the rise of the regulatory state - harvard university

40
The Rise of the Regulatory State Citation Glaeser, Edward L, and Andrei Shleifer. 2003. The Rise of the Regulatory State. Journal of Economic Literature 41, no. 2: 401–425. doi:10.1257/002205103765762725. Published Version doi:10.1257/002205103765762725 Permanent link http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:30747197 Terms of Use This article was downloaded from Harvard University’s DASH repository, and is made available under the terms and conditions applicable to Other Posted Material, as set forth at http:// nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:dash.current.terms-of-use#LAA Share Your Story The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Submit a story . Accessibility

Upload: others

Post on 15-Feb-2022

1 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: The Rise of the Regulatory State - Harvard University

The Rise of the Regulatory State

CitationGlaeser, Edward L, and Andrei Shleifer. 2003. The Rise of the Regulatory State. Journal of Economic Literature 41, no. 2: 401–425. doi:10.1257/002205103765762725.

Published Versiondoi:10.1257/002205103765762725

Permanent linkhttp://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:30747197

Terms of UseThis article was downloaded from Harvard University’s DASH repository, and is made available under the terms and conditions applicable to Other Posted Material, as set forth at http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:dash.current.terms-of-use#LAA

Share Your StoryThe Harvard community has made this article openly available.Please share how this access benefits you. Submit a story .

Accessibility

Page 2: The Rise of the Regulatory State - Harvard University

NBER WORKING PAPER SERIES

THE RISE OF THE REGULATORY STATE

Edward L. GlaeserAndrei Shleifer

Working Paper 8650http://www.nber.org/papers/w8650

NATIONAL BUREAU OF ECONOMIC RESEARCH1050 Massachusetts Avenue

Cambridge, MA 02138December 2001

We are grateful to Simeon Djankov, Claudia Goldin, Oliver Hart, Simon Johnson, Larry Katz, Louis Kaplow,Rafael La Porta, Florencio Lopez-de-Silanes, Steven Shavell, and Lawrence Summers for helpful comments,and to the NSF for funding. The views expressed herein are those of the authors and not necessarily thoseof the National Bureau of Economic Research.

© 2001 by Edward L. Glaeser and Andrei Shleifer. All rights reserved. Short sections of text, not to exceedtwo paragraphs, may be quoted without explicit permission provided that full credit, including © notice, isgiven to the source.

Page 3: The Rise of the Regulatory State - Harvard University

The Rise of the Regulatory StateEdward L. Glaeser and Andrei ShleiferNBER Working Paper No. 8650December 2001JEL No. K2, K13, K42, L51, N41

ABSTRACT

During the Progressive Era at the beginning of the 20 th century, the United States replaced

litigation by regulation as the principal mechanism of social control of business. To explain why this

happened, we present a model of choice of law enforcement strategy between litigation and regulation

based on the idea that justice can be subverted with sufficient expenditure of resources. The model

suggests that courts are more vulnerable to subversion than regulators, especially in an environment of

significant inequality of wealth and political power. The switch to regulation can then be seen as an

efficient response to the subversion of justice by robber barons during the Gilded Age. The model makes

sense of the progressive reform agenda, and of the successes and failures of alternative law enforcement

strategies in different countries.

Edward L. Glaeser Andrei ShleiferHarvard University Harvard University315A Littauer Center M9 Littauer CenterCambridge, MA 02138 Cambridge, MA 02138and NBER and [email protected] [email protected]

Page 4: The Rise of the Regulatory State - Harvard University

3

1. Introduction.

Before 1900, significant commercial disputes in the United States were generally

resolved in courts. Courts ruled on liability in industrial accidents, on anti-competitive practices

such as railroad rebates, on safety of foods and medicines, and even on the constitutionality of

the income tax. In the three decades between 1887, when Congress passed the Interstate

Commerce Act, and 1917, when “participation in the war put an end to the Progressive

movement,” (Hofstadter, 1955), this situation changed radically. Over thirty years, reformers

eroded the 19th century belief that litigation was the only appropriate response to the socially

harmful acts. During the Progressive Era, regulatory agencies at both the state and the federal

level began to replace courts in anti-trust policy, railroad pricing, food and drug safety, and many

other areas. At the same time, the U.S. politics experienced other important changes, such as

reform of the civil service, use of voter referendums to decide local issues, direct election of

senators, recall of judges, and the growth of government more generally. In this paper, we

attempt to understand why these changes occurred in the United States between 1887 and 1917.

Conventional economic theories of regulation do not help understand the Progressive

movement. The standard public interest theory holds that regulation deals with market failures

and externalities (Pigou 1934, Stiglitz 1989), but does not explain why either contract or tort law

could not address these problems in the first place. Coase (1960) draws attention to this failure of

regulatory economics to deal with the alternative possibility of judicial enforcement of laws and

contracts, but does not address the choice of courts versus regulators. Posner (1992) and Shavell

(1984a) discuss this choice between courts and regulators from the efficiency perspective. Posner

(1992) emphasizes the fixed cost of lawsuits as a potential argument for regulation, whereas

Shavell (1984a) points to the limits on the violator’s ability to pay as a drawback of litigation.

Both of these theories predict that as cases became larger and the defendants’ pockets deeper

Page 5: The Rise of the Regulatory State - Harvard University

4

during the Gilded Age, efficiency calls for more litigation and less regulation. The reality, of

course, was the opposite. Finally, Stigler (1971) and McChesney (1987) rejuvenated the

economic theories of regulation by questioning the motives and the capabilities of the regulators.

Their theories, however, are not helpful in thinking about the Progressive era, when the pressure

for regulation came from the public and populist politicians rather than industry itself.

To discuss progressive reforms, we present a model of choice of a law enforcement

regime between court-enforced liability and regulator-enforced input controls. A society can

impose liability payments for accidents, for example, or require precautionary investments.

Whatever approach a society chooses, law enforcement is not free, and the incentives, costs and

opportunities facing law enforcers crucially shape the efficiency of alternative choices. As a

consequence, different institutional arrangements are appropriate for different countries at

different stages of economic and political development.

In our model, the crucial difference between liability and regulation as alternative

systems of controlling market behavior is their vulnerability to subversion by the potential

violator. Subversion includes such techniques as intimidating judges and regulators, bribing

them, and using delay tactics to postpone a trial or a liability payment. By expending sufficient

resources on subversion of justice, the potential violator can avoid either regulatory compliance

or a liability payment. However, because liability regimes entail large payments with a small

probability, such regimes are more vulnerable to ex post subversion than the regulation of inputs,

especially in countries lacking law and order in the first place. Moreover, the problem of

subversion of liability regimes becomes worse in situations of extreme inequality of economic

and political resources between plaintiffs and defendants. In such circumstances, regulation is

more efficient than liability. This reason for the switch to regulation complements several others

Page 6: The Rise of the Regulatory State - Harvard University

5

of relevance to progressive reform, such as the stronger incentives and greater specialization of

regulators compared to judges (Landis 1938, Glaeser, Johnson, and Shleifer 2001).

The theoretical analysis points to a fundamental change that made it efficient for the

American society to increasingly rely on regulation. The commercialization and industrialization

of the economy in the second half of the 19th century created extreme inequality of resources

among the parties in tort and contract disputes, and therefore gravely exacerbated the problem of

subversion. When courts and legislatures could be bought or manipulated, individuals and small

companies were unlikely to prevail against “robber barons” in accident, restraint of trade, or

discriminatory tactics disputes. From our perspective, the regulation of markets was first and

foremost a response to the problem of subversion of law enforcement through courts. Moreover,

the other political changes of this period, such as the Civil Service reform, increasing importance

of direct elections, and judicial recalls can also be understood from the perspective of controlling

subversion.

Woodrow Wilson (1913) held the failure of courts to be a crucial reason for the necessity

of regulation in his New Freedom program.

The judicial process is the ultimate safeguard of the things that we must hold stable in thiscountry. But suppose that that safeguard is corrupted; suppose that it does not guard myinterests and yours, but guards merely the interests of a very small group of individuals;and whenever your interest clashes with theirs, yours will have to give way, though yourepresent ninety percent of the citizens, and they only ten percent. Then where is yoursafeguard? (Wilson, 1913, p. 240).

