the stakeholder theory of the corporation concepts evidence and implications donaldson preston 1995

28
The Stakeholder Theory of the Corporation: Concepts, Evidence, and Implications Author(s): Thomas Donaldson and Lee E. Preston Reviewed work(s): Source: The Academy of Management Review, Vol. 20, No. 1 (Jan., 1995), pp. 65-91 Published by: Academy of Management Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/258887 . Accessed: 26/04/2012 10:31 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Academy of Management is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Academy of Management Review. http://www.jstor.org

Upload: angelicazz

Post on 14-Aug-2015

574 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: The Stakeholder Theory of the Corporation Concepts Evidence and Implications Donaldson Preston 1995

The Stakeholder Theory of the Corporation: Concepts, Evidence, and ImplicationsAuthor(s): Thomas Donaldson and Lee E. PrestonReviewed work(s):Source: The Academy of Management Review, Vol. 20, No. 1 (Jan., 1995), pp. 65-91Published by: Academy of ManagementStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/258887 .Accessed: 26/04/2012 10:31

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range ofcontent in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new formsof scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

Academy of Management is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Academyof Management Review.

http://www.jstor.org

Page 2: The Stakeholder Theory of the Corporation Concepts Evidence and Implications Donaldson Preston 1995

? Academy of Management Review 1995, Vol. 20, No. 1, 65-91.

THE STAKEHOLDER THEORY OF THE CORPORATION: CONCEPTS, EVIDENCE,

AND IMPLICATIONS

THOMAS DONALDSON Georgetown University

LEE E. PRESTON University of Maryland

The stakeholder theory has been advanced and justified in the man- agement literature on the basis of its descriptive accuracy, instrumen- tal power, and normative validity. These three aspects of the theory, although interrelated, are quite distinct; they involve different types of evidence and argument and have different implications. In this article, we examine these three aspects of the theory and critique and integrate important contributions to the literature related to each. We conclude that the three aspects of stakeholder theory are mutually supportive and that the normative base of the theory-which includes the modern theory of property rights-is fundamental.

If the unity of the corporate body is real, then there is reality and not simply legal fiction in the proposition that the man- agers of the unit are fiduciaries for it and not merely for its individual members, that they are . . . trustees for an institu- tion [with multiple constituents] rather than attorneys for the stockholders.

E. Merrick Dodd, Jr. Harvard Law Review, 1932

The idea that corporations have stakeholders has now become com- monplace in the management literature, both academic and professional. Since the publication of Freeman's landmark book, Strategic Manage- ment: A Stakeholder Approach (1984), about a dozen books and more than 100 articles with primary emphasis on the stakeholder concept have ap- peared. (Significant recent examples include books by Alkhafaji, 1989; Anderson, 1989; and Brummer, 1991; and articles by Brenner & Cochran, 1991; Clarkson, 1991; Goodpaster, 1991; Hill & Jones, 1992; and Wood, 1991a,b; plus numerous papers by Freeman and various collaborators,

The development of this article benefited greatly from discussions held at the Confer- ence on Stakeholder Theory at the University of Toronto, May 1993, and from the specific comments of many people, including Professors Aupperle, Carroll, Clarkson, Halal, Free- man, Jones, and Sethi.

65

Page 3: The Stakeholder Theory of the Corporation Concepts Evidence and Implications Donaldson Preston 1995

66 Academy of Management Review January

individually cited.) Stakeholder management is the central theme of at least one important recent business and society text (Carroll, 1989), and a diagram purporting to represent the stakeholder model has become a standard element of "Introduction to Management" lectures and writings.

Unfortunately, anyone looking into this large and evolving literature with a critical eye will observe that the concepts stakeholder, stakeholder model, stakeholder management, and stakeholder theory are explained and used by various authors in very different ways and supported (or critiqued) with diverse and often contradictory evidence and arguments. Moreover, this diversity and its implications are rarely discussed-and possibly not even recognized. (The blurred character of the stakeholder concept is also emphasized by Brummer, 1991.) The purpose of this article is to point out some of the more important distinctions, problems, and implications associated with the stakeholder concept, as well as to clarify and justify its essential content and significance.

In the following section we contrast the stakeholder model of the corporation with the conventional input-output model of the firm and sum- marize our central thesis. We next present the three aspects of stake- holder theory -descriptive/empirical, instrumental, and normative found in the literature and clarify the critical differences among them. We then raise the issue of justification: Why would anyone accept the stake- holder theory over alternative conceptions of the corporation? In subse- quent sections, we present and evaluate the underlying evidence and arguments justifying the theory from the perspective of descriptive, in- strumental, and normative justifications. We conclude that the three ap- proaches to stakeholder theory, although quite different, are mutually supportive and that the normative base serves as the critical underpin- ning for the theory in all its forms.

THE CENTRAL THESES

We summarize our central theses here:

Thesis 1: The stakeholder theory is unarguably descrip- tive. It presents a model describing what the corporation is. It describes the corporation as a constellation of co- operative and competitive interests possessing intrinsic value. Aspects of this model may be tested for descrip- tive accuracy: Is this model more descriptively accurate than rival models? Moreover, do observers and partici- pants, in fact, see the corporation this way? The model can also serve as a framework for testing any empirical claims, including instrumental predictions, relevant to the stakeholder concept (but not for testing the concept's normative base).

Thesis 2: The stakeholder theory is also instrumental. It

Page 4: The Stakeholder Theory of the Corporation Concepts Evidence and Implications Donaldson Preston 1995

1995 Donaldson and Preston 67

establishes a framework for examining the connections, if any, between the practice of stakeholder manage- ment and the achievement of various corporate perfor- mance goals. The principal focus of interest here has been the proposition that corporations practicing stake- holder management will, other things being equal, be relatively successful in conventional performance terms (profitability, stability, growth, etc.).

Thesis 3: Although Theses 1 and 2 are significant aspects of the stakeholder theory, its fundamental basis is nor- mative and involves acceptance of the following ideas: (a) Stakeholders are persons or groups with legitimate interests in procedural and/or substantive aspects of cor- porate activity. Stakeholders are identified by their in- terests in the corporation, whether the corporation has any corresponding functional interest in them. (b) The interests of all stakeholders are of intrinsic value. That is, each group of stakeholders merits consideration for its own sake and not merely because of its ability to further the interests of some other group, such as the shareowners.

Thesis 4: The stakeholder theory is managerial in the broad sense of that term. It does not simply describe existing situations or predict cause-effect relationships; it also recommends attitudes, structures, and practices that, taken together, constitute stakeholder manage- ment. Stakeholder management requires, as its key attribute, simultaneous attention to the legitimate inter- ests of all appropriate stakeholders, both in the estab- lishment of organizational structures and general poli- cies and in case-by-case decision making. This requirement holds for anyone managing or affecting corporate policies, including not only professional man- agers, but shareowners, the government, and others. Stakeholder theory does not necessarily presume that managers are the only rightful locus of corporate control and governance. Nor does the requirement of simulta- neous attention to stakeholder interests resolve the long- standing problem of identifying stakeholders and eval- uating their legitimate "stakes" in the corporation. The theory does not imply that all stakeholders (however they may be identified) should be equally involved in all processes and decisions.

The distinction between a stakeholder conception of the corporation and a conventional input-output perspective is highlighted by the con-

Page 5: The Stakeholder Theory of the Corporation Concepts Evidence and Implications Donaldson Preston 1995

68 Academy of Management Review January

trasting models displayed in Figures 1 and 2. In Figure 1, investors, employees, and suppliers are depicted as contributing inputs, which the "black box" of the firm transforms into outputs for the benefit of customers. To be sure, each contributor of inputs expects to receive ap- propriate compensation, but the liberal economics, or "Adam Smith" in- terpretation, of this model in long-run equilibrium is that input contribu- tors, at the margin, receive only "normal" or "market competitive" benefits (i.e., the benefits that they would obtain from some alternative use of their resources and time). Individual contributors who are partic- ularly advantaged, such as possessors of scarce locations or skills, will, of course, receive "rents," but the rewards of the marginal contributors will only be "normal." As a result of competition throughout the system, the bulk of the benefits will go to the customers. (There is, of course, a Marxist-capitalist version of this model in which both the customer and the investor arrows are reversed, and the object of the game is merely to produce benefits for the investors. This interpretation now seems to be confined almost exclusively to the field of finance.)

