einschachtelung] 2) epigenesis, [the claim] that humans are produced entirely

anew. In the first case man is an educt, in the second a product; if we have grounds

for accepting the system of epigenesis, then we should assume man is a product,—

 propagatio per traducem  would then transpire in the case of souls. Is it possiblethat the soul could produce other substances?  —This is contrary to  first principles,

for substances persist—and they would in that case have to be composite—and

the soul is a simple substance. The claim for a  propagatio per traducem is absurd

[ungereimt ] and has not the least concept of possibility . . .108

107 Roger (1968).108 Kant,  Vorlesungen, AA 28, 684.

Page 19: This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

7/24/2019 This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/this-inscrutable-principle-of-an-original-organization 19/37

91 J.H. Zammito / Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 34 (2003) 73 – 109

The same ground is covered in slightly different language in another set of notes

from the metaphysics lectures:

A substance [ Materie] is 1) an educt, that is what was once in another substancebut is now presented separately [; or] 2) A product, what before was not yet

present, but now is generated [erzeugt ] for the   first time . . . Whoever assumes

the soul is an educt . . . assumes the system of the preexistence of souls. Whoever

assumes the soul is the product of the parents believes in the system of propagation

. . . The systems of human generation are twofold: 1) involution (encapsulation[ Einschachtelung]): all children lay within their original parents, 2) epigenesis,

according to which humans, as far as bodies are concerned, are brought forth

entirely new. According to the   first, man is a mere educt (educt was already

present before birth, only in combination with other material, so that it appears

by disaggregation). If we have cause to assume the system of epigenesis, then

we also have cause to assume the soul as a product, because otherwise the soul

must have existed somewhere, and then become conjoined with the newly created

body. Thus here one would have to assume in connection with the soul a  propaga-

tio per traducem. But a substance cannot generate another substance, and the same

is true for the soul. A soul cannot put forth other souls from itself, for then it

would be a composite . . . To assume the propagation of human souls  per traducem

is absurd, because we do not know how to judge it at all. If the soul were a

product, then the souls of the parents would have a creative force [scho  pfende

Kraft ]. All generation of a substance is   productio ex nihilo, creation; becausebefore the substance there was nothing. A creature, however, does not itself have

a creative, but only a developmental [bildende] force, i.e., [the ability] to divide

or to compound things that are already given. There is no alternative, accordingly,

but to assume the soul is preformed [ pra  formiert ], however it may be with the

creation of the body.109

The student notes are not entirely coherent, but we can make certain clear inferences

from these two passages. First, Kant found the contrast of  educt  and  product  crucial

for his conceptualization.110 The difference between them is that in an educt all the

relevant material preexists, and only its aggregation is shuf fled, whereas in a product,altogether new things emerge, presumably by immanent processes ( per traducem).

Kant saw this as a mode of thought already established in chemistry and he clearly

saw the theories of generation in the life sciences as variants of the same method

of conceptualization. Thus there were, for him, only   two  theoretical possibilities for

the generation of bodies (or souls), namely preformation (the educt-theory) and epi-

genesis (the product-theory). Kant presented epigenesis in both sets of notes as a

hypothetical, not an  assertoric   judgment:   if  we have grounds for assuming the epi-

genesis theory,  then . . . Clearly, Kant was not committing himself to the hypothesis;

109 Kant,  Vorlesungen, AA 29, 760–761.110 It reappears in a crucial context: Kant (1790), AA 5, 423.

Page 20: This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

7/24/2019 This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/this-inscrutable-principle-of-an-original-organization 20/37

92   J.H. Zammito / Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 34 (2003) 73 – 109

he was not saying   ‘since  we have grounds . . .’   Indeed, if we are attentive to both

passages what emerges is that Kant in fact  rejected   this hypothesis, and therefore

rejected epigenesis, as he made clear especially at the close of the second passage:

‘there is no alternative but to assume the soul is preformed’. Zoller makes the pointthat Kant distinguished in his   Re fl exionen   between an   epigenesis psychologica   and

an   epigenesis intellectualis, and it is really the latter, the origin of the categories,

that is at issue at B167.111 That is altogether correct, yet what concerns me here is

not the question of the origin of the soul (a transcendent metaphysical concern,

according to orthodox interpretation of the critical philosophy) but rather the wayin which Kant conceived of preformation and epigenesis. My point is that in all this

material there is still nothing like an unequivocal af firmation of epigenesis, and we

are still not entitled to claim that we understand what Kant had in mind by the phrase

‘a system, as it were, of the  epigenesis  of pure reason’.

What could Kant possibly have been thinking at B167? Why, for the  first time,

would he have put preformation in a negative context and epigenesis in a remarkably

and unprecedentedly positive one? In terms of the educt/product distinction, we have

a clearer sense of what Kant thought the essential point of epigenesis was. But we

also see it as problematically creative or spontaneous, from Kant’s vantage, as ascrib-

ing too much power to mere created substances. That is, the metaphysical issue with

epigenesis was still hylozoism. Was there something that Kant now saw in the idea

of epigenesis that could help him elucidate the peculiar and essential spontaneity of 

the understanding in his transcendental deduction? What did the phrase  ‘self-thought 

first principles  a priori

’ signify? If epigenesis needs to be understood on the modelof a product, what were the necessary preconditions for immanent emergence? Kant

wanted to stress the difference between a Leibnizian sense of the innate  capacities

of mind and a Cartesian sense of innate   ideas.112 The categories themselves should

not be seen as preformed, but only as produced spontaneously by an innate  capacity

or  power —a  ‘faculty’  of mind, whose own origin was utterly inscrutable. Like New-

ton, Kant would, for convenience, employ the term  ‘force’  [Kraft ] in this metaphys-ical context, but he was happier with the idea of a   ‘principle’, precisely because of 

its ontological   ‘inscrutability’.

Spontaneity of the categories was not suf ficient for Kant’s transcendental

deduction, he also needed their constitutive sovereignty over experience. Theordering force of the innate (‘epigenetic’) powers of mind had to be ef ficacious in

empirical experience; it had to be able to  produce new knowledge (‘synthetic a priori

 judgments’). That is, it had to be a  real  cause (of knowledge), though a cause in a

sense different from what would be asserted within specific empirical judgments

regarding sensible intuition. Kant’s epigenesis analogy, in short, built intellectual

causation (determination; constitution) into the fundamental structure of the transcen-

dental deduction of the possibility of experience.

We have reason to suspect that Kant—however clear he may have been about

111 Zoller (1988), pp. 82–83.112 Genova (1974), p. 269; Zoller (1989), p. 227.

Page 21: This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

7/24/2019 This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/this-inscrutable-principle-of-an-original-organization 21/37

93 J.H. Zammito / Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 34 (2003) 73 – 109

what he wanted to accomplish in the transcendental deduction—may not have

grasped clearly what he was playing with in the analogy to epigenesis. Stealing it

from Herder may have gratified him; it may even have led him to an increased clarity

about the sort of spontaneity he needed for the origination and systematicity of hiscategories. But he really did not know the best literature in the life sciences on this

question, and he was especially ignorant of the revolution in thinking about this

phenomenon inaugurated by Blumenbach in 1781. When Kant did learn of it, he

had to rethink matters.

When did this happen, how, and with what consequences? We need to considerKant’s response to Forster in this light. Kant’s reference to Blumenbach in the foot-

note to ‘On the Use of Teleological Principles’ invoked the  Handbuch der Naturges-

chichte,  first edition, 1779, which Kant owned.113 As we know, Blumenbach revol-

utionized his thought shortly after publishing that work, developing his theory of the

 Bildungstrieb   in 1780/81. In that new work, Blumenbach strongly repudiated   any

sense   of germs [Keime].114 Thus, Kant’s invocation of Blumenbach in 1788 must

have proved an ambivalent experience for the latter, since Kant was invoking a

position he had already repudiated. On the other hand, in Kant’s footnote to Blumen-

bach in the 1788 essay we   find added the observation:   ‘this insightful man also

ascribes the  Bildungstrieb, through which he has shed so much light on the doctrine

of generation, not to inorganic matter but solely to the members of organic being ’.115

Thus, Kant had   some   acquaintance with Blumenbach’s term already in the fall of 

1787 when he composed the essay. Kant did not own the   first version of Blumen-

bach’s book, but ownership is a poor index of Kant

’s voracious reading. It is not atall impossible that Kant should have read it or about it. Blumenbach was clearly a

celebrity in the medical science of Germany in his day, so that his work would very

likely have appeared in bookshops in Konigsberg for the attention of the medical

faculty of that university. There would also have been reviews of the work, which

Kant may have encountered. In addition there were two Latin versions of Blumen-

bach’s work, one published in 1785 and a second in 1787.116 Kant did use the Ger-man term, and therefore the likelihood is that he was aware of the German version

of Blumenbach’s theory.

