the riddle of dreams. nadav matalon

Upload: highdreams1988

Post on 06-Jul-2018

224 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/17/2019 The Riddle of Dreams. Nadav Matalon

    1/21

    Philosophical Psychology Vol. 24, No. 4, August 2011, 517–536 

    The riddle of dreams

    Nadav Matalon

    In   The interpretation of dreams   Freud famously claimed to have finally solved the

    riddle of dreams. Yet amidst all the heated debates and intense controversies that ensued 

    in the wake of this groundbreaking work, one fundamental question has been entirely 

    overlooked, namely: in what sense, exactly, are dreams analogous to riddles? It will be theburden of this paper to show that a critical investigation of this seemingly simple question

    reveals a fundamental and hereto unnoticed discrepancy between Freud’s rhetoric on his

    method of dream interpretation and its application in practice. More specifically,

    whereas Freud argues that the psychoanalytic method can effectively solve the riddles

    of dreams by uncovering their pre-existing solutions, careful examination reveals that 

    dream interpretations of this kind are the product of a very different solving technique,

    one that proceeds along a retroactive timeline rather than a linear one. Drawing on

    Wittgenstein’s distinction between two kinds of riddles and the manner in which they are

    solved, I expound on the nature of retroactive riddle-solving, thus generating a distinctly different picture of psychoanalytic dream interpretation than the one envisioned and 

    advocated by Freud.

    Keywords: Dream Interpretation; Freud; Psychoanalysis; Retroactivity; Riddle;

    Wittgenstein

    In my youth I felt an overpowering need to understand something of the riddles of the world in which we live and perhaps even to contribute something to theirsolution. (Freud, 1926, p. 253)

    The riddle   does not exist. (Wittgenstein, 1922/1963, section 6.5)

    1. Introduction

    Echoing young Freud’s aspirations,  The interpretation of dreams  (Freud, 1900) aims

    to unravel one of the most formidable and enduring mysteries of the human mind.

    Freud named it ‘‘the riddle of dreams,’’ and rendered its solution the sine qua non of 

    Correspondence to: Nadav Matalon, Department of Philosophy, King’s College London, Strand, London WC2R 

    2LS UK E il N d M t l @k l k

    Nadav Matalon is a Doctoral Researcher at the Department of Philosophy, King’s College London, UK.

  • 8/17/2019 The Riddle of Dreams. Nadav Matalon

    2/21

    accurate diagnosis and effective treatment of mental pathologies. ‘‘Anyone who has

    failed to explain the origin of dream-images,’’ he exclaimed unequivocally in the

    preface to his magnum opus, ‘‘can scarcely hope to understand phobias, obsessions or

    delusions or to bring a therapeutic influence to bear on them’’ (Freud, 1900, p. xxiii).The doctrine from which this bold assertion derives has been met with a rainbow of 

    reactions, spanning from avid enthusiasm to acerbic criticism and everything

    in between.1 Yet amidst all the heated debates and intense controversies that ensued

    in   Interpretation’s wake, one fundamental question has been entirely overlooked,

    namely: in what sense, exactly, are dreams analogous to riddles? It will be the burden of 

    this paper to show that a critical investigation of this seemingly simple question bears

    unexpected insights, as well as far-reaching implications, with regard to the Freudian

    method of dream interpretation.

    I begin this paper with a brief exegesis of the dream-riddle analogy and its unique

    status within the Freudian theory of dreams (section 2). I then proceed to examine

    the conceptual underpinnings of Freud’s method of dream interpretation, including

    its core tenets and tacit assumptions (section 3). Subsequently, in a (seemingly) sharp

    transition, I turn to draw on Wittgenstein’s philosophy in order to develop an

    important distinction between two kinds of riddles and the manner in which they are

    solved (section 4). On the basis of this distinction, I expound on the nature of 

    retroactive riddle-solving, thereby revealing an important and hereto unnoticed

    discrepancy between Freud’s rhetoric on his method of dream interpretation and its

    application in practice. Consequently, an entirely new picture of psychoanalytic

    dream interpretation emerges, one that significantly diverges from that which wasenvisioned and advocated by Freud (section 5). I end the discussion with a number of 

    concluding remarks (section 6).

    2. Dreams as Riddles of the Psyche

    ‘What is it that hangs on the wall and that one can dry one’s hands on?’ It would bea stupid riddle if the answer were ‘a hand-towel’. But that answer is rejected.—‘No,a herring.’—‘But for heaven’s sake’, comes the infuriated protest, ‘a herring doesn’thang on the wall.’—‘You can hang it there.’—‘But who in the world is going to dry 

    his hands on a herring?’—‘Well’, is the soothing reply, ‘you don’t  have to.’ (Freud,1905b, p. 215)

    The analogy between dreams and riddles, ‘‘like some letter in cipher’’ (Freud, 1900,

    p. 135), ‘‘a  rebus’’ (p. 277), or ‘‘hieroglyphic script’’ (p. 321), recurs time and again

    in   The interpretation of dreams. Addressing the works of his predecessors, Freud

    maintains that in their writings one finds, ‘‘little or nothing that touches upon the

    essential nature of dreams or that offers a final solution of any of their enigmas’’

    (1900, p. 1). Elsewhere he asserts that, ‘‘dreams really have a secret meaning’’ (Freud,

    1900, p. 146), and that in the absence of an appropriate solving-method, ‘‘all the

    conundrums which the authorities [i.e., Freud’s predecessors] have observed indreams would remain unsolved’’ (p. 146). At a later stage, Freud suggests that,

    ‘‘a dream is a picture puzzle’’ (1900 p 278) and in a similar vein upon recounting

    518   N. Matalon

  • 8/17/2019 The Riddle of Dreams. Nadav Matalon

    3/21

    one of his personal dreams, he proceeds to declare in near exasperation that, ‘‘this

    dream exhibits so many . . . puzzling features, indeed, that I would give a great deal to

    be able to present the complete solution of its conundrums’’ (p. 422).2

    Many similar remarks on the cryptic nature of dreams and the importance of discovering their solution can be found throughout the Freudian corpus.3 It is

    therefore rather surprising to learn that Freud offers no explanation with regard to

    the exact nature of his dream-riddle simile, nor does he make any attempt to justify it

    in any of his writings.4 Could this be merely an oversight on the part of the great

    ‘‘Unriddler of Riddles’’?5 I highly doubt that it is. Ranked among the most gifted

    writers of his time, Freud exercised both precision and care in the application of 

    rhetorical devices, and his treatment of analogies is no exception to this rule. Having

    drawn a comparison between the analyst’s task and that of the chemist or

    archeologist, for example, he immediately proceeds to qualify these parallels so as to

    clarify their exact explanatory function and avoid unnecessary obfuscation of his

    views.6 Evidence of this cautious approach is also available in the form of more

    general caveats. Hence, on one occasion Freud himself warns that, ‘‘analogies never

    carry one more than a certain distance; a point is soon reached at which the subjects

    of the comparison take divergent paths’’ (1926, p. 254); whereas in another he

    stipulates that, ‘‘the two objects compared need only coincide at a single point and

    may be entirely different from each other in everything else’’ (1919, p. 161). It would

    seem quite unlikely that Freud’s emphatic silence on the analogy between dreams and

    riddles has been the result of mere carelessness or unintentional omission.