The stakeholder model (Figure 2) contrasts explicitly with the input- output model in all its variations. Stakeholder analysts argue that all persons or groups with legitimate interests participating in an enterprise do so to obtain benefits and that there is no prima facie priority of one set of interests and benefits over another. Hence, the arrows between the firm and its stakeholder constituents run in both directions. All stakeholder relationships are depicted in the same size and shape and are equidistant from the "black box" of the firm in the center. The distinctive features of this conception, as contrasted with conventional input-output concep- tions, will become apparent as our analysis proceeds.

This summary of the stakeholder theory and our discussion through- out this article refer specifically to the theory's application to the investor-

FIGURE 1 Contrasting Models of the Corporation: Input-Output Model

Investors

Suppliers - FIRM -* ustomersg

Empl oyee

Page 6: The Stakeholder Theory of the Corporation Concepts Evidence and Implications Donaldson Preston 1995

1995 Donaldson and Preston 69

FIGURE 2 Contrasting Models of the Corporation: The Stakeholder Model

Governments Investors Poitical Groups

Suppliers FIRM Customers

Trade Associations Employe C ommunities

owned corporation. Although stakeholder concepts have been applied in other settings (e.g., government agencies and social programs), these situations are fundamentally different, and simultaneous discussion of a variety of possible stakeholder relationships leads, in our view, to con- fusion rather than clarification. The critical corporate stakeholder issues, both in theory and in practice, involve evidentiary considerations and conceptual issues (e.g., the meaning of property rights) unique to the corporate setting.

It is also worth noting at the outset that the extent to which the stake- holder theory is understood to represent a controversial or challenging approach to conventional views varies greatly among market capitalist economies. These differences are highlighted in a recent issue of The Economist (1993: 52):

In America, for instance, shareholders have a compara- tively big say in the running of the enterprises they own; work- ers . . . have much less influence. In many European coun- tries, shareholders have less say and workers more . . . [I]n Japan . . . managers have been left alone to run their compa- nies as they see fit-namely for the benefit of employees and of allied companies, as much as for shareholders.

ALTERNATIVE ASPECTS OF STAKEHOLDER THEORY: DESCRIPTIVE/EMPIRICAL, INSTRUMENTAL, AND NORMATIVE

One of the central problems in the evolution of stakeholder theory has been confusion about its nature and purpose. For example, stakeholder theory has been used, either explicitly or implicitly, for descriptive pur- poses. Brenner and Cochran (1991: 452) offered a "stakeholder theory of the firm" for "two purposes: to describe how organizations operate and to help predict organizational behavior." They contrasted this "theory,"

Page 7: The Stakeholder Theory of the Corporation Concepts Evidence and Implications Donaldson Preston 1995

70 Academy of Management Review January

which they developed only in outline form, with other "theories of the firm," but they did not ask whether the various theories cited have com- parable purposes.

In fact, different theories have different purposes and therefore dif- ferent validity criteria and different implications. For example, according to Cyert and March (1963), the neoclassical theory of the firm attempts to explain the economic principles governing production, investment, and pricing decisions of established firms operating in competitive markets. In contrast, their behavioral theory of the firm attempts to explain the process of decision making in the modern firm in terms of goals, expec- tations, and choice-making procedures. Aoki's (1984) cooperative game theory of the firm attempts to explain internal governance, particularly the balance between owners' and workers' interests. In contrast to all of these contributions, transaction cost theory attempts to explain why firms exist (i.e., why economic activities are coordinated through formal orga- nizations rather than simply through market contacts) (Coase, 1937; Williamson & Winter, 1991). (Although all of these theories are put for- ward as "positive" or "scientific" conceptions, there is a tendency for them to be used for normative purposes as well.)

The stakeholder theory differs from these and other "theories of the firm" in fundamental ways. The stakeholder theory is intended both to explain and to guide the structure and operation of the established cor- poration (the "going concern" in John R. Commons' famous phrase). To- ward that end it views the corporation as an organizational entity through which numerous and diverse participants accomplish multiple, and not always entirely congruent, purposes. The stakeholder theory is general and comprehensive, but it is not empty; it goes well beyond the descrip- tive observation that "organizations have stakeholders." Unfortunately, much of what passes for stakeholder theory in the literature is implicit rather than explicit, which is one reason why diverse and sometimes confusing uses of the stakeholder concept have not attracted more atten- tion.

The stakeholder theory can be, and has been, presented and used in a number of ways that are quite distinct and involve very different meth- odologies, types of evidence, and criteria of appraisal. Three types of uses are critical to our analysis.

Descriptive/Empirical

The theory is used to describe, and sometimes to explain, specific corporate characteristics and behaviors. For example, stakeholder theory has been used to describe (a) the nature of the firm (Brenner & Cochran, 1991), (b) the way managers think about managing (Brenner & Molander, 1977), (c) how board members think about the interests of corporate con- stituencies (Wang & Dewhirst, 1992), and (d) how some corporations are actually managed (Clarkson, 1991; Halal, 1990; Kreiner & Bhambri, 1991).

Page 8: The Stakeholder Theory of the Corporation Concepts Evidence and Implications Donaldson Preston 1995

1995 Donaldson and Preston 71

Instrumental

The theory, in conjunction with descriptive/empirical data where available, is used to identify the connections, or lack of connections, between stakeholder management and the achievement of traditional corporate objectives (e.g., profitability, growth). Many recent instrumen- tal studies of corporate social responsibility, all of which make explicit or implicit reference to stakeholder perspectives, use conventional statisti- cal methodologies (Aupperle, Carroll, & Hatfield, 1985; Barton, Hill, & Sundaram, 1989; Cochran & Wood, 1984; Cornell & Shapiro, 1987; McGuire, Sundgren, & Schneeweis, 1988; Preston & Sapienza, 1990; Pre- ston, Sapienza, & Miller, 1991). Other studies are based on direct obser- vation and interviews (Kotter & Heskett, 1992; O'Toole, 1985; see also, O'Toole, 1991). Whatever their methodologies, these studies have tended to generate "implications" suggesting that adherence to stakeholder prin- ciples and practices achieves conventional corporate performance objec- tives as well or better than rival approaches. Kotter and Heskett (1992) specifically observed that such highly successful companies as Hewlett- Packard, Wal-Mart, and Dayton Hudson-although very diverse in other ways-share a stakeholder perspective. Kotter and Heskett (1992: 59) wrote that "[a]lmost all [their] managers care strongly about people who have a stake in the business-customers, employees, stockholders, sup- pliers, etc."

Normative

The theory is used to interpret the function of the corporation, includ- ing the identification of moral or philosophical guidelines for the opera- tion and management of corporations. Normative concerns dominated the classic stakeholder theory statements from the beginning (Dodd, 1932), and this tradition has been continued in the most recent versions (Carroll, 1989; Kuhn & Shriver, 1991; Marcus, 1993). Even Friedman's (1970) famous attack on the concept of corporate social responsibility was cast in nor- mative terms.

Contrasting/Combining Approaches

Each of these uses of stakeholder theory is of some value, but the values differ in each use. The descriptive aspect of stakeholder theory reflects and explains past, present, and future states of affairs of corpo- rations and their stakeholders. Simple description is common and desir- able in the exploration of new areas and usually expands to generate explanatory and predictive propositions. (All such activities shall be called descriptive for our purposes.) Instrumental uses of stakeholder the- ory make a connection between stakeholder approaches and commonly desired objectives such as profitability. Instrumental uses usually stop short of exploring specific links between cause (i.e., stakeholder manage- ment) and effect (i.e., corporate performance) in detail, but such linkage

Page 9: The Stakeholder Theory of the Corporation Concepts Evidence and Implications Donaldson Preston 1995

72 Academy of Management Review January

is certainly implicit. The much-quoted Stanford Research Institute's (SRI) definition of stakeholders as "those groups without whose support the organization would cease to exist" (SRI, 1963; quoted in Freeman, 1984: 31) clearly implies that corporate managers must induce constructive contri- butions from their stakeholders to accomplish their own desired results (e.g., perpetuation of the organization, profitability, stability, growth).