The important point, however, is that, whatever Kant may have know of Blumen-

bach’s  Bildungstrieb, he did not alter his own theory in any significant measure inhis essay of 1788. Most tellingly, he persisted in his use of  Keime. What is new—

or more developed—in the essay is the idea of purposiveness in connection with the

original endowments, and the criterion of purposiveness as a key to species variation

and adaptation. When we ask after the specific point for which Kant actually invoked

Blumenbach, it was to dismiss what in the   Critique of judgment   he would call a

‘daring adventure of reason’, namely the transformation of the great chain of being

113 Sloan (2002) recognizes the decisive significance of this.114 Blumenbach (1781); Sloan (2002).115 Kant (1788), AA 8, 180n.116 Blumenbach (1785, 1787).

Page 22: This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

7/24/2019 This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/this-inscrutable-principle-of-an-original-organization 22/37

94   J.H. Zammito / Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 34 (2003) 73 – 109

from a taxonomy to a phylogeny which had been raised by Forster.117 This   ‘widely

cherished notion preeminently advanced by Bonnet’, Kant was happy to report, came

under appropriate critical scrutiny in Blumenbach’s   Handbuch der Naturgesichte.118

Indeed, Blumenbach shared Kant’s skepticism about the genetic continuity of lifeforms. What bound them most together was their commitment to the fixity of species.

But how could the transmutationist implications of epigenesis be contained within

the limits of the   fixity of species? This was the essential question that Kant had

posed in his second essay on race in 1785, and the stakes of the question were not

small. Without some regulation in the history of generation, the prospect of thescientific reconstruction of the connection between current and originating species

[ Naturgeschichte, in Kant’s new sense, or the   ‘archaeology of nature’   as he would

call it in the third  Critique] would be altogether hopeless.

But it was not simply a   methodological   issue, however dire. There was also an

essential   metaphysical   component. When we read Kant’s highly charged language

in the 1785 essay on race we cannot but discern that again it is the idea of   hylo-

 zoism—of any radical spontaneity in matter itself —that Kant could not abide.119 All

organic form had to be fundamentally distinguished from mere matter. ‘Organization’demanded separate creation. Eternal inscrutability was preferable to any ‘speculative’

science. In the third   Critique   Kant would twice insist that no human could ever

achieve a mechanist  (he meant, as well, a  materialist ) account of so much as a  ‘blade

of grass’.120 Kant remained adamant that the  ultimate  origin of   ‘organization’  or of 

formative force required a   metaphysical, not a physical, account:   ‘How this stock 

[of  Keime] arose, is an assignment which lies entirely beyond the borders of humanlypossible   natural philosophy, within which I believe I must contain myself ’, Kant

wrote in 1788.121 He invoked Blumenbach for support in these  metaphysical   reser-

vations.122

In 1789 Blumenbach sent Kant a copy of the second edition of his essay on the

 Bildungstrieb, one which not only expounded its epigenetic aspects but also set it

in methodological terms that showed clearly the influence of Kant’s own argumentsabout distinguishing mechanical from teleological explanation. Blumenbach af firmed

this second book version with the advice to disregard his earlier,  ‘immature’  formu-

117 Kant (1790), AA 5, 419n. Forster (1786) had introduced something like this.118 Kant (1788), AA 8, 180n.119 ‘[I]f some magical power of imagination . . . were capable of modifying . . . the reproductive faculty

itself, of transforming Nature’s original model or of making additions to it, . . . we should no longer know

from what original Nature had begun, nor how far the alteration of that original may proceed, nor . . .

into what grotesqueries of form species might eventually be transmogrified . . . I for my part adopt it as

a fundamental principle to recognize no power . . . to meddle with the reproductive work of Nature . . .

[to] effect changes in the ancient original of a species in any such way as to implant those changes in

the reproductive process and make them hereditary’   (Kant, 1785b, AA 8, 97).120 Kant (1790), AA 5, 400, 409.121 Kant (1788), AA 8, 179.122 Ibid., 180 n.

Page 23: This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

7/24/2019 This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/this-inscrutable-principle-of-an-original-organization 23/37

95 J.H. Zammito / Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 34 (2003) 73 – 109

lations.123 What differences did he introduce? Perhaps most prominent was an

explicit Newtonian analogy.124 Second, as noted, Blumenbach showed awareness of 

the teleology/mechanism problem which Kant highlighted in the 1788 essay. That

is, in the 1789 version, Blumenbach was self-consciously assimilating his methodol-ogical presuppositions to Kant’s. Above all, Blumenbach repudiated hylozoism:  ‘No

one could be more totally convinced by something than I am of the mighty abyss

which nature has   fixed [befestigt ] between the living and the lifeless creation,

between the organized and the unorganized creatures’.125 This was what Kant found

most gratifying in the new book, as he reported in his letter of acknowledgmentto Blumenbach.126

By the time Kant came to write the crucial passage in the   Critique of judgment ,

then, we can presume that he was aware of Blumenbach’s sophisticated theory of 

epigenesis. One indication, as Phillip Sloan has noted, was that Kant suppressed any

mention of  Keime  in that work, though it still thronged with the term  Anlage.127 But

what progress had Kant made on the conundrum of preformation versus epigenesis?

It is important to distinguish two quite distinct sets of discriminations in the  Critique

of judgment  that both point back to B167, but with different implications. The  first

discriminations come in a footnote to  §80; the second come in the main text of  §81.

The footnote to  §80 evokes the familiar term generatio aequivoca in order, as before,

to disparage it. The contrast, however, is not to epigenesis or to preformation, but

rather to generatio univoca, which Kant further subdivides into  generatio homonyma

and  generatio heteronyma. While spontaneous generation was once again dismissed

as contradictory, Kant asserted that transmutation of species [generatio heteronyma]was not contradictory, only unfound in experience. Thus, the issue at stake in this

discrimination is the principle of the persistence of species. In   §81, however, we

come upon a different schematization. Here, Kant postulated that we must think of 

organisms on the analogy of an intelligent creation, and that when we do so we face

alternatives that can best be grasped   in terms drawn from metaphysics   (i.e., the

obverse of the analogy at B167). The categories Kant offered were:  occasionalism

and   prestabilism. He dismissed occasionalism as curtly as he had dismissed spon-

taneous generation (though, of course, for different reasons), and in turning to   ‘pre-

stabilism’  he distinguished two subsets:   individual preformation, which he identified

with the ‘theory of evolution’ (i.e., encapsulation) and termed an  ‘educt’, and generic

123 Blumenbach (1791), p. 13. But:  ‘In fact, the  only clear substantive difference in the key formulations

of the theory of the  Bildungstrieb  between the  ‘more mature’ and the  ‘immature’ phase is the replacement

of an   ‘innate’  drive by a   ‘general’  drive’  (McLaughlin, 1982, p. 371).124 ‘The term   Bildungstrieb   just like all other life forces such as sensibility and irritability explains

nothing itself, rather it is intended to designate a particular force whose constant effect is to be recognized

from the phenomena of experience, but whose cause, just like the causes of all other universally recognized

forces, remains for us an occult quality. That does not hinder us in any way whatsoever, however, from

attempting to investigate the effects of this force through empirical observations and to bring them under

general laws’  (Blumenbach, 1797, p. 19).125 Blumenbach (1789), p. 71.126 Kant to Blumenbach, August 5, 1790, Kant,  Briefwechsel, AA 11, 176–177.127 Sloan (2001) and (2002).