Writing during the New Deal, Landis (1938) saw regulation as a political response to the failure

of courts to keep up with the community ideas of justice. He thought that the advocacy of

“leaving the problems of railroad charges and management to work themselves out in the courts

as questions arise from time to time…indicates a singular unawareness of the fact that the chief

drive for the resort to the administrative process in the field of railroad regulation arose from a

Page 7: The Rise of the Regulatory State - Harvard University

6

recognition that the remedies that the courts could provide were insufficient to make effective the

policies that were being demanded.” In effect, our model provides an efficiency rationale for this

switch from litigation to regulation.

In addition to helping clarify a crucial period of U.S. economic theory, the model sheds

light on a number of theoretical and policy problems of law enforcement. Economists since

Coase (1960) have been interested in the question of whether regulation or litigation is a better

way to deal with tort problems. Coase argued generally that “transaction costs” should

determine the answer, and the successor literature has identified a range of such costs (e.g.,

Shavell 1984a, 1984b). Here we point to a different kind of transaction costs, namely the ability

of the violators to subvert a law enforcement mechanism that imposes on them a very high

penalty, and argue that this force is crucial for the choice of law enforcement strategy. This

approach also helps us understand why Becker’s (1968) “boil them in oil” enforcement

strategies, which entail very high penalties with a very small probability and hence minimize

investigation costs, are rarely workable: they will be subverted ex post.2

More generally, the analysis sheds light on a critical determinant of optimal law

enforcement strategy, namely how vulnerable the system of justice is to subversion. In situations

of extreme vulnerability to corruption or intimidation, the optimal strategy might be no legal or

regulatory restrictions at all, as the alternative is the socially costly regime in which rules are

simply subverted. In the intermediate regimes, the most efficient policy is regulation. Although

it is not as efficient as litigation absent subversion, regulation is less vulnerable to subversion

2 This reasoning suggested to us an alternative title for the paper, “The Denise Rich effect” in recognitionof a friend of President Clinton who secured a pardon for her former husband by making a donation of afew million dollars to the Clinton Presidential library. This event apparently followed an offer to the U.S.government from Mr. Rich, a fugitive financier, of $100 million to settle all charges against him, whichwas turned down by the U.S. Justice Department that wanted him to stand trial and go to jail. The pointhere, as in our model, is that harsh penalties lead to subversion of justice.

Page 8: The Rise of the Regulatory State - Harvard University

7

than litigation, and might be socially preferred for that reason. Finally, in the regimes where the

system of justice is least vulnerable to subversion, liability regimes – either strict liability or

negligence – become the optimal strategy. In broad terms, the paper suggests that the optimal

strategy of law enforcement depends on how much order the country has in the first place.

In the next section, we sketch the U.S. regulatory situation in the second half of the 19th

century, and the changes it underwent during the Progressive era. In Section 3, we present a

model of the choice of a law enforcement strategy. In Section 4, we apply the model to the U.S.

experience, while in Section 5 we draw broader implications. Section 6 concludes the paper.

2. Enforcement by courts in the 19th century

We start with three claims about the United States during the “Gilded Age” between the

Civil War and the Progressive Era. First, until the end of the 19th century, the U.S. in many

respects followed the laissez-faire ideal in which courts rather than regulatory agencies dealt

with socially harmful acts. Second, after the Civil War, wealth and power regularly subverted

the workings of the court system. Third, this subversion of courts entailed outcomes radically

different from those suggested by Coase’s (1960) benign vision of judicial enforcement.

Traditional arguments for the failure of the Coase theorem, such as transaction costs (Shavell

1987), do not explain the limits of the late 19th century American justice. Instead, 19th century

courts failed because money and power regularly influenced the path of justice.

By the late 19th century, tort law became one of the great edifices of the common law,

whose development was greatly accelerated by the industrial revolution in general and railroads

in particular. “Trains were also wild beasts; they roared through the countryside, killing

livestock, setting fires on houses and crops, smashing wagons at grade crossings, mangling

passengers and freight. Boilers exploded; trains hurtled off tracks; bridges collapsed;

Page 9: The Rise of the Regulatory State - Harvard University

8

locomotives collided in a grinding scream of steel. Railroad law and tort law grew up, then,

together. In a sense, the two were the same (Friedman 1985, p. 468).” In cases of both personal

and social harm, individual sought damages in common law courts. In theory at least, legal

doctrine of the 19th century was more strongly oriented towards eliminating externalities than

modern doctrine. Horwitz (1992) describes how the maxim sic utere, “use your own so as not to

injure others,” was invoked by many common law judges. This maxim justified court action

against a variety of perceived nuisances (saloons, gunpowder storage facilities, slaughterhouses)

“which could be abated without any justification of the defendant.”

In the development of tort law, the 19th century saw the great debate between strict

liability and negligence standards (Horwitz 1992).3 The English case of Rylands v. Fletcher

(1868), in which a court held a landowner liable when a reservoir he built on his own property

accidentally flooded the plaintiff’s coal mine, stands as the great statement of strict liability. In

contrast, American jurists, most notably Holmes (1881), sought to make negligence a more

common rule. Several great legal reputations of this period, including those of Holmes, Cardozo

and Brandeis, are intimately linked to their contributions to the development of tort law.4

While the courts developed the law, they also protected their dominance in this area.

Supreme courts regularly struck down nascent attempts at regulation by appeals to freedom of

contract. In Lochner v. New York (1905), the New York and U.S. supreme courts ruled that

maximum hours legislation was unconstitutional for bakeries because “there is no reasonable

ground for interfering with the liberty of person or the right of free contract, by determining the

3 Strict liability means that the plaintiff just needs to show causation. Negligence means that the plaintiffneeds to show both causation and some form of negligence.4 Schwartz (1981, 1989) argues that the movement from strict liability to negligence is not detectableprior to the Civil War. Our theory focuses on the post-civil-war period, where the change is clearer.

Page 10: The Rise of the Regulatory State - Harvard University

9

hours of labor, in the occupation of a baker.” In the Gilded Age, courts provided remedies for

harm. Regulation was rare and regulatory agencies almost non-existent.

Despite the dominance of the courts, many observers of the Gilded Age see them as

ineffective and partial arbiters of justice. Skocpol (1992) complains about the pro-business

attitudes of the courts. Horwitz (1992) argues that this era is replete with pro-business jurists,

and associates the negligence principle with attempts by pro-business jurists to protect firms

from lawsuits. Lockard and Murphy (1992) claim that judges supported corporations because of

“a campaign to ‘educate’ judges about the sacredness of private property.” According to

Friedman (1985), “What they [the leading concepts of tort law] added up to was also crystal-

clear. Enterprise was favored over workers, slightly less so over passengers and members of the

public…. The thrust of the rules, taken as a whole, approached the position that corporate

enterprise should be flatly immune from actions for personal injury (p. 475).”

Judicial ideology, of course, was itself shaped by the selection of judges, and through

their influence on the political machines, industrialists were able to determine who sat on the

bench. According to Woodrow Wilson (1913, p.242), “The disease lies in the region where

these men [judges] get their nominations; and if you can recover for the people the selecting of

judges, you will not have to trouble about their recall. Selection is of more radical consequence

than election.” Callow (1966, p. 135) writes that “the appointment of the right men to key posts

is the third step in making the law as much a matter of politics as of justice.”

After the selection, judges as well as prosecutors were influenced by the rich and

powerful through both legal and illegal means. Nineteenth century corporations projected

substantial political influence, superior lawyers and ready access to large legal war chests. Their

lawyers produced briefs that exonerated their clients and slowed down the wheels of justice for

years. Last but not least, they routinely bribed legislators, judges, and juries.

Page 11: The Rise of the Regulatory State - Harvard University

10

Lloyd (1894) describes how Standard Oil subverted the attempts of its opponents to

secure damages in courts by intimidation and bribery of witnesses, payments and political

pressures on judges and legislators, and theft and destruction of evidence. Tarbell (1903)

corroborates the outline of Lloyd’s account. In “Robber Barons,” Josephson (1934) relates the

story of the battle for the Erie railroad between Commodore Vanderbilt and Jay Gould. The

battling barons acquired a number of judges and legislators, who issued laws, rules and

injunctions preventing each party from exercising their powers over the railroad on request. The

battle culminated in an open auction of policies by the New York legislature, which Gould won

by paying higher bribes to more legislators.