In normative uses, the correspondence between the theory and the observed facts of corporate life is not a significant issue, nor is the asso- ciation between stakeholder management and conventional performance measures a critical test. Instead, a normative theory attempts to interpret the function of, and offer guidance about, the investor-owned corporation on the basis of some underlying moral or philosophical principles. Al- though both normative and instrumental analyses may be "prescriptive" (i.e., they may express or imply more or less appropriate choices on the part of decision makers), they rest on entirely different bases. An instru- mental approach is essentially hypothetical; it says, in effect, "If you want to achieve (avoid) results X, Y, or Z, then adopt (don't adopt) princi- ples and practices A, B, or C." The normative approach, in contrast, is not hypothetical but categorical; it says, in effect, "Do (Don't do) this because it is the right (wrong) thing to do." Much of the stakeholder literature, including the contributions of both proponents and critics, is clearly nor- mative, although the fundamental normative principles involved are of- ten unexamined.

A striking characteristic of the stakeholder literature is that diverse theoretical approaches are often combined without acknowledgement. Indeed, the temptation to seek a three-in-one theory-or at least to slide easily from one theoretical base to another-is strong. Clarkson (1991: 349), for example, asserted an explicit connection among all three when he concluded that his stakeholder management model represents a new framework for "describing, evaluating, and managing corporate social performance."

All three types of theory are also to be found in the work of Freeman, whom many regard as the leading contributor to the stakeholder litera- ture. In his original treatise, he asserted that changing events create a descriptive fit for the theory:

Just as the separation of the owner-manager-employee required a rethinking of the concept of control and private property as analyzed by Berle and Means (1932), so does the emergence of numerous stakeholder groups and new strategic issues require a rethinking of our traditional picture of the firm. . We must redraw the picture in a way that accounts for the changes. (1984: 24)

At the same time, he also endorsed the theory's instrumental basis. We should, he noted, "explore the logic of this concept in practical terms, i.e., in terms of how organizations can succeed in the current and future business environment" (1984: 25). Instrumental concerns are also reflected

Page 10: The Stakeholder Theory of the Corporation Concepts Evidence and Implications Donaldson Preston 1995

1995 Donaldson and Preston 73

in Freeman's extensive discussion of stakeholder management imple- mentation techniques, both in his 1984 treatise and in other papers (Free- man & Gilbert, 1987; Freeman & Reed, 1983). In a later work, however, Evan and Freeman (1988: 97) justified stakeholder theory on normative grounds, specifically its power to satisfy the moral rights of individuals. They asserted that the theory of the firm must be reconceptualized "along essentially Kantian lines." This means each stakeholder group has a right to be treated as an end in itself, and not as means to some other end, "and therefore must participate in determining the future direction of the firm in which [it has] a stake."

The muddling of theoretical bases and objectives, although often un- derstandable, has led to less rigorous thinking and analysis than the stakeholder concept requires. To see the significance of the distinctions among descriptive, instrumental, and normative uses of the stakeholder concept, consider the current controversy over the special privileges of top managers in large corporations, particularly in connection with merg- ers and acquisitions. There is considerable evidence that in the burst of large corporate takeovers during the 1980s, share values typically rose for acquired firms and fell for acquiring firms. Many observers have specu- lated that self-serving managerial activity accounts for both results (Jensen, 1989; Weidenbaum & Vogt, 1987). The acquired firms gain in value because, prior to the takeover, they were burdened by inefficient, self-serving managers, and the acquiring firms lose in value because the impetus for the acquisition was not return on investment for owners but ego gratification and career advancement for their top managers. If this analysis is accurate, and if managers' nests are often feathered in other ways (e.g., salaries, bonuses) at the expense of shareowners, then it is descriptively true that managers' interests have priority over those of other stakeholders, including shareowners. But we cannot move directly from an is claim-the de facto priority of managers' interests-to an ought claim in either instrumental or normative contexts. Moreover, even if it were true that higher paid managers did, in fact, achieve higher levels of profitability (thus meeting instrumental criteria), it would still not follow that higher pay/profit results were normatively justifiable. (Wit- ness the near-universal condemnation of the income/profit achievements of the 19th-century robber barons.)

THE PROBLEM OF JUSTIFICATION

The underlying epistemiological issue in the stakeholder literature is the problem of justification: Why should the stakeholder theory be ac- cepted or preferred over alternative conceptions? Until this question is addressed, the distinctions among empirical, instrumental, and norma- tive approaches can be papered over. Moreover, the answer to this ques- tion must be related to the distinct purpose that the theory is intended to serve. That is, reasons to accept the stakeholder theory as a descriptive

Page 11: The Stakeholder Theory of the Corporation Concepts Evidence and Implications Donaldson Preston 1995

74 Academy of Management Review January

account of how managers behave, or of how the business world is con- stituted, are different from reasons to accept the stakeholder theory as a guide for managerial behavior, and so on.

The stakeholder theory is justified in the literature, explicitly or im- plicitly, in ways that correspond directly to the three approaches to the theory set out in the previous section: descriptive, instrumental, and nor- mative. Descriptive justifications attempt to show that the concepts em- bedded in the theory correspond to observed reality. Instrumental justifi- cations point to evidence of the connection between stakeholder management and corporate performance. Normative justifications appeal to underlying concepts such as individual or group "rights," "social con- tract," or utilitarianism. (Brummer's recent survey of this literature ig- nores descriptive issues but emphasizes "power and performance," i.e., instrumental, and "deontological," i.e., normative, arguments; cf. Brum- mer, 1991.)

In our view, the three aspects of the stakeholder theory are nested within each other, as suggested by Figure 3. The external shell of the theory is its descriptive aspect; the theory presents and explains relation- ships that are observed in the external world. The theory's descriptive accuracy is supported, at the second level, by its instrumental and pre- dictive value; if certain practices are carried out, then certain results will be obtained. The central core of the theory is, however, normative. The descriptive accuracy of the theory presumes the truth of the core norma- tive conception, insofar as it presumes that managers and other agents act as if all stakeholders' interests have intrinsic value. In turn, recogni- tion of these ultimate moral values and obligations gives stakeholder management its fundamental normative base. In the following sections,

FIGURE 3 Three Aspects of Stakeholder Theory

DsNormative

\ \\: >esript

Page 12: The Stakeholder Theory of the Corporation Concepts Evidence and Implications Donaldson Preston 1995

1995 Donaldson and Preston 75

we survey the evidence and argument involved in each of these ap- proaches to the justification of the stakeholder theory.

DESCRIPTIVE JUSTIFICATIONS

There is ample descriptive evidence, some of which has already been cited, that many managers believe themselves, or are believed by others, to be practicing stakeholder management. Indeed, as early as the mid- 1960s, Raymond Baumhart's (1968) survey of upper-level managers re- vealed that about 80 percent regarded it as unethical management be- havior to focus solely in the interest of shareowners and not in the interest of employees and customers. Since then, other surveys asking similar questions about the stakeholder sensitivity of managers have returned similar results (Brenner & Molander, 1977; Posner & Schmidt, 1984). On- going empirical studies by both Clarkson (1991) and Halal (1990) attempt to distinguish firms that practice stakeholder management from those that do not, and both investigators found significant numbers of firms in the first category. Managers may not make explicit reference to "stake- holder theory," but the vast majority of them apparently adhere in prac- tice to one of the central tenets of the stakeholder theory, namely, that their role is to satisfy a wider set of stakeholders, not simply the share- owners. (Note, however, that the 171 managers surveyed by Alkhafaji, 1989, did not believe that the corporate governance roles of any stake- holders, including shareowners, should be increased. Perhaps not sur- prisingly, they strongly favored increased dominance of corporate gover- nance by management).

Another kind of descriptive justification for the stakeholder theory stems from the role it plays as the implicit basis for existing practices and institutions, including legal opinion and statutory law. Recent court de- cisions and new legislation have weakened the so-called "business judg- ment rule," which vests management with exclusive authority over the conduct of a company's affairs only on the condition that the financial welfare of stockholders is single-mindedly pursued (Chirelstein, 1974: 60). At last count, at least 29 states have adopted statutes that extend the range of permissible concern by boards of directors to a host of non- shareowner constituencies, including employees, creditors, suppliers, customers, and local communities (Orts, 1992). Furthermore, courts have tended to support these statutes. For example, the well-known Delaware Supreme Court decision in Unocal, although requiring corporate directors to show that a "reasonable" threat exists before fighting hostile takeover offers, nonetheless allowed a number of concerns to affect the determi- nation of such "reasonableness," including "the impact [of the takeover] on 'constituencies' other than shareholders (i.e., creditors, customers, em- ployees, and perhaps even the community generally)" (Unocal Corp. v. Mesa Petroleum Co., 1985). In a more recent Delaware case, Paramount Communications, Inc. v. Time, Inc. (1990), the Unocal rationale was ex-

Page 13: The Stakeholder Theory of the Corporation Concepts Evidence and Implications Donaldson Preston 1995

76 Academy of Management Review January

panded to allow directors to include factors such as long-range business plans and a corporation's "culture." In one of the most dramatic chal- lenges to the ownership rights of hostile acquirers, the Supreme Court of the United States upheld an Indiana statute that in the Court's own words "condition[s] acquisition of control of a corporation on approval of a ma- jority of the pre-existing disinterested shareholders" (emphasis added) (CTCS Corp. v. Dynamics Corp. of America, 1987).

