the value of aesthetics in the ecological crisis of reason

Upload: thais-zoares

Post on 09-Mar-2016

219 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

DESCRIPTION

copyrighted

TRANSCRIPT

  • The Value of Aesthetics in the Ecological Crisis of Reason

    Thais MamedeSoares

    Independent Research Project

    Roosevelt Academy

    Dr. Aiken and Dr. Mueller-Friedman

    May14, 2012

    APA style

    Thais

    Thais

  • The Value of Aesthetics in the Ecological Crisis of Reason 2

    Abstract

    Val Plumwood proposed an interspecies ethic which is necessary in the current ecological crisis

    of reason. This research paper uses the same approach to the environmental crisis, but attempts

    to complement Plumwoods sensitive ethic with environmental aesthetics. The perception,

    cognition and emotion elements of aesthetic experiences have been historically, culturally and

    socially contextualized through a multidisciplinary literature review. Although current

    environmental aesthetics is based on the logic of domination which Plumwood rejects, it has

    proven to have a potential for the education of ethical sensitivities. Moreover, it seems that the

    transformation of reason alone, without aesthetics, is not enough to make real social-ecological

    change. The historical separation of aesthetics from ethics has resulted in a complex

    development towards consumerist life styles. In conclusion, the trivialization of aesthetics is

    largely discouraged, while on the other hand, research on aesthetics traditions and potentials are

    largely encouraged.

  • The Value of Aesthetics in the Ecological Crisis of Reason 3

    Table of Contents

    Introduction 6 General Background 6

    Research Question and Hypothesis 7

    Research Guidelines

    Plumwood & Environmental Aesthetics 9

    Plumwoods Critique of Environmental Ethics 9

    Plumwoods Major Works 9

    Mastery over Nature 9

    Ecological Crisis of Reason 11

    Framework and Critiques 14

    Framework and Sympathies 14

    Critiques 15

    Environmental Aesthetics 16

    Origins of Environmental Aesthetics 16

    Pre-Enlightenment 16

    Post-Enlightenment 17

    The Sublime, the Beautiful and the Picturesque 18

    Environmental Aesthetics after Environmentalism 19

    Cognitive and Non-Cognitive Approaches 20

    Practicality and Problems 23

    Closing Remarks 25

  • The Value of Aesthetics in the Ecological Crisis of Reason 4

    Steps to Discover Ethics within Aesthetic Experiences 26

    The Malleability of Vision: Scopic Regimes 26

    Antiquity 27

    Middle Ages 27

    Modern and Contemporary Regimes 28

    The Age of Show 30

    Gaze Ethics 32

    Gaze as action: ethics 32

    Gaze as non-action : pathological 33

    Ideological Aesthetics 37

    Cultural Politics of Representation 37

    Environmental Design 41

    Ideological Construction of Subjectivity 42

    Closing Remarks 43

    Ethical Contradictions in Environmentalist Aesthetics 45

    Tradition of Domination 45

    Historical Roots 45

    Disinterestedness and Vision 46

    Tourism and Scopic Regime 48

    Propagating Consumerism 48

    Aesthetics roots in Consumerism 48

    Ethical Consumption 52

    From Commodity to Ecological Aesthetics 54

  • The Value of Aesthetics in the Ecological Crisis of Reason 5

    Closing Remarks 55

    Discussion: Vices and Virtues of Aesthetics 57

    Conclusion 63

    References 64

  • The Value of Aesthetics in the Ecological Crisis of Reason 6

    INTRODUCTION

    In the face of the ecological crisis, the development of environmental ethics is a

    contemporary demand. The ecological crisis is a recent term, which encompasses the

    preoccupation with colossal environmental hazards, created by human impact that is mostly the

    fruit of irresponsible behaviour. According to Val Plumwood,the ecological crisis is not just or

    even primarily a crisis of technology, but is rather a crisis of rationality, morality, and

    imagination (Plumwood, 2002, p. 98). In the same spirit, this paper will look at the

    environmental crisis as a crisis in human (inter-)subjectivity, where different forms of

    subjectivity, more specifically in aesthetic experiences, are in confrontation. Although

    subjectivity is an ambiguous term, this paper will simply mean personal experiences and not in a

    negative sense.

    Plumwood has started to develop an interspecific ethic which should be built on

    perceptual, epistemic and emotional sensitivities (Plumwood, 2002, p. 142). Unfortunately, she

    does not go too in-depth on this statement, which seems to be very important. The first question

    that comes to mind is how humans are supposed to develop or recognize these sensitivities. This

    paper introduces aesthetics as a mode of education in the sensitive and ethical understanding that

    Plumwood demands. Aesthetics is a good candidate, since it involves perceptual, epistemic and

    emotional sensitivities. It becomes important especially when its elements are linked to ethics,

    which is what this paper will attempt to accomplish.

    It is true that Plumwood discards aesthetics right away as anthropocentric, but that does

    not mean that it is not worth investigating. If it does not teach one how to develop these ethical

    sensitivities, then at least it can show how one ought not to develop them. Besides, aesthetics is

    incredibly present in the presentations of environmentalists, without being highly regarded.

    Scholars concerned with the field of environmental aesthetics often utter statements like

    although aesthetic considerations have always practical weight in the environmental movement,

    they have often been ignored by theorists of environmental ethics (Fisher, 2001, p.265), and

    environmentalists have tended to deemphasize this dimension of natures value (Jamieson,

  • The Value of Aesthetics in the Ecological Crisis of Reason 7

    2007, p.159). This study will thus also attempt to find out why aesthetics is devalued and

    question whether that should be so.

    Research Question and Hypothesis

    The research question can be formulated as:

    What is the possible role of environmental aesthetics in the development of Plumwoods

    interspecific ethic?

    Because of Plumwoods emphasis on a communicative and sensitive relationship with

    other species, the hypothesis is that indeed aesthetics should have a greater importance as in

    being a medium of sensibility which involves more than human, or androcentric, verbal

    communication and understanding. On the other hand, the trivialization of aesthetics will

    probably subjugate it to anthropocentric and biocentric values. The thesis statement of this

    research is then:

    Environmental aesthetics can be an important complementation to Plumwoods ethic when used

    less trivially, becoming a focus of academic and practical research as a mode of education

    inethical sensitivities.

    Research Guidelines

    While the term aesthetics was officially coined by A. Baumgartner in 1735, meaning

    taste or beauty experience, the term is used in a variety of ways and is applied to periods before

    the coining of the term (Eagleton, 1990). The authors used for this study use the term without

    further explanation, and all still seem to use it in (slight) different ways. Eagleton has expressed

    the difficulty of making a strict definition of the term, which is not a handicap. According to

    him:

    The aesthetic has played such a dominant role in modern thought, (...) but if the aesthetic returns with such persistence, it is partly because of a certain indeterminacy of definition which allows it to figure in a varied span of preoccupations: freedom and legality, spontaneity and necessity, self-determination, autonomy, particularity and universality, along with several others. (p. 3)

  • The Value of Aesthetics in the Ecological Crisis of Reason 8

    The original purpose of this study is to focus on aesthetic experience and its underlying

    processes, but it is very difficult to talk about this without using related terms such as art,

    representation, commodity and (aesthetic) consumerism. For this study, thus, aesthetics will be

    put on a web or family of meaning. Perception, cognition, emotion and environment are the three

    elements which, when woven together, form an aesthetic experience (Wang, n.d.). In this

    experience, none of the elements can exist independently. Of course, these main elements are

    further related to culture, society, history, biology, etc. As such, aesthetic experiences are always

    relational and complex. This paper will attempt to explore this complexity through existing

    literature on the topic.

    The conducted research is a literary review with a multidisciplinary perspective. This is

    an important aspect of the work. If this paper was written from one perspective only, it would

    become more of a field expertise, such as art history or evolutionary psychology, instead of an

    exposure of a common problem of contemporary times. The paper will thus contain literature

    and concepts from various fields such as (environmental) philosophy, art history, (critical)

    sociology, history, and human geography. Together, these fields bring in different aspects of the

    same problem: environmental aesthetics and ethics.

    This research will proceed in a few steps. The first step is to explicate Plumwoods

    development of the interspecies ethic, and to have a general understanding of what the field of

    environmental aesthetics encompasses. The second step will be an exploration of ethics within

    aesthetic experiences, which will first seek ethics within regimes of perceptual experiences and

    then in ideologies of representation, design and subjectivity. The third step will be to find

    contradictions between environmentalist ethics and the ethics that emerge from the aesthetics

    that they use. Finally, the vices and virtues of different aesthetics will be discussed along with an

    example of the possibly virtuous aesthetics of Bateson.