The subversion of justice is a pervasive theme of the muckrakers. In “Tweed Days in St.

Louis,” Lincoln Steffens tells the story of a young Circuit Attorney, Mr. Folk, who was put on

the Democratic ticket by mistake, and upon election began putting both Democratic and

Republican officials behind bars for corruption. Having failed to persuade Mr. Folk to cease and

desist, the local political machine decided to get rid of him. “At the meeting of corruptionists

three courses were decided upon. Political leaders were to work on the Circuit Attorney by

promise of future reward, or by threats. Detectives were to ferret out of the young lawyer’s past

anything that could be used against him. Witnesses would be sent out of town and provided with

money to remain away until the adjournment of the grand jury.” In Minneapolis, Steffens

describes the coercion of the jury in the trial of the corrupt Mayor Ames. He points to the

foreman of the jury, “to whom $28,000 was offered to quit, and for whose slaughter a slugger

was hired to come from Chicago” (Steffens, 1906).

Albert Cardozo—the father of the great progressive jurist Benjamin Cardozo—is a

classic example of a judge in league with a political machine. Appointed by William Marcy

Tweed to the New York State Supreme Court, Albert Cardozo served Tweed ably. “He became

Page 12: The Rise of the Regulatory State - Harvard University

11

a kind of escape hatch for criminals; through his good offices he pardoned or dismissed several

hundred known criminals who were or might be useful to the [Tweed] Ring (Callow 1966).” At

his own impeachment hearings, Cardozo was accused of crimes ranging from standard nepotism

(his nephew was a beneficiary of his power) to releasing convicted clients, to helping Fisk and

Gould reduce the losses from their Gold Conspiracy through the legal system.

The pervasive distortion of justice through legal and illegal forms of influence decided

many cases and had a broad influence on the 19th century economy. Courts often failed to

address the grievances of the parties damaged in the new economy, such as workers suffering

from accidents, producers suffering from abusive tactics by the railroads, or consumers poisoned

by bad food, and ruled in favor of large corporations. Tort claims against railroads, following

large scale accidents that often killed third parties, proved to be slow and often unsuccessful. In

Ryan v. New York Central Railroad (1866), the New York court of appeals argued that even if a

railroad caused a fire, its liability extended only to the immediately adjacent house and not to

other homes destroyed by the fire. The court held that “to sustain such a claim…would subject

[the railroad] to a liability against which no prudence could guard, and to meet which no private

fortune could be adequate” (Friedman 1985, p. 469). More generally, the courts’ view of such

accidents was “NOBODY TO BLAME” (Friedman 1985, p. 470).

Fishback and Kantor (2000) describe the extreme inequality between firm and employee

in industrial accident claims. The legal strength of corporations meant that many injured

families settled for relatively small amounts of money. Summarizing a number of studies,

Fishback and Kantor estimate that families of workers killed in industrial accidents received an

average of 8 months pay, and nothing in about 40% of the cases (p.34). Under political (and

perhaps more direct) pressure from manufacturers, courts adopted the position that the estate of

Page 13: The Rise of the Regulatory State - Harvard University

12

an injured worker must prove negligence by the company, and that evidence of negligence by the

worker himself, or by one of his co-workers, absolved the company of liability.

In sum, the system of dispute resolution by courts, which emerged in agrarian America in

the 18th and early 19th centuries, was not suited for the conditions of the late 19th century. The

reason for this failure is that large corporations possessed economic resources far in excess of

those at the disposal of their opponents – whether individuals or small firms – and could use

these resources to subvert justice. The mechanisms of subversion ranged from superior legal

talent to political pressure to outright bribery. For our purposes, the exact mechanism does not

matter. What matters is that courts did not make the perpetrators pay for the social harm of their

actions. As a consequence, the system broke down.

The Regulatory Response

As the courts supported the corporations, political actors sought a different response to

social harm. Starting with Charles Francis Adams and the Massachusetts Railroad Commission,

regulatory agencies became a substitute for judicial action. The reforms started with states and

municipalities, but eventually moved to the federal level. In 1887, the Interstate Commerce Act

created the Interstate Commerce Commission, which – combined with subsequent legislation –

had the power to stop railroad rebates and ultimately, under the Hepburn Act of 1906, to set

rates. In 1890, Congress passed the Sherman Act, restricting the formation of trusts.

The real growth of regulatory activity occurred during the Progressive era after the turn

of the century, under the presidencies of Theodore Roosevelt and Woodrow Wilson. In 1906,

under muckraking pressures, Congress passed Pure Foods and Drugs to control the distribution

of medicines, as well as a federal meat-inspection law. Under Wilson, banking came under

federal regulation in the Federal Reserve Act of 1913 and anti-trust enforcement was intensified

Page 14: The Rise of the Regulatory State - Harvard University

13

under the Clayton Act in 1914, to name just two measures. Fishback and Kantor (2000) take the

adoption of workers compensation laws by several U.S. states around the turn of the century to

be a response to the failure of courts to address the problems of workers injured or killed in

industrial accidents.

Although the growth of regulation slowed down, and arguably retreated, under the

Republican presidencies of the 1920s, it revived and accelerated under Franklin Roosevelt in the

1930s. Among the most notable measures of this period were the Securities Acts of 1933 and

1934, written in part by Landis, which brought securities markets under federal regulation.

When Landis wrote in 1938, he could confidently conclude that “the administrative” has

replaced “the judiciary” as the principal form of social control of business.

3. The Model.

A firm can take a level of precaution, equal to 1Q or 2Q , in order to avoid an accident.

The high level of precaution, 2Q , requires a cost of S times C, while the low level of precaution,

1Q , is free. The parameter C represents the cost of precaution per unit of production—the level

of S represents the scale of the firm. There are two types of firms that might be responsible for

the accident: α’s and β’s. For α types the probability of an accident is unaffected by precaution

and equals αP . This implies, importantly, that it is not efficient for type α firms to invest in a

high level of precaution. Let απ be a proportion of firms that are of type α. For type β firms the

probability of an accident equals 1P or 2P , with 21 PP > , depending on whether the level of

precaution is 1Q or 2Q . The accident imposes a social cost of S times D, where D refers to the

social cost per unit of economic activity and S refers again to the scale of the firm.

Page 15: The Rise of the Regulatory State - Harvard University

14

For our purposes, it is not important whether D is concentrated (as in the case of a

workplace accident) or widely shared (as in the case of pollution). When the damage is

concentrated, simple ex ante contracts can sometimes deal with possible damages, even without

a liability regime. For example, an employee working in a dangerous occupation would receive

a higher wage, which compensates him for the risk of an accident. Even in such situations,

however, it is generally efficient for the firm to provide the risk–averse employee with some

accident insurance (Shavell 1987). As a consequence, the firm has an incentive to avoid paying

after the accident takes place. To the extent that the dispute needs to be settled in court, as such

issues often are (Fishback and Kantor 2000), our analysis remains pertinent. We make:

Assumption 1: CDPP >− )( 21 ,

so that for the β types, unlike for the α types, the high level of precaution is socially valuable.

We consider the standard menu of possible regulatory schemes: (1) strict liability, (2)

negligence, and (3) regulation of inputs.

1. Strict liability requires that, in case of an accident, the firm must pay a fine any time that

damages occur.

2. Negligence means that a fine is charged whenever damages occur and when the firm

undertakes the low level of precaution.

3. Regulation requires that the high level of precaution be taken and imposes a fine, F,

whenever the firm fails to do so. We assume that the regulator cannot distinguish

between the two types of firms.

With no problems of enforcement, strict liability can achieve the first best as long as the fine

(denoted by F) is greater than 21 PP

SC−

. Negligence can also achieve the first best whenever

Page 16: The Rise of the Regulatory State - Harvard University

15

αPSCF

PSC <<

1

. Note that 211 PP

SCPSC

−< . Because strict liability uses less information, it

requires a larger fine. At the same time, strict liability provides no incentives for the type α

firms to invest in the useless for them high level of precaution, and therefore eliminates this

source of inefficiency.