As Orts noted, this trend toward stakeholder law is not solely a U.S. phenomenon and is reflected in the existing and emerging laws of many developed countries. The so-called codetermination laws of Germany re- quire employee representation on second-tier boards of directors. The Companies Act of Great Britain mandates that company directors shall include the interests of employees in their decision making (Companies Act, 1980). The new "harmonization" laws of the European Community (EC) will, when approved, include provisions permitting corporations to take into account the interests of creditors, customers, potential investors, and employees (Orts, 1992). Finally, the well-known corporate gover- nance model in Japan-through both law and custom-presumes that Japanese corporations exist within a tightly connected and interrelated set of stakeholders, including suppliers, customers, lending institutions, and friendly corporations.

Another series of legal developments in the U.S. asserts the interests of third-party stakeholders-specifically, unsuccessful job applicants- in business operations. Title VII of the Civil Rights Act of 1964 explicitly makes it a violation of law for an employer "to fail or refuse to hire . . . any individual" on the basis of discriminatory criteria (42 U.S.C. ?? 2000e-2a(l) & (2), 1982). This legislation has become the focus of numerous legal complaints and some substantial settlements. In a class action suit in- volving Potomac Electric Power Co., Washington, DC, complainants charged that the company had hired far fewer Blacks from its applicant pool than would have been expected on statistical grounds. The judge certified a "class" of more than 7,000 unsuccessful Black applicants, most of whom will be eligible for compensation out of a $38.4 million settlement pool (which is also available to employees experiencing discrimination) (The Washington Post, 21 February 1993).

Both of these sets of legal developments reinforce our initial state- ment that stakeholders are defined by their legitimate interest in the corporation, rather than simply by the corporation's interest in them. But neither the legal developments nor the management survey results pro- vide definitive epistemological justification for the stakeholder theory. Managers adopting the stakeholder approach may be relieved to learn that they are not alone, and indeed that they are conforming to the latest management or legal trends, but both the survey results and legal devel- opments are, at bottom, simply facts. They do not constitute the basis for the stakeholder (or any other) theory of management. Indeed, even if the stakeholder concept is implicit in current legal trends (a proposition that

Page 14: The Stakeholder Theory of the Corporation Concepts Evidence and Implications Donaldson Preston 1995

1995 Donaldson and Preston 77

is not universally accepted), one cannot derive a stakeholder theory of management from a stakeholder theory of law any more than one can derive a "tort" theory of management from the tort theory of law.

The hazards of using purely descriptive data, whether jurisprudential or otherwise, as justification for a broad theory are well known. There is the problem of the so-called "naturalistic fallacy," moving from is to ought or from describe to evaluate, without the necessary intervening analysis and explanation (Moore, 1959/1903: 15-16). Then, again, there is the sim- ple problem of hasty generalization. By the logic of descriptive justifica- tion, if new surveys showed that managers were abandoning stakeholder orientations, or if the legal support for broad stakeholder interests were to weaken, the theory would be invalidated. But this observation offers a significant clue about the nature of the theory itself, because few if any of its adherents would be likely to abandon it, even if current legal or man- agerial trends were to shift. This suggests that the descriptive support for the stakeholder theory, as well as the critiques of this support to be found in the literature, are of limited significance and that the most important issues for stakeholder theory lie elsewhere.

INSTRUMENTAL JUSTIFICATIONS

Because the descriptive approach to grounding a stakeholder theory is inadequate, justifications based on a connection between stakeholder strategies and organizational performance should be examined. Con- sider, for example, the simple hypothesis that corporations whose man- agers adopt stakeholder principles and practices will perform better fi- nancially than those that do not. This hypothesis has never been tested directly, and its testing involves some formidable challenges. (Clarkson's ongoing work is the only significant effort of this type known to us; cf. Clarkson, Deck, & Shiner, 1992.) The view that stakeholder management and favorable performance go hand in hand has, however, become com- monplace in the management literature, both professional and academic. The earliest direct statement is probably that of General Robert E. Wood, then-CEO of Sears, in 1950: "All I can say is that if the other three parties named above [customers, employees, community] are properly taken care of, the stockholder will benefit in the long pull" (quoted in Worthy, 1984: 64). A recent effort to introduce practicing managers to the stakeholder concept and to improve their ability to implement stakeholder manage- ment practices is the work by Savage, Nix, Whitehead, and Blair (1991). Brummer (1991) cited not only Freeman (1989) but also Ackoff; Manning; Maslow; Peters and Waterman; Starling; Sturdivant; and others in support of stakeholder theory's instrumental base.

Unfortunately, the large body of literature dealing with the connec- tions, if any, between various aspects of corporate social performance or ethics, on one hand, and conventional financial and market performance indicators, on the other, does not translate easily into a stakeholder the-

Page 15: The Stakeholder Theory of the Corporation Concepts Evidence and Implications Donaldson Preston 1995

78 Academy of Management Review January

ory context. Whatever value the social/financial performance studies may have on their own merits, most of them do not include reliable indicators of the stakeholder management (i.e., the independent variable) side of the relationship. There is some evidence, based on analysis of the For- tune corporate reputation surveys, that the satisfaction of multiple stake- holders need not be a zero sum game (i.e., that benefits to one stakeholder group need not come entirely at the expense of another) (Preston & Sapi- enza, 1990). As previously noted, Kotter and Heskett's (1992) case studies of a small number of high-performance companies indicated that the managers of those companies tend to emphasize the interests of all major stakeholder groups in their decision making. However, there is as yet no compelling empirical evidence that the optimal strategy for maximizing a firm's conventional financial and market performance is stakeholder management.

Analytical Arguments

Even without empirical verification, however, stakeholder manage- ment can be linked to conventional concepts of organizational success through analytical argument. The main focus of this effort in the recent literature builds on established concepts of principal-agent relations (Jensen & Mechling, 1976) and the firm as a nexus of contracts (Williamson & Winter, 1991). Agency theory and firm-as-contract theory, although aris- ing from different sources, are closely related and share a common em- phasis: efficiency. (They also share the terminology and methodology of the new transaction cost literature; cf. Williamson, 1985.) Agency theorists argue that corporations are structured to minimize the costs of getting some participants (the agents) to do what other participants (the princi- pals) desire. Firm-as-contract theorists argue that participants agree to cooperate with each other within organizations (i.e., through contracts), rather than simply deal with each other through the market, to minimize the costs of search, coordination, insecurity, etc.

Hill and Jones (1992: 132, 134) are responsible for the most ambitious attempt to integrate the stakeholder concept with agency theory (see also, Sharplin & Phelps, 1989). These authors enlarged the standard principal- agent paradigm of financial economics, which emphasizes the relation- ship between shareowners and managers, to create "stakeholder-agency theory," which constitutes, in their view, "a generalized theory of agency." According to this conception, managers "can be seen as the agents of [all] other stakeholders." They noted that stakeholders differ among themselves with respect to (a) the importance (to them) of their stake in the firm and (b) their power vis-a-vis the managers. They also noted that there is considerable friction within the stakeholder-agent ne- gotiation process-some of it because of some participants' ability to retard equilibrating adjustments that are unfavorable to themselves. They therefore argued that there is no reason to assume that stakeholder- agent relationships are in equilibrium at any particular time. (This con-

Page 16: The Stakeholder Theory of the Corporation Concepts Evidence and Implications Donaldson Preston 1995

1995 Donaldson and Preston 79

trasts sharply with the "perfect markets" hypothesis favored in the fi- nance literature.) In their view, the process, direction, and speed of adaptation in stakeholder-agent relationships, rather than the equilib- rium set of contributions and rewards, should be the primary focus of analysis. This brief summary cannot do justice to their rich conception, but the key point for current purposes is that the stakeholders are drawn into relationships with the managers to accomplish organizational tasks as efficiently as possible; hence, the stakeholder model is linked instru- mentally to organizational performance.