    Is there another possible way by which to account for this striking anomaly? As astarting point, I would like to suggest the following thesis. Rather than associating

    two distinct entities so as to generate an analogy in the conventional sense, Freud

    employs the dream-riddle idiom heuristically. That is, for him, the notion of dreams

    qua   riddles functions as a meta-theoretical hub which grounds his entire theory of 

    dreams. Thus construed, the dream-riddle analogy is not merely a convenient

    metaphorical idiolect aimed at highlighting certain similarities between two disparate

    things—it is a pivotal axiom upon which Freud proceeds to develop his intricate

    interpretive method. In short, for Freud, dreams are not like riddles, they  are  riddles.

    These considerations bring us to the heart of the matter. Completely engrossed inhis quest to discover ‘‘the most satisfactory solution of the riddle of dreams’’ (Freud,

    1910, p. 34), Freud glosses over the antecedent issue of providing cogent

    underpinnings for this particular analogy. Moreover, as I will show in the following

    sections, critical perusal of precisely this issue leads to the unavoidable conclusion

    that Freud’s account of dream interpretation and the actual application of his

    method are ultimately incongruous.

    3. The Psychoanalytic Method of Dream Interpretation

    The first step is the one that altogether escapes notice. (Wittgenstein, 1953/1999,section 308)

    Philosophical Psychology    519

  • 8/17/2019 The Riddle of Dreams. Nadav Matalon

    4/21

    So far our discussion has focused on the meta-theoretical status of the dream-riddle

    idiom in Freud’s conception of dreams. But what makes this simile so natural and

    compelling? Why, that is, did it go entirely unnoticed for more than a hundred years?

    Taking a closer look at our intuitive attitude toward dreams may help clarify thereasons for this peculiar anomaly. To begin with, conventional wisdom holds that

    our dreams are capable of exerting a profound and powerful effect on us (cf.,

    Wittgenstein, 1966/1994, pp. 45–46). On occasion, such phenomenal experiences

    may even produce the uncanny impression that they were meant to tell us

    something—to convey an important message perhaps—yet what that message is and

    where it came from often remains shrouded in mystery. Seen in this light, Freud’s

    first ingenious move has been to tap into this intuitive source by developing an

    elaborate ontology of dreams, one that effectively incorporates their everyday 

    conception within a sophisticated model of the human psyche.

    Broadly speaking, the psychoanalytic theory of dream interpretation is built on the

    core assumption that all dreams consist of two distinct, yet closely related,

    components. In Freud’s terminology, these are the manifest content  and  latent content 

    of the dream. The former denotes the dream-narrative which is consciously 

    experienced by the dreamer during sleep; whereas the latter designates the real

    meaning of the dream, i.e., that which lies hidden (or, more precisely, repressed)

    within the unconscious region of the dreamer’s psyche.7 According to Freud, the

    relation between these two components is one of  disguised representation, that is, the

    manifest content of the dream constitutes a distorted reconstruction of its latent

    content. Freud calls the process by which the latent content becomes manifest dreamwork , and proceeds to explicate its rationale as follows:

    For the dream is one of the roads along which consciousness can be reached by thepsychical material which, on account of the opposition aroused by its content, hasbeen cut off from consciousness and repressed, and has thus become pathogenic.The dream, in short, is one of the détours by which repression can be evaded ; it is oneof the principal means employed by what is known as the indirect method of representation in the mind. (Freud, 1905a, p. 15)

    On Freud’s psychogenic model, dreaming constitutes an indirect channel by which

    disagreeable and/or distressing materials can bypass the psyche’s defenses and risefrom the dreamer’s unconscious toward her conscious awareness.8 However, en route

    to becoming manifest content, the latent content of dreams undergoes a process of 

    substantial transformation or  dream work   so as to keep their true meaning hidden.

    Hence, according to Freud, dreams can only convey their real meaning  indirectly  and

    it is that particular mode of presentation which effectively renders them riddles of 

    the psyche.

    Webster’s Dictionary  (1994) defines a riddle as ‘‘a question or statement so framed

    as to exercise one’s ingenuity in answering it or discovering its meaning.’’ This

    seemingly plain definition corresponds well with the psychoanalytic approach to

    dreams and their inherent aptness for interpretation. Dreams, says Freud, are always

    constructed by the psyche with the specific aim of concealing their true significance

    520   N. Matalon

  • 8/17/2019 The Riddle of Dreams. Nadav Matalon

    5/21

    Considerable effort and resilience are therefore required in order to penetrate their

    perplexing façades and uncover the real meaning which presumably lies underneath.

    This picture, however, is still very vague: it tells us what we are looking for, but not

    how to find it. Seen from this perspective, Freud’s second ingenious move has been todevise a systematic procedure for solving the riddle of dreams, or as he himself put it,

    ‘‘a method by which the unintelligible content of a dream might be replaced by one

    that was comprehensible and significant’’ (1900, p. 4). Let us briefly consider what

    this procedure involves.

    Designed to uncover the dream’s latent content, Freud’s dream interpretation

    technique may be broadly described as advancing in three successive steps.9 First, the

    manifest content of the dream is dismantled into discrete elements (e.g., people or

    objects that appeared in the dream, distinct features of the general scenery, etc.; cf.,

    Freud, 1900, pp. 103–104, 449). Second, the dreamer is encouraged to consider each

    of these elements and report whatever comes into her mind, regardless of how 

    embarrassing, irrelevant or unintelligible these ‘‘free associations’’ might strike her

    upon reflection.10 And third, with the dreamer’s ‘‘free associations’’ in hand, the

    analyst is then able to construct the solution to the dream’s riddle by putting together

    the discordant pieces into a coherent and intelligible interpretation (cf., Freud, 1937,

    pp. 255–258).

    In   The interpretation of dreams, Freud likens the psychoanalytic procedure of 

    dream interpretation to that of solving a  rebus (1900, pp. 277–278).11 This parallel is

    highly instructive as it points to an important presupposition built into the Freudian

    conception of dreams. Presented with a  rebus, one naturally assumes that it  already has an appropriate solution even if the latter is presently unknown. If it turns out that

    it doesn’t, one may plausibly argue that the so-called ‘‘riddle’’ is really nothing more

    than a frivolous jest or a hoax. To state this intuition counterfactually: a riddle with

    no solution is no riddle at all.

    Concurrently, from a psychoanalytic perspective, no matter how obscure, confused

    or nonsensical the manifest content of a dream appears to be, it must nevertheless

    contain a hidden layer of meaning which is already present within the dreamer’s

    unconscious prior  to the act of dreaming.12 For Freud, then, it would be impossible to

    interpret a dream that has no latent meaning just as it would be impossible to solve a

    riddle that has no solution. A dream with no solution, Freud might have said, is no

    riddle at all.