Finally, we assume that the regulator learns that the firm is using low levels of precaution

with exogenous probability p. We have also considered the case where p is endogenous. Since it

yields qualitatively similar results, we focus here on the simpler scenario with exogenous p. To

allow regulation to be a potentially efficient scheme in the presence of subversion we make:

Assumption 2: 1Pp > .

The idea behind this assumption is that the regulation can be designed so that detection of the

failure to invest in precaution is relatively inexpensive and certain. This could involve

mandating well-specified “bright line” rules, such as the use of safety equipment or of warning

labels for customers. In addition, some regulations are designed to encourage third party

enforcement. For example, employees or customers themselves can occasionally cheaply

identify violations and complain (Glaeser and Shleifer 2001a).

We turn next to optimal law enforcement in the presence of subversion. We assume that

the firm can impose a cost of A on the law enforcer who wants to punish it. This cost may

reflect character assassination, complaints to superiors, intimidation, delay, or political

contributions to opponents. The cost to the firm of imposing A on the law enforcer is given by

K(A), which we take to be a social as well as a private cost. A downward shift of the function

K(A) can be interpreted as an improvement in the technology to subvert justice available to the

firm, so we think of regimes with a higher K(A) as possessing higher levels of “law and order.”

Page 17: The Rise of the Regulatory State - Harvard University

16

For simplicity, we assume that the firm must invest in K(A) up front, before any

accidents occur or decisions as to its liability are taken by law enforcers. This can be thought of

as an investment in the capacity to impose pain (“armaments”). Once this capacity is acquired,

we assume that the marginal cost of imposing pain A on the law enforcer is zero, so that the firm

is always willing to do so when it does not like the decision. This formulation avoids the

credibility issues inherent in most crime and punishment models, where the violator might not

want to follow through with punishing the law enforcer (and vice versa). This formulation also

avoids the possibility of the firm bargaining with the law enforcer over the verdict and the bribe.

However, this model better describes intimidation and legal tactics than bribes per se.

The benefit to a law enforcer such as a judge or a regulator of enforcing the law equals B,

which we take to be exogenous. It can reflect the degree of judge/regulator’s career concerns or

innate integrity (Posner 1995). In this paper, we do not consider the differences in incentives

between judges and regulators, which might be important (Glaeser, Johnson, and Shleifer 2001).

If BA ≥ , the violator subverts justice and avoids punishment. In this case, the violator rationally

chooses A=B and incurs a cost of X ≡ K(B). The possibility of subversion of justice means that

if the fine is greater than X, the firm will choose to subvert justice and pay X instead.

Recall that we have assumed (Assumption 2) that 211 PP

CPC

pC

−<< , where

pC ,

1PC and

21 PPC−

are minimal fines that overcome the subversion of justice in regulation, contributory

negligence and strict liability schemes respectively. We can now formulate

Proposition 1. If 1PP <α , then:

(a) for pC

SX < the only feasible option is laissez faire;

Page 18: The Rise of the Regulatory State - Harvard University

17

(b) for 1P

CSX

pC << regulation dominates laissez faire if

))(1( 21 PPCD

−−>

απ, and vice versa if

this condition does not hold;

(c) for 211 PP

CSX

PC

−<< negligence achieves first-best; and

(d) for 21 PP

CSX

−> both negligence and strict liability achieve first-best.

If 1PP >α , then:

(a) for pC

SX < the only feasible option is laissez faire;

(b) for 21 PP

CSX

pC

−<< regulation dominates laissez faire if

))(1( 21 PPCD

−−>

απ (negligence

achieves the same social outcomes but requires larger fines), and vice versa if this condition

does not hold.

(c) for 21 PP

CSX

−> strict liability achieves the first-best.

For 1PP <α , Figure 1 illustrates the proposition graphically.

Negligence

Regulation

Nothing

21 PPC−1P

CpC

D

SX

Nothing

Strictliability

Figure 1

Page 19: The Rise of the Regulatory State - Harvard University

18

Proof. We consider four different cases with respect to the level of the cost of the subversion of

justice, X/S, relative to the minimum fines necessary to implement alternative enforcement

schemes (see Figure 2).

1. pC

SX < . In this case, the firm has access to cheap intimidation technology, so no

regulatory scheme can force the firm to invest in precaution. Any fine – from regulation,

strict liability, or negligence, will be undone. The expected social loss if there is no

regulation equals SDPSDPLN 1)1( ααα ππ −+= .

2. 1P

CSX

pC << . In this case, neither strict liability nor negligence schemes can implement

efficient level of precaution for the type β firms. The two relevant options are to regulate

or to do nothing. Regulation forces firms to maintain the high level of precaution if the

fine, F, is set in the interval XFp

SC <≤ . Under our assumptions, both types of the firms

choose the high level of precaution, which is excessive for type α firms. The expected

social loss under regulation equals SCSDPSDPLR +−+= 2)1( ααα ππ . When C is small,

i.e. CDPP >−− ))(1( 21απ , then excessive precaution is less wasteful than the expected

damage from its absence, and regulation dominates laissez faire regime. When

DPPC ))(1( 21 −−> απ , then doing nothing is more efficient.

SX /

pC

1PC

21 PPC−

1 2 3 4

Figure 2

Page 20: The Rise of the Regulatory State - Harvard University

19

3. For X/S in the interval 211 PP

CSX

PC

−<< negligence becomes a subversion-of-justice-

proof option. If 1PP <α then negligence achieves the first best outcome when F is set in

the interval },min{1 αP

SCXFPSC << . The expected loss in this case is equal to

FBCN LSCSDPSDPL =+−+= ))(1( 2ααα ππ .

If 1PP >α then negligence cannot achieve both the efficiently low level of precaution

for the type α firms and the efficiently high level of precaution for the type β firms. The

social loss coincides with that under regulation, and the choice between laissez faire and

regulation is the same as in case 2.

4. If 21 PP

CSX

−> , then the subversion of justice is not an acute problem, and high fines

necessary for strict liability scheme cannot be avoided. Any fine larger than 21 PP

SC−

and

smaller than X leads to the first best outcome in the strict liability scheme.

In sum, among the three possible regulatory schemes, only negligence and strict liability

can in principle achieve the first best outcome. Strict liability, to be feasible, requires high cost of

the subversion of justice, but has the advantage that it does not incentivize firms that do not

benefit from precaution to invest in it. Negligence is less prone to subversion of justice, but does

distort the incentives of the firms that do not benefit from it.

Perhaps the principal message of this model is the tight relationship between the “law and

order” already prevailing in a society, and the optimality of alternative law enforcement

schemes. As Figure 1 illustrates, in the environment of low law and order, doing nothing might

Page 21: The Rise of the Regulatory State - Harvard University

20

be superior to imposing legal and regulatory rules that are only going to be subverted at some

social cost. In either case, harmful conduct is not punished, but with laissez-faire, corruption and

other forms of subversion are avoided. In the regime of intermediate law and order, regulation

might be efficient precisely because the fines it entails to achieve compliance are modest, and

therefore will not be avoided through subversion of justice. The efficiency of regulation in this

regime comes precisely from the fact that the penalties associated with the liability regime are

too high, and therefore in such a regime justice is subverted. It is more efficient to have the

cruder but enforceable system of regulation, than the finer and unenforceable system of liability.

Finally, after high levels of law and order are already achieved, the society can attempt to resolve

disputes through courts, using either a contributory negligence or a strict liability system. These

systems call for the imposition of high fines ex post, and are therefore only feasible when the

liable parties can be compelled to pay these fines without subverting justice.

The case for optimality of regulation suggested by this model is related to, but different

from, those considered in our earlier work. Glaeser, Johnson, and Shleifer (2001) follow Landis

(1938) and present a model in which it is easier for the society to provide high powered

incentives for regulators than for judges. In the terminology of this model, B is higher for

regulators than for judges. This too provides a rationale for regulation in some circumstances,

especially when the costs of identifying violations are high. Glaeser and Shleifer (2001a) do not

deal with the incentives of law enforcers, but rather with the costs of identifying violations. The

paper argues that, in some circumstances, regulatory “bright line rules” make it cheaper to

identify and penalize violations than extracting damages for harm or taxing undesirable conduct.

For example, blue laws forbidding liquor sales on Sundays may be easier to enforce than Sunday

liquor taxes, especially when private detection of violations is part of enforcement.