A similar theme emerges from the firm-as-contract analysis of Free- man and Evan (1990; see also Evan & Freeman, 1988). They recommended integrating the stakeholder concept with the Coasian view of the firm-as- contract and a Williamson-style analysis of transaction costs to "concep- tualize the firm as a set of multilateral contracts over time." According to Freeman and Evan,

Managers administer contracts among employees, owners, suppliers, customers, and the community. Since each of these groups can invest in asset specific transactions which affect the other groups, methods of conflict resolution, or safeguards must be found. (1990: 352)

They emphasized that all parties have an equal right to bargain and, therefore, that a minimal condition for the acceptance of such multi- partite arrangements by each contracting party is a notion of "fair con- tract," i.e., governance rules that "ensure that the interests of all parties are at least taken into consideration" (1990: 3r Once again, the stake- holder model (and its implementation through a set of acceptable implicit contracts) is seen as essential to successful organizational performance.

The stakeholder interpretations of both agency theory and firm-as- contract theory give special attention to the differential position and spe- cial role of managers vis-a-vis all other stakeholders. Hill and Jones (1992: 140) emphasized "information asymmetry" between managers and other stakeholders and contrasted the concentration of resource control by man- agers with the diffusion of control within stakeholder groups in which there may be no mechanism to gain command over a significant portion of the group's total resources. Evan and Freeman (1993: 102-103) asserted that "management has a duty of safeguarding the welfare of the abstract entity that is the corporation" and of balancing the conflicting claims of multiple stakeholders to achieve this goal. They further declared:

A stakeholder theory of the firm must redefine the purpose of the firm.... The very purpose of the firm is, in our view, to serve as a vehicle for coordinating stakeholder interests. (102- 103)

According to this perspective, success in satisfying multiple stakeholder

Page 17: The Stakeholder Theory of the Corporation Concepts Evidence and Implications Donaldson Preston 1995

80 Academy of Management Review January

interests-rather than in meeting conventional economic and financial criteria-would constitute the ultimate test of corporate performance.

But how will multiple and diverse stakeholders be assured that their interests are being coordinated in ways that lead to the most favorable possible results for themselves (i.e., the most favorable results consistent with the requirements of other stakeholders)? Hill and Jones (1992: 140- 143) stressed the importance of (a) monitoring devices that have the effect of reducing information asymmetry (e.g., public reporting requirements) and (b) enforcement mechanisms, including law, "exit" (the possibility, or credible threat, of withdrawal from the relationship), and "voice." Free- man and Evan (1993) emphasized the notion of fairness. Going beyond the notion of "fair contracting," they recommended that the criterion of "fair- ness" in stakeholder bargains be a Rawlsian "veil of ignorance." Under a "veil of ignorance," parties to a bargain agree upon a set of possible outcomes prior to determining which outcome will be received by which party (e.g., one person cuts the cake, another takes the first slice) (Rawls, 1971, cited in Freeman & Evan, 1990: 352-353).

Both pairs of analysts, Hill and Jones and Freeman and Evan, placed greater emphasis on the process of multiple-stakeholder coordination than on the specific agreements/bargains. Both groups stressed that mu- tual and voluntary acceptability of bargains by all contracting stakehold- ers is the necessary criterion for efficient contracts. Both neglected the roles of potential stakeholders not conspicuously involved in explicit or implicit contracts with the firm. The two pairs of authors differed slightly in one respect: Hill and Jones saw the network of relationships as con- sisting of separate implicit contracts between each stakeholder group and "management" (as a central node), whereas Freeman and Evan ulti- mately viewed the firm "as a series of multilateral contracts among [all] stakeholders" (1990: 354).

Weaknesses of Instrumental Justifications

Perhaps the most important similarity between these two indepen- dent attempts to justify the stakeholder model lies in the fact that al- though they draw initially on the conceptual apparatus of instrumental or efficiency-based theories (i.e., principal-agent relations and "firm-as- contract" theory), they ultimately rely upon noninstrumental or normative arguments. This shift is less conspicuous in the case of Hill and Jones, who implied that monitoring and enforcement mechanisms will be suffi- cient to curb opportunistic behavior by managers at the expense of other stakeholders. The authors would no doubt agree, however, that the ulti- mate success of stakeholder-agency theory would require a fundamental shift in managerial objectives away from shareowners and toward the interests of all stakeholders; such a shift would necessarily involve nor- mative, rather than purely instrumental, considerations. Freeman and Evan's recourse to a Rawlsian concept of "fairness" as the ultimate crite- rion for stakeholder bargains is an overt elevation of normative criteria

Page 18: The Stakeholder Theory of the Corporation Concepts Evidence and Implications Donaldson Preston 1995

1995 Donaldson and Preston 81

over instrumental ones. No theorist, including Rawls, has ever main- tained that bargains reached on the basis of a "veil of ignorance" would maximize efficiency. By elevating the fairness principle to ca central role, Freeman and Evan shifted their attention from ordinary economic con- tracts of the sort envisaged by Coase, Wlilliamson, and the mainstream agency theorists, which are governed by individual efficiency consider- ations. Instead, they emphasized what have been called "heuristic" or "social" contracts that rest upon broad normative principles governing human conduct (Donaldson & Dunfee, In. press, 1994).

It should come as no surprise that stcxkeholder theory cannot be fully justified by instrumental considerations. The empirical evidence is inad- equate, and the analytical arguments, although of considerable sub- stance, ultimately rest on more than purely instrumental grounds. This conclusion carries an important implication: Although those who use the stakeholder concept often cite its consistency with the pursuit of conven- tional corporate performance objectives (and there is no notable evidence of its inconsistency), few of them would abandon the concept if it turned out to be only as equally efficacious as other conceptions. O'Toole (1991: 18-19), for example, examined a case in which the economic conse- quences of stakeholder versus conventional management "ended up neu- tral"; he stressed that "it is the moral cornsequerices that are at issue" and described stakeholder analysis as "the sine quo non of business virtue" (emphasis in the original).

NORMATIVE JUSTIFICATIONS

The normative basis for stakeholder theory involves its connection with more fundamental and better-accepted philosophical concepts. The normative assumptions of traditional economic theory are too feeble to support stakeholder theory, and the concept of a free market populated with free and rational preference seekers, however correct and important, is compatible with both stakeholder and nonstakeholder perspectives. Of course, the two normative propositions, stated at the beginning of this article-that stakeholders are identifiecd by their interest in the affairs of the corporation and that the interests of all stakeholders have intrinsic value-can be viewed as axiomatic principles that require no further justification. Unfortunately, this approach provides no basis for respond- ing to critics who reject these propositions out of hand.

One way to construct a normative foundation for the stakeholder model is to examine its principal competitor, the model of management control in the interests of shareowners, as represented by the business judgment rule. As noted in previous sections, there is considerable criti- cism of this model on descriptive grounds. Pejovich (1990: 58) noted that in the modern corporation (as opposed to the owner-managed firm) the rights of shareowners are "attenuated" by the dispersion of ownership and by high agency costs; he stressed that "the economic system," not "the

Page 19: The Stakeholder Theory of the Corporation Concepts Evidence and Implications Donaldson Preston 1995

82 Academy of Management Review January

legal system," is responsible for this "attenuation of the right of owner- ship" (emphasis in original). Many direct observers (e.g., Geneen & Mos- cow, 1984; Pickens, 1987) have questioned managers' devotion to share- owner welfare, and survey results such as those of Alkhafaji (1989) and Posner and Schmidt (1992) provide statistical support for these percep- tions.