Page 24: This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

7/24/2019 This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/this-inscrutable-principle-of-an-original-organization 24/37

96   J.H. Zammito / Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 34 (2003) 73 – 109

 preformation, which Kant suggested was the proper sense of   epigenesis. That is,

while a   ‘product’, epigenesis   ‘still performed in accordance with the internally pur-

posive predispositions that were imparted to its stock ’.128 Kant expressed a clear

preference for epigenesis over individual preformation. What attracted him to epigen-esis, Kant averred succinctly, was that it entailed   ‘the least possible application of 

the supernatural’  in scientific theory.129 Hence even as he was prepared to advocate

epigenesis, Kant set strict limits upon it: ultimately this was still just  ‘generic prefor-

mation’, i.e., it, too, required the intervention of a  transcendent   causality.130

This is the decisive passage and it requires careful exegesis. First, it is apparentthat Kant reconfigured his whole conceptualization  under the aegis of preformation.

Second, there is no strict parallelism between the distinctions of   §80 and of   §81:

the distinction between   generatio homonyma   and   generatio heteronyma   does not

map neatly onto that between individual and generic preformation. That suggests

that a different point is being made in the latter distinction, and indeed this point

has to do with the character of the  causality that must be employed in conceptualizing

organic forms altogether, namely the inadequacy not merely of  mechanism but above

all of   materialism.131 Yet there is at least a measure of spillage between the two

patterns of discrimination, for Kant found the idea of the transmutation of species—

generatio heteronyma—to induce the very sorts of loose thinking in science that

might read  epigenesis  as hylozoism, as a  vital  materialism. It was this above all that

he wished to circumvent, both with his ontological argument that even epigenesis

depended upon an original creation which instilled organization into inert matter,

and with his methodological argument that an empirical science of life forms couldonly work with maxims of reflective judgment imputing purposiveness, and thus that

the very idea of a natural purpose was merely a heuristic  fiction suited to our limited

reason. It was just these elements in Blumenbach’s new work on the  Bildungstrieb

which Kant found so gratifying. The leading life scientist of the day seemed to be

af firming just the same metaphysical and methodological discriminations he him-

self demanded.But what is also clear, as Sloan has argued, is that Kant had still not come to

terms with the implications for his analogy between epigenesis and transcendental

philosophy.132 If epigenesis signified what Blumenbach was urging, then the security

of   Keime, with their determinate restrictions on species change in biology, wouldhave to be forsaken. And, by analogy, the implications for Kant’s transcendental

grounding of the categories would be similarly grave. Kant certainly essayed to trans-

fer all the metaphysical weight to his notion of   Anlagen, but it is not clear that

this is consistent with Blumenbach’s theory or with the full-fledged epigenesis that

it implied.

Epigenesis incites a fundamental erosion of Kant’s boundary between the consti-

128 Kant (1790), AA 5, 423.129 Ibid., 424.130 Ibid., 423.131 Genova (1974), p. 465; Zoller (1988), p. 90.132 Sloan (2001) and (2002).

Page 25: This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

7/24/2019 This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/this-inscrutable-principle-of-an-original-organization 25/37

97 J.H. Zammito / Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 34 (2003) 73 – 109

tutive and the regulative, between the transcendental and the empirical: a naturalism

beyond anything Kant could countenance, though his own thought carried him there.

With epigenesis, the  ‘order of nature’   is greater than the order of Kant’s version of 

Newtonian physics, and the paradigm for science necessarily exceeds the  ‘Newtoni-an’   constraints Kant wished to impose upon it.133 His demand that the life sciences

submit to the methodological principles of his   ‘Newtonianism’  (as in his critique of 

Herder and his dispute with Forster, and above all in his Preface to the  Metaphysical

 foundations of natural science) was misguided.134 To be consistent, what Kant had

to do was to  disqualify his conception of  ‘Newtonian’ science in order to make roomfor the ontological possibility of life forces.135 Of course Kant’s escape was to sug-

gest an epistemological evasion of this unpalatable ontological prospect. He argued

for the  ‘irreducibility  of biology to physics’  (Zumbach) but not because ontological

reductionism was unacceptable. Indeed, it  was  possible—though not comprehensible

by   finite human reason—that there could be a physico-chemical basis for organic

forms.136 Indeed, Kant went further and supported the   methodological   program to

seek reduction to mechanical explanation.137 However, he argued that just here the

methodological program would come up against an insuperable   epistemological

stumbling block —grounded in the limitations of human reasoning, not in the   ‘order

of nature’   itself.138 Zumbach phrases it suitably:   ‘Kant’s claim that there are free

causes in living processes is elliptical. He is actually claiming that living processes

must be viewed in terms of the   idea  of a free cause’.139 That is an  epistemological

strategy, a heuristic, not a fact. In Kantian terms, there is a subjective necessity—a

‘need of reason

’—for this move, but no objective necessity, no natural law evidentin the matter at hand (the  ‘order of nature’).140 This is the famous argument of Kant’s

Dialectic of Teleological Judgment, and his resolution is that in order to make organic

forms intelligible at all we must have recourse to the analogy of purpose or design.141

Kant transposes his metaphysical problem into a methodological one, his ontological

133 And thus his effort to   ‘police’   the practices of the experimental physics of his day was unavailing.

See Zammito (1998).134 Kant (1786), AA 4, 467–469 and passim.135 ‘Whilst the extensionalist mathematical Newtonian approach offers the potential for (mathematical)

a priori processing of physical nature, the price which this pays is that since forces do not have in thisscheme any basic or   ‘essential’   place, they have (because of the conceptual doubt attaching to them) to

be introduced ad hoc (from  ‘without’), by way of hypothesis only. The objection to this, of course, . . .[is]

that such a basic and powerful notion as force (let alone the force of attraction) ought not to be surrounded

with the suspicion which—particularly during the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries—surrounded any-

thing   ‘hypothetical’   in science’  (Buchdahl, 1986, 150–1).136 Kant (1790), AA 5, 388.137 Ibid., 417–418.138 Ibid., 382.139 Zumbach (1984), p. 99.140 ‘[T]his claim has a decidedly negative import; it is essentially just an af firmation that the mechanical

conception of nature and its conception of causality fails to provide a complete characterization of living

systems . . . Thus, the claim that there are free causes in living systems has no ontological force. It is

rather a transcendental claim, i.e., one concerning the possibility of our judgments’  (ibid., 107).141 Kant (1790), AA 5, 405–410.

Page 26: This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

7/24/2019 This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/this-inscrutable-principle-of-an-original-organization 26/37

98   J.H. Zammito / Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 34 (2003) 73 – 109

need into an epistemological constraint:  ‘nature [i.e, the ‘order of nature’ as a system]

can only be understood as meaningful if we take it at large to be designed’.142 That

is,   ‘we need to be able to comprehend all of nature, not as a living being, but as a

rational analog of a living being’.143

3.   ‘Looseness of fit’ in Kant’s philosophy of science

As Robert Butts has noted,   ‘It is only in the   Critique of judgment   that [Kant]comes to deal with science, not as a  finished system, but as a research program’.144

That is, Kant came to take seriously the problem of empirical entailment, in which

rather than merely   prescribing   to nature, human inquiry had to   presume   and then

seek out  an   ‘order’   that was somehow already available for discovery and compre-

hension.145 Kant never doubted that concrete empirical laws would need to be found,

not simply made. More, he took seriously the   finitude of human intellect and sus-

pected that the establishment not only of particular empirical laws but especially

also their integration into a higher order system would be a   task   that might well

exceed forever a human grasp. At the same time, however, Kant did insist that genu-

ine natural   science   would have to claim some kind of universality and necessity,

those traits he associated with the   a priori. We must recollect that one of the ways

in which Kant characterized his critical project in philosophy was precisely to dem-

onstrate how synthetic a priori judgments of natural science were possible.146 Some-

how, empirical laws needed to be  grounded —

or, in Buchdahl’s more tolerant formu-lation,   ‘nested’—in the transcendental a priori principles through which alone

experience was possible for humans while, at the same time, these empirical laws

could not simply be  deduced  from a priori principles of reason.147

The   ‘mixed status’  of empirical laws and the question of the possibility of their

systematicity became, accordingly, central issues for Kant’s philosophy of science.148

It was by distinguishing between   ‘transcendental lawlikeness’, established by Kantin the transcendental analytic of the first Critique, and ‘empirical lawlikeness’, which

Kant explored under the rubric of the   ‘hypothetical use of reason’  in the transcen-

dental dialectic of that work and then under the rubric of   ‘reflective judgment’   in

142 Butts (1990), p. 5.143 Ibid., p. 7; McLaughlin (1990).144 Butts (1990), p. 1.145 Kant (1790), AA 5, 183; Buchdahl (1965), (1967), (1969).146 Kant (1783), AA 4, 294–326.147 ‘[T]he pure faculty of understanding, through mere categories, does not suf fice to prescribe any a

priori laws to appearances other than those on which  a nature in general, as lawfulness of experience in

space and time, depends. Particular laws, since they concern empirically determined appearances, can  not 

be completely derived   from those, although they all stand under them’  (Kant, 1781/1787, B165).   ‘To be

sure empirical laws, as such, can by no means derive their origin from pure understanding . . . But all

empirical laws are only particular determinations of the pure laws of the understanding, under which and

according to whose norm they are all  first possible’  (Kant, 1781/1787, A127–8).148 Guyer (1990a), (1990b); Morrison (1989).