Page 22: The Rise of the Regulatory State - Harvard University

21

Finally, in Glaeser and Shleifer (2001b), we also consider the problem of subversion of

justice, but focus on the historical development of common and civil law. We argue that the

civil law institutions of state-employed professional judges following clear legal rules under

constant superior review developed in France as a response to high levels of disorder prevailing

in the society. These institutions were a mechanism of protecting law enforcers from subversion

by powerful litigants. In contrast, the common law institutions of adjudication by lay juries

following broad principles of community justice with only perfunctory appeal were more

appropriate for the relatively more orderly England, where subversion of justice by the powerful

magnates was a less pervasive problem. Although this paper and Glaeser and Shleifer (2001b)

are clearly cousins, they deal with very different consequences of the problem of subversion.

4. Implications of the Model for the Progressive Era.

We can use the model of the previous section to understand the rise of regulation in the

United States at the end of the 19th and the beginning of the 20th centuries. Our interpretation is

that “S”—the scale of economic activity—rose dramatically over the 19th century. During the

industrial revolution, firms grew sharply in size. The social costs of harm grew roughly

proportionately, but the costs of subverting justice did not. As a result, a legal system that may

have operated well during the agrarian period, failed when faced with entities that had huge

incentives to subvert it. Because higher levels of “S” lead to subversion of both strict liability

and negligence, regulation became the efficient response.

During the first half of the 19th century, the bulk of the economy was agricultural; 64

percent of workers in 1850 were in farm occupations. The manufacturing that did exist was

concentrated in small firms. The McLane report, a large but incomplete survey of the economy,

found only 106 manufacturing firms in 1832 with assets above $100,000. Chandler (1977) saw

Page 23: The Rise of the Regulatory State - Harvard University

22

production in the mid-19th century as “being carried out by a large number of small units

employing less than fifty workers…”

When a firm caused social harm in 1830, the judicial system could usually deal with it.

Assessed damages would generally be small and the firm did not have a strong incentive to

subvert justice. Moreover, the firm itself was small and did not have the resources to subvert the

system. We take this to mean that the U.S. in 1830 is described by the right part of Figure 1,

where 21 PP

SCX−

> . In that region, strict liability produces the first best outcome.

This situation changed after the Civil War. The building of railroads, the growth of

industrial enterprises and mines, and the creation of large financial firms introduced into the

American economy disputes between parties of highly differentiated economic and political

resources. America became far less agricultural; by 1900, only 37 percent of workers were in

farm occupations. The manufacturing industry grew more than tenfold (measured by number of

employees) over this time period. The new technologies often proved to be deadly. Thousands

of passengers and third parties died in railroad accidents. By 1900, there were approximately

35,000 deaths and two million injuries annually in industrial accidents (Friedman, 1985).

New technologies also raised the scale of both railroads and manufacturing firms, as

national markets developed. Innovations in organizational form made larger firm size feasible.

Chandler (1977) identifies 278 firms with more than $20 million in assets in 1917. Hofstadter

(1955) writes that “the Morgan interests at the peak of the financial systems held 341

directorships in 112 corporations … with aggregate resources or capitalization of

$22,245,000,000.” This vast expansion in firm size corresponds to an increase in the parameter

“S” in the model.

Page 24: The Rise of the Regulatory State - Harvard University

23

The model corresponds most closely to situations where the industrial revolution raised

both the precaution costs and the size of single accidents, e.g., train wrecks or factory fires (such

as the famous Triangle Shirtwaist Fire, where 146 workers died). In other instances, such as

industrial accidents involving individual workers, the cost of precaution and the number of

accidents rise with enterprise size, but the size of each individual case remains small. If such

cases are isolated, it might not pay a firm to subvert justice. In practice, however, the stakes in

such cases are large for large firms, because of the power of legal precedents. When a steel mill

or a railroad concedes liability in an industrial accident, it becomes vulnerable to claims in all the

future similar accidents. As a consequence, even in such situations, the assumption of the model

that the willingness to subvert justice rises with the scale of the firm is appropriate.

The model treats S as exogenous, but also points to an incentive for firms to increase it.

In the regimes of either strict liability or negligence, rising values of S make no difference to

corporate profits when corporations actually pay the fines, as long as fines scale with S.

However, when X is independent of S, when firms subvert justice, higher values of S lead to

lower payments for social harm. The payment per unit of economic activity is X/S and as such,

larger firms pay less.5 Indeed, the advantage of scale in subverting the legal system is a

competitive edge of 19th century corporation. The muckraking literature sees the largest firms as

particularly effective in shaping legal outcomes.

The economic creations of the late 19th century, such as national railroad systems and

trusts, may have been designed to gain political and not just economic power. The entrepreneurs

5 This is not so when disputes are between two entities possessing comparable abilities to subvert justice,as in the battle for the Erie railroad. In this case, a judge or a legislator can just auction off a decision,with the result that X actually scales up with S. It has been said that commercial law in Russia in the1990s was developing through the disputes between the so-called oligarchs, where each side has thecapacity to bribe a judge, and so must appeal to the law as well in order to win its case.

Page 25: The Rise of the Regulatory State - Harvard University

24

could use the economic and political resources that such combinations brought to buy both

politics and justice. In a similar vein, and for similar reasons, financial-industrial groups were

created in Russia in the 1990s with the basic goal of attaining political rather than economic

influence (Nagel 1999).6

The progressives cited the rise in the scale of enterprise as a primary reason for new

government action. In 1888, Charles Eliot noted that a modestly sized Boston railroad had three

times as many employees as the Commonwealth of Massachusetts. The first chapter of Wilson’s

manifesto The New Freedom states that “the employer is now generally a corporation or a huge

company of some kind,” and as a result “new rules must be devised…” Wilson’s progressive

rival Theodore Roosevelt viewed Herbert Croly’s The Promise of American Life as his

intellectual sourcebook. Because of “the existing concentration of wealth and financial power in

the hands of few irresponsible men,” Croly believes “efficient regulation there must be.”

Progressives saw the scale of industrial enterprise as the root of the republic’s problems.

The model helps us understand Croly’s call for regulation. As S rises, the society moves

leftward across Figure 1. First, negligence becomes optimal and should replace strict liability.

We have already noted that, in the 1870s, negligence replaced strict liability as the standard in

tort law. As S continues to rise, negligence itself fails to produce desirable results. When S is

sufficiently high, and when D is also high, regulation provides the only reliable recourse against

social harms. This is ultimately our explanation of why the progressives saw the need for

6 In the first volume of the American Economic Review in 1887, Henry Adams wrote as follows: “Thepolicy of restricting public powers within the narrowest possible limits tends to render government weakand inefficient, and a weak government placed in the midst of a society controlled by the commercialspirit will quickly become a corrupt government; this in its turn reacts upon commercial society byencouraging private corporations to adopt bold measures for gaining control of government machinery.Thus the doctrine of laissez-faire overreaches itself; for the application of the rule which it lays down willsurely destroy the harmony between public and private duties essential to the best results in either domainof action.”

Page 26: The Rise of the Regulatory State - Harvard University

25

regulation. Because input regulation is more consistently applied and involves smaller penalties,

it provides a weaker incentive for the subversion of justice. If government action is at all

responsive to efficiency, the model predicts exactly the course of the Progressive era: increased

government regulation of business should follow the increase in its scale.

The Progressives themselves saw the problems of the judiciary and advocated regulation.

In The New Freedom, Wilson argues that it is “the right of government … to see whether

accidents were properly guarded against,” and that “if somebody puts a derrick improperly

secured on top of a building or overtopping the street, then the government of the city has the

right to see that that derrick is so secure that you and I can walk under it and not be afraid that

the heavens are going to fall on us.” Why doesn’t Wilson just trust the tort system as

administered by the judiciary? He also writes:

There have been courts in the United States which were controlled by the privateinterests. There have been supreme courts in our states before which plain mencould not get justice. There have been corrupt judges; there have been controlledjudges; there have been judges who acted as other men’s servants and not asservants of the public (Wilson, 1913, p. 240).

Croly also casts aspersions on judges and calls them “creatures of the political machine,” and

advocates his own more ambitious plan of government ownership. As Hofstadter (1955) writes:

“the average American tended more and more to rely on government regulation, to seek in

governmental actions a counterpoise to the power of private business.”