  • The Value of Aesthetics in the Ecological Crisis of Reason 9

    PLUMWOOD AND ENVIRONMENTAL AESTHETICS

    PLUMWOODS CRITIQUE OF ENVIRONMENTAL ETHICS

    MAJOR WORKS

    Feminism and the Mastery of Nature

    Plumwood argues that the long hyper-dualistic tradition of western culture is the culprit

    for the environmental crisis which is occurring nowadays, and that the solution to this crisis is to

    become critical of dominant ways of thinking. She formulated her thinking firstly in her book

    Feminism and the Mastery of Nature (1993). In a later book, Environmental Culture: The

    Ecological Crisis of Reason (2002), she reformulated the same core ideas and reshaped them

    through more recent trends and critiques. In Feminism and the Mastery of Nature, Plumwood

    argues that dualisms are the result of a denied dependency on the subordinated other (p. 41).

    This master-subordinator relationship in turn defines the identity of each of the categories. She

    distinguishes dualism from other forms of differentiation and hierarchy; it is the sort of

    differentiation that naturalizes a hierarchy of irrevocably separate realms. While in hierarchical

    systems and differentiation there is still a possibility for shifting of positions, such change is not

    possible in dualisms. The categories of dualism become opposites. A set of these dualism pairs

    can be found in Table 1.

  • The Value of Aesthetics in the Ecological Crisis of Reason 10

    The master values of dualisms work through several ways. The first distinguishable way

    is the backgrounding of the slave-component, the denial of its importance in existence, which

    results in the universalization of the master values. Radical exclusion through opposition has

    already been mentioned. Another way is through the definition of the slave-component as

    lacking what the master-component is, which she calls incorporation. The slaves are thus not

    seen in their own rights, but they have to put aside their values for the masters and in doing so

    slaves become instruments for masters values. Plumwood argues that homogenization and

    stereotyping of the dominated class support instrumentalization, incorporation and radical

    exclusion.

    Another important part of her argument is the consideration of the logic of dualism. This

    is particularly important, because Plumwoods argumentation may be seen as a critique of reason

    and differentiation in general, while it is not. She criticizes classical (Aristotelian) logic, but does

    not see it as the only possible logic in the world. Also, she does not deny difference or

    dichotomies; rather she distinguishes dualism as a particular logical type, which is marked by

    negation. When the world is only known through Ps and not-Ps, not-Ps cannot have an

    independent existence from P (See figure 1). This logical definition of not-P in terms of P is

    TABLE 1: CONTRASTING PAIRS OF DUALISTIC WESTERN THOUGHT (PLUMWOOD, VAL 1993, P. 43).

  • The Value of Aesthetics in the Ecological Crisis of Reason 11

    exactly what produces radical exclusion and homogenization. Backgrounding, incorporation and

    instrumentalization are caused by the other feature of classical logic: truth-suppression. When

    the assumption behind the premises is true, it can be hidden. Even though the outcome is

    dependent on this hidden premise, this is formally denied, which causes backgrounding of the

    hidden assumption. Truth-interchangeability follows truth-suppression, which means that certain

    truths may be changed by other truths as long as the implicational properties stay the same. In

    other words, the means can change, as long as the same end is achieved; thus instrumentalization

    is embedded in classical logic.

    According to Plumwood, these features of classical logic are not inevitable to reason. The

    discerning reason should not be denied nor does Plumwood deny difference. What has to happen

    is the rectification of the distorted differences, which are created by dualistic thinking often

    through the very denial of them, e.g. through homogenization.

    The Ecological Crisis of Reason

    Plumwoods account of environmental ethics, which is best articulated in Environmental

    Culture: The Ecological Crisis of Reason (2002), argues that historically developed systems of

    power have corrupted rationality to employ dualisms in order to justify and naturalize the

    privilege of people over nature. This dominant form of rationality, dualistic thinking, is also

    FIGURE 1 P AND -P (PLUMWOOD, 1993, P.57).

  • The Value of Aesthetics in the Ecological Crisis of Reason 12

    predominant in scientific, political, economic and ethical systems of reasoning. Rationalism is

    not equated to reason, just as she has explained that classical logic is not the same as logic.

    The philosophical task to find solutions in this environmental crisis is divided in two

    attempts: re-situating humans in ecological terms, and situating non-humans in ethical terms for

    the first time. The first attempt is easier and does not require a complete reframing of ethics.

    Utilitarianism is not opposed to a more sustainable planet. The second task, however, is more

    problematic and usually considered to be less important. From there arises the whole debate of

    intrinsic value, for instance. The roots of these problems lie in the Cartesian dualistic rationality,

    which dictates that a rational-conscious mind confronts a mindless and morally meaningless

    universe (Plumwood, 2002, p. 143). This rationality makes it impossible for humans to justify

    that animals, plants and rocks may have any form of intrinsic value whatsoever.

    Neo-Cartesian dualism is used in the defence of animals with higher consciousness to

    include them in the realm of persons rights. This is the typical case of minimal moral extension,

    which does not overthrow moral bases founded on Cartesian dualism. This moral fundament is

    described as the ethics of commoditization, because it separates persons from things, and its aims

    are to maximize the amount of things for consumption by persons, which are the minimum elite.

    (Neo-)Cartesian ethics cut off sharp boundaries between the privileged and the unprivileged,

    denying the continuity of planetary life. Moral dualisms are also moral boomerangs: the

    exclusion of lower classes reinforces the exclusion of a bit higher classes in other areas. This

    means that when humans tend to exclude animals in their worthiness of moral considerations,

    they are also more drawn to exclude unprivileged human races in their worthiness of

    employment considerations. The practice of exclusion will reinforce the moral dualism that also

    deteriorates the less privileged class in each atmosphere. Conversely, the practice of openness

    and communication, even to non-humans, will make humans more ethical.

    The denial of human embeddedness in nature, through Cartesian rationality and

    anthropocentrism, leads to the Ecological denial- a denial of the environmental crisis. Centrism

    is understood as an essential form of cognition, since it categorizes into superior and inferior.

    But, says Plumwood, it is much more a matter of moral epistemology, of frameworks for

    noticing, perception, attention and focus, and for self-perception, in framing concepts of

    autonomy for example (Plumwood, 2002, p. 101). Her wording in this quote is abundant with

    concepts intimately linked to aesthetics. She notices that in centrism the focus is on the victims

  • The Value of Aesthetics in the Ecological Crisis of Reason 13

    irrationality, whereas there are blinders in the master perspective which do not need to be

    exposed for all of its aspects are irrationally assumed to be universally valid. This superior-

    inferior relationship does not only affect the inferior negatively, but also the superior (as shown

    in the example of gender under critiques of ecofeminism). Centrism is grounded on dualisms

    and the master values of dualism that have been described above.

    Related to this centrism is the biocentrism as proposed by deep ecology. Plumwood

    criticizes its view that dualisms need to be bridged by unity and identification. In the unity of

    deep ecology even atomic bombs would be part of identification, and natures independence and

    difference are neglected. Thus, it does not fit her communication model for ethics. The

    existential gulf between nature and human is still important. One can also feel respect for nature

    through the experience of the Other (such as in a sublime-pristine nature scenario). The focus of

    deep ecology on the biocentric Self, thus the self-interests of the total biotic community, is just

    an expansion of the self in the self/other duality. For a relationship based ethic, there needs to be

    regard for both self and other and their continuous balance and movement. Moreover, prudence

    does not have to be abandoned in a non-centered ethic. Human-centeredness is associated with

    egoism, although prudence does not have to be so. Those who can take care of themselves can

    also take care of others.

    Plumwood also states that Global capitalism is the expression of Cartesian dualism,

    which divides person and property. The world is structured through egoism and competition.

    However, Plumwood pleads for the move from a competitive to a complementary approach to

    ethics. She says that her counter hegemonic program is self-critical and reflecting. Rather than

    testing whether animals are good enough to have rights, it tests whether humans are qualified for

    ethics.In order to be qualified for ethics, humans need to denaturalize assumptions of the Other,

    including objectifying stereotypes. Humans also need to be aware of over-centred concepts of the

    mind and open to the other as a communicative being. She further describes two features of an

    interspecies ethic. The first is intentional recognition in order to see agency in non-humans. The

    second is panpsychism, which is the view that Cartesian consciousness is in continuous

    graduated ways permeating the natural world.(146). These features form the basis for new

    interspecies ethics that open up to communicative, recognition-based and sensitive relationship.

    As was mentioned in the introduction, Plumwood dismisses aesthetics, even though it seems to

    be very close to the core of her ethic: Ultimately, a durable relationship between we humans

  • The Value of Aesthetics in the Ecological Crisis of Reason 14

    and our planetarypartners must be built on the kinds of perceptual, epistemic and emotional

    sensitivities which are best founded on respect, care and love (Plumwood, 2002, p. 142). This

    research paper will look for exactly these perceptual, epistemic and emotional sensitivities in

    aesthetics.