But the management serving the shareowners model (i.e., the prin- cipal-agent model in its standard financial economics form) is not only descriptively inaccurate; careful analysis reveals that it is normatively unacceptable as well. Changes in state incorporation laws to reflect a "constituency" perspective have been mentioned. The normative basis for these changes in current mainstream legal thinking is articulated in the recent American Law Institute report, Principles of Corporate Governance (1992). The relevant portion of this document begins by affirming the cen- tral corporate objective of "enhancing corporate profit and shareholder gain," but it immediately introduces qualifications: "Even if corporate profit and shareholder gain are not thereby enhanced," the corporation must abide by law and may "take into account ethical considerations" and engage in philanthropy (Sec.2.01(a)(b); 1992: 69). The accompanying commentary explicitly affirmed the stakeholder concept:

The modern corporation by its nature creates interdependen- cies with a variety of groups with whom the corporation has a legitimate concern, such as employees, customers, suppliers, and members of the communities in which the corporation operates. (1992: 72)

The commentary further noted that response to social and ethical consid- erations is often consistent with long-run (if not short-run) increases in profit and value, but it continues:

Nevertheless, observation suggests that corporate decisions are not infrequently made on the basis of ethical consider- ation even when doing so would not enhance corporate profit or shareholder gain. Such behavior is not only appropriate, but desirable. Corporate officials are not less morally obliged than any other citizens to take ethical considerations into ac- count, and it would be unwise social policy to preclude them from doing so .... [The text] does not impose a legal obliga- tion to take ethical considerations into account. However, the absence of a legal obligation to follow ethical principles does not mean that corporate decisionmakers are not subject to the same ethical considerations as other members of society. (American Law Institute, 1992: 80-82, emphasis added)

FORMAL ANALYSIS: THEORY OF PROPERTY

To go beyond this practical rejection of the "management serving the shareowners" model, more formal normative justifications of stakeholder theory might be based either on broad theories of philosophical ethics,

Page 20: The Stakeholder Theory of the Corporation Concepts Evidence and Implications Donaldson Preston 1995

1995 Donaldson and Preston 83

such as utilitarianism, or on narrower "middle-level" theories derived from the notion that a "social contract" exists between corporations and society. A comprehensive survey of this terrain would go far beyond the scope of this article, and much of it has been recently traversed by others (Brummer, 1991; Freeman, 1991; see also, Donaldson, 1982). Here, we offer a brief sketch of a normative basis for the stakeholder theory that com- bines several different philosophical approaches and that is, we believe, original in the literature. We argue that the stakeholder theory can be normatively based on the evolving theory of property.

There is a subtle irony in proposing that the stakeholder model can be justified on the basis of the theory of property, because the traditional view has been that a focus on property rights justifies the dominance of shareowners' interests. Indeed, the fact that property rights are the criti- cal base for conventional shareowner-dominance views makes it all the more significant that the current trend of thinking with respect to the philosophy of property runs in the opposite direction. In fact, this trend- as presented in the now-classic contributions of Coase (1960) and Honore (1961) and in more recent works by Becker (1978, 1992a,b,c) and Munzer (1992)-runs strongly counter to the conception that private property ex- clusively enshrines the interests of owners.

Considerable agreement now exists as to the theoretical definition of property as a "bundle" of many rights, some of which may be limited. More than 30 years ago, Coase (1960: 44) chided economists for adhering to a simplistic concept of ownership:

We may speak of a person owning land . . . but what the land-owner in fact possesses is the right to carry out a circum- scribed list of actions. The rights of a land-owner are not un- limited . . . [This] would be true under any system of law. A system in which the rights of individuals were unlimited would be one in which there were no rights to acquire.

Honore (1961) specifically included the notion of restrictions against harm- ful uses within the definition of property itself. Pejovich (1990: 27-28), probably the most conservative economic theorist working in this area, emphasized that "property rights are relations between individuals" and thus "it is wrong to separate human rights from property rights"; he fur- ther noted that "the right of ownership is not an unrestricted right."

The notion that property rights are embedded in human rights and that restrictions against harmful uses are intrinsic to the property rights concept clearly brings the interests of others (i.e., of non-owner stake- holders) into the picture. Of course, which uses of property should be restricted and which persons should count as stakeholders remain un- specified. Simply bringing nonowner stakeholders into the conception of property does not provide by itself justification for stakeholder arguments assigning managerial responsibilities toward specific groups, such as employees and customers. The important point, however, is that the con-

Page 21: The Stakeholder Theory of the Corporation Concepts Evidence and Implications Donaldson Preston 1995

84 Academy of Management Review January

temporary theoretical concept of private property clearly does not ascribe unlimited rights to owners and hence does not support the popular claim that the responsibility of managers is to act solely as agents for the share- owners. (The necessary compromise between individual property rights and other considerations is highlighted in the "takings" issue-i.e., mod- ified to protect the interests of others or society in general. For a survey of current views on this complex matter, see Mercuro, 1992.)

These comments examine the scope of property rights, but it is also relevant to examine their source (i.e., What basic principles determine who should get [and be allowed to keep] what in society?). Unless prop- erty rights are regarded as simple, self-evident moral conceptions, they must be based on more fundamental ideas of distributive justice. The main contending theories of distributive justice include Utilitarianism, Libertarianism, and social contract theory (Becker, 1992). The battle among competing theories of distributive justice is most often a battle over which characteristics highlighted by the theories-such as need, ability, effort, and mutual agreement-are most relevant for determining fair distributions of wealth, income, etc. (The role of theories of justice within organizations is attracting considerable current attention; cf. Greenberg, 1987.)

For example, when the characteristic of need (a feature highlighted by Utilitarianism) is the criterion, the resulting theory of property places formidable demands upon property owners to mitigate their self-interest in favor of enhancing the interests (i.e., meeting the needs) of others. When ability or effort (features highlighted by Libertarianism) is the cri- terion, the resulting theory leaves property owners freer to use their re- sources (acquired, it is assumed, as a result of ability and effort) as they see fit. Social contract theory places primary emphasis on expressed or implied understandings among individuals and groups as to appropriate distributions and uses of property.

Many of the most respected contemporary analysts of property rights reject the notion that any single theory of distributive justice is univer- sally applicable. Indeed, it seems counterintuitive that any one principle could account for all aspects of the complex bundle of rights and respon- sibilities that constitutes "property." Beginning with Becker's (1978) anal- ysis, the trend is toward theories that are pluralistic, allowing more than one fundamental principle to play a role (Becker, 1992a; see also, Munzer, 1992). But if a pluralistic theory of property rights is accepted, then the connection between the theory of property and the stakeholder theory becomes explicit. All critical characteristics underlying the classic theo- ries of distributive justice are present among the stakeholders of a corpo- ration, as they are conventionally conceived and presented in contempo- rary stakeholder theory. For example, the "stake" of long-term employees who have worked to build and maintain a successful business operation is essentially based on effort. The stake of people living in the surround- ing community may be based on their need, say, for clean air or the

Page 22: The Stakeholder Theory of the Corporation Concepts Evidence and Implications Donaldson Preston 1995

1995 Donaldson and Preston 85

maintenance of their civic infrastructure. Customer stakes are based on the satisfactions and protections implicitly promised in the market offer, and so on. One need not make the more radical assertion that such stakes constitute formal or legal property rights, although some forceful critics of current corporate governance arrangements appear to hold this view (Nader & Green, 1973). All that is necessary is to show that such charac- teristics, which are the same as those giving rise to fundamental concepts of property rights, give various groups a moral interest, commonly re- ferred to as a "stake," in the affairs of the corporation. Thus, the normative principles that underlie the contemporary pluralistic theory of property rights also provide the foundation for the stakeholder theory as well.

MANAGERIAL IMPLICATIONS

A full discussion of the managerial implications of this analysis would require much more discussion. As a summary, the two points we emphasize are (a) the recognition of specific stakeholders and their stakes by managers and other stakeholders and (b) the role of managers and the management function, as distinct from the persons involved, within the stakeholder model. These two issues are intimately intertwined.

It is the responsibility of managers, and the management function, to select activities and direct resources to obtain benefits for legitimate stakeholders. The question is, Who are the legitimate stakeholders? Some answers in the literature are, in our view, too narrow; others are too broad. The firm-as-contract view holds that legitimate stakeholders are identified by the existence of a contract, expressed or implied, between them and the firm. Direct input contributors are included, but environ- mental interests such as communities are also believed to have at least loose quasi-contracts (and, of course, sometimes very specific ones) with their business constituents.

We believe that the firm-as-contract perspective, although correct, is incomplete as a description of the corporation. For example, many busi- ness relationships with "communities" are so vague as to pass beyond even the broadest conception of "contract." The plant-closing controversy of the last couple of decades clearly shows that some communities had come to expect-and sometimes were able to enforce-stakeholder claims that some firms clearly did not recognize. As another example, potential job applicants, unknown to the firm, nevertheless have a stake in being considered for a job (but not necessarily to get a job). Lacking any connection to the firm, these potential employees are difficult to view as participating in the firm by reason of a contract, either implied or explicit. (We do not mean, however, to rule out possible relevance of so-called social contracts to such situations; cf. Donaldson & Dunfee, 1994b.) Stake- holders are identified through the actual or potential harms and benefits that they experience or anticipate experiencing as a result of the firm's actions or inactions. In practice, and in addition to legal requirements,

Page 23: The Stakeholder Theory of the Corporation Concepts Evidence and Implications Donaldson Preston 1995

86 Academy of Management Review January

appraisal of the legitimacy of such expectations is an important function of management, often in concert with other already recognized stakehold- ers.