Page 27: This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

7/24/2019 This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/this-inscrutable-principle-of-an-original-organization 27/37

99 J.H. Zammito / Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 34 (2003) 73 – 109

its teleological use in the third   Critique, that Gerd Buchdahl sought to make sense

of this whole problematic in terms of   ‘looseness of  fit’.149

Michael Friedman, while acknowledging the power and persuasiveness of Buch-

dahl’s interpretation, nevertheless raises some very important reservations. He setsout from what Buchdahl seemed to have established, namely that   ‘the law-govern-

edness of nature under universal transcendental laws of the understanding does not

at all guarantee that nature is also governed by particular empirical laws’.150 But

then he invokes the peculiar   ‘mixed status’   of empirical laws, which in virtue of 

their empirical character have to be  contingent , but in virtue of their status as lawshave somehow to   claim necessity.151 For Friedman this means that Kant had to

uphold the  ‘claim that particular empirical laws are somehow made possible by—are

grounded in or determined by—the transcendental principles’.152 The crucial point is

that  ‘even empirical laws too must have a more than merely inductive status’.153 The

problem is, Friedman acknowledges, that   ‘we are left quite in the dark concerning

the precise nature of this   ‘grounding’.’154

While Buchdahl appeared to resort   entirely   to the regulative role of reason and

to the transcendental principle of teleological judgment, and thus to the demand for

systematicity in Kant’s conceptualization of reason as the faculty of ideas, Friedman

believes this unduly restricts the role of the understanding and of the transcendental

principles of objective experience that Kant had worked out in the transcendental

analytic of the  first   Critique  and which Kant always believed represented the most

important insight he had obtained into theoretical reason. Friedman urges that to go

all the way with Buchdahl is to eviscerate the faculty of understanding in Kant’stheory of knowledge.   ‘Indeed, not only is the understanding entirely powerless with

respect to particular empirical concepts and particular empirical laws, but the search

for such concepts and laws lies rather within the purely regulative province of reflec-

tive judgment’.155 This could not be quite right, Friedman argues, and he therefore

urges the restoration of scope to the properly  constitutive domain of knowledge, over

against the merely  regulative, or, in other terminology, to  determinant , over against

re fl ective, judgment.156 Friedman recognizes an important duality in Kant’s notion

of   ‘constitutivity’.

149 Buchdahl (1965), (1967), (1969), etc.150 Friedman (1992a), p. 167.151 Thus, Kant was careful always to write that we view empirical laws as necessary and universal; this

in contrast to simply knowing it. See Kant (1783), AA 4, 312.152 Friedman (1992a), pp. 171–172.153 Ibid., p. 172.154 Ibid., p. 174.155 Friedman (1991), p. 76.156 Nevertheless, he does so in a manner which I would contend is far closer to Buchdahl than Friedman

and his critics seem to admit. Buchdahl, that is, seems to invoke some sense of  ‘application’  of the same

categories in empirical laws which are involved in the transcendental constitution of the object in general.

It is not clear that Buchdahl wants or needs to ascribe all  the  ‘nesting’ of levels of validity to systematicity.

Page 28: This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

7/24/2019 This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/this-inscrutable-principle-of-an-original-organization 28/37

100   J.H. Zammito / Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 34 (2003) 73 – 109

Kant’s solution . . . is thus to distinguish two senses of constitutivity. The math-

ematical concepts and principles (of quantity and quality) are constitutive with

respect to intuition. The dynamical concepts and principles are constitutive with

respect to experience but only regulative with respect to intuition. The ideas of reason, on the other hand, are not even constitutive with respect to experience:

they are   purely   regulative.157

Holding out for the  constitutive  role of the principles of the understanding in the

formation of empirical laws, Friedman concentrates on the role Kant assigned toNewtonian physics.158 Friedman holds that Kant not only assigned to Newton’s law

of universal gravitation a special status as an  a priori   universal and necessary law,

but that in his account of how that law got constituted for human reason Kant laid

out as clearly as he ever managed exactly how such promotion to a priori status

could be possible for an  empirical   judgment.159

To be sure, there was an ineluctably empirical moment—in this instance, the

empirical concept of   matter —but what Friedman shows is that Kant believed that

in the dynamic of reasoning from the merely empirical generalizations of Kepler’s

laws through the three laws of mechanics to Newton’s law of universal gravitation

he could demonstrate the advance from the modality of possibility through that of 

actuality to the essential domain of necessity.160 Therewith, Friedman argues, Kant

had established

the constitutive principles of determinative judgement are also of fundamentalimportance in articulating the content of at least some empirical concepts. Indeed,

in the case of the empirical concept of matter, it is the constitutive procedure of 

determinative judgement alone that renders it   ‘a priori suitable for application to

outer experience’.161

Thus, Friedman concludes,   ‘the constitutive principles of the understanding extendto the very highest genus and very highest law of empirical natural science: the

empirical concept of matter and the law of universal gravitation’.162 These represent

a   ‘special metaphysic’   in Kant’s  critical  sense, namely a construction grounded in

transcendental principles but applied to a general empirical concept.163

157 Friedman (1991), p. 79.158 E.g. Buchdahl (1965), p. 207, (1971), pp. 34–44 and (1986) recognized that the Newtonian laws

were the crucial case for Kant. See also Buchdahl (1970) and Friedman (1990).159 ‘[T]he Newtonian derivation of the law of universal gravitation precisely illustrates the procedure of 

transforming mere   ‘empirical rules’   into necessary   ‘laws’   . . .’   (Friedman, 1991, p. 85).160 Friedman (1992a), pp. 177–180. On the relation of  transcendental to  metaphysical expositions, much

is revealed in the passage from A66 already cited: pure concepts  ‘on the occasion of experience, develop

and through exactly the same understanding are displayed in their purity, freed from their attending

empirical conditions’  (my italics).161 Friedman (1991), p. 82.162 Ibid., p. 90.163 Buchdahl (1986).

Page 29: This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

7/24/2019 This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/this-inscrutable-principle-of-an-original-organization 29/37

101 J.H. Zammito / Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 34 (2003) 73 – 109

Two concerns arise. First, there is no guarantee that the development of empirical

science  ‘from below’  will converge neatly with that  ‘top down’   structure established

by Kant’s metaphysics of Newtonian science.164 For, as Friedman observes,

all the rest of empirical natural science remains solely within the regulative pur-

view of reason and reflective judgement, the aim of which is to ascend from lower

level empirical concepts and laws towards ever more general empirical concepts

and laws so as eventually (in prospect) to attain a complete classificatory and

hierarchical system . . . under the highest level empirical concept and law alreadyconstituted as such in the  Metaphysical foundations of natural science.165

This is the notorious problem of a   ‘gap’  in the critical system that from at least the

time of the  Critique of judgment   haunted the Kantian enterprise.166

More drastically still, there was something in the very   ‘top down’  constitution of 

the   ‘Newtonian’  metaphysical principles that threatened   in principle   the   ‘necessary

convergence of constitutive and regulative procedures . . . absolutely essential to

Kant’s entire project’.167 This second point arises because Kant purchased the deter-

minacy of his metaphysical principles at a significant cost. The binding constraint

of the concept of matter he adopted in the   Metaphysical foundations of natural

science   was that the laws he generated could apply   only   to outer sense. This   ‘has

the effect of restricting our attention to nonliving material substances’.168 This was

a dramatic  restriction   in scope relative to the transcendental principles, which held

for all aspects of possible experience, including   inner sense. As Friedman notes,

Thus, the metaphysical principles of pure natural science apply only to the activi-

ties and powers of nonliving, nonthinking beings: beings represented solely

through predicates of outer sense. The transcendental principles of the understand-

ing, by contrast, apply to all beings without distinction—where, for example, inner

principles of causality (appropriate to living beings) are just as permissible asexternal causes.169

Friedman elaborates:  ‘only thinking beings—or, more generally, living beings—pos-

sess  inner  principles of causality’.170

But by defining matter as essentially  lifeless  inorder to construe Newton’s inertia, Kant excluded all such aspects  in principle  from

conformity to the metaphysical foundations of natural science, and hence precluded

164 ‘So what assurance do we have that the regulative operation of reason and reflective judgement will,

proceeding from the bottom up, actually converge in the direction of this already constituted higher level?’