    PLUMWOODS FRAMEWORK AND CRITIQUES

    Framework and Sympathies

    Although there is a great variety of focuses within the field of ecofeminism, there is a

    general agreement that the domination of nature should be understood through its connection

    with the domination of women (Davion, 2001). Within the field, Plumwood is known for her

    philosophical explication of value dualisms and the logic of domination (Davion, 2001). The

    idea of logic domination is actually the intellectual product of Kate Warren, but is highly

    compatible with Plumwoods thoughts (Davion, 2001). Plumwood is also memorable through

    the fact that she rejected other radical environmentalist movements, such as social and deep

    ecology. She rejected their assumptions that are still based on androcentric values, which is

    contradictory to their struggle for equality (Davion, 2001). Through the logic of domination, not

    only women, but also races and classes that are considered to be inferior, are connected with the

    domination of the environment (Davion, 2001). This idea is supported by environmental justice,

    the movement that sees the degradation of life of minorities behind and due to the degradation of

    the environment (Davion, 2001). Therefore, it is important to take into account that ecofeminists

    inspirations come from a history of social inequality and that their attempt is to find the roots of

    this inequality in order to make justice to oppression. It is straightforward that scholars in

    environmental justice, ecofeminism and post-colonial studies will look for historical and social

    power dynamics behind concepts that are assumed to be universal. Rather than victimizing

    nature, these groups are criticizing the dominant modern subject and his ethics. This paper will

    take the same approach when studying environmental aesthetics.

  • The Value of Aesthetics in the Ecological Crisis of Reason 15

    Critiques

    The general critique of ecofeminism is that there is a tendency to romanticize oppressed

    groups and give them full uncritical credit in the construction of an ecofeminist ethic (Davion,

    2001). Ecofeminists, including Plumwood, want to go back to the feminine values that have

    been devalued by the patriarchal western society (Davion, 2001). By doing so, feminists accept

    the gender roles that function under patriarchy uncritically (Davion, 2001). Moreover, they

    essentialize femininity and nature without taking historical, class and race differences within

    these categories into account (Davion, 2001). Also, that men or the ruling class does not only

    have benefits from this duality is barely ever talked about (except for Plumwood). This is

    something to think about when evaluating the effects on humans of the Cartesian separation

    between humans and non-humans.

    Despite these charges, ecofeminism is still valid. Uncritical, activist based solutions of

    feminists should not overshadow their highly critical studies. Their important discovery is that

    dualisms are legitimizing oppression. These dualisms are so inherent to people that even when

    women are not happy with them and want to move away from this oppression, they fall in the

    same ways of thinking. Feminists recognize that the domination logic consists of a hyper-

    separation of categories, but they seek to solve the problem by exalting the oppressed categories,

    instead of doing away with the dichotomies altogether. Equally important is the critique that

    biocentrism comes from the same dichotomy as anthropocentrism. There can be no good

    biocentrism if it is forms a dualist pair with anthropocentrism.After these essentialist charges,

    Plumwood renamed her position as Critical feminist eco-socialism in order to distinguish

    herself from the essentialist feminists (Gaard, 2011, p. 27). Such a change has been well

    expressed in The Ecological Crisis of Reason.

    A more specific critique of Plumwood comes from Eaton (2002). He points out that there

    is a danger that does with attempting to see embedded cultural phenomena in overtly abstract

    symbolic terms (Eaton, 2002, p. 178). According to him, this creates a reductionism that fails to

    understand highly complex contextualized situations in all their aspects (Eaton, 2002). In other

    words, Plumwoods theory may be as reductionist as the very rationality which it criticizes.

    Indeed, Plumwood seems to go too fast in her judgements of what is right and wrong. This paper

    will therefore still take aesthetics in consideration, even though she has dismissed it.

  • The Value of Aesthetics in the Ecological Crisis of Reason 16

    ENVIRONMENTAL AESTHETICS

    ORIGINS OF ENVIRONMENTAL AESTHETICS

    Pre-Enlightenment

    Although environmental aesthetics has only emerged as discipline in the second half of

    the twentieth century, there have been signs of symbolic values of nature for millennia. The

    fundamental questions of modern environmental aesthetics have their foundations already in

    Platos characterisation of the soul. As Wang et al put it: Such an idea that humans have some

    common qualities with nature and yet differ from nature in some crucial aspects has shown the

    fundamental complexity of understanding natural beauty, the very prime subject of

    environmental aesthetics (p. 2). This already points out that the struggle of understanding and

    dealing with differences, sometimes expressed as dualities, is crucial to the field of

    environmental aesthetics.

    Nature and landscape have had different meanings across historic-geographical lines

    (Gold & Revill, 2004). From the Classical, Medieval and Renaissance period there are three

    important legacies. The first is the pastoral landscape, which is the ideological symbol that

    connects the Classical rural idyll with the Christian Garden of Eden (Gold & Revill, 2004, p.

    80-115). The second is the animate nature, which is a model of the world where nature is the

    expression of spirituality, religious values and emotions (Gold & Revill, 2004). The third legacy

    is how landscape has come to be linked to identity. The land becomes property, a representation

    of life style and a treasure of memories and history (Gold & Revill, 2004). These three major

    legacies have been very important in the eighteenth and nineteenth century (and further), the

    period of time when environmental aesthetics started its academic development towards its most

    current form.

  • The Value of Aesthetics in the Ecological Crisis of Reason 17

    Post-Enlightenment

    Eighteenth-century early development of nature aesthetics occurred through a tension of

    two values (Rueger, 2007). The first was the value of freedom, which required nature

    appreciation to be free of domestication, free of artistic judgment values (Rueger, 2007). The

    second was the value of the picturesque, which was exactly the opposite: nature was only

    beautiful when it looked like art (Rueger, 2007). This same tension was still present in the

    revival of environmental aesthetics in the twentieth-century. The remaining question throughout

    these periods is always what an appropriate appreciation of nature is (Rueger, 2007). The

    dominant answer to this is the appreciation of nature for what it is, rather than for what it is not,

    namely art (Rueger, 2007). Even though this question of appropriate appreciation already stems

    from art, and the attempts to categorize nature appreciation in terms of beauty and sublime are

    also derived from art, there is a tendency to distinguish between art and environmental aesthetics.

    Kant is very important in this debate, for he is known to have manufactured the first

    systematic study of aesthetics (Wang, n.d.). Kant is famous for being in favour of natural beauty

    that is free from external concepts (Rueger, 2007). His concept of disinterestedness has become

    central to the philosophy of aesthetic experience, which has to be detached from personal and

    practical interestedness or everyday life (Wang, n.d.).

    Rueger (2007) gives a comprehensive explanation of Kants ideas on nature aesthetics.

    The pure form of judgements of taste is non-cognitive, and nevertheless universal. It is the

    freedom from conceptualization that triggers the joyful experience of beauty. What happens is

    that imagination and understanding, which are elements of the universal cognitive function, are

    involved in the process of judgement of taste. However, these two elements do no behave in the

    same way as in conceptual cognition, which makes taste judgments not objective. It seems that

    pleasure is purposive; however, it cannot be, for taste judgments are not conceptual. It is also

    very important that natural beauty is not purposeful. Nature must be mechanical, so that it does

    not have purposes or intentions that correspond to the roots of aesthetic pleasure:only as a

    mechanism does nature produce forms freely, without purposes or intentions (Rueger, 2007, p.

    154). Pure aesthetic pleasure can only occur when there is no purpose or desire for the object.

    Appropriate aesthetic judgements are judgments of appreciation for what it is; concepts about the

    object or sensations should be undermined in order for the judgment to be pure.

    Thus, the disinterested attitude is a normative concept that is grounded on the assumption

  • The Value of Aesthetics in the Ecological Crisis of Reason 18

    of a mechanical, passive nature and on the strict distinction between humans and nature.

    Although this philosophical idea or assumption seems to disappear from sight later on, it is

    inherent in the disinterestedaesthetic experience. This exemplifies how bodily experiences can be

    grounded on ideas. Of course, the age of Enlightenment is also the age of Cartesian rationality

    and the exaltation of the superior Reason. This compromises the field of (environmental)

    aesthetics from the start. However, there have been changes and conflicts throughout the

    development of the field. Therefore it is still important to trace this development.