Understanding the Progressive Program

The Progressive program was not merely a revolution in regulation. The law saw a switch

from strict liability to negligence, which according to the model should follow an increase in

scale. More generally, the model suggests that efficient reforms should aim to raise X or reduce

S. Many progressive reforms can indeed be understood from this perspective.

Page 27: The Rise of the Regulatory State - Harvard University

26

One progressive innovation was the introduction of regulatory agencies to oversee

specific areas of the economy and to punish socially harmful conduct.7 Glaeser, Johnson and

Shleifer (2001) argue that the fundamental difference between courts and regulators lies in the

incentives of regulators. In the common law tradition, judges are regularly protected from

politicized incentives. Regulators, in contrast, are rewarded for finding violations. In the model,

the incentives created by regulation increase B. Many progressives also supported the “recall” of

government officials, especially judges. This innovation made it possible for voters to oust

officials failing to perform as the public wanted. We see this as an attempt to raise B for judges,

or alternatively to increase the cost they face if they give in to coercion, i.e. X.

Equally important to the progressives was the professionalization of bureaucracies, or

civil service reform. Croly advocates a more widespread use of life tenure for judges, which

would have a similar effect of reducing the political influence on them. The progressives’

simultaneous support of increased democracy in the form of judicial recall and of reduced

democracy in the form of civil service reform is puzzling. Both reforms, however, can be

understood as attempts to increase X. While the recalls aimed to punish bad judges, civil service

reform attempted to decrease the influence of the political machines in the administrative

process. Since political machines were used by business to select and coopt judges, eliminating

their influence raised the cost of subverting justice, i.e., the K(A) function. Since this also raises

X, civil service reform can also be seen as an efficient response to the increased scale of activity.

An alternative to using regulation or raising B was to reduce S directly. In his platform

of the New Freedom, Woodrow Wilson opposed “the [Roosevelt] doctrine that monopoly is

7 One can argue that when a regulator ultimately needs to go to court to obtain a judgment, the problem ofsubversion of courts remains. Courts, however, are much less likely to be subverted by defendants whenaction is brought by organized and powerful regulators, then when the plaintiffs are individual victims.

Page 28: The Rise of the Regulatory State - Harvard University

27

inevitable and that the only course open to the people of the United States is to submit to and

regulate it.” Instead, he advocated reducing firm size “to prevent private monopoly by law, to see

to it that the methods by which monopolies have been built up are legally made impossible.”

Indeed, the whole trust-busting program aimed at eliminating the power of trusts to

coerce politics and justice as much as reducing prices. Hofstadter (1955, p. 227) writes:

The progressive case against business organization was not confined to economicconsiderations, nor even to the more intangible sphere of economic morals. Stillmore widely felt was a fear founded in political realities—the fear that the greatbusiness combinations, being the only centers of wealth and power, would beable to lord it over all other interests and thus put an end to traditional democracy

Our model sheds light on such comments. Competitive prices may prevail in a duopoly

with two very large firms, but the scale of these enterprises may enable them to subvert justice.

Progressive trust-busting should be seen as a response to the subversion of justice, as well as a

means of addressing standard problems of monopoly pricing.

Along similar lines, our model might help explain the support for labor unions among

many progressives. Traditionally, economists understand labor unions as a means of restricting

labor supply and raising wages. Unions, however, can also become a political “countervailing

power” to large firms by projecting comparable economic resources (Galbraith 1952). When

large firms meet large unions in a political and economic marketplace, the efforts to subvert

justice by one meet countervailing efforts by the other. The formation of labor unions parallels

the creation of trusts and large industrial firms as a competitive reaction to subversion.

A final reform proposed by many progressives is the complete control of industry by the

government. If large firms subvert justice, or corrupt politicians to extract rents, then government

ownership may appear attractive. Because the nature of ownership changes a firm’s objective

function (as in Hart et al. 1997), government-owned firms may be less likely to corrupt the

system to extract rents (Glaeser 2001). Croly in particular favored this response to subversion of

Page 29: The Rise of the Regulatory State - Harvard University

28

justice: “if the interest of a corporation is so essentially hostile to the public interest … the

logical inference is not a system of semi-official and semi-private management, but a system of

exclusively public management.” This type of reform was unpopular in the U.S., perhaps

because the many problems of public ownership were appreciated, but European countries

moved in that direction. In those countries weaker rule of law meant that less extreme measures

could not be relied on to discipline big firms.

Discussion

Of necessity, a simple model like ours cannot deal with many important aspects of the

Progressive era. It may be worthwhile, therefore, to point out some of the key omissions and

alternative interpretations.

The first question is why the reforms took place at the time they did, and not before or

after? This question is especially important in view of our claim that the switch to regulation

was efficient, since it is not typically the case that efficiency considerations drive public policies.

In the United States, the increases in scale that warranted an efficient switch to regulation

occurred several years, and possibly decades, before the turn of the century. Compared to

efficiency, reforms were significantly delayed. One possible explanation of such stability, and

of why it was eventually overcome, is that inefficient methods of market regulation did not

matter to enough voters to shape their choices, or at least did not matter enough. By the end of

the 19th century, a growing number of voters became involved in the commercial and industrial

economy, and thus were affected by the subversion of justice. More and more people working

for corporations and railroads were exposed to industrial accidents. Increasing numbers of

people lived in the cities and suffered from the subversion of city administration. More and

more farmers and small businessmen were expropriated by railroads with market power, or by

Page 30: The Rise of the Regulatory State - Harvard University

29

larger competitors who made special deals with the railroads. “Politically, the rage of the

victims counted for very little in 1840, not much in 1860; by 1890, it was a roaring force”

(Friedman 1985, p. 476).

While this rage was the dominant factor behind the success of the progressives, at least

three other forces mattered. First, in the middle of the 19th century, relations between the North

and the South dominated politics. For years after the Civil War, venal Republican candidates

could whip up public support by “waving the bloody shirt,” and reminding voters of the North-

South issue. The reforming Horace Greeley was soundly beaten at the polls by Ulysses S.

Grant—a corrupt President who symbolized Northern dominance. Second, changing technology

in publishing facilitated the rise of popular muckraking journals. Free entry in this national

industry made it possible for journals such as McClure’s to thrive without the support of the local

business community, and indeed to flourish by attacking industry. Finally, a crucial

development in U.S. politics was the ascent of Theodore Roosevelt, who ran both his first term

and the election of 1904 on the platform of subversion of the judiciary and of restoration of

justice through regulation.

The second important question is whether our insistence on the efficiency of regulatory

reforms during the progressive era is correct. This question is especially relevant in light of the

fact that Progressivism in the United States followed the period of Populism. The simplest

alternative theory of regulatory reform is that its objective was redistribution from the haves to

the have nots rather than efficiency.

Redistribution certainly played some role in reforms, but efficiency considerations were

extremely important. First, many regulatory reforms were supported not just by the working

classes, but also by the urban elite, whose interests were championed both by the muckrakers and

by the Republicans Theodore Roosevelt and William H. Taft. This was hardly the populist

Page 31: The Rise of the Regulatory State - Harvard University

30

reform of William Jennings Bryan. In addition, it is important to remember that, unlike the West

European countries, the U.S. during this period does not develop a redistributive welfare state. If

redistribution was the principal goal of the progressives, there were much more direct ways of

reaching it than regulatory reform.

Third, our theory is derived from the assumption that regulators are less subject to

subversion than the courts (because the penalties from regulation are lower than those from

liability). In the 20th century, the capture of regulators by the industry through revolving door

and other policies became important, and dominated professional thinking about regulation after

World War II (McCraw 1984, Stigler 1971). Were the theories of superiority of regulation just a

figment of progressive imagination?

We do not believe so. We take on face value the progressives’ concern about political

appointment, intimidation, and corruption of judges. At the turn of the 20th century, these

concerns were vastly stronger than those about revolving door policies of professional regulatory

commissions. As the U.S. became more of a democratic and orderly society, concerns about

corruption and intimidation of judges have naturally receded, and those about regulatory capture

came into view. Not surprisingly, and in line with our argument that policies eventually move

toward efficiency, the end of the 20th century saw substitution of litigation for regulation.