(Friedman, 1991, p. 94).165 Ibid., pp. 90–91.166 Forster (1987).167 Friedman (1991), p. 95.168 Friedman (1992a), p. 185.169 Ibid., p. 182.170 Ibid.

Page 30: This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

7/24/2019 This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/this-inscrutable-principle-of-an-original-organization 30/37

102   J.H. Zammito / Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 34 (2003) 73 – 109

by definition any empirical (‘bottom up’) integration of empirical concepts and laws

in these domains which could converge with the   ‘top down’   foundation of his

science.171

It is here that Henry Allison makes a telling criticism of Friedman’s reconstruction.Allison takes up Friedman’s claim that   ‘transcendental principles have a greater

scope than the metaphysical principles, since the former apply to all entities in the

phenomenal world, including living and thinking things, while the latter  ‘apply only

to the activities and powers of nonliving, nonthinking beings’,’   but he alleges that

Friedman   ‘effectively denies [the] significance’  of this difference.172 Friedman pro-ceeds as if the determinations expressed in the metaphysical principles must hold

ubiquitously for the scientific ‘lawlikeness’ of an empirical  ‘order of nature’.173 This,

Allison correctly observes, precludes the extension of science to the domain of inner

sense. Indeed, there is considerable textual evidence that this was Kant’s own view,

not simply Friedman’s inference.174 But there is a more drastic implication which

Allison does not raise: not just a science of  ‘inner sense’, such as psychology, but any

science involving  ‘internal purposiveness’  becomes irreconcilable with  ‘Newtonian’

science. Indeed, this is the point toward which my whole exposition has been aiming,

for it brings into glaring salience the problem of reconciling biology   at all   with

Kant’s prescriptions for science. Organisms rupture the  ‘top down’ / ’bottom up’  inte-

gration of Kant’s scientific system.

I think it is essential to dwell for a moment on Kant ’s suggestion that there is a

radical incongruity  between his notion of organic form as   ‘intrinsic purposiveness’

and the conventions of natural science:  ‘

its form is not possible according to merenatural laws, i.e., those laws which can be cognized by us through the understanding

alone when applied to objects of sense’.175 First, in Buchdahl’s terms, is Kant here

addressing   ‘transcendental lawlikeness’   or only   ‘empirical lawlikeness?’176 Given

that it is   ‘understanding alone . . . applied to objects of sense’, one might infer the

most extreme construction that  organisms are incoherent according to the transcen-

dental possibility of objective experience.177 But let us settle for the weaker claim:organisms are not amenable to empirical laws after the fashion of mechanism:   ‘It is

171 ‘The inertia of matter is and signifies nothing but its lifelessness, as matter in itself. Life means the

capacity of a substance to determine itself to act from an internal principle, of a   finite substance todetermine itself to change, and of a material substance to determine itself to motion or rest as change of 

its state. Now, we know of no other internal principle of a substance to change its state but desire and

no other internal activity whatever but thought . . .’   (Kant, 1786, AA 4, 544).172 ‘I think it is fair to say that for Friedman the transcendental principles stand in roughly the same

relationship to the metaphysical principles as the categories stand to their schemata. Just as the schemata,

as transcendental determinations of time, both realize the categories and restrict the range of their appli-

cation to what is given in sensible intuition, so the metaphysical principles, by linking their transcendental

correlates to the empirical concept of matter, both ensure their applicability to corporeal nature, qua

merely corporeal, and limit this applicability to the same sphere’   (Allison, 1994, p. 295).173 Ibid.174 See Kant (1786), AA 4, 471.175 Kant (1790), AA 5, 370.176 Buchdahl (1971).177 Lenoir (1981a), p. 149, recognizes this radical possibility.

Page 31: This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

7/24/2019 This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/this-inscrutable-principle-of-an-original-organization 31/37

103 J.H. Zammito / Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 34 (2003) 73 – 109

indeed quite certain that we cannot even become suf ficiently knowledgeable of, much

less provide an explanation of organized beings and their internal possibility accord-

ing to mere mechanical principles of nature’.178 What does  ‘internal possibility’  sig-

nify here? How does it relate to the   ‘real possibility’   which Buchdahl and othersinsist it is Kant’s main object as philosopher of science to establish?179 And what are

we to make of the distinction Kant introduces between knowledge and  explanation in

this passage? Is  ‘knowledge’ an  intelligibility which we can distinguish from determi-

nate constitution   (‘explanation’)—i.e., is this a formulation of the

regulative/constitutive distinction?180

Robert Butts provides us with some fruitful ideas here. He sets out from the notion

that for any actually practiced science there are always  ‘recalcitrant particulars’, that

is,   ‘items in experience that cannot be fully understood, and for which no specific

theoretical concepts are ready at hand’.181 To make sense of them, Butts suggests,

we need to resort to   judgment . That is, we work   ‘from below’   to reintegrate these

anomalies   into our reigning   paradigm   (to use Kuhnian terms and invoke Kuhnian

implications).182 My point is, some anomalies prove   so   ‘recalcitrant’   that it is not

they but the paradigm that will require adjustment or even abandonment.

Butts notes that there is a peculiar uniformity among many of the   ‘recalcitrant

particulars’  in Kant’s scheme of things, namely their association with  design  or  pur-

 pose. To become in the least intelligible, Butts continues, these anomalies ‘all presup-

pose an understanding of purposiveness modeled on human purposive action’.183

Quite simply, we conceive of organic forms as purposive without purpose; we impute

design but deny a designer (to ascribe literal design would indeed fall back into fl

atanimism). Here Butts recognizes something that has not occasioned enough attention:

Kant’s characterization of these anomalies   ‘reflects reliance on perfect knowledge

of our own purposive behavior’.184 That is,   ‘basic to Kant’s treatment of teleology

is the unquestioned assumption that we have an already perfect understanding of 

human purposive action because we ourselves act purposively’.185 To claim that the

projection of design or purposiveness enables us to make organic forms intelligibleis to claim that purpose can be transparently comprehensible for the human intellect.

But are we warranted in this comfortable self-interpretation? What Butts implies,

and what I wish to stress, is that this presumption may be unjustified.

Indeed, purpose-thinking—the very form of viewing human practice as causal by

178 Kant (1790), AA 5, 400.179 Buchdahl (1974), (1981), (1986).180 Zumbach suggests that and more:   ‘there is an a priori principle absent from the mechanical view of 

nature which the biological point of view instantiates’  (Zumbach, 1984, p. 80). But this is to suggest that

this transcendental principle bears upon   theoretical  reason, not  practical   reason, and has to do with cog-

nition, not just (rational) belief. Here we need to resort to Buchdahl and the discrimination of  ‘subjective’

from   ‘objective’  necessity.181 Butts (1990), p. 2.182 Kuhn (1970).183 Butts (1990), p. 3.184 Ibid., p. 5.185 Ibid., p. 15 n.