    The sublime, the beautiful and the picturesque

    The valuation of wilderness experienced a transformation from fear and repulsion to

    touristic and romantic attraction to spectacular nature (Gold & Revill, 2004). The sublime and

    picturesque can be seen as visual theories and codes which make it possible for people to

    reinterpret the terrible wilderness as a meaningful and pleasurable experience (Gold & Revill,

    2004). This is an example of the power of visual codes, aesthetics, to change the meaning and

    feeling of experiences. Kant is considered to have coined the term sublime, and Burke is his

    successor in the elaboration of it (Gold & Revill, 2004). At the same time that the sublime is

    dangerous and involving, it is also comforting through the distance of the spectator. (Gold &

    Revill, 2004). The beautiful is the opposite of the sublime: it is carefully calculated and orderly.

    The picturesque draws elements from both sublime and beautiful, and is best seen as a painting

    or arrangement as in a picture. Both sublime and picturesque are products of the legacies of the

    old pictorial tradition of seventeenth-century Italian painters (Gold & Revill, 2004). Table 2

    shows more specific qualities of the three visual codes.

  • The Value of Aesthetics in the Ecological Crisis of Reason 19

    ENVIRONMETALISM AND REVIVAL OF NATURE AESTHETICS

    While the interest in nature aesthetics had faded away for about a century, mainly

    through Hegels assertion that art is the highest form of the aesthetic, it has been revived after the

    1960s with the rise of environmental movements (Carlson, 2010). This is also due to the fact

    that the environmental concern has reached the academic world, producing not only the field of

    environmental aesthetics, but also environmental ethics (Carlson, 2010).

    It is important to note that in the eighteenth-century British birth of early environmental

    aesthetics, philosophers saw nature appreciation as a personal and passive acceptance of sensory

    stimuli, what has become characterized as subjective (Wang, n.d.). It was only with the

    Romantics in the nineteenth-century that a new element of objective impression was introduced

    along with scientific knowledge as factors of what is to be properly appreciated (Wang, n.d.).

    Around the corner of the twentieth-century, environmental aesthetics became a serious scientific

    study, which, with the aid of cognitive psychology, acknowledges and supports an interactive

    appreciation of the environment (Wang, n.d.). This transformation has left behind different

    methods of studying environmental aesthetics: subjective, objective, distant or involved methods.

    TABLE 2: THE SUBLIME, THE BEAUTIFUL AND THE PICTURESQUE (GOLD & REVILL, 2004, P. 141).

  • The Value of Aesthetics in the Ecological Crisis of Reason 20

    Within the philosophy of environmental aesthetics, there are several positions which are

    generally divided in two groups: cognitive and non-cognitive approaches. Cognitive

    approaches often take the form of realism, seeing nature as a manifestation of divine beauty or

    orderly objectivity (Jamieson, 2001). Non-cognitive approaches tend to take a sort of post-

    modern subjectivist position which states that beauty is on the eye of the beholder (Jamieson,

    2001). Of course, there is a middle ground to that, where one believes that there are general

    objective principles behind the judgement of beauty and that some properties of objects work in

    subjective organs in such a way that compels people to find them beautiful (Jamieson, 2001).

    The main question behind the cognitive and non-cognitive approaches is in the

    comparison between artistic and nature appreciation (Carlson, 1998; 2011). The appreciation of

    nature needs a different context than the context of art, which is mostly art history (Carlson,

    1998; 2011). The cognitive approach uses scientific understanding, whereas the non-cognitive

    approach uses a kind of subjectivity or holism as the new context. Most scholars in these fields

    are also concerned with environmentalism, and tend to make aesthetics work for it in a way or

    another. The question of appropriate appreciation is then also often submerged in

    environmentalism and in the world views that produce different types of environmentalism.

    Cognitive and Non-Cognitive Approaches

    Important in the cognitive approach are scientific cognitivism and positive aesthetics

    which go hand in hand. Scientific cognitivism is the view that scientific knowledge is necessary

    and appropriate for aesthetic appreciation of nature (Carlson, 2007). This means that in order for

    people to appreciate all nature, including its normally considered revolting parts, as beautiful,

    they need to understand it scientifically (Carlson, 2007). Whatever is not beautiful at first sight

    may become beautiful when understood in a larger scientific context (Carlson, 2007). Rolston is

    famous for his example of the rotten carcass of an elk, full of maggots. (Carlson, 2007, p. 111).

    It is revolting at first, but becomes beautiful as the insight of the whole recycling of nature (see

    figure 2). People need to develop an all-seeing point of view or Gods-eye view in order to

    reach the complex beauty of real nature (Carlson, 2007, p. 112). The point of view that Real

    nature, or virgin nature, will always essentially be beautiful comes from positive aesthetics. The

    threat for the subjectivity and insignificance of aesthetics is made invalid through this new

  • The Value of Aesthetics in the Ecological Crisis of Reason 21

    scientific ground of aesthetics (Carlson, 2007). Unfortunately, the question why the carcass is

    revolting in the first place is not asked. This question would lead to a larger understanding of the

    processes behind aesthetic experiences. It seems that the field of environmental aesthetics is less

    concerned with this understanding, than it is with the modification and justification of aesthetic

    experiences.

    However, the cognitive views are condemned for they put the object of aesthetic

    appreciation outside of immediate experience or perception (Carlson, 2007). There is absolutely

    no guarantee that people will find the maggots in the rotting carcass beautiful for what they

    represent. In other words, in order for people to find the parts of the whole beautiful, it needs to

    be somehow presented in the perceptual composition (Carlson, 2007). A slight response to this

    is that science can re-illuminate objects through their description (Carlson, 2007). Science

    redescribes natural objects in a factious way that contends value: symbiotic relationships already

    contend stability and harmony in them (Carlson, 2007). Moreover, organisms themselves are

    described as harmonious and symbiotic, which means that the particular case is made beautiful

    as well (Carlson, 2007). Scientific cognitivism also tries to find the roots of aesthetic experience

    FIGURE 2 BEAUTIFUL, HARMONIOUS RECYCLING OF NATURE (MAGGOTS SERVED ON A DEAD ANIMAL, 2011).

  • The Value of Aesthetics in the Ecological Crisis of Reason 22

    through psychological experiments and evolutionary psychology. The greatest critiques of this

    stance come from the side of non-cognitive approaches, which will be described below.

    Non-cognitive approaches usually completely reject the disinterestedness of art

    appreciation (Carlson, 2010). The subject of appreciation (Carlson, 2010) must be completely

    immersed in the object of appreciation, or the appreciation must be purely emotional and

    imaginative (Carlson, 2010). This means that there is an attempt to transcend nature/human and

    subject/object dualisms (Carlson, 1998; 2011). The scope of aesthetic experience is broadened to

    also include artistic objects and emotional responses such as wonder and intimacy (Carlson,

    1998; 2011). Although the scientific cognitivism is far from being suitable for Plumwood, this

    approach is not incompatible at first.

    This approach is also criticized. Because there is no framework or painter around nature,

    the non-cognitive approach usually disregards the questions of appropriate nature appreciation

    (Carlson, 1998; 2011). These questions can never be answered. What is more important is to be

    immersed in nature, appreciate and enjoy it freely (Carlson, 1998; 2011). This approach

    effectively creates a validation to immediately accessible aesthetic experience (Carlson, 1998;

    2011).

    However, because of the broadness and perhaps vagueness of this approach, there is no

    distinction between aesthetic experiences, which makes it rather trivial (Carlson, 1998; 2011).

    One can appreciate both a tree and a skyscraper. The trust in subjective experience is thus the

    main problem of this approach, which has lead to responses that try to make it more objective

    (Carlson, 1998; 2011). This is where the old dualisms need to get involved in this approach. This

    can be seen best in Emily Bradys (1998) critique of scientific cognitivism. She does not have a

    problem with objectivity per se, but finds several problems with that position: it is difficult to

    understand what exactly counts as scientific knowledge, and once it is understood, knowledge

    can indeed expand appreciation, but is not essential to it. To make aesthetic value have an

    important place in the ecological field, it needs to be unique and not simply subjective or trivial.

    Science makes it less subjectivist, which is a good start, but it is imagination and perception that

    make aesthetics unique. Science takes aesthetic appreciation too far away from the realm of

    perception. Another distinct feature of environmental aesthetics is that they are free and

    disinterested from practical interests. Brady completely neglects the roots of this approach in the

    fundamental distinction between humans and nature. However, she continues, a science-based

  • The Value of Aesthetics in the Ecological Crisis of Reason 23

    approach makes appreciation limited, fixed and conventional; only imagination can make

    appreciation be free and fresh all the time.

    Her approach needs to be educated: aesthetic experience depends on the effort of the

    observer which connects attentive observation with imagination. She gives two flexible

    guidelines to make imagination appropriate, thus non-trivial and arbitrary. The first guideline

    must be Kantian disinterestedness. The second and last is called imagining well (p. 146),

    which entails that imagination must be appropriate to context and all irrelevant imagination must

    be cut off through virtuous skill. This connection of aesthetics with virtuous skill is at the core of

    the argument of this paper. It shows the educational aspect of aesthetics which is largely

    undermined.