    4. Two Kinds of Riddles

    A puzzle picture. What does it amount to to say that after the solution the picturemeans something to us, whereas it meant nothing before? (Wittgenstein, 1974/1993, p. 27, section 125)

    The dream-riddle analogy, then, does not reflect an idiosyncratic figure of speechused by Freud for rhetorical purposes, but a deeply held conviction concerning their

    nature and etiological origins As riddles Freud tells us dreams necessarily have

    Philosophical Psychology    521

  • 8/17/2019 The Riddle of Dreams. Nadav Matalon

    6/21

    hidden solutions and it is one of the main tasks of psychoanalysis to bring these

    solutions to light. But is the relation between riddles and their solutions always as

    simple and straight-forward as we tend to believe? Our intuitive notion of riddles

    clearly endorses a positive response to this question. Yet, as philosophers are painfully aware, intuitions can be highly misleading, especially when language comes into play.

    Ludwig Wittgenstein, a contemporary of Freud’s and arguably the greatest

    philosopher in the 20th century, had an exceptional talent for disrupting

    conventional views and standard conceptions. In this respect, his remarks on

    riddles—though relatively rare and characteristically opaque—are no different. For

    our purpose here, I would like to focus on a particularly useful distinction

    Wittgenstein draws between two different kinds of riddles.13 On the one hand are

    riddles for which a pre-established solving-method is already in place. This means

    that, though one may not know  what  the correct solution to the riddle might be, one

    does know (or at least, one is in a position to learn)  how  to go about finding it in

    a systematic way. Here are two relatively easy examples:

    A snail falls to the bottom of a 30 feet well and wants to get out. If it crawls 3 feetup each day, but slips 2 feet down each night, how many days will it take it to getout of the well?

    What English word can have 4 of its 5 letters removed and still retain its originalpronunciation?

    Discovering the correct solution to these riddles, then, is only a matter of applying

    the appropriate method in the correct manner (this is perhaps less obvious in thesecond example, but true nonetheless).14 Hence, while the relevant method may vary 

    significantly from one riddle to the next, its systematic application serves to

    effectively preclude disputes over the identity of the correct solution in each

    particular case.

    On the other hand, as the preceding discussion suggests, there are also riddles of a

    very different kind, namely: those for which no predefined solving-method currently 

    exists. Trying to solve such riddles is ‘‘like trying to move one’s ears when one has

    never done so, like trying to unravel a knot which one does not even know is actually 

    a knot’’ (Diamond, 1995, p. 267). One is literally ‘‘groping in the dark,’’ as

    Wittgenstein (1974/1993, p. 175) once put it, since one is not only searching for thecorrect solution, but also for the route by which that solution might actually be

    obtained. Riddles of this kind, Wittgenstein explains, are:

    Like the problem set by the king in the fairy tale who told the princess to comeneither naked nor dressed, and she came wearing fishnet. That might have beencalled not naked and yet not dressed either. He didn’t really know what he wantedher to do, but when she came thus he was forced to accept it. It was of the form‘‘Do something that I shall be inclined to call ‘neither naked nor dressed’ . . . [thatis,] some-thing which I shall be inclined to accept as a solution, though I don’tknow now what it will be like.’’ (Cited in Diamond, 1995, p. 267)15

    Prima facie, it certainly appears as if the king has presented the princess with a

    straight forward riddle However as Wittgenstein points out in the above quoted

    522   N. Matalon

  • 8/17/2019 The Riddle of Dreams. Nadav Matalon

    7/21

    remark, when the king commands the princess to come before him ‘‘neither naked

    nor dressed,’’ not only does he not know how this particular feat might be

    accomplished—a fortiori, he has good reasons to assume that it is virtually an

    impossible task.16

    Two questions immediately suggest themselves in this context:(a) if the king’s riddle was deliberately designed so as to have no solution, what (if 

    anything) makes it into a riddle? And (b) in the absence of a pre-established solving-

    method for this riddle how did the princess achieve the seemingly impossible feat of 

    actually solving it? On Wittgenstein’s view, these perplexing questions arise from our

    erroneous tendency to conflate riddles of the first and second kinds by subsuming all 

    riddles under the former while overlooking the latter. Simply put, we intuitively 

    presuppose that for every riddle there must already be a legitimate solution, as well as

    an appropriate solving-method, even if they are presently unknown to us.

    From a philosophical perspective, the intuitive inclination to regard all riddles as

    riddles of the first kind bears significant implications. To see why this is so, let us

    return to the fairytale once more. To begin with, recall that when he first presented

    his riddle, the king had neither a solution nor solving-method to accommodate his

    unconventional demand. This point is crucial because it enables us to recognize that

    the original paradoxical utterance—‘‘neither naked nor dressed’’—has actually 

    become meaningful   only in retrospect.   That is to say, rather than discovering the

    so-called ‘‘hidden meaning’’ of the king’s riddle, the princess has effectively 

    transformed it,   ex post facto,   from an essentially nonsensical utterance into a

    meaningful one via her solution. As Cora Diamond aptly puts it, ‘‘the prin-

    cess. . .

    does not find something satisfying a description [put forward by the king],but   a way of making the king’s words into a description   [italics added]’’ (1995,

    p. 270).17 And to that, it is important to add, she does so  retroactively .

    But if the king’s original utterance has gained its sense only in retrospect, why are

    we predisposed to treat it as meaningful right from the start? More explicitly stated:

    why does the expression ‘‘neither naked nor dressed’’ seem to convey a meaningful

    indirect description even before one is able to say what exactly it is that this expression

    purports to describe? The root of the problem, says Wittgenstein, can be traced back 

    to the structural similarity between language-games of the particular kind discussed

    here (i.e., the king’s riddle) and other, more familiar language-games commonly used

    in everyday discourse.18

    Consider, for illustration, a person who asks her friend: ‘‘come neither before nor

    after the scheduled time.’’ It is safe to assume that, in this colloquial context, both

    interlocutors already know what sort of action would comply with the speaker’s

    request. As such, the said utterance conveys a meaningful indirect description precisely 

    because the criteria for its legitimate employment have been previously defined by 

    shared linguistic and behavioral standards. (In this case, the expectation that one

    would come precisely on time.) Now, although the king’s riddle portrays a similar

    ‘‘neither-nor’’ syntactic structure, it is important to notice that the meaning of the

    king’s original utterance (i.e., its appropriate discursive application) has not beenspecified by pre-established criteria prior to its presentation. Hence, despite its

    misleading appearance the king’s utterance and the princess’s solution work jointly

    Philosophical Psychology    523

  • 8/17/2019 The Riddle of Dreams. Nadav Matalon

    8/21

    to create a completely   different   language-game, one that cannot be considered an

    indirect description of anything prior to its successful completion.

    At this juncture, the following objection would seem highly plausible: even if the

    relevant criteria for solving a particular riddle have not been predefined, why shouldthis prevent us from trying to solve it anyway? Surely one is entitled to claim: ‘‘I shall

    know the correct solution if I see it’’ (cf., Wittgenstein, 1976, p. 84), even if one has

    no idea how to go about looking for it. This may seem like a legitimate claim;

    however, it is very misleading. The assertion that one would be able to recognize the

    correct solution if the latter was made available to her rests on the presupposition

    that the correct solution  has already been determined  prior to, or in tandem with, the

    presentation of the riddle. And yet, while this assumption is completely justified with

    relation to riddles of the first kind, it is essentially unwarranted when it comes to

    riddles of the second kind. The argument which merits this claim runs as follows. To

    begin with, note that the identity of the correct solution can only be determined on

    the basis of some criterion or other. Hence, in the absence of  any  criterion by which

    to evaluate putative solutions, the question of their correctness (or incorrectness)

    cannot even be raised. That is, as long as what would be considered an appropriate

    criterion has  not  been established, there is simply no sense in talking about correct

    (or incorrect) solutions at all.