Page 32: This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

7/24/2019 This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/this-inscrutable-principle-of-an-original-organization 32/37

104   J.H. Zammito / Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 34 (2003) 73 – 109

design—is as much a function of the limitations of human discursive reasoning as

causal thinking of the specific sort Kant described in the dialectic of teleological

 judgment.186 How it is possible for us to have purpose is no more theoretically

transparent than it is for organisms to  appear  purposive for us.  We, after all, are yetsome organic forms among others. That suggests that objectively we are fully as

mysterious as any other organisms. The whole structure of purposiveness rests upon

the presumption of the ontological coherence—the real possibility—of  ‘intrinsic pur-

posiveness’—or, in other language, an   ‘end in itself ’—acting ef ficaciously in the

phenomenal world. While it is possible to   ‘think ’   this, and to think ourselves underthat concept, it is by no means clear that it can play any theoretical role whatsoever.

The very possibility of reasoning   by analogy with   this presumed character of 

human action, upon which teleological judgment is founded, presupposes the real

possibility or objective reality of humans as such ends in themselves: a  theoretical

matter. What I wish to suggest is that Kant’s argument for the very intelligibility of 

organic forms presses to the verge of an  ontological  claim what he asserts can only

be a  practical  one. Kant is comfortable with this precisely because (though he does

not claim to know it determinately) he presumes that we are in fact endowed with

a soul. To use Kant as cruelly with his own words as he wished to use Herder in

penning them: is this not to seek to understand what we do not know by invoking

what we know even less?187 Either Kant must entertain the   ‘objective reality’   of 

some   end in iself, some actual purpose—as an   ontological   matter—or his whole

system of analogy in teleological judgment—the invocation of the causality of ideas

as a model—

simply lacks any warrant.But that does not put the point perspicuously enough. For us, it is not merely the

theoretical possibility of making sense of the   ‘order of nature’  as a rational system

accessible to our intelligence, a merely  epistemological  concern, but the  ontological

 possibility  of  beings like us—intrinsic purposes—in an   ‘order of nature’   that is ulti-

mately at stake. What we have tumbled upon is a nest of Kant’s most adamant

metaphysical commitments—to the possibility of moral freedom and therewith tothe compatibility of moral freedom with causal order in physical nature—and his

compulsion to limit understanding to make room for faith. The problem of organic

form—because we are caught up in it at our most fundamental   ontological, not

simply epistemological essence—brings all this into urgent articulation. In the wordsof the Introduction to Kant’s   Critique of judgment   which I take as the clearest

expression of his ultimate philosophical concerns:

186 ‘[T]his maxim of the reflecting power of judgment is essential for those products of nature which

must be judged only as intentionally formed thus and not otherwise, in order to obtain even an experiential

cognition of their internal constitution; because even the thought of them as organized things is impossible

without associating the thought of a generation with an intention’  (Kant, 1790, AA 5, 398).  ‘[W]e under-

stand completely only that which we ourselves can make and bring about in accordance with concepts.

Organization, however, as the internal end of nature, infinitely surpasses all capacity for a similar presen-

tation by art . . .’   (ibid., 383).   ‘Strictly speaking, the organization of nature is therefore not analogous

with any causality that we know’  (ibid., 375).187 Kant (1785), AA 8, 53–54.

Page 33: This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

7/24/2019 This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/this-inscrutable-principle-of-an-original-organization 33/37

105 J.H. Zammito / Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 34 (2003) 73 – 109

[A]n immense gulf is   fixed between the domain of the concept of nature, the

sensible, and the domain of the concept of freedom, the supersensible, so that no

transition from the sensible to the supersensible (and hence by means of the theor-

etical use of reason) is possible, just as if they were two different worlds, the  firstof which cannot have any influence on the second; and yet the second   is  to have

an influence on the  first, i.e., the concept of freedom is to actualize in the world

of sense the purpose enjoined by its laws. Hence it must be possible to think of 

nature as being such that the lawfulness in its form will harmonize with at least

the possibility of [achieving] purposes that we are to achieve in nature accordingto the laws of freedom.188

In short, Kant’s theory of organic form can only be contained within the critical

system by the kind of radical disjunction between transcendental lawlikeness and

empirical lawlikeness that Buchdahl has striven to establish, and yet its purport is

even more profound, for it betokens Kant’s ultimate metaphysical need to make

room for the possibility of freedom and hence for human moral actualization.

References

Adickes, E. (1924).  Kant als Naturforscher . Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

Allison, H. (1991). Kant’s antinomy of teleological judgment.   Southern Journal of Philosophy,

30(Supplement   System and teleology in Kant ’s  Critique of judgment), 25–42.

Allison, H. (1994). Causality and causal laws in Kant: A critique of Michael Friedman. In P. Parrini(Ed.),  Kant and contemporary epistemology   (pp. 291–308). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

Aulie, R. (1961). Caspar Friedrich Wolff and his   ‘Theoria generationis’, 1759.  Journal of the History of 

 Medicine,   16 , 124–144.

Barnaby, D. (1988). The early reception of Kant’s   Metaphysical foundations of natural science. In R.

Woolhouse (Ed.),  Metaphysics and philosophy of science in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries

(pp. 281–306). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

Beddoes, T. (1815).  Observations on the nature and cure of calculus, sea scurvy, consumption, catarrh,

and fever. Together with conjectures upon several other subjects of physiology and pathology. Philad-

elphia: Webster.

Bernasconi, R. (2001a). Who invented the concept of race? Kant’s role in the Enlightenment’s construction

of race. In R. Bernasconi (Ed.),  Race   (pp. 11–36). Oxford: Blackwell.

Bernasconi, R. (2001b). Kant and Blumenbach on the Bildungstrieb. Paper presented at the Conferenceof the American Society of Eighteenth-Century Studies, New Orleans, April, 2001.

Blumenbach, J. F. (1779).  Handbuch der Naturgeschichte. Gottingen: Dieterich.

Blumenbach, J. F. (1781).  U ¨ ber den Bildungstrieb und das Zeugungsgescha  fte.  Gottingen: Dieterich.

Blumenbach, J. F. (1785).  De Nisu formativo et generationis negotio nuperae observationes. N.p.

Blumenbach, J. F. (1787).  De nisu formativo et generationis negotio nuperae observationes. Gottingen:

Dieterich.

Blumenbach, J. F. (1789).  U ¨ ber den Bildungstrieb. Gottingen: Dieterich.

Blumenbach, J. F. (1791).  Handbuch der Naturgeschichte   (4th ed.). Gottingen: Dieterich.

Blumenbach, J. F. (1792).  An essay on generation  (A. Crichton, Trans.). London: Cadell.

Blumenbach, J. F. (1797).  Handbuch der Naturgeschichte. 5th Edition. Gottingen: Dieterich.

188 Kant (1790), AA 5, 176.

Page 34: This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

7/24/2019 This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/this-inscrutable-principle-of-an-original-organization 34/37

106   J.H. Zammito / Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 34 (2003) 73 – 109

Bodemer, C. (1964). Regeneration and the decline of preformationism in eighteenth-century embryology.

 Bulletin of the History of Medicine,   38 , 20–31.

Breidenbach, O. (1995). Die Geburt des Lebendigen—Embryogenese der Formen oder Embryologie der

Natur?—

Anmerkungen zum Bezug von Embryologie und Organismustheorien vor 1800.  Biologisches Zentralblatt ,   114, 191–199.

Buchdahl, G. (1965). Causality, causal laws and scientific theory in the philosophy of Kant. British Journal

 for Philosophy of Science,   16 , 187–208.

Buchdahl, G. (1967). The relation between   ‘understanding’   and   ‘reason’   in the architectonic of Kant’s

philosophy.  Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society,   67 , 209–226.

Buchdahl, G. (1969a). The Kantian   ‘dynamic of reason’, with special reference to the place of causality

in Kant’s system. In L. W. Beck (Ed.),  Kant studies today   (pp. 341–374). La Salle, IL: Open Court.

Buchdahl, G. (1969b).   Metaphysics and the philosophy of science: The classical origins: Descartes to

Kant . Cambridge: MIT Press.

Buchdahl, G. (1970). Gravity and intelligibility: Newton to Kant. In R. E. Butts, & J. Davis (Eds.),  The

methodological heritage of Newton   (pp. 74–102). Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

Buchdahl, G. (1971). The conception of lawlikeness in Kant’s philosophy of science. Synthese, 23, 24–46.Buchdahl, G. (1974). Transcendental reduction: A concept for the interpretation of Kant’s critical method.

In G. Funke (Ed.),   Akten des 4. Internationalen Kant-Kongresses Mainz 6  – 10. April 1974   (Vol. 1,

pp. 28–44). Berlin & New York: Walter de Gruyter.