    Practicality and problems

    Bradys approach already exemplifies the attempt to find a middle ground between the

    various approaches. This is done in order to strengthen rather than weaken the field of

    environmental aesthetics. All this effort seems to go into the practical goal of making aesthetic

    experience both pleasant and motivational for a better connection with nature. In other words, to

    make aesthetic experience appropriate to environmental ethics. Aesthetics is not connected to

    duty, but neither is ethic, says Rolston (2002). Ethic is logically and psychologically closer to

    caring (p.127). According to him, humans must learn to move from shallow to deep aesthetics,

    where aesthetics is embedded in scientific understanding and in the embodiment of humans in

    the landscape.

    There are also attempts to ecologize aesthetics, that is, not merely attempts to make

    aesthetic values important motives for environmentalism, but attempts to make landscape design

    ecological and to educate aesthetic experience to become ecological, or even to base

    environmental ethics on environmental aesthetics. Traditional aesthetics is often in the way of

    ecological practices (Rolston, 2002; Parsons, 1995). The emphasis is on how to make the

    environments always beautiful in a consistent way, instead of focussing on health. According to

    a study of Parsons (1995), this position is less certain. Aesthetics is potentially in conflict with

    ecological goals of landscape ecology, but there is evidence for both psychological benefits and

  • The Value of Aesthetics in the Ecological Crisis of Reason 24

    of visual experiences of wild life, which in turn can stimulate positive environmental action.

    There needs to be more research on their effect, according to him.

    There are certainly more attempts to find a universal effect of being in nature in humans

    through the scientific method, which are generally positive of psychological benefits (Gobster, et

    al, 2007). These approaches come from a modernist perspective: Aesthetic value is a function

    of aesthetic response (Fisher, 2001). They come along with biophilia: the evolutionary

    psychology position that holds that humans have evolved to have psychological benefits from

    engaging with natural surroundings and natural organisms (Fisher, 2001). However,

    psychological effects do not guarantee that they will outweigh other cognitive processes and

    social influences.

    Loftis (2003) points out three problems of aesthetic foundations of environmental

    ethics which rise independently from psychological effects. Firstly, it provides weak reasons for

    actions, which are not comparable to motivation from basic necessities. Secondly, not every

    nature carries positive aesthetic qualities; environmentally un-friendly culture, like skyscrapers,

    can be just as aesthetic as environmental scenery. Thirdly, aesthetic values are associated with

    Hollywood movie stars. They cannot be taken serious enough to justify sacrificial acts, such as

    job and complete lifestyle changes.

    Nonetheless, aesthetics is quite powerful, because it influences natural science.

    According to Kovacss et al (2006) study, aesthetics influences the practice of ecology through

    the appreciation of ecologists. One of the main motives for people to become ecologists is their

    attraction to environmental aesthetics. Landscape ecology is also influenced in its design;

    interpretation of ecology and even public perception of ecological processes are not left out.

    Aesthetics may be in conflict with scientific practice, but it also may stimulate discoveries and

    bring them in a particular direction.

  • The Value of Aesthetics in the Ecological Crisis of Reason 25

    CLOSING REMARKS

    There are lots of other problems with environmental aesthetics: it rises up as a sort of

    independent and new field which casts its past influences as inexistent. It merges on the one hand

    with science and scientism and on the other hand with Romantic environmentalism, roughly

    speaking. Along with these areas, it takes assumptions of objectivity and subjectivity in its

    discussions for granted, without further elaborating on these notions, leaving them only half

    criticized. Its disregards the massive use of aesthetics in environmentalist representation and art,

    leading to a further disregard of the socio-ideological aspects of aesthetics. It tends to direct

    aesthetic experience to become a motivation for environmental action, but does not see what the

    untrained experience itself already tells about motivation, ideals and ethics. In all senses, this

    new academic discourse is unshaped and muddled. Indeed, Wang et al have also come to the

    same conclusion when trying to trace a methodology for the aesthetic discourse.

    All in all, environmental Aesthetics is a new field with some environmentalist purposes

    and has a history in Cartesian rationality. This field does attempt to unify ethics, emotion and

    reasonability. The non-cognitive approach also attempts to bridge the subject/object divide,

    although not without problems. Although it is clear that environmental aesthetics is rooted in

    Cartesian dualisms, which is unsuitable for Plumwoods ethic, there are attempts to unify the

    elements needed in her ethical sensitivity: ethics, perception, emotions and epistemology. The

    failure of these attempts may lie in the lack of coherence and clarity of the field. The following

    section will be an attempt to understand the relationship between these elements through

    historical, social and ideological contextualization. The main purpose will be to connect

    sensitivity or perception with ethics and find the political or ideological relation to it.

  • The Value of Aesthetics in the Ecological Crisis of Reason 26

    STEPS TO DISCOVER ETHICS WITHIN AESTHETIC EXPERIENCES

    THE MALLEABILITY OF VISION: SCOPIC REGIMES

    One of the ways of discovering aesthetics relation to ethics is through historical

    contextualization. One will then find that the problematic connection between aesthetics and

    ethics lies already at perception. Today it is not common to think that perception can be trained

    into a virtuous skill. However, this very unthinkable property already points to the existing ethic

    of the modernist period, which will be explained below.

    There are writers that trace the change in perception habits throughout western history.

    More specifically, they trace the different regimes of vision, or so-called scopic or ocular

    regimes. These regimes are about the eye as an organ and vision as a socio-historical

    phenomenon. While there are many theories of vision, predominant scientific theories cancel all

    theories that do not follow the scientific method. These authors do not see one type of vision as

    being more real than the other. Rather, they link vision to culture and history. This connection

    goes to an extent that not only interpretations of vision are cultural, but also what is visible to the

    eye. The scientific explanation of vision is thus not more correct than the medieval

    understanding of seeing; it is only a manifestation of different cultural ethos. This section will

    illustrate how vision is not merely a naturalist or a-historical phenomenon of perceiving, but

    takes different forms and is malleable through social, historical, and political forces. Vision will

    be the focus of this particular section, since there is more literature available on it.

  • The Value of Aesthetics in the Ecological Crisis of Reason 27

    ANTIQUITY

    The starting point of Illich (1998; 2001) is in Ancient Greece, where Opsis, i.e. to gaze, is

    a human action that can be trained and be made into an ethical skill or virtue (2001, p. 5). The

    science of opsis is the basis and guide for human activity. Among the Greeks the gaze is a fleshy

    projection out of the skin, or psychopodia. It touches the objects to reveal their internal

    characteristics just the way that the sun reveals their colours (See figure 3). The fusion between

    object and subject occurs outside of the body in the cosmic event where the glance [is] coloured

    by the world, the world coloured [is] by the glance (1998, p. 6). Knowledge of the world is thus

    based on the conaturality(or shared nature) of the fleshy gaze and world.

    MIDDLE AGES

    In the Middle Ages, the gaze is still going outwards, but does no longer fuse with the

    object; it extracts universal meanings from the characteristics emanated from it (Illich, 1998).

    The gaze transcends material reality and unites with the eternal Forms or love of Christ (Illich,

    1998). That religion is important in the visual experience of individuals has also been

    FIGURE 3 PSYCHOPODIA REACHING OUT FOR BUNNY (OWN IMAGE).

  • The Value of Aesthetics in the Ecological Crisis of Reason 28

    underscored in the book The Medieval Vision, by Carolly Erickson (1976). According to her

    research findings, it also seems that the gaze is an activity connected to divinity. It was normal

    for travelling monks to see mystical creatures, for vision was creative energy rather than

    passive recording (p. 13). It is not so that people could not distinguish sober visions from more

    imaginative visions, but the creative component of vision was acknowledged and celebrated. In

    fact, it was mans visual capabilities, Macrobius wrote, that determined the degree of his

    participation in the divine mind (p. 13).

    MODERNIST AND CONTEMPORARY REGIMES

    In this period, the gaze becomes an instrument, a Camera Obscura (See figure 4), where it

    is detached from the body and mediates a pictorial reality (Illich, 1998; 2001). Reality is now

    objectified and can be directly perceived through such detached instrumentation (Illich, 1998;

    2001). However, there is still a common ground that can bring the spectator to understanding of

    the picture: the perspective (Illich, 2001). This change occurs due to the inversion of the gaze ray

    (Illich, 1998; 2001). In this regime, light comes inside the passive eye (Illich, 1998; 2001). This

    implies that metaphysics invites itself to the cognition to know it. Men can have direct

    knowledge of the world through the eyes, which is now equal or even inferior to an observatory

    device (Illich, 1998; 2001). Instrumental, pictorial observation becomes the only way in which

    the world could be logically derived and represented (Illich, 1998; 2001). The image, and not

    what is behind it, becomes essential to observation and reality.