    Reviewing the possibility of using guesswork as means for finding the correct

    solution would help clarify this point. Presented with either kind of riddle, one can

    obviously try and guess what the solution should be. Nevertheless, once again our

    indiscriminate use of language is liable to obscure an important distinction betweenthe two cases. In the context of riddles of the first kind, determining whether or not

    a haphazard guess has been successful in hitting its mark constitutes a relatively 

    straight-forward affair given that the relevant criteria for evaluation are already in

    place. In contrast, speculation over the correctness of a solution to riddles of the

    second kind involves a markedly different procedure. The basic argument that

    underlies this contention is very similar to the one presented in the previous

    paragraph. And so, to avoid unnecessary repetition, I would like to further explore

    this issue by offering a concrete illustration instead.

    Consider the Sphinx’s riddle to Oedipus: ‘‘what walks upon four feet in the

    morning, upon two at noon, and upon three at night?’’ Our intuition tells us that itmust be possible to rule-out putative solutions in advance. But is this really the case?

    Let us assume that, weighing his options, Oedipus ponders whether ‘‘a human being’’

    might be the correct response. But then, as soon as this idea crosses his mind, he is

    forced to reject it since arguably humans typically walk on two feet, or in some cases,

     just one, but never on three. Thus, in the absence of a pre-established  criterion for the

    evaluation of tentative solutions, Oedipus finds himself compelled to use an  ad hoc 

    criterion (‘‘on how many feet do humans ordinarily walk?’’) in order to discard what,

    in retrospect , will turn out to be the correct solution.

    Moreover, we can easily imagine someone who has been told the solution to theSphinx’s riddle and yet still struggles to understand what qualifies it as the correct

    solution Alternatively that person may insist that the proposed solution is wrong

    524   N. Matalon

  • 8/17/2019 The Riddle of Dreams. Nadav Matalon

    9/21

    and proceed to offer an alternative solution in its stead. In all these cases the

    proposed solution and the criteria for its correctness go hand in hand. And in all

    these cases, they jointly work to give meaning to the original utterance in retrospect.

    It thus becomes apparent that, despite the temptation to view the Sphinx’s riddleas a meaningful indirect description of something hidden or unknown, the

    monster’s enigmatic utterance actually remains  meaningless so long as an acceptable

    solution—and, concurrently, the criteria for its correctness—have not been

    determined (cf., Wittgenstein, 1974/1993, p. 377).

    Here, however, another objection may be forthcoming. Why, it may be asked,

    should we regard the Sphinx’s riddle (or that of the king) as  meaningless prior to its

    solution? After all, are we not able to understand riddles of this kind regardless of 

    whether or not an appropriate solution has been found? Reasonable and intuitive as

    this objection may appear, it cannot be coherently upheld for the following reasons.

    Imagine someone who has been presented with the king’s riddle for the first time

    and subsequently proceeds to insist that she understands the utterance ‘‘neither

    naked nor dressed’’ perfectly well despite the fact that she does not have a clue as to

    what it is meant to describe. The question is what would such ‘‘understanding’’

    consist in? To assert that the king’s utterance is indeed a description without being

    able to specify what it is ‘‘a description of’’ clearly begs the question. Likewise, that

    one understands, and can therefore explain, the meaning of each particular word in

    that utterance is of no help either. It is the utterance as a whole that requires making

    sense of, not each of its distinct constituents, and to accomplish that, one would have

    to put the entire utterance into some kind of context. That is, the person in questionwould have to find one or more conventionally accepted language-games in which

    the utterance may be legitimately used. Yet, any attempt to do just that means that

    one has perforce assumed the role of the princess, i.e., one is already engaged in the

    process of generating her  own solution  to the king’s riddle by specifying the criteria

    that will retroactively turn it into a meaningful description.

    Another way of explicating this counterintuitive point may be as follows. As noted

    above, we naturally assume that all riddles constitute an   obscure   or   indirect 

    description of something which is not yet known. This picture certainly works well

    with riddles of the first kind wherein it is possible to employ pre-established criteria

    in order to determine the identity of correct solutions. However, in the case of riddlesof the second kind the situation is markedly different since there are no criteria by 

    which to distinguish between correct and incorrect solutions before the riddle has

    actually been solved. Consequently, it turns out that, although riddles of the second

    kind are typically taken to convey ambiguous or indirect descriptions, the fact of 

    the matter is that they only create the grammatical illusion of fulfilling this role.

    To see this, ask yourself what ought to be considered the equivalent, direct

    description of the king’s utterance   before the riddle was solved ? As there are no

    generally accepted criteria by which to perform this judgment, the question itself 

    turns out to be meaningless (cf., Wittgenstein, 1976, pp. 64–65, 1974/1993, pp. 363–364). Hence, rather than constituting an indirect description whose meaning has

    been fixed in advance the king’s utterance actually consists in what may be called a

    Philosophical Psychology    525

  • 8/17/2019 The Riddle of Dreams. Nadav Matalon

    10/21

     provisional description, namely: a  meaningless utterance that may be converted into a

    meaningful description by the provision of a solution that will retroactively specify the

    appropriate criterion for its own legitimacy.

    To recapitulate the foregoing discussion, two key points should be borne in mind:(a) unlike riddles of the first kind, in the case of riddles of the second kind, on top of 

    not knowing  what   the correct solution should be, we do not even know  how   to go

    about looking for it. Thus, the only criterion serving to guide our attempts at solving

    riddles of the latter kind is captured by the counterintuitive   dictum: ‘‘show me

    something I can accept as fulfilling the terms of the riddle’’; and, (b) despite their

    misleading appearance, riddles of the second kind are not meaningful indirect

    descriptions whose meaning has been determined in advance. Rather, they consist of 

     provisional descriptions  that may be transformed into  meaningful descriptions  by the

    espousal of solutions that retroactively specify the appropriate criteria for their

    acceptance.