Buchdahl, G. (1981). Reduction-realization: a key to the structure of Kant’s thought. Philosophical Topics,

12, 39–98.

Buchdahl, G. (1984). Zum Verhaltnis von allgemeiner Metaphysik der Natur und besonderer meta-

physischer Naturwissenschaft bei Kant. In B. Tuschling (Ed.),  Probleme der   ‘Kritik der reinen Ver-

nunft ’   (pp. 97–142). Berlin & New York: Walter de Gruyter.

Buchdahl, G. (1986). Kant’s   ‘special metaphysics’  and the  Metaphysical foundations of natural science.

In R. E. Butts (Ed.),  Kant ’s philosophy of physical science   (pp. 121–161). Dordrecht: Reidel.

Butts, R. E. (1990). Teleology and scientific method in Kant’s  Critique of judgment .  Nous,  24, 1–16.

Butts, R. E. (1991). Comments on Michael Friedman:  ‘Regulative and constitutive’.  Southern Journal of 

Philosophy,  30(Supplement   System and teleology in Kant ’s  Critique of judgment), 103–108.

Dawson, V. (1991). Regeneration, parthenogenesis, and the immutable order of nature.  Archives of Natural

 History,  18 , 309–321.

Duchesneau, F. (1979). Haller et les theories de Buffon et C. F. Wolff sur l’epigenese.   History and 

Philosophy of the Life Sciences,  1, 65–100.

Duchesneau, F. (1985). Vitalism in late eighteenth-century physiology: The cases of Barthez, Blumenbach

and John Hunter. In W. F. Bynum, & R. Porter (Eds.),   William Hunter and the eighteenth-century

medical world   (pp. 259–295). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Fambach, O, (Ed.). (1959).   Der Aufstieg zur Klassik in der Kritik der Zeit. Die wesentlichen und die

umstrittenen Rezensionen aus der periodischen Literatur von 1750 bis 1795, begleitet von den Stimmen

der Umwelt .  Ein Jahrhundert deutscher Literaturkritik (1750-1850)  (Vol. 3). Berlin: Akademie.Forster, E. (1987). Is there a   ‘gap’   in Kant’s critical system?   Journal of the History of Philosophy,   25,

533–555.

Forster, G. (1786). Noch etwas uber die Menschenraßen.   Teutsche Merkur ,   57  – 86 , 150–166.

Friedman, M. (1986). The metaphysical foundations of Newtonian science. In R. E. Butts (Ed.),  Kant ’s

 philosophy of physical science  (pp. 25–60). Dordrecht: Reidel.

Friedman, M. (1990). Kant and Newton: Why gravity is essential to matter. In P. Bricker, & R. I. G.

Hughes (Eds.),   Philosophical perspectives on Newtonian science   (pp. 185–202). Cambridge, MA:

MIT Press.

Friedman, M. (1991). Regulative and constitutive. Southern Journal of Philosophy, 30(Supplement System

and teleology in Kant ’s  Critique of judgment), 73–102.

Friedman, M. (1992a). Causal laws and the foundations of natural science. In P. Guyer (Ed.),  The Cam-

bridge companion to Kant   (pp. 161–199). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Friedman, M. (1992b).   Kant and the exact sciences. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Gaissinovich, A. E. (1968). Le role du Newtonianisme dans la renaissance des idees epigenetiques en

Page 35: This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

7/24/2019 This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/this-inscrutable-principle-of-an-original-organization 35/37

107 J.H. Zammito / Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 34 (2003) 73 – 109

embryologie du XVIIIe siecle. In   Actes du XIe Congres International d ’ Histoire des Sciences   (Vol.

5, pp. 105–110).

Genova, A. C. (1974). Kant’s epigenesis of pure reason.  Kant-Studien,  65, 259–273.

Girtanner, C. (1791).  Neue chemische Nomenklatur fu r die deutsche Sprache. Berlin: Unger.Girtanner, C. (1795).   Anfangsgru nde der antiphlogistische Chemie  (2nd ed.). Berlin: Unger.

Girtanner, C. (1796).   U ¨   ber das Kantische Prinzip fu r die Naturgeschichte. Gottingen: Vandenhoeck &

Ruprecht.

Gregory, F. (1989). Kant’s influence on natural scientists in the German Romantic period. In R. P. W.

Visser, H. J. M. Bos, L. C. Palm, & H. A. M. Snelders (Eds.),   New trends in the history of science

(pp. 53–66). Amsterdam & Atlanta: Rodopi.

Guyer, P. (1990a). Kant’s conception of empirical law.   Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society,

64(Supplement), 221–242.

Guyer, P. (1990b). Reason and reflective judgment: Kant on the significance of systematicity.  Nous,  24,

17–43.

Haigh, E. (1976). Vitalism, the soul, and sensibility: The physiology of Theophile Bordeu.   Journal of 

the History of Medicine,   31, 30–41.Harvey, W. (1943).  On generation. Ann Arbor: Edwards. First published 1651.

Herder, J. G. (1887).  Ideen zur Philosophie der Geschichte der Menschheit . In B. Suphan (Ed.).  Herders

Sa mtliche Werke   (Vol 13). Berlin: Weidmann. First published 1784.

Ingensiep, H. (1994). Die biologischen Analogien und die erkenntnistheoretischen Alternativen in Kants

Kritik der reinen Vernunft B  §   27.  Kant-Studien,  85, 381–393.

Jahn, I. (1995). Georg Forsters Lehrkonzeption fur eine   ‘Allgemeine Naturgeschichte’  (1786-1793) und

seine Auseinandersetzung mit Caspar Friedrich Wolffs   ‘Epigenesis’-Theorie.  Biologisches Zentral-

blatt ,  114, 200–206.

Kant, I. (1763). Der einzig mo gliche Beweisgrund zu einer Demonstration des Daseins Gottes.  Akademie-

Ausgabe (Vol. 2, pp. 63–164).

Kant, I. (1775/7). Von den verschiedenen Racen der Menschen. Akademie-Ausgabe (Vol. 2, pp. 427–444).

Kant, I. (1781/87).  Kritik der reinen Vernunft   (A   =  1781; B   =  1787). Akademie-Ausgabe (Vols. 3–4).Kant, I. (1783).   Prolegomena zu einer jeden ku nftigen Metaphysik, die als Wissenschaft wird auftreten

ko nnen. Akademie-Ausgabe (Vol. 4, pp. 253–384).

Kant, I. (1785a). Recensionen von J. G. Herders   Ideen zur Philosophie der Geschichte der Menschheit.

Theil 1. 2. Akademie Ausgabe (Vol. 8, pp. 43–66).

Kant, I. (1785b). Bestimmung des Begriffs einer Menschenrace. Akademie-Ausgabe (Vol. 8, pp. 89–106).

Kant, I. (1786)   Metaphysische Anfangsgru nde der Naturwissenschaft . Akademie-Ausgabe (Vol. 4, pp.

465–566).

Kant, I. (1788). Uber den Gebrauch teleologischer Principien in der Philosophie. Akademie-Ausgabe (Vol.

8, pp. 157–184).

Kant, I. (1790).  Kritik der Urteilskraft . Akademie-Ausgabe (Vol. 5, pp. 165–486).

Kant, I. (1798).  Anthropologie in pragmatischer Hinsicht . Akademie-Ausgabe (Vol. 7, pp. 117–334).

Kant, I. (1802).   Physische Geographie. Akademie-Ausgabe (Vol. 9, pp. 151–436).Kant, I.  Briefwechsel. Akademie-Ausgabe (Vols. 10–13).

Kant, I.  Re fl exionen. Akademie-Ausgabe (Vols. 17–18).

Kant, I.  Vorlesungen u ber Metaphysik . Akademie-Ausgabe (Vols. 28–29).

Kitcher, I. (1986). Projecting the order of nature. In R. E. Butts (Ed.).   Kant ’s philosophy of physical

science   (pp. 201–235). Dordrecht: Reidel.

Kitcher, I. (1993). Knowledge, society, and history.  Canadian Journal of Philosophy,  23, 155–178.