Indeed, toward the end of the 20th century, the U.S. saw a different kind of potential

subversion of justice, where juries awarded enormous damages to plaintiffs suing corporations

for harm suffered in industrial and consumer product accidents. In response to such litigation,

corporations rather than the public sought protection from regulation, because the resources

required to fight liability claims in courts exceeded the potential costs from accepting regulation.

Page 32: The Rise of the Regulatory State - Harvard University

31

5. Implications for Law Enforcement.

Figure 1 allows us to consider the desirability of alternative modes of law enforcement in

different countries and for different activities. We can think of X – the cost of subverting justice

– as varying across countries and across activities. Some countries might have highly

independent, disciplined and efficient bureaucrats and regulators, who are invulnerable to

political pressure and bribes; this is the situation of a very high X. Other countries might have

poor, politically vulnerable, and easily corruptible officials, who cannot stand up to the pressure

from private parties they are supposed to regulate; this is a situation of low X. We can also think

of X varying across activities: a country might have enough bureaucratic prowess to control

violence within its borders, but not enough to administer securities or anti-trust laws. Our

framework allows us to consider the consequences of such variations. In this discussion, we take

X to be exogenous, even though many progressive and other reforms aimed to increase X.

The first, and arguably most important, message of the model is that in situations of

extremely low X, the optimal government policy is to do nothing. When the administrative

capacity of the government is severely limited, and both its judges and regulators are vulnerable

to intimidation and corruption, it might be better to accept the existing market failures and

externalities than to deal with them through either the administrative or the judicial process. For

if a county does attempt to correct market failures, justice will be subverted, and resources will

be wasted on subversion without successfully controlling market failures.

This implication of the model is of great significance.8 Some economists (e.g., Stiglitz

1989) see market failures as pervasive in the emerging and transition economies, and recommend

heavier regulation of economic activity in such economies than in advanced welfare states. Our

8 For many further examples of appropriate institutions, see (2001) World Development Report.

Page 33: The Rise of the Regulatory State - Harvard University

32

model, in contrast, implies that countries operating at low levels of law and order in the first

place should institute fewer laws and regulations of economic activity, because their officials

cannot administer more without being subverted. A number of examples illustrate this point.

In 1992, under pressure from Western donors, the government of the Russian Federation

established an anti-monopoly commission to address the problems of industrial consolidation. It

became immediately apparent that the new commission could not stand up to the political power

of large enterprises, and it did not even try to regulate their activities. Instead, the commission

started to compile lists of small firms, such as bakeries, taking the position that such firms had

the potential of abusing their local market power. Small entrepreneurs had to register with the

commission, and often to pay bribes just to get off the lists of potential monopolies. The

commission did nothing about the real problems of market power, added a level of regulation of

small firms, and provided lucrative opportunities for its own employees (Boycko et al. 1995).

This phenomenon is more general. Most countries in the world, including the poorest

ones, require many procedures for new firms to begin operating legally. Most of these

procedures on paper have market failure justifications: officials check that the new entrepreneurs

do not have criminal records, have professional qualifications and bank accounts, obey sanitary

restrictions, and so on. These regulations, however, are often subverted through bribes or

operations in the unofficial economy (De Soto 1989). In a cross-section, countries with more

regulations of entry exhibit higher corruption and larger unofficial economies, but not superior

social outcomes that regulation allegedly aims for (Djankov et al. 2002).

The model, then, helps us reconcile the apparent greater extent of market failures in

emerging economies stressed by Stiglitz (1989), with the equally apparent failure of regulation.

The problem is not that these countries do not have a need for dealing with social harm. Rather,

Page 34: The Rise of the Regulatory State - Harvard University

33

the problem is that these countries cannot administer the solutions. When neither the courts nor

the regulators can resist subversion, the optimal policy is to leave even imperfect markets alone.

The second message of the model is that, with intermediate enforcement capacity,

especially in cases of high social damage from market activities, regulation is efficient. When

externalities cause large damages, fines necessary to ensure desirable conduct are very high, and

therefore liability regimes are especially vulnerable to subversion. Under such circumstances,

court enforcement might fail to achieve efficiency, but regulation of inputs stands a better

chance. This case is even stronger if, as Landis (1938) maintains, it is more expensive to subvert

career regulators than judges. The United States in the early 20th century may in fact have

exhibited the conditions under which, for efficiency reasons, regulation was preferred to tort.

Glaeser, Johnson and Shleifer (2001) give another example of the same phenomenon by

comparing the regulation of securities markets in Poland and the Czech Republic in the 1990s, at

the time when their per capita incomes were roughly comparable to that of the U.S. during the

Progressive era. During this period, the Czech government adopted a laissez-faire approach to

securities regulation, expecting the judicial system to fill the necessary gaps. Poland, in contrast,

adopted strict regulations patterned after the U.S. Securities Acts, and created an independent

regulatory commission to enforce them. The result has been the collapse of securities markets in

the Czech Republic, as the existing system of law enforcement failed to deal with pervasive

fraud in the market. In contrast, the Polish stock market developed rapidly, and there is some

evidence that the Securities Commission actually managed to enforce the existing rules.

This analysis also sheds light on a well-known recommendation of Becker (1968) that an

optimal penalty system in the world of costly law enforcement should exhibit low probabilities

of detection and conviction with very high penalties or fines. Such a strategy combines desirable

deterrence effects with cost-savings on enforcement. A large literature explains why we do not

Page 35: The Rise of the Regulatory State - Harvard University

34

see such law enforcement schemes in reality (Kaplow and Shavell 2000). Leading explanations

of limited penalties include risk aversion or bankruptcy constraints of the violators (Polinsky and

Shavell 1979) and considerations of fairness (Dickens et al. 1989). We argue, alternatively, that

the defendants are likely to spend enormous resources subverting a Beckerian scheme of high

penalties, and may well succeed. The Denise Rich example mentioned above illustrates this

point. From our perspective, Becker’s solution of raising fines has precisely the reverse effect: it

only increases the incentives to subvert justice and diminishes the likelihood of good conduct.

The point of this discussion is not that regulation is always the optimal mode of law

enforcement. As Stigler (1971) has taught us, regulators can be captured or subverted, just as the

judges can, and in many instances doing nothing is preferred to regulation. The point of these

examples is rather that, at least in some instances, administrative enforcement of rules is both

feasible and preferred to a liability system, and that failure of courts to deal with the problems of

market failure is one indication of the possibility that regulation might do better.

Finally, the model implies that societies with the highest costs of subversion should rely

on courts rather than regulators. The reason for this is that the liability system – as long as it is

not subverted – can achieve first best efficiency, whereas regulation never can. Is this prediction

realistic? Advanced economies appear to have both more litigation and more regulation, so it is

difficult to say which they have more of, relatively speaking. At the same time, it is striking that,

since the 1970s, the United States has followed the path of significant deregulation of many

industries, such as gas transmission, trucking, financial services, and airlines. One interpretation

of such deregulation is that many issues can now be effectively addressed in courts, and therefore

regulation is less efficient than litigation.

In concluding this section, we return to its general point. The law and order conditions in

a country are in themselves a crucial determinant of its optimal strategies for regulating

Page 36: The Rise of the Regulatory State - Harvard University

35

economic activity. Institutions cannot be built without recognizing where the country is in the

first place. The finesse with which courts resolve disputes is appropriate for a country that has

high levels of law and order. In the extreme contrast, a country beginning with low levels of law

and order should tread gingerly in giving officials more power to shape economic life.

6. Conclusion.

In 1960, Ronald Coase posed a crucial problem for economics: what is the optimal

strategy of protecting property rights? Many of Coase’s followers have interpreted his article as

supporting the "free market” idea that a well-functioning market economy, with well-defined

property rights, only requires courts to enforce contracts and tort claims. In such a world,

regulation is unnecessary. But Coase’s reasoning does not necessarily imply the superiority of

the judiciary. Efficiency depends on whether courts, or regulators, or neither, work better to

address the problems raised by Coase. Different institutions might be most efficient – and most

attractive to a libertarian – under different circumstances.

In this paper, we have presented a model of choice of a law enforcement strategy between

doing nothing, regulation, and litigation. We showed that the choice depends crucially on the

vulnerability of law enforcement in a country to subversion by powerful interests that might be

affected. We argued that the model helps explain the rise of regulation of business in the United

States between 1887 and 1917, as well as a range of evidence from other countries.