    Jay (1998) focuses on the plurality and hierarchy of scopic regimes present in the modern

    period, which started with the Renaissance. The field of perception is here fundamentally non

    reflexive, visual and quantitative (p.3). According to him, authors such as Rorty, Foucault and

    Debord confirm that vision is dominant in the modern period (Jay, 1998). Jay suggests a

    hierarchy of visual subcultures in modernity, and characterizes the hegemonic visual culture of

    the modern period as a Cartesian perspectivalism. This is in line with the reality that imprints

    its representation on the retinal canvas, which Illich has thought to be characteristic of this

    period. It corresponds to the idea that scientific observation is equivalent to the natural world.

  • The Value of Aesthetics in the Ecological Crisis of Reason 29

    According to Jay several authors have written on the perspectivalist revolution and its

    technical, aesthetic, economical, psychological and political aspects (p. 5). Both Illich and Jay

    talk about the monocular gaze that looks through a geometrical rooster and peephole, which

    makes the gaze fixated and disembodied (See figure 5). The resulting image becomes

    eternalized, or a-historical, and is reduced to one point of view. This is done when the three-

    dimensional rationalized space is put to a two-dimensional medium. This perpectival gaze is cold

    and distant. This corresponded with the dissociation of narrative from text, and the neutrality of

    FIGURE 4 CAMERA OBSCURA WHICH MERGES THE HEAD OF THE PICTURE TAKER AND INSTRUMENT INTO ONE, (CAMERA OBSCURA, 2012).

    FIGURE 5 INSTRUMENT FROM 1925 FOR MONOCULAR AND DISINTERESTED VISION (ALBRECHT DURER, 2012).

  • The Value of Aesthetics in the Ecological Crisis of Reason 30

    the researcher. The doors from the world of art to the world of capitalist commodity were open:

    Separate from the painter and the viewer, the visual field depicted on the other side of the

    canvas could become a portable commodity able to enter the circulation of capitalist exchange

    (p. 8). Also, according to Martin Heidegger, the natural world could now be viewed as resources

    that can be kept under surveillance and be manipulated in an impersonal manner.

    Jay distinguishes two other scopic regimes in the modern period. One is the spontaneous

    photographic regime that is not respectful of the Cartesian explanations, but can be unified in its

    de-narrative stance and commoditization. The baroque regime, on the other hand, is more

    radically opposed to the hegemony. It denies that nature is understandable and readable in purist

    ways. It sees that vision and rhetoric go hand in hand together, the same way that images are

    signs and concepts are imagitistic (p. 9). According to him, the Baroque is the sublime as

    opposed to the beautiful Cartesian perspective.

    The author sees the baroque regime taking over the hegemonic power that Cartesian

    perspectivalism once had. This is due to the rise of hermeneutics and post-structuralism that

    challenge scientific epistemology. However, he sees this as a slightly dangerous move, since the

    other regimes are no more closer to true vision (p.10) than the Cartesian. He pleads, on the

    contrary, to maintain a plurality of scopic regimes, and explore all negative and positive aspects

    of each.

    The Age of Show

    Illich (1998; 2001) describes a more recent phenomenon, which is that viewpoints are no

    longer affected by standpoints. Since the 70s, virtual spaces make the individual standpoint-less,

    directing where he/she looks, manipulating the visible world, in order to seduce the eyes and

    swallow up the consumer . The eye is trained for perception and interpretation of appearances

    that could never be touched. (1998, p.15) This is also called the resorptive gaze. The act of

    seeing becomes digital, that of recording. Seeing is now dull and segregated from the fleshly

    presence of the other (2001, p.20). Illich calls the last thirty years the Age of the Show,

    because what the eyes do is replicate replications. The actual person behind the image is no

    longer reached out for.The representations are no longer views, but measurements of

  • The Value of Aesthetics in the Ecological Crisis of Reason 31

    instruments; no longer things that people can walk to or grab or reach, but things as they are in

    a distant and unreachable objective reality. People are trained to see graphic shows of things that

    are invisible to their natural eye, and to take them for reality. This does not mean only

    microscopic images, but also graphic representations of abstract notions such as Gross National

    Product and population growth and climate change (2001, p.22). See figure 6.

    Instead of critically reading the image, to grasp essential truths of the world (even if

    changing ones), peoples perception is now merely the gateway for directly objectified and

    distorted reality, which takes the measurements of instruments for direct reality.

    FIGURE 6 POPULATION GROWTH MADE VISIBLE, (POPULATION GROWTH, 2008).

  • The Value of Aesthetics in the Ecological Crisis of Reason 32

    ETHICAL GAZE

    It can be concluded from the studies above that there are various ways of viewing reality

    with the carnal eye, and that there is a certain visual hegemony during different historical

    periods. What can also be stated, and most importantly, is that depending on the understanding of

    the gaze, humans may or may not gaze with the awareness of ethical repercussions involved in

    the act. The two positions, the passive objective gaze and the active ethical gaze will be

    juxtaposed in this section. This dualistic contrast will merely be done for the sake of finding

    differences. There are of course different gradients of active perception and passive action

    (consumerism).

    GAZE AS ACTION

    Until a certain point in history one had to guard the eyes, for the gaze was a powerful

    action, says Illich (2001). The eyes can be trained just as the ears can be trained by music and

    taste can be trained by food. His view is inspired by the virtue ethics of Aristotle. The training of

    the senses is also fundamental to character formation, since the realization that the gaze is an

    action, has implication to the disciplined reflection of this action which builds up personal

    habits, character and attitudes. In other words, it has implications for ethics, especially for

    Aristotelian virtue ethics, in which attitudes are built. The eyes can be trained as a skill just the

    way that one learns to walk and talk virtuously. The propensities of the gaze must be understood

    along with what might be detrimental to character and what might harm others. Illich further

    recognizes the age of the show as detrimental to this virtuous life. Perceptions should be

    synesthetic; the eye should not be segregated from other senses or from the fleshy presence of

    other beings.

    Illich pointed out that when the gaze is action, to be more specific a kind of relational

    action, it needs to be considered morally. It seems to him that the gaze has been more and more

    detached from the body and attained less moral responsibilities. That this development is parallel

    to the development of contemporary capitalist western culture has been more explicitly

  • The Value of Aesthetics in the Ecological Crisis of Reason 33

    demonstrated by Jay (1998). At the same time that the gaze got exempted from its moral

    responsibilities, the object of appreciation became a commodity that could be controlled and

    dominated. The path to a virtuous aesthetics will be one which leads humans to actively

    experiences in a moral relational manner. This aesthetics will make it impossible to objectify and

    commodify, for the body is no longer separated from action. Instead of being an instrument of

    action, the body is part of a character which is in constant relation to others.

    GAZE AS NON-ACTION: PATHOLOGICAL

    According to Kant, aesthetic or empirical judgments can never be moral judgments

    (Rueger, 2007). Aesthetics has then been fundamentally separated from morality for centuries.

    This is probably due to the Cartesian separation of morality in the mind from empirical or

    emotional experience in the body. Scientific explanations of vision that can be learnt in high

    school textbooks only talk about the light which comes into the eyes.

    Illich made clear that the less active the gaze becomes, the less agency and character the

    gaze has and also the less ethical it is. It appears that the conaturality of the gaze and world,

    along with synesthesia (or connectivity of senses) is essential for the construction of ethical

    relationships. When the gaze is absorbed, as in the resorptive gaze, in a world of fiction, it has to

    rely on appearance and less on intentions and relationships. Living is then no longer about

    relationships and full embodiment, but is more like a vegetative state of dreaminess. This feeding

    of sensory signals, a conditioning, resembles the image of the broiler chickens in the chicken

    factory. The same concern for other species can thus be directed to those, humans, who concern.

    It has already been mentioned above that the Cartesian perspectivalism, or the gaze

    exempted from character and action, can be detrimental for the environment, for it justifies

    control and domination. Yet there is another account for why the gaze that is not self-aware is

    pathological. It comes from a post-structuralist perspective on impairment. Although this

    discussion is about impairment, it can be interchangeably applied to non-humans, which are by

    definition lacking human perfection.

    Hughes (1999) has written on the aesthetic of oppression through the perspective of

    impairment as a critique of modernity. The author also writes on a scopic regime, which the

  • The Value of Aesthetics in the Ecological Crisis of Reason 34

    author calls the scopic regime of modernity. According to him, modernity is characterized as the

    production of strangers, which this paper can compare to the characteristics of duality as laid out

    by Plumwood. Strangers are conceived as a disturbance from and a threat to the order. The

    treatment to strangers is then exclusionary (tolerance) or assimilative (neglect of differences),

    which again resemble Plumwoods radical exclusion and incorporation. The author then

    formulates that these treatment strategies are executed through the gaze which casts out images

    of normality (p. 157). See figure 7.