    5. Turning Dreams into Riddles

    A writer is someone who can make a riddle out of an answer. (Karl Kraus)

    If we apply the above analysis to dreams, it becomes patently clear that Freud takes

    their manifest content to be riddles of the first kind. Nevertheless, whereas riddles

    of this kind require pre-established criteria for the purpose of judging the correctness

    of putative solutions, Freud does not place similar restrictions on his dreaminterpretation technique. More explicitly stated, throughout the course of formu-

    lating the dream’s interpretation, the psychoanalytic procedure is methodologically 

    unbound by any constraint whatsoever. Consequently, the psychoanalytic method

    may indeed yield fascinating dream interpretations, but   it does not determine their 

    correctness (or otherwise) in advance. To circumvent this methodological discrepancy,

    Freud resorts to different criteria at different times: from the patient’s espousal of the

    proposed interpretation, to the coherence of the interpretation   per se, to the

    authoritative verdict of the analyst. Neither sufficient nor necessary in themselves,

    these disparate criteria are employed  ad hoc  so as to determine,  in retrospect , what the

    correct interpretation should be (cf., Wittgenstein, 1966/1994, p. 42).19

    Pinpointing Freud’s failure to supply definitive criteria by which to judge the

    correctness of dream interpretations   prior   to their actual formulation is of vital

    importance since it allows us to recognize psychoanalytic dream interpretations for

    what they really are, namely:   solutions to riddles of the second kind . That is to say,

    rather than revealing the latent content of dreams, Freud’s interpretive procedure

    works in the opposite direction: it is the psychoanalytic interpretation that serves to

    retroactively  convert the manifest content of a dream into the riddle it is purporting

    to solve.20

    In the terminology developed here, when the analysand discusses the manifestcontent of her dream with the analyst, she is not putting forth a meaningful indirect

    description whose meaning has already been settled by commonly accepted criteria

    526   N. Matalon

  • 8/17/2019 The Riddle of Dreams. Nadav Matalon

    11/21

    Instead, she may be seen as presenting the analyst with a provisional description,

    i.e., a collection of utterances which may be turned into a riddle after  its solution has

    been duly constructed and accepted. The analysand and analyst thus find themselves

    in the same position as the king and the princess only in reversed roles: the analysandis the one who asks the analyst: ‘‘show me something that I can accept as the solution

    to the riddle of my dream’’, to which the analyst then responds by constructing

    an interpretation that will strike the analysand as the correct one. Hence, it may be

    said that Freud does not solve the riddle of the analysand’s dream, but rather,

    he retroactively renders her dream into a riddle by means of synthesizing her free

    associations into a highly persuasive interpretive narrative.21

    The main upshot of the retroactive ascription of meaning to the dream’s manifest

    content is clear: no latent or hereto unknown etiological structure in the dreamer’s

    psyche was   necessarily discovered   by means of the psychoanalytic interpretation.22

    Strange and counterintuitive as it may sound, the fact that dreams are somehow 

    caused  (presumably as a result of complex neural processes in the brain) is entirely 

    beside the point.23 Nor is the high level of creativity which Freud often exhibits in

    formulating some of his more ingenious dream interpretations relevant to these

    considerations.24 What is crucial to recognize is that as   convincing   solutions,

    psychoanalytic dream interpretations can retroactively convert the manifest content

    of dreams into riddles of the second kind, that is, they are capable of turning

    inexplicable phenomenal experiences into riddles that may actually be solved.

    This picture of psychoanalytic dream interpretation sheds light on another

    controversial aspect of the Freudian   modus operandi. One of Freud’s primary assumptions is that every dream has only one correct interpretation. To justify this

    tenet, Freud evokes the jigsaw puzzle metaphor, stating that:

    What makes him [the analyst] certain [that the correct solution has beenfound] . . . is precisely the complication of the problem before him, which is like thesolution of a jig-saw puzzle . . . . If one succeeds in arranging the confused heap of fragments, each of which bears upon it an unintelligible piece of drawing, so thatthe picture acquires a meaning, so that there is no gap anywhere in the design andso that the whole fits into the frame . . . then one knows that   one has solved the

     puzzle and that there is no alternative solution  [italics added]. (Freud, 1923, p. 116)

    Following the rationale of riddles of the first kind, the motivation behind Freud’sanalogy can be easily identified. If every dream constitutes the disguised represen-

    tation of a particular tacit wish, then only the correct interpretation will be able to

    point back to that wish. Hence, if Freud is right, a dream can only have one correct

    solution. On the other hand, construed as riddles of the second kind, dreams may 

    have anything from none to infinite legitimate solutions, seeing as their correctness

    is not determined in advance, but rather, in retrospect. To illustrate this point, let us

    revisit the king’s riddle one last time.

    Recall that in the fairytale, the princess’s solution consisted of shrouding herself in

    a fisherman’s net. Nevertheless, it is certainly possible to imagine the princess comingup with different yet equally legitimate solutions. For example, she could have come

    to the king wrapped only in her long hair The point is that in contrast with riddles

    Philosophical Psychology    527

  • 8/17/2019 The Riddle of Dreams. Nadav Matalon

    12/21

    of the first kind, the specific character of putative solutions to riddles of the second

    kind does not influence their legitimacy. The only thing which really matters is that

    the interlocutor (the king in the fairytale or the analysand in Freud’s care) would be

    willing to espouse the proposed solution and as a result retroactively convert theoriginal utterance or image-narrative into a meaningful indirect description that

    appears to have been concealing its true identity from the start.25 As Wallerstein

    correctly observes:

    Skilled psychoanalytic clinicians can construct differing, but often equally compel-ling, formulations of psychoanalytic case material and . . . no ready method toestablish the truth claims of alternative formulations has yet come to win wideacceptance within the clinical psychoanalytic world. (Wallerstein, 2006, p. 304)26

    At first glance it may appear as if the above analysis leads to the unpalatable

    conclusion that as far as psychoanalytic dream interpretations are concerned‘‘anything goes.’’ In other words, it may be tempting to conclude that the retroactive

    model effectively reduces Freud’s dream interpretations to arbitrary constructions

    forced on the analysand by the analyst in an act of brute persuasion. However, closer

    examination shows that this conclusion is ultimately unjustified. In the first place, we

    should keep in mind that neither dreams nor their psychoanalytic interpretations can

    be detached from the analysand’s life (cf., Freud, 1900, pp. 98–100, 105; Lear, 2005,

    pp. 90–92). As such, the particular life-circumstances of the latter constitute a general

    referential framework which imposes significant restraints on the retroactive

    evaluation of putative interpretations. Simply put, psychoanalytic dream interpre-

    tations are typically formulated within the wider and idiosyncratic context of the

    analysand’s world and it is precisely this context which provides the backdrop against

    which their correctness is retrospectively assessed.

    Furthermore, we should also take into account that the analyst does not introduce

    dream interpretations for their own sake but as a catalyst for pushing the analysis

    forward. More specifically, via dream interpretations the analyst aims to enable the

    analysand to explore new ways of self-understanding. As already noted above, from

    Freud’s perspective, this goal may be actualized only if the analysand can be brought

    to overcome the barriers of repression and recognize the so-called ‘‘true meaning’’ of 

    her dreams. However, if dream interpretations represent solutions to riddles of thesecond kind, then the question of their correctness cannot be determined in advance.