In conclusion, we come back to some issues that the model has swept under the rug.

First, as we already indicated, we have taken the cost of subverting justice to be exogenous and

considered optimal enforcement policies in its light. In reality, the laws and regulations

themselves can raise the costs of subverting justice. They can do so directly by improving

enforcement capacity, or indirectly, by introducing rules that make it harder to subvert

Page 37: The Rise of the Regulatory State - Harvard University

36

enforcement. The more general way to put this point is that law and order does not come from

nowhere: it comes from the government introducing laws and orders that are obeyed. A more

complete model would endogenize the cost of subversion, and consider how enforcement

strategies can themselves raise this cost.

Second, we consider the problem from the point of view of efficiency, and thereby ignore

other costs of regulation. Stigler (1971) argued that regulation is generally acquired by the

industry to increase its own profits. McChesney (1987) wrote that regulation is introduced by

politicians in order to encourage campaign contributions and bribes. Our framework allows for

regulatory capture, campaign contributions, and bribes, but sees them as manifestations of

subversion of law enforcement, rather than its raison d’etre to begin with. In the context of the

U.S. Progressive era, it is difficult to see the growth of regulation as being a source of increased

industry profits, campaign contributions, or bribes, since both the industry and the venile

politicians vehemently opposed the new regulations. Nonetheless, a more general view must

obviously consider the fact that, in many instances, Stigler’s and McChesney’s objectives

become central to regulatory design. This possibility mediates in favor of doing nothing.

But despite the caveats, we reiterate the general point. The goal of economic institutions

is the same across times and places, namely to secure property and to make perpetrators of

harmful acts accountable. But even though the goals are constant, which institutions are

appropriate for achieving them varies. A key determinant of appropriateness is law and order in

the society. In the United States during the Progressive Era, regulation replaced courts as the

efficient institution. In other times and places, the appropriate institutions could be the courts, or

even nothing. This focus on the efficiency of alternative arrangements can be helpful in

advancing the institutional analysis more generally as well.

Page 38: The Rise of the Regulatory State - Harvard University

37

References

Adams, Henry (1887), “Relation of the State to Industrial Action,” American Economic Review1, 7-85.

Becker, Gary (1968), “Crime and Punishment: An Economic Approach,” Journal of PoliticalEconomy 76, 169-217.

Becker, Gary and George Stigler (19740 “Law Enforcement, Malfeasance, and theCompensation of Enforcers,” Journal of Legal Studies 3, 1-19.

Boycko, Maxim, Andrei Shleifer, Robert Vishny (1995) Privatizing Russia, Cambridge: MITPress.

Callow, Alexander B. (1966), The Tweed Ring, New York: Oxford University Press.

Chandler, Alfred (1977), The Visible Hand, Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Coase, Ronald (1960), “The Problem of Social Cost,” Journal of Law and Economics 3, 1-44.

Croly, Herbert (1965), The Promise of American Life, Cambridge, MA: Harvard UniversityPress.

DeSoto, Hernando, (1989) The Other Path, New York: Harper and Row.

Dickens, William, Lawrence Katz, Kevin Lang, and Lawrence Summers (1989), “EmployeeCrime and the Monitoring Puzzle,” Journal of Labor Economics 7, 331-347.

Djankov, Simeon, Rafael La Porta, Florencio Lopez-de-Silanes, and Andrei Shleifer (2001),“The Regulation of Entry,” forthcoming, Quarterly Journal of Economics.

Fishback, Price V. and Shawn Kantor (2000), A Prelude to the Welfare State: The Origins ofWorkers’ Compensation, Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press.

Friedman, Lawrence M. (1985), A History of American Law, New York: Simon and Schuster.

Galbraith, John Kenneth (1952), American Capitalism: The Concept of Countervailing Power,Boston, MA: Houghton Mifflin.

Glaeser, Edward (2001), “Public Ownership in the American City,” Harvard University Mimeo.

Glaeser, Edward and Andrei Shleifer (2001a) “A Reason for Quantity Regulation” AmericanEconomic Review Papers and Proceedings 91, 431-435.

Glaeser, Edward and Andrei Shleifer (2001b) “Legal Origins,” NBER Working Paper 8272,Cambridge, NA: National Bureau of Economic Research.

Page 39: The Rise of the Regulatory State - Harvard University

38

Glaeser, Edward, Simon Johnson, and Andrei Shleifer (2001) “Coase Versus the Coasians,”Quarterly Journal of Economics 116, 853-899.

Goldman, Eric (1947), Rendezvous with Destiny; a History of Modern American Reform, NewYork: Knopf.

Hart, Oliver, Andrei Shleifer, and Robert Vishny (1997), “The Proper Scope of Government,”Quarterly Journal of Economics 112, 1127-1161.

Hofstadter, Richard (1955), The Age of Reform, New York: Random House.

Holmes, Oliver Wendell (1881), The Common Law, Boston, MA: Little Brown and Company.

Horwitz, Morton (1992), The Transformation of American Law 1870-1960, Oxford: OxfordUniversity Press.

Josephson, Matthew (1934), The Robber Barons, New York: Harcourt, Brace & Company.

Kaplow, Louis and Steven Shavell (1999), “Economic Analysis of Law,” NBER Working Paper9960, Cambridge, MA: National Bureau of Economic Research.

Landis, James M., (1938) The Administrative Process, New Haven: Yale University Press.

Lloyd, Henry Demarest (1894), Wealth Against Commonwealth, New York: Harper andBrothers.

Lockard, Duane and Walter F. Murphy (1992), Basic Cases in Constitutional Law, Washington:CQ Press.

McChesney, Fred S. (1987), “Rent Extraction and Rent Creation in the Economic Theory ofRegulation,” Journal of Legal Studies 16, 101-118.

McCraw, Thomas K. (1984), Prophets of Regulation, Cambridge, MA: Harvard UniversityPress.

Nagel, Mark (1999), Supplicants, Robber Barons, and Pocket Banks, Ph.D. dissertation,Department of Government, Harvard University.

Polinsky, A. M. and Steven Shavell (1979), “The Optimal Tradeoff Between the Probability andMagnitude of Fines,” American Economic Review 69, 880-891.

Posner, Richard (1992), Economic Analysis of Law, Boston: Little Brown.

Posner, Richard (1995), “What Do Judges Maximize?” Chapter 3 in Overcoming Law ,Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Page 40: The Rise of the Regulatory State - Harvard University

39

Schwartz, Gary T. (1981), “Tort Law and the Economy of 19th Century America: AReinterpretation,” Yale Law Journal 90, 1717-1775.

Schwartz, Gary T. (1989), “The Character of Early American Tort Law,” UCLA Law Review 36,641-718.

Shavell, Steven (1984a), “A Model of the Optimal Use of Liability and Safety Regulation,” RandJournal of Economics 15, 271-280.

Shavell, Steven (1984b) “Liability for Harm Versus Regulation of Safety,” Journal of LegalStudies 13, 357-374.

Shavell, Steven (1987), Economic Analysis of Accident Law, Cambridge: Harvard UniversityPress.

Shleifer, Andrei and Robert Vishny (1998) The Grabbing Hand, Cambridge: Harvard UniversityPress.

Skocpol, Theda (1992) Protecting Soldiers and Mothers, Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Steffens, Lincoln, 1906, “The Shame of Minneapolis,” reprinted in Arthur and Lila Weinberg,eds The Muckrakers, 2001. Chicago, IL: University of Illinois Press.

Stigler, George J., 1971: “The Theory of Economic Regulation,” Bell Journal of Economics andManagement Science II, 3-21.

Stiglitz, Joseph E., 1989, Wither Socialism?, Cambridge: MIT Press.

Tarbell, Ida M., 1903, “The History of the Standard Oil Company: The Oil War of 1872—Howthe ‘Mother of Trusts’ operated” reprinted in Arthur and Lila Weinberg, eds The Muckrakers,2001. Chicago, IL: University of Illinois Press.

Wilson, Woodrow (1913), The New Freedom, New York: Doubleday, Page and Company.

World Bank (2001), World Development Report 2002: Building Institutions for Markets,Washington, D.C.: Oxford University Press.