Excessive breadth in the identification of stakeholders has arisen from a tendency to adopt definitions such as "anything influencing or influenced by" the firm (Freeman, 1984, quoting with approval Thompson, 1967). This definition opens the stakeholder set to actors that form part of the firm's environment-and that, indeed, may have some impact on its activities-but that have no specific stake in the firm itself. That is, they stand to gain no particular benefit from the firm's successful operation. The two types of interests that have cropped up most frequently in this connection are (a) competitors and (b) the media. Competitors were intro- duced as factors that have "an influence on managerial autonomy" in Dill's (1958) article, which is appropriately cited in the literature as a precursor of stakeholder analysis. However, neither the term stakeholder nor the notion of a stake (i.e., potential benefit) was explicitly introduced in Dill's analysis. In any event, in the normal course of events, competi- tors do not seek benefits from the focal firm's success; on the contrary, they may stand to lose whatever the focal firm gains. Competitive firms may, of course, join in common collaborative activities (e.g., through trade associations), but here the shared (noncompetitive) interests ac- count for the stakeholder relationship. The notion that the media should be routinely recognized as stakeholders was originally introduced by Freeman (1984), but it seems to have been eliminated (without explicit explanation) from his later writings. It is essential to draw a clear dis- tinction between influencers and stakeholders: some actors in the enter- prise (e.g., large investors) may be both, but some recognizable stake- holders (e.g., the job applicants) have no influence, and some influencers (e.g., the media) have no stakes.

The role of managers within the stakeholder framework described in the literature is also contradictory. Aoki (1984), for example, recognized only investors and employees as significant stakeholders and saw man- agers as essentially "referees" between these two stakeholder groups. He acknowledged neither (a) the essential role of management in the iden- tification of stakeholders nor (b) the fact that managers are, themselves, stakeholders-and, indeed, a very privileged class of stakeholders-in the enterprise. Williamson (1985) is almost alone among academic ana- lysts in emphasizing the fact that the managers of a firm are one of its most important and powerful constituencies and that-wittingly or un- wittingly-they are extremely likely to practice opportunistic and self- aggrandizing behavior.

This last point is absolutely critical for our argument, and recognition of it confirms our most important proposition: that the stakeholder the- ory is fundamentally normative. We observed at the close of our discus- sion of instrumental justifications that the instrumental case for stake- holder management cannot be satisfactorily proved. Here we restate that

Page 24: The Stakeholder Theory of the Corporation Concepts Evidence and Implications Donaldson Preston 1995

1995 Donaldson and Preston 87

observation and add that the ultimate managerial implication of the stakeholder theory is that managers should acknowledge the validity of diverse stakeholder interests and should attempt to respond to them within a mutually supportive framework, because that is a moral require- ment for the legitimacy of the management function.

It is feared by some that a shift from the traditional shareowner ori- entation to a stakeholder orientation will make it more difficult to detect and discipline self-serving behavior by managers, who may always claim to be serving some broad set of stakeholder interests while they increase their powers and emoluments. Indeed, Orts (1992: 123) saw this as the "greatest danger" of the new "constituency statutes" for corporate governance, although he nevertheless supported the constituency ap- proach.

Our response to this fear is twofold: First, the conventional model of the corporation, in both legal and managerial forms, has failed to disci- pline self-serving managerial behavior. In this era of multimillion dollar CEO compensation packages that continue to increase even when profits and wages decline (Bok, 1993), it is difficult to conceive of managers having greater scope for self-serving behavior than they have already. Second, the stakeholder model we have advanced here entails compre- hensive restrictions on such behavior. Indeed, its very foundation prohib- its any undue attention to the interests of any single constituency. To be sure, it remains to implement in law the sanctions, rules, and precedents that support the stakeholder conception of the corporation; in short, it remains to develop the legal version of the stakeholder model. (See, for example, Eisenberg's [1976] attempt to restructure the legal model of the corporation.) Yet over time, statutory and common law are almost cer- tainly capable of achieving arrangements that encourage a broader, stakeholder conception of management-one which eschews single- minded subservience to shareowners' interests-while at the same time restraining the moral hazard of self-serving managers.

CONCLUSION

We have argued that the stakeholder theory is "managerial" and recommends the attitudes, structures, and practices that, taken together, constitute a stakeholder management philosophy. The theory goes be- yond the purely descriptive observation that "organizations have stake- holders," which, although true, carries no direct managerial implica- tions. Furthermore, the notion that stakeholder management contributes to successful economic performance, although widely believed (and not patently inaccurate), is insufficient to stand alone as a basis for the stake- holder theory. Indeed, the most thoughtful analyses of why stakeholder management might be casually related to corporate performance ulti- mately resort to normative arguments in support of their views. For these reasons, we believe that the ultimate justification for the stakeholder

Page 25: The Stakeholder Theory of the Corporation Concepts Evidence and Implications Donaldson Preston 1995

88 Academy of Management Review January

theory is to be found in its normative base. The plain truth is that the most prominent alternative to the stakeholder theory (i.e., the "management serving the shareowners" theory) is morally untenable. The theory of property rights, which is commonly supposed to support the conventional view, in fact-in its modern and pluralistic form-supports the stake- holder theory instead.

REFERENCES

Alkhafaji, A. F. 1989. A stakeholder approach to corporate governance: Managing in a dy- namic environment. New York: Quorum Books.

American Law Institute. 1992. Principles of corporate governance: Analysis and recommen- dations. (Proposed final draft, March 31, 1992). Philadelphia, PA: Author.

Anderson, J. W., Jr. 1989. Corporate social responsibility. New York: Quorum Books.

Aoki, M. 1984. The co-operative game theory of the firm. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Aupperle, K. E., Carroll, A. B., & Hatfield, J. D. 1985. An empirical examination of the rela- tionship between corporate social responsibility and profitability. Academy of Manage- ment Journal, 28(2): 446-463.

Barton, S. L., Hill, N. C., & Sundaram, S. 1989. An empirical test of stakeholder theory predictions of capital structure. Financial Management, 18(1): 36-44.

Baumhart, R. 1968. An honest profit: What businessmen say about ethics in business. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston.

Becker, L. C. 1978. Property rights. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

Becker, L. C. 1992a. Property. In L. D. Becker & C. B. Becker (Eds.), Encyclopedia of ethics, vol. 2: 1023-1027. New York: Garland.

Becker, L. C. 1992b. Places for pluralism. Ethics, 102: 707-719.

Becker, L. C. 1992c. Too much property. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 21: 196-206.

Berle, A., & Means, G. 1932. Private property and the modern corporation. New York: Mac- millan.

Bok, D. 1993. The cost of talent: How executives and professionals are paid and how it affects America. New York: Free Press.

Brenner, S. N., & Cochran, P. 1991. The stakeholder theory of the firm: Implications for business and society theory and research. Paper presented at the annual meeting of the International Association for Business and Society, Sundance, UT.

Brenner, S. N., & Molander, E. A. 1977. Is the ethics of business changing? Harvard Business Review, 58(1): 54-65.

Brummer, J. J. 1991. Corporate responsibility and legitimacy: An interdisciplinary analysis. New York: Greenwood Press.

Carroll, A. B. 1989. Business and society: Ethics and stakeholder management. Cincinnati, OH: South-Western.

Chirelstein, M. A. 1974. Corporate law reform. In J. W. McKie (Ed.), Social responsibility and the business predicament: 41-78. Washington, DC: The Brookings Institution.

Civil Rights Act, Title VII; 42 USC ?? 2000e-2a(l) & (2), 1982.

Clarkson, M. B. E. 1991. Defining, evaluating, and managing corporate social performance: A stakeholder management model. In J. E. Post (Ed.), Research in corporate social per- formance and policy: 331-358. Greenwich, CT: JAI Press.

Page 26: The Stakeholder Theory of the Corporation Concepts Evidence and Implications Donaldson Preston 1995

1995 Donaldson and Preston 89

Clarkson, M. B. E., Deck, M. C., & Shiner, N. J. 1992. The stakeholder management model in practice. Paper presented at the annual meeting of the Academy of Management, Las Vegas, NV.