    In other words, any attempt to impose restrictions on what would be considered the

    correct solution prior to its formulation will inevitably founder since the solution

    itself serves to define the criteria for its own legitimacy in retrospect. But if this is

    indeed the case, how can we counter the claim that ‘‘anything goes’’? The answer lies

    in the realization that, as we are dealing here with an inverse time-line wherein

    meaning is ascribed retroactively, restrictions on the legitimacy of dream interpre-

    tations need not (and, in fact, cannot) be imposed in advance.27 However, they can

    be imposed retroactively provided one is willing to relinquish absolute conceptions of pre-determined ‘‘correctness’’ and ‘‘truth’’ in favor of relative and time-dependent

    notions like ‘‘efficacy’’ and ‘‘consequence ’’ By taking dream interpretations to be

    528   N. Matalon

  • 8/17/2019 The Riddle of Dreams. Nadav Matalon

    13/21

    tools for self-examination and development within the analytic setting, the real

    question becomes whether or not they actually succeed in serving their purpose,

    i.e., whether, and to what extent, they enable the analysand to engage with—or,

    as Freud liked to say, ‘‘work-through’’—new possibilities of self-understanding(cf., Freud, 1914b, 1937). Somewhat ironically, Freud himself made precisely this

    point in ‘‘Constructions in Analysis,’’ when he wrote,

    Only the further course of the analysis enables us to decide whether ourconstructions are correct or unserviceable. We do not pretend that an individualconstruction is anything more than a conjecture which awaits examination,confirmation or rejection. We claim no authority for it, we require no directagreement from the patient, nor do we argue with him if at first he denies it. Inshort, we conduct ourselves on the model of a familiar figure in one of Nestroy’sfarces—the manservant who has a single answer on his lips to every question or

    objection: ‘It will all become clear in the course of future developments’ [italicsadded]. (1937, p. 265).

    Hence, as Freud himself openly concedes in the passage just quoted, it is only by 

    examining the actual effects that the dream interpretation has on the analysand that

    one is able to evaluate its correctness. In other words, there are indeed no pre-

    established criteria by which the correctness of the psychoanalytic interpretation may 

    be asserted   prior   to its formulation, and whilst particular restrictions (e.g., the

    correspondence of the interpretation to the analysand’s life) may certainly be applied,

    their application as means for evaluating the correctness of a given dream

    interpretation is always carried out in retrospect.

    6. Concluding Remarks

    If you are led by psycho-analysis to say that really you thought so and so or thatreally your motive was so and so, this is not a matter of discovery, but of persuasion . . . . One thinks of certain results of psycho-analysis as a discovery Freudmade, as apart from something persuaded to you by a psycho-analyst, and I wishto say this is not the case. (Wittgenstein, 1966/1994, p. 27)

    The argument presented in this paper endeavored to show that a fundamental

    discrepancy exists between Freud’s rhetoric on his method of dream interpretationand its application in practice. Taking dreams to be riddles of the first kind, Freud

    claims to have formulated an efficient solving-method by which their correct

    solutions can be found. Hence, on Freud’s account, psychoanalytic interpretations

    chart the real  and therefore the only possible route from a dream’s manifest content

    to the tacit wish it presumably conceals.28 Nevertheless, for all its intuitive appeal,

    this conception cannot be reconciled with the retroactive mode of operation Freud

    actually employs in order to determine what ought to be considered the correct

    interpretation of a particular dream.29 The absence of pre-established criteria for the

    evaluation of putative solutions   prior   to their formulation suggests that Freud’sdream interpretation technique actually represents a solving-method to riddles of the

    second kind Thus construed Freud’s methodology effectively transforms provisional

    Philosophical Psychology    529

  • 8/17/2019 The Riddle of Dreams. Nadav Matalon

    14/21

    descriptions of dream-narratives into   indirect meaningful descriptions  of latent wishes

    via the construction of persuasive dream interpretations. These interpretations, in

    turn, gain verisimilitude and potential efficacy not because they necessarily reveal

    latent or unconscious materials, but rather, because they are accepted as such. Atbottom line, Freud does not simply solve the riddle of dreams; he retroactively turns

    dreams  into  riddles by producing highly convincing solutions to them.

    Acknowledgements

    Special thanks to Daniele Moyal-Sharrock and two anonymous reviewers at

    Philosophical Psychology   for extensive commentaries and discussions on previous

    versions of this paper. I am also grateful to Frank Cioffi, Jim Hopkins, Derek Bolton,

    Rai Gaita, and Eran Guter for valuable suggestions and critique. The preparation of this paper has benefited from the generous support of the AVI Fellowships program.

    Notes

    [1] Although there has certainly been a steady decline in the status and practice of 

    psychoanalysis in the past sixty years or so (Kandel, 1999; Wallerstein, 2006), heated

    debates over Freud’s theory of dreams are still very much alive among contemporary 

    researchers. One prominent example consists of the vigorous controversy in the field of 

    neuropsychology between pro-Freudian commentators (Kandel, 1999; Shevrin & Eister,

    2000; Solms, 2000, 2001; Solms & Turnbull, 2002, 2007) and their opponents (Hobson,2005, 2007; Hobson & Pace-Schott, 2002; Hobson, Pace-Schott, & Stickgold, 2000) on the

    genesis and nature of dreams.

    [2] For further examples, see Freud, 1900, pp. 40, 94, 158, 163, 267, 515, 565, 590.

    [3] See, e.g., Freud’s comments on the subject of finding, ‘‘a simple and satisfactory solution of 

    the riddle of dreams’’ (Freud, 1901, p. 646), or even more ambitiously, ‘‘the most

    satisfactory solution of the riddle of dreams’’ (Freud, 1910, p. 34). Remarks of a similar

    nature also appear in many other works by Freud (1901, pp. 633, 635, 640, 643, 651, 658,

    680, 1911a, p. 93, 1916–1917, pp. 101, 201, 233–234, 1918, p. 70, 1923, p. 116, 1925b,

    pp. 127, 135).

    [4] Freud’s comparison between the solution of dreams and that of jigsaw puzzles (1923, p. 116)

    might be construed as an exception to this general claim. However, as I will show in section

    5, Freud’s discussion in this context appears to enhance rather than resolve the discrepancy 

    between his rhetoric on dream interpretation and its actual application.

    [5] This perceptive epithet was originally attributed to Freud by Schorske (1973) in his ‘‘Politics

    and practice in Freud’s   Interpretation of dreams.’’

    [6] These analogies appear in Freud (1919, pp. 159–161) and Freud (1937, pp. 259–260),

    respectively.

    [7] According to Freud’s theory of dreams, the said ‘‘hidden meaning’’ ordinarily consists of a

    repressed wish that the dreamer is unwilling or unable to fulfil in the course of waking life

    due to its disagreeable or distressing nature (cf., Freud, 1900, p. 122, 1901, p. 641, 1910,

    pp. 34–35, 1940, pp. 165–166).

    [8] On Freud’s early topographical model, the psyche’s defense mechanism ( Zensur ) functions

    as a kind of partition (Schrim) that prevents repressed materials from gaining access toconsciousness. However, under certain conditions (e.g., sleep or hypnosis) the mechanism’s

    control is diminished thereby allowing some repressed content to pass albeit in disguised

    530   N. Matalon

  • 8/17/2019 The Riddle of Dreams. Nadav Matalon

    15/21

    form. Later on, during the transition to his later structural model, Freud revised this notion

    by shifting from an abstract mechanism to a more structured aspect of the super-ego (cf.,

    Freud, 1900, pp. 141–144, 466–468, 505–506, 1914a, pp. 97–98, 1923, p. 112).