    The gaze works in positive social sciences and biomedicine, where observations

    determine what is normalized or pathological. Normative order is taken uncritically for an

    empirical given, through the disembodied gaze. However, vision does not provide immediate

    access to the external world as Cartesian perspectivalism suggests (Illich and Jay would agree).

    The aesthetic view on the production of knowledge sees through how vision is blurred by

    interpretation. The Cartesian attitude of seeing is believing, is simply an attitude, although a

    powerful one.

    Hughes explains the discursive power of the gaze through Sartre, who talks about the

    gaze which victimizes its object and is hostile and alienating in its intersubjectivity: the self is

    limited by the temporalization and spatialization of the others gaze. This is why supervision

    FIGURE 7 THE GAZE CASTS OUT IMAGES OF NORMALITY, ASSIMILATING OR EXCLUDING STRANGERS (DOWN SYNDROME, 2012; MONKEY TALKS, 2012).

  • The Value of Aesthetics in the Ecological Crisis of Reason 35

    corresponds to loss of freedom (of being). This is the rise of the power of vision and the

    panopticum in the sense of manipulation and domination rather than oppression. Along with this

    comes the understanding of the act of gazing as a carnal validation and invalidation, constitutive

    of a moral, aesthetic, cognitive and political point of view. Non-disablement reaffirms itself

    through the disabled lack of perfection that stems from discourses. The author further argues that

    the gaze constructed from non-disablement is pathological. It is pathological in the sense that it is

    not self-aware, not recognizing its roots in discourses (moral, medicine and aesthetics) that are

    not neutral as they claim to be, but are rather immersed in mythologies of normality, truth,

    beauty and perfection (p. 164).

    Finally, there are two political themes of the aesthetic of oppression: the tyranny of

    perfection and personal tragedy theory. The first constitutes the fact that beauty has become the

    form in which morality is recognized in the post-modern world (or current culture of

    appearances). This is how a strong and fetishized body is seen as a mark of self-control. Even

    though people realized the flaw in such categorization, and try to take pride of their deviant

    appearances, this normalization still lives on through institutions.

    The personal tragedy theory describes how the disability of people is individualized so

    that it does not change capitalist social and economic structures. Just as poor people are

    stigmatized as weak in character, so are disabled people (or animals) in need of charity. People

    have recognized the problem described by the personal tragedy theory, but they have attacked

    only the economic system of capitalist production.The power of the gaze which maintains the

    image of personal tragedy, however, is left untouched.

    Modernitys vision is looking for a perspective, a fixed point that will freeze the flow of

    visions own dynamism: it gathers the world in itself with the certainty that there is nothing else

    worth seeing (p. 169). However, gazing is not biologically determined, it needs training. The

    technological visualization is an aid in this training of constructing a hyper-real reality. This

    training leads to a philosophy of life, one that in its extreme has lead to the disposal of strangers

    in the holocaust. The irrational extermination of demonized insects is another manifestation of

    this problem (see figure 8). The myth of Aryan perfection has been replaced by the myth of

    beauty, and is still present as a scopic regime in the contemporary consumption life style culture.

    This myth of beauty and stereotype creations, which Hughes describes, may of course also be in

    the way of understanding ways of living with humans and other species. It might even be that

  • The Value of Aesthetics in the Ecological Crisis of Reason 36

    nature is now inevitably seen as tragic and in need for charity and human directed control, while

    the power of the gaze and its myths slowly disappear from the mind.

    It must be said though that Hughes rejects the gaze of modernity that discerns pathology

    from normality at the same time that he describes the modern gaze as pathological himself. One

    must always be careful with installing one type of normality in replacement of another. Thus,

    while these critiques of the modern gaze may be valid, one needs to be careful with the

    imposition of alternative gazes. Both Jay and Illich have demonstrated how innovations in

    aesthetic work, be it scientific, artistic or philosophical have their impacts on the habits of

    society. Aesthetic experience can be further linked to morality through the construction and

    interpretation of representation.

    FIGURE 7 KILL THE FILTHY COCKROACH! (AFASTANDO BARATAS, 2012).

  • The Value of Aesthetics in the Ecological Crisis of Reason 37

    IDEOLOGICAL AESTHETICS

    CULTURAL POLITICS OF REPRESENTATION

    The book Representing the Environment by Gold & Revill (2004) offers a good basis

    for the understanding of environmental representations, and their role in the relation between

    individual action and social structure. Media is a means of aesthetic reproduction and exchange

    (Gold & Revill, 2004). Media is the transmission of content in symbolic form to the audience,

    which includes clothes, food packaging and cinema (Gold & Revill, 2004). Commodities,

    including actual designed environments, can thus also be seen as media. Because signs are

    arbitrary and do not directly correspond to their signified meaning, there needs to be an active

    perception of media (Gold & Revill, 2004). At the extremes of the continuum of views on the

    relationship between representation, meaning and social value, there are two points of view:

    Voluntarism and Determinism. In the first theory, meaning is created by individuals own

    interpretational choices (Gold & Revill, 2004). In that view, humans are also the sole cause of

    their own actions, uninfluenced by exterior forces. The determinist theory goes against that idea,

    stating that individual creation and interpretation of representations, and according values and

    behaviour, are products of external forces (Gold & Revill, 2004). None of these views are

    plausible, for the reality is rather complex (Gold & Revill, 2004). One can thus not say that art

    and representation simply determines the individual gaze or perception.

    However, environmental representations can influence individuals perceptions in a

    variety of ways. Representations reflect the social organization of institutions,which in turn

    reflect ideologies (Gold and Revill, 2004). In this context, ideology can be defined as the

    system of signification which facilitates the pursuit of particular group interests and which

    sustain specific relations of domination (Gold and Revill, 2004,p. 59). That is to say, one

    ideology seeks to dominate others (Gold and Revill, 2004). Ideology contains ideas, beliefs and

    images which compete or antagonize with other groups ideologies (Gold and Revill, 2004). All

    institutions who produce representation have viewpoints, which are expressions of their own

    interests (ideologies), and which they offer to their consumers to adopt (Gold and Revill, 2004).

  • The Value of Aesthetics in the Ecological Crisis of Reason 38

    Of course, the audience gives meaning to it only through their own understanding and

    motives in the world (Gold & Revill, 2004). It is important to complement this understanding by

    seeing this understanding and consuming of ideologies as a loop rather than a one-directional

    process. The way that people understand the world affects ideologies and the way that ideologies

    are presented affects their understanding of the world. An important concept to illustrate the

    interconnectedness of representations and understanding of the world ishabitus: the same

    material which regulates and limits life is the material that can be used creatively to create new

    circumstances. This concept can be applied to representations, where the symbolic and practical

    are often intermeshed:the making and interpretation of representations both reproduces and

    remakes, or creates anew, the social relations on which they initially depend (Gold and Revill,

    p. 52). Representations and practices are thus in constant dialogue and negotiation (Gold &

    Revill, 2004).

    At this point the term cultural politics, which is the intersection between cultural and

    political dimensions in representations, becomes important. This intersection involves questions

    concerning who has the power or which is the dominant culture that is behind the meanings and

    values of representations (Gold & Revill, 2004). This does not mean that only those in power are

    the ones behind representations, although their representation may be more legitimatized.

    Environmental issues can be represented through cultural politics that express nationalism,

    racism and sexism (Gold & Revill, 2004). By contrast, minorities may represent environmental

    degradation as a link to their own oppression and urge to fix this through a new values and

    identities (Gold & Revill, 2004). This means that certain groups oppose each other through the

    power that they give their values in these representations (Gold & Revill, 2004). One can see

    here thus that in order to understand the environmental crisis one has to understand the social

    conflicts that are related to it. The cultural politics of representations has the following key

    powers: The power to name, the power to represent common sense, the power to create official

    versions, and the power to present the legitimate social world (Gold & Revill, 2004). See figure

    9; the power to represent common sense and create official versions are featured through the

    clich you are what you eat and the depiction of people who eat genetically engineered food as

    aberrations.

  • The Value of Aesthetics in the Ecological Crisis of Reason 39

    FIGURE 8 ENVIRONMENTAL ACTIVISM, (GOLD & REVILL, 2004, P. 66).