Coase, R. H. 1937. The nature of the firm. In 0. E. Williamson & S. G. Winter (Eds.), The nature of the firm: Origins, evolution, and development: 18-33. New York: Oxford Uni- versity Press.

Coase, R. H. 1960. The problem of social cost. Journal of Law and Economics, 3: 1-44.

Cochran, P. L., & Wood, R. A. 1984. Corporate social responsibility and financial perfor- mance. Academy of Management Journal, 27(1): 42-56.

Companies Act, 1980, Great Britain.

Cornell, B., & Shapiro, A. C. 1987. Corporate stakeholders and corporate finance. Financial Management, 16: 5-14.

CTS Corp. v. Dynamics Corp. of America. 1987. U.S. Supr., 481, 69, 87.

Cyert, R. M., & March, J. G. 1963. A behavioral theory of the firm. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.

Dill, W. R. 1958. Environment as an influence on managerial autonomy. Administrative Science Quarterly, 2: 409-443.

Dodd, E. M., Jr. 1932. For whom are corporate managers trustees? Harvard Law Review, 45: 1145-1163.

Donaldson, T. 1982. Corporations and morality. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.

Donaldson, T., & Dunfee, T. W. 1994. Towards a unified conception of business ethics: Integrative social contracts theory. Academy of Management Review, 19: 252-284.

Donaldson, T., & Dunfee, T. W. In press. Integrative social contracts theory: A communitar- ian conception of economic ethics. Economics and Philosophy.

The Economist. 1992. [Corporate governance special section] September 11: 52-62.

Eisenberg, M. A. 1976. The structure of the corporation: A legal analysis. Toronto: Little, Brown.

Evan, W. M., & Freeman, R. E. 1988. A stakeholder theory of the modern corporation: Kant- ian capitalism. In T. Beauchamp & N. Bowie (Eds.), Ethical theory and business: 75-93. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.

Freeman, R. E. 1984. Strategic management: A stakeholder approach. Boston: Pitman.

Freeman, R. E. (Ed.). 1991. Business ethics: The state of the art. New York: Oxford University Press.

Freeman, R. E., & Evan, W. M. 1990. Corporate governance: A stakeholder interpretation. The Journal of Behavioral Economics, 19(4): 337-359.

Freeman, R. E., & Gilbert, D. R., Jr. 1987. Managing stakeholder relationships. In S. P. Sethi & C. M. Falbe (Eds.), Business and society: 397-423. Lexington, MA: Lexington Books.

Freeman, R. E., & Reed, D. L. 1983. Stockholders and stakeholders: A new perspective on corporate governance. California Management Review, 25(3): 88-106.

Friedman, M. 1970. The social responsibility of business is to increase its profits. New York Times Magazine, September 13: 32-33, 122, 126.

Geneen, H., & Moscow, A. 1984. Managing. Garden City, NY: Doubleday.

Goodpaster, K. E. 1991. Business ethics and stakeholder analysis. Business Ethics Quarterly, 1(1): 53-73.

Greenberg, J. 1987. A taxonomy of organizational justice theories. Academy of Management Review, 12: 9-22.

Page 27: The Stakeholder Theory of the Corporation Concepts Evidence and Implications Donaldson Preston 1995

90 Academy of Management Review January

Halal, W. E. 1990. The new management: Business and social institutions in the information age. Business in the Contemporary World, 2(2): 41-54.

Hill, C. W. L., & Jones, T. M. 1992. Stakeholder-agency theory. Journal of Management Stud- ies, 29: 131-154.

Honore, A. M. 1961. Ownership. In A. G. Guest (Ed.), Oxford essays in jurisprudence: 107- 147. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Jensen, M. C. 1989. Eclipse of the public corporation. Harvard Business Review, 67(5): 61-74.

Jensen, M. C., & Mechling, W. 1976. Theory of the firm: Managerial behavior, agency costs, and capital structure. Journal of Financial Economics, 3(October): 305-360.

Kotter, J., & Heskett, J. 1992. Corporate culture and performance. New York: Free Press.

Kreiner, P., & Bambri, A. 1991. Influence and information in organization-stakeholder rela- tionships. In J. E. Post (Ed.), Research in corporate social performance and policy, vol. 12: 3-36. Greenwich, CT: JAI Press.

Kuhn, J. W., & Shriver, D. W., Jr. 1991. Beyond success: Corporations and their critics in the 1990s. New York: Oxford University Press.

Marcus, A. A. 1993. Business and society: Ethics, government and the world economy. Home- wood, IL: Irwin.

McGuire, J. B., Sundgren, A., & Schneeweis, T. 1988. Corporate social responsibility and firm financial performance. Academy of Management Journal, 31: 354-372.

Mercuro, N. (Ed.). 1992. Taking property and just compensation. Boston: Kluwer.

Moore, G. E. 1959. Principia ethica. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press. (Original work published 1903)

Munzer, S. R. 1992. A theory of property. New York: Cambridge University Press.

Nader, R., & Green, M. J. (Eds.). 1973. Corporate power in America. New York: Grossman.

Orts, E. W. 1992. Beyond shareholders: Interpreting corporate constituency statutes. The George Washington Law Review, 61(1): 14-135.

O'Toole, J. 1985. Vanguard management. Garden City, NY: Doubleday.

O'Toole, J. 1991. Do good, do well: The business enterprise trust awards. California Man- agement Review, 33(3): 9-24.

Paramount Communications, Inc. v. Time, Inc. 1990. Del. Supr., 571 A. 2d 1140.

Pejovich, S. 1990. The economics of property rights; Towards a theory of comparative sys- tems. Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

Pickens, T. B. 1987. Boone. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.

Posner, B. Z., & Schmidt, W. H. 1984. Values and the American manager. California Man- agement Review, 26(3): 202-216.

Preston, L. E., & Sapienza, H. J. 1990. Stakeholder management and corporate performance. Journal of Behavioral Economics, 19: 361-375.

Preston, L. E., Sapienza, H. J., & Miller, R. D. 1991. Stakeholders, shareholders, managers: Who gains what from corporate performance? In A. Etzioni & P. R. Lawrence (Eds.), Socio-economics: Toward a new synthesis: 149-65. Armonk, NY: M. E. Sharpe.

Rawls, J. 1971. A theory of justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Savage, G. T., Nix, T. W., Whitehead, C. J., & Blair, J. D. 1991. Strategy for assessing and managing organizational stakeholders. Academy of Management Executive, 5(2): 61-75.

Sharplin, A., & Phelps, L. D. 1989. A stakeholder apologetic for management. Business and Professional Ethics Journal, 8(2): 41-53.

Page 28: The Stakeholder Theory of the Corporation Concepts Evidence and Implications Donaldson Preston 1995

1995 Donaldson and Preston 91

Thompson, J. 1967. Organizations in action. New York: McGraw-Hill.

Unocal Corp. v. Mesa Petroleum Co. 1985. Del. Supr., 493 A. 2d 946.

Wang, J., & Dewhirst, H. D. 1992. Boards of directors and stakeholder orientation. Journal of Business Ethics, 11: 115-123.

Washington Post. 1993. Pepco bias suit heads for 38 million settlement. February 21: Al.

Weidenbaum, M., & Vogt, S. 1987. Takeovers and stockholders: Winners and losers. Cali- fornia Management Review, 29(4): 157-168.

Williamson, 0. E. 1985. The economic institutions of capitalism. New York: Free Press.

Williamson, 0. E., & Winter, S. G. (Eds.). 1991. The nature of the firm: Origins, evolution, and development. New York: Oxford University Press.

Wood, D. J. 1991a. Corporate social performance revisited. Academy of Management Re- view, 16: 691-718.

Wood, D. J. 1991b. Social issues in management: Theory and research in corporate social performance. Journal of Management, 17: 383-405.

Worthy, J. C. 1984. Shaping an American institution: Robert E. Wood and Sears, Roebuck. Urbana: University of Illinois.

Thomas Donaldson is the John F. Connelly Professor of Business Ethics in the School of Business at Georgetown University. He is also an adjunct professor in the De- partment of Philosophy and a senior research fellow at the Kennedy Institute of Ethics. His current research focuses on the intersection between social contract and stakeholder theories of ethics, especially in the context of international business.

Lee E. Preston received his Ph.D. from Harvard University. He is a professor of business and public policy in the College of Business and Management at the University of Maryland. His current research interests include international busi- ness-government relations.