    [9] I shall restrict the following presentation to a very rudimentary sketch of Freud’s dream

    interpretation technique since it is all that is needed to make my case here. However, it isimportant to note that this schema should be construed as pedagogical rather than

    diachronic given that in actual practice the particular steps involved in this technique

    often interrelate and coalesce with one another throughout the analysis (cf., Freud, 1937,

    pp. 260–261).

    [10] Freud has famously taken the ‘‘free associations’’ (Freier Einfall ) technique to represent the

    ‘‘fundamental rule of psycho-analysis’’ (1910, p. 39, 1913, pp. 134–135, 1925a, p. 40).

    Notice, however, that the English translation of this term is rather misleading since, as Freud

    himself notes, ‘‘we must bear in mind . . . that free association is not really free’’ (1925a,

    p. 40). The reason for this, according to Freud, is that even though the dreamer’s train of 

    thought may appear to proceed spontaneously (i.e., without conscious control or intentional

    guidance), it is nevertheless deterministically guided by her unconscious (e.g., Freud, 1900,p. 101, 1919, p. 160).

    [11] The point may be easily illustrated by a simple example. Consider the puzzling expression:

    ‘‘CUL8ER.’’ At first glance, this odd string of signs would probably strike most of us as

    utterly meaningless. However, by concentrating our attention on each discrete sign, while

    concurrently keeping an eye on its immediate interrelations with the other signs, sooner or

    later this procedure will (hopefully) yield the realization that the key to this riddle lies in

    reading the signs phonetically rather than semantically, thereby revealing the colloquial

    expression ‘‘see you later.’’

    [12] In his later writings, Freud qualified his original claim about the hidden meaning of dreams

    by stipulating that there are two types of dreams which do not represent latent wishes,

    namely: dreams that occur in traumatic neurosis and so-called punishment dreams (cf.,Freud, 1923, p. 118). Notice, however, that in these cases, the psychoanalytic procedure of 

    dream interpretation becomes redundant as the meaning of the dream is assumed to be

    directly perceivable.

    [13] Wittgenstein’s remarks on what is generally referred to here as ‘‘riddles’’ typically appear

    within the broader context of his discussions on the nature of mathematical problems

    (cf., Wittgenstein, 1953/1999, sections 334–338 & 352, 1956/1998, p. 370, 1967/1998, p. 120,

    1974/1993, pp. 361–365, 1975/1998, pp. 184–191, 1976, pp. 64–68 & 83–86). However,

    the core distinction which these remarks serve to delineate can be easily extended to

    other domains as Wittgenstein himself indicates in his 1956/1998 (p. 370) and 1974/1993

    (pp. 363–364). An extrapolation of this kind appears in Diamond (1995).

    [14] The solutions to these riddles are ‘‘28 days’’ and ‘‘queue’’ respectively. As to the first riddle,

    basic arithmetic is all that is really required in order to calculate the correct solution

    (provided one does not fail to notice that by the 28th day the snail has only 3 feet left to

    cover and therefore arrives to the edge of the well). The second riddle requires a more

    sophisticated approach. The key is to notice that after 4 of the word’s 5 letters have been

    removed only one remains. At this point, one can simply recite the letters of the ABC out

    loud whilst keeping a vigilant ear for legitimate English words. After rejecting inadmissible

    possibilities like ‘‘bee’’ and ‘‘see’’ on the basis of having an insufficient number of letters,

    the correct solution is inevitably reached.

    [15] This quote originally appeared in Margaret Macdonald’s notes to Wittgenstein’s lectures in

    1935 which have not been published yet. The fairytale to which Wittgenstein is alluding in

    his above-quoted remark is most likely ‘‘The Clever Farmer’s Daughter.’’ A common version

    of this fairytale appears in Grimm & Grimm (1987, pp. 347–349). Wittgenstein’s remark isdiscussed,   inter alia, in Diamond & Gerrard (1999, p. 142), Floyd (1995, p. 394), and

    Putnam (2000 pp 224 225)

    Philosophical Psychology    531

  • 8/17/2019 The Riddle of Dreams. Nadav Matalon

    16/21

    [16] That the king has formulated his challenge with the deliberate intention of failing the

    princess is made evident by the explicitly paradoxical nature of his riddle. It is, as Putnam

    puts it, ‘‘a command impossible of fulfillment’’ (2000, p. 224), whose explicit aim was to

    annul the possibility of producing a legitimate solution (or so the king initially believed).

    [17] Putnam makes the same point by saying: ‘‘we are able to give the [king’s] words a sense only after   [italics added] we know the solution; the solution bestows sense on the riddle-

    question’’ (2000, p. 224).

    [18] In Wittgenstein’s memorable words, ‘‘we remain unconscious of the prodigious diversity of 

    all the everyday language-games because the clothing of our language makes everything

    alike’’ (1953/1999, p. 224). Furthermore, following Read’s (2005) well-argued caveat against

    the off-handed deployment of so-called Wittgensteinian ‘‘magic words,’’ note that I do not

    employ the term ‘‘language-game’’ in some sort of highly specialized technical sense

    allegedly specified by the great philosopher (it was not, as section 65 in his 1953/1999 makes

    patently clear), but rather in the widest and most mundane possible sense, that is, as a

    convenient abbreviation for denoting any kind of linguistic activity (including paralinguistic

    features and extralinguistic markers) taking place between two or more interlocutors for thepurpose of communication.

    [19] It is important to note in this context that the issue here is not that Freud’s criteria are

    vague or ambiguous in themselves. The fact that a particular criterion is vague does not

    imply that one cannot employ it effectively. Rather, the point is that for Freud the question

    of   which criterion   should be used remains open until after an acceptable solution has

    been presented. It is   a different kind of ambiguity   similar to the one with which the

    princess was faced when contemplating the king’s riddle. The difficulty in that case was

    not how or to what degree should a pre-defined criterion be applied, but rather, the

    challenge of generating a solution that will retroactively define the criterion for its own

    correctness.

    [20] It is important to emphasize that the current analysis is strictly descriptive and notprescriptive, i.e., it should not be taken to suggest that the Freudian doctrine requires some

    kind of ‘‘correction’’ or ‘‘reform.’’ As I shall explicate later on, construed as solutions to

    riddles of the second kind, the efficacy of psychoanalytic dream interpretations need not

    depend on their particular character, but rather on the analysand’s willingness to accept

    them as correct and work through their implications.

    [21] It is noteworthy that Freud was not only familiar with the notion of retroactive processes,

    but actually coined the German term ‘ Nachträ glichkeit ’ to denote their manifestation in the

    psychological domain. Typically translated as ‘‘deferred action’’ and featuring,   inter alia,

    in the case studies of ‘‘Emma’’ (Freud, 1895) and the ‘‘Wolf-man’’ (Freud, 1918),

    ‘ Nachträ glichkeit ’ is thus used by Freud to portray an inverse and counterintuitive time-

    structure wherein earlier events in the analysand’s life gain new significance in light of later

    events. Despite its striking similarity to the psychoanalytic procedure of dream interpre-

    tation as explicated here, it is clear why Freud would not have been willing to apply the logic

    of this retroactive model to his entire  modus operandi. To do so, he would have had to

    relinquish the foundational axioms of his theory of dreams, most central of which is the

    assumption that the solution of a dream (i.e., its latent meaning) exists prior to and

    independently of the acts of dreaming and/or interpretation. Furthermore, as in the case of 

    ‘‘free associations,’’ here too the English translation is somewhat misleading inasmuch as the

    term ‘‘deferred action’’ completely obfuscates the most important aspect of these

    psychological processes, namely: their   retroactive   mode of functioning. The term ‘‘retro-

    activity,’’ suggested by Puhl (2004), thus appears to be a more suitable translation in this

    context. Also on this topic, see Laplanche and Pontalis (1973, pp. 111–114).