    Gold and Revill further describe strategies that reinforce dominant readings of

    representations: coercion, persuasion and negotiation. Coercion means regulations of what can

    be said in public. Persuasion involves strategies that justify commonsense. Negotiation is

    consensus building and suppression of differences. Dominant readings of representations occur

    through hegemony:Hegemony describes the way that politically powerful groups maintain their

    power by presenting their view of the world as commonsense and part of the natural order for

    those who are in fact subordinated by it (p. 69). In this sense, representation is not fixed and is

  • The Value of Aesthetics in the Ecological Crisis of Reason 40

    based on negotiation that perpetuates the hegemony (Gold and Revill, 2004). That is not really

    favourable to the minority, when it is the sort of assimilation as described by Plumwood and

    Hughes.

    Another powerful tool of hegemony, as described by Foucault, is discourse. A discourse

    is a regulated way of speaking or writing about the world, where regulated means that it takes

    place according to the rules and conventions of the society and its culture (Gold and Revill,

    2004, p. 74). Discourses create symbolic knowledge of objects because of its coherence, self-

    referentiatlity, account of reality and because the rules of what can be said and known (truth,

    beauty and good) are shaped by the very same discourse (Gold and Revill, 2004). There are

    formal and informal discourses (Gold and Revill, 2004). Aesthetics is a formal discourse (Gold

    and Revill, 2004), and watching a picturesque motion picture on the TV is an informal discourse.

    In discourses, who has the knowledge has the power, and regulation of action is more efficacious

    within a discourse (Gold and Revill, 2004). Discourses constitute individuals identities and

    subjectivities (Gold and Revill, 2004), because they regulate the way in which people give

    meaning to their practices. In figure 9, one can see the Frankenstein monsters, which are

    embedded in an informal discourse where GMOs are simply abnormal. Interestingly, the

    abnormal is at the same time an aesthetic negative, intended to provoke disgust and disapproval.

    The note on the side of the poster includes Personally in order to internalize the regulation of

    boycotting genetically engineered food: Combining the practical and the symbolic, the material

    and the social, discourse stresses the hybrid qualities of social life (p. 76).

    Thus, although there needs to be an active reception of media, there are a variety of tools

    to convince and enforce ways of understanding the world. One of these ways is the discourse of

    aesthetics, which cannot be seen separately from the rules and conventions of society and its

    culture (Gold and Revill, 2004, p. 74), or ideology. Later on, the notions and concepts of

    environmental aesthetics will be analyzed by these terms.

  • The Value of Aesthetics in the Ecological Crisis of Reason 41

    ENVIRONMENTAL DESIGN

    Another scholar who confirms the socio-political dimensions of aesthetics, argues that

    although environments are largely perceived as a symbol of social and political relations,

    professionals involved in their design never regard that (Appleyard, 1979). Moreover, the citizen

    of urban environments has formerly been seen as a passive observer of the city, but this situation

    is changing through political movements concerned not only with the transformation of

    production but also of consumption (Appleyard, 1979). This trend will be later elaborated upon

    under Ethical Consumption.

    Appleyard (1979) pleads for recognition of the intentions of environmental change,

    which are intentions towards the self, the action or others. Often, the motive for environmental

    action is masked as instrumental or aesthetic, because personal intentions are not regarded as

    professional. This creates a lack of communication between the different parties involved in the

    environmental creation and consumption: initiators (initiative takers), executives (designers),

    monitors (citizens) and interpreters (media).

    Behind aesthetics there are more motives than just form, space and texture, according to

    Appleyard. In the aesthetic lies the creation of symbolism for self-identity, especially in

    contemporary culture. Especially the poor, powerless and new migrants have this need for

    aesthetic display; the rich try to be modest and hide their power. Communication of power and

    expression of group identity is thus an integral part of aesthetic display in environmental action.

    When this is not recognized, but rather done invisibly, social-environmental conflicts cannot be

    approached correctly. This error is parallel to the development that people are more and more

    dependent on appearances to learn what is going on (p. 150), since social meaning is

    dematerialized in myths of social media and academia. Appleyards discussion adds up to Illichs

    and Hughes concern about the role of aesthetic experience which is based only on appearances,

    lacking the dimension of a critical gaze which investigates the depths of being. Apparently this

    lack of recognition of social intentions is connected to the reliance on appearances; the shallow

    look is a form of relating.

    This transference of social meaning to myths also causes people depend on appearances

    and to forget the origins of environmental conflicts. This means that people will fight over the

    design or utility of an environment, instead of social inequality, for instance. As he phrases it:

  • The Value of Aesthetics in the Ecological Crisis of Reason 42

    (..) perhaps environmental conflicts occur in cases where social meaning is especially critical.

    (p. 150). Appleyard finds the distinction of distance and home to be the most relevant in

    environmental conflicts. Since distance is symbolically light, planners and tourists depend on

    appearances to attribute social meaning, which by virtue of its superficiality is idealized,

    mythological and stereotypical. At the same time, distance can be a search for authenticity and

    identity, which is characteristic of tourism. There is also certain imperialism in the reactions of

    people in their home-places when strangers arrive. The distance between people can also

    reinforce identity, however also superficial and stereotypical that may be.

    CONSTRUCTION OF SUBJECTIVITY

    A more direct link between aesthetics and ideology is made by Eagleton (1990), in his

    book The Ideology of the Aesthetic. In eighteenth century Germany, the call for an aesthetic

    was part of a result of absolutist power (p. 14). Philosophers realized that the political order

    rested solely on the ruling rationality and overlooked the whole world of sensations and passions.

    Exempted from political and financial power, the bourgeoisie sought its supremacy in its

    intellectual and cultural Enlightenment. In order for absolutist power to be perpetrated, not only

    reason but also the sensitive life needs to be under its rule. Aesthetics needed to bring the

    inferior sensuous in union with the supreme reason. In this, aesthetics is autonomous but at the

    same time guided and informed by the rules of reason. This can be seen in the search for

    appropriate aesthetic judgments, which need to be guided by Cartesianscientific knowledge in

    one way or another. The law of the aesthetic is an inferior sort of law which the individual is

    willing to obey, because of its pleasant component.

    However, at the same time that Aesthetics is employed in structures of power, it can be

    used for the liberation from it, argues the Marxist Eagleton. It is in this period of modernity that

    epistemology, ethics and aesthetics have become separated. While once, ethics has been

    intermeshed with aesthetics, (in a way that to do the right thing feels good), now art has become

    autonomous. However, this autonomy was only possible since art has been integrated into the

    capitalist mode of production, into the commodity production. It has been released from its social

    functions, and has ceased to be the medium of ethics. Aesthetics as a philosophical field has

  • The Value of Aesthetics in the Ecological Crisis of Reason 43

    been born when art could be used for political forces. Only it is used in a way that everything

    should become aesthetic now (p. 363): truth and morality are also governed by what is

    pleasurable and fashionable (instead of the other way around). On the other hand, it is used as a

    mute guerrilla medium that subverts subjugation, gets out of the semantics and representation

    that oppresses. It becomes negative aesthetics that is a mute gesture of resistance upon social

    order, something that can be shown, but not spoken, and is thus incompetent for politics (p.

    376). Aesthetics is a highly contradictory concept and its meanings and values can serve a

    counter-hegemonic goal as well as the hegemonic project. Eagleton adverts that aesthetics must

    be served along with dialectic in order to make a real difference. Because Eagleton does not deal

    with environmental aesthetics in particular, this paper will elaborate more on a similar finding by

    Morton later on.

    CLOSING REMARKS

    The scopic regimes have revealed a development of perception paradigms. The gaze has

    proven to be malleable, trained by social, cultural and historical forces. A certain scopicregime,

    the modernist, has been linked to commoditization. The regime following the latter is theAge of

    Show, which contains the gaze that is trained for consumption. These regimes seem to form the

    example of how one ought not to develop the ethical sensitivities which Plumwood has talked

    about. When the gaze is embodied in a relational and virtuously developing character, it would

    not be fit for consumerism. It is thus possible that this could be used in the development of

    ethical sensitivities. Hughes has demonstrated how one ought to be aware of the myths and

    limitations upon which the (aesthetic) gaze is grounded, in order to avoid aesthetic oppression.

    He also remarked that the current oppressing myth is ideal Beauty. Subsequently, the research

    focused on the social and cultural forces that would influence aesthetic perception, or even train

    it. Environmental representations convey ideological messages and attempt to normalize

    symbolic meaning in images. Sometimes images express social meanings that people do not or

    cannot express in daily life, because they are creations of new social meaning based on old

    structures. This same phenomenon occurs in environmental design, where aesthetics serves to

    mediate unspoken intentions of the designer.

  • The Value of Aesthetics in the Ecological Crisis of Reason 44

    The loss of legitimacy of material, aesthetic social meaning on the one hand, and the

    transference of meaning to academic myths on the other, forces people to rely on superficial

    appearances in