Kitcher, I. (1994). The unity of science and the unity of nature. In P. Parrini (Ed.). Kant and contemporary

epistemology   (pp. 253–272.). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

Kitcher, P. (1983). Kant’s philosophy of science.  Midwest Studies in Philosophy,   8 , 387–407.

Korner, S. (1955).  Kant . Harmonsworth: Penguin.

Kuhn, T. (1970).  The structure of scienti fic revolutions (2nd ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Larson, J. (1979). Vital forces: regulative principles or causal agents?   Isis,  70, 235–249.

Larson, J. (1994). Interpreting nature: The science of living form from Linnaeus to Kant . Baltimore: Johns

Hopkins University Press.

Page 36: This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

7/24/2019 This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/this-inscrutable-principle-of-an-original-organization 36/37

108   J.H. Zammito / Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 34 (2003) 73 – 109

Lenoir, T. (1980). Kant, Blumenbach, and vital materialism in German biology.   Isis,  71, 77–108.

Lenoir, T. (1981a). The Gottingen school and the development of transcendental Naturphilosophie in the

Romantic Era.   Studies in History of Biology,  5, 111–205.

Lenoir, T. (1981b). Teleology without regrets. The transformation of physiology in Germany 1790–

1847.Studies in History and Philosophy of Science,   12, 293–354.

Lenoir, T. (1988). Kant, Von Baer, and causal-historical thinking in biology.   Poetics Today,  9, 103–115.

McLaughlin, P. (1982). Blumenbach und der Bildungstrieb: Zum Verha ltnis von epigenetischer Embryolo-

gie und typologischem Artbegriff.   Medizinhistorisches Journal,  17 , 357–372.

McLaughlin, P. (1990).   Kant ’s critique of teleology in biological explanation: Antinomy and teleology.

Lewiston: Mellen.

Mocek, R. (1995). Caspar Friedrich Wolffs Epigenesis-Konzept—ein Problem im Wandel der Zeit.  Biolo-

gisches Zentralblatt ,  114, 179–190.

Morrison, M. (1989). Methodological rules in Kant’s philosophy of science.  Kant-Studien,  92, 155–172.

Muller-Sievers, H. (1993).   Epigenesis: Naturphilosophie im Sprachdenken Wilhelm von Humboldts . Pad-

erborn: Schoningh.

Muller-Sievers, H. (1997).   Self-generation: Biology, philosophy and literature around 1800. Stanford:Stanford University Press.

Okruhlik, K. (1983). Kant on the foundations of science. In W. Shea (Ed.),   Nature mathematicized   (pp.

251–268). Dordrecht: Reidel.

Querner, H. (1990). Christoph Girtanner und die Anwendung des Kantischen Prinzips in der Bestimmung

des Menschen. In G. Mann, & F. Dumont (Eds.),  Die Natur des Menschen: Probleme der Physischen

 Anthropologie und Rassenkunde (1750 – 1850)   (pp. 123–136). Stuttgart: G. Fischer.

Reill, P. H. (1989). Anti-mechanism, vitalism and their political implications in late Enlightened scientific

thought.   Francia,   16 , 195–212.

Reill, P. H. (1992). Between mechanism and hermeticism: Nature and science in the late Enlightenment.

In R. Vierhaus (Ed.),   Fru he Neuzeit  — Fru he Moderne?   (pp. 393–421). Gottingen: Vandenhoeck &

Ruprecht.

Reill, P. H. (1998). Analogy, comparison, and active living forces: Late Enlightenment responses to theskeptical critique of causal analysis. In J. van der Zande, & R. Popkin (Eds.),  The skeptical tradition

around 1800   (pp. 203–211). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

Rescher, N. (2001).   Cognitive pragmatism. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

Rheinberger, H.-J. (1981). Uber Formen und Grunde der Historisierung biologischer Modelle von Ordnung

und Organisation am Ausgang des 18. Jahrhunderts. In M. Hahn, & H.-J. Sandku hler (Eds.),  Gesell-

schaftliche Bewegung und Naturproze ß   (pp. 71–81). Cologne: Paul-Rugenstein.

Rheinberger, H.-J. (1986). Aspekte des Bedeutungswandels im Begriff organismischer Ahnlichkeit vom

18. zum 19. Jahrhundert.   History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences,   8 , 237–250.

Riedel, M. (1980). Historizismus und Kritizismus: Kants Streit mit G. Forster und J. G. Herder. In B.

Fabian, & W. Schmidt-Biggemann (Eds.),  Deutschlands kulturelle Entfaltung   (pp. 31–48). Munich:

Kraus.

Roe, S. (1979). Rationalism and embryology: Caspar Friedrich Wolff ’s theory of epigenesis.  Journal of the History of Biology,  12, 1–43.

Roger, J. (1968). Leibniz et les sciences de la vie. Studia Leibnitiana.  Supplementa,   2, 209–219.

Sloan, J. (1979). Buffon, German biology, and the historical interpretation of biological species.   British

 Journal for the History of Science,   12, 109–153.

Sloan, J. (2001). Kant and epigenetic embryology: The implications for his post-1790 philosophy. Paper

presented at the   Conference of the American Society of Eighteenth-Century Studies, New Orleans,

April, 2001.

Sloan, P. (1973). The idea of racial degeneracy in Buffon’s Histoire naturelle. In H. Pagliaro (Ed.). Racism

in the eighteenth century (pp. 293–321). Cleveland/London: Case Western Reserve University Press

(=  Studies in Eighteenth-Century Culture, 3).

Sloan, P. (2002). Preforming the categories: Kant and eighteenth-century generation theory.   Journal of 

the History of Philosophy,  2, 229–253.

Stawson, P. (1966).   The bounds of sense. London: Methuen.

Tuschling, B. (1991). The system of transcendental idealism: Questions raised and left open in the  Kritik 

Page 37: This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

7/24/2019 This Inscrutable Principle of an Original Organization

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/this-inscrutable-principle-of-an-original-organization 37/37

109 J.H. Zammito / Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 34 (2003) 73 – 109

der Urteilskraft .  Southern Journal of Philosophy,  30(Supplement System and teleology in Kant ’s  Cri-

tique of judgment), 109–128.

Wegelin, C. (1957). Dr. Med. Christoph Girtanner (1760–1800).  Gesnerus,   14, 141–163.

Williams, L. P. (1973). Kant, Naturphilosophie and scientifi

c method. In R. Giere, & R. Westfall (Eds.),Foundations of scienti fic method: The nineteenth century   (pp. 3–22). Bloomington: Indiana Univer-

sity Press.

Wolff, C. F. (1966).  Theorie von der Generation. Reprint Stuttgart: G. Fischer. First published 1764.

Wubnig, J. (1968/69). The epigenesis of pure reason.  Kant-Studien,  60, 147–152.

Zammito, J. (1992).   The genesis of Kant ’s   Critique of judgment. Chicago/London: University of 

Chicago Press.

Zammito, J. (1998).  ‘Method’ versus  ‘manner’? Kant’s critique of Herder’s Ideen in the light of the epoch

of science, 1790-1820. In H. Adler, & W. Koepke (Eds.),   Herder-Jahrbuch/Herder Yearbook 1998 

(pp. 1–26). Stuttgart: Metzler.

Zammito, J. (2001a). Epigenesis: Concept and metaphor in Herder’s   Ideen. In R. Otto, & J. Zammito

(Eds.),  Vom Selbstdenken: Aufkla rung und Aufkla rungskritik in Johann Gottfried Herders   ‘ Ideen zur 

Philosophie der Geschichte der Menschheit ’   (pp. 131–145). Heidelberg: Synchron.Zammito, J. (2001b). Policing polygeneticism in Germany, 1775: (Kames,) Kant and Blumenbach.  Paper 

 presented at the Conference on the   ‘German invention of race’, Harvard University, May 2001.

Zoller, G. (1989). From innate to  a priori: Kant’s radical transformation of a Cartesian-Leibnizian legacy.

 Monist ,   72, 222–235.

Zoller, G. (1988). Kant on the generation of metaphysical knowledge. In H. Oberer, & G. Seel (Eds.),

Kant: Analysen — Probleme — Kritik   (pp. 71–90). Wurzburg: Konigshausen & Neumann.

Zumbach, C. (1984).   The transcendent science: Kant ’s conception of biological methodology. The

Hague: Nijhoff.