    [22] In his recent work on Freud, Lear endeavors to show that this tenet is actually consonantwith later developments in Freud’s conception of dream interpretation (cf., Lear, 2005,

    pp 101 104 133 135)

    532   N. Matalon

  • 8/17/2019 The Riddle of Dreams. Nadav Matalon

    17/21

    [23] This claim is more modest than it may appear. The realization that psychoanalytic

    interpretations constitute solutions to riddles of the second kind does not preclude the

    possibility that they could actually succeed in hitting upon the so-called ‘‘psychological

    etiology’’ of the dream. On the contrary, it is conceivable, in principle at least, that the

    analyst’s interpretation may perfectly coincide with the genuine cognitive processes fromwhich a dream originated (assuming, of course, that these processes are taken to be

    recognizable and definable). The point is that, as it stands, there is nothing in the

    psychoanalytic procedure that can be used to show whether or not that is indeed the case.

    Hence, we can certainly   speculate   what might have been the underlying reasons which

    brought forth the dream, and we may even become utterly convinced that we have found the

    right ones, but all this is still a far cry from being able to guarantee that our speculations are

    necessarily true as Freud purports to do.

    [24] This is not to say that the formulation of solutions to riddles of the second kind in general,

    or psychoanalytic dream interpretations in particular, has nothing to do with creative

    thinking. In fact, it is probably safe to assume that imagination and creativity play a pivotal

    role in the construction of such solutions. Nevertheless, we should bear in mind that,regardless of how inspired a particular solution may be, it cannot be considered a solution at

    all prior to its recognition as such. Put in a slightly different way, though there is certainly 

    room for disagreement on whether or not a particular solution is adequate, it is important to

    notice that debates of this kind can only take place   after   the putative solution has been

    actually posited. Hence, for example, one could surely criticize the king for lack of 

    imagination had he refused to accept the creative solution offered by the princess. Yet,

    polemics of this kind already  presuppose that what the princess has done indeed represents  a

    solution.

    [25] ‘‘We are agreed on this route,’’ Wittgenstein says in this context, but hastens to add, ‘‘and

     yet, it is obvious here that there may easily be different routes, on each of which we can be in

    agreement, each of which we might call consistent’’ (1956/1998, p. 370). Furthermore,spelling out the far-reaching implications this model entails with respect to the potential

    efficacy of psychoanalytic interpretations is a complicated issue I intend to develop in a

    future publication. For the moment, I can therefore only hint at these implications by saying

    that the ability of psychoanalytic interpretations to retroactively transform incomprehen-

    sible symptoms into meaningful—and thus fully   intelligible   and   soluble—psychological

    accounts may have a profound effect on analysands who are haunted by feelings of 

    frustration and helplessness deriving from their hereto inexplicable condition.

    [26] For concrete instances of this diagnostic ‘‘Rashomon Effect,’’ compare, e.g., Freud (1918)

    with Abraham and Torok (1986), and Freud (1911b) with Macalpine and Hunter (1953).

    Also see in this context Wittgenstein (1953/1999, sections 139–141).

    [27] The impossibility of using  ad hoc   criteria so as to determine in advance what would be

    considered the correct solution to riddles of the second kind is discussed in section 4.

    [28] Readers acquainted with emergent trends in psychoanalytic research during the second half 

    of the 20th century may recognize certain affinities between my account of Freudian dream

    interpretation and that of the so-called ‘‘hermeneutic’’ movement in psychoanalysis

    (Wallerstein, 2006, pp. 308–309). Particularly pertinent in this context is the controversial

    conception developed by Donald P. Spence in a long series of books and articles (cf., Spence,

    1981, 1982, 1983a, 1983b, 1986, 1991, 2001). Briefly, on Spence’s view, psychoanalytic

    interpretations do not represent ‘‘historical truths,’’ that is, faithful reconstructions of actual

    past events in the analysand’s life, but rather, ‘‘narrative truths,’’ i.e., creative constructions

    of compelling hypothetical ‘‘stories’’ that the analysand may be persuaded to accept.

    Nevertheless, it is important to notice that, despite his bold attempt to break from more

    traditional conceptions, Spence’s position remains well entrenched within the boundariesof conventional psychoanalytic wisdom since he continues to adhere to the Freudian axiom

    according to which dreams are essentially riddles of the first kind viz enigmatic

    Philosophical Psychology    533

  • 8/17/2019 The Riddle of Dreams. Nadav Matalon

    18/21

    phenomenal experiences whose hidden meanings exist prior to and independently of the acts

    of either dreaming or interpretation. Though much more can and should be said about the

    hermeneutic approach to psychoanalytic interpretations and the manner in which it relates

    to the thesis presented here, a comprehensive explication of these issues would be the task of 

    another occasion.[29] I would like to emphasize that my aim in this paper is not to disparage psychoanalysis, nor is

    it to engage in what Jonathan Lear calls ‘‘Freud-bashing’’ (1998, pp. 17, 54–55). As Lear and

    other commentators have shown, there is still much to be said about Freud’s invaluable

    contributions to, and lasting impact on, the study of human psychology. This, however,

    should not detract us from challenging deep-seated assumptions and commonly held beliefs

    about dreams and the psychoanalytic method of their interpretations.

    References

    Abraham, N., & Torok, M. (1986).   The Wolfman’s magic word: A cryptonymy . Minneapolis:University of Minnesota Press.

    Diamond, C. (1995). Riddles and Anselm’s riddle.   The realistic spirit: Wittgenstein, philosophy, and 

    the mind  (pp. 267–289). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Diamond, C., & Gerrard, S. (1999). How old are these bones? Putnam, Wittgenstein and

    verification.  Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes,  73, 99–150.

    Floyd, J. (1995). On saying what you really want to say: Wittgenstein, Gö del, and the trisection of 

    the angle. In J. Hintikka (Ed.),   From Dedekind to Gödel: Essays on the development of the

     foundations of mathematics (pp. 373–425). The Netherlands: Kluwer.

    Freud, S. (1895). Project for a scientific psychology. In J. Strachey (Ed. & Trans.),  The standard 

    edition of the complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud   (Vol. 1, pp. 347–357). London:

    Hogarth.Freud, S. (1900). The interpretation of dreams. In J. Strachey (Ed. & Trans.),  The standard edition of 

    the complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud  (Vols. 4–5, pp. 1–627). London: Hogarth.

    Freud, S. (1901). On dreams. In J. Strachey (Ed. & Trans.),  The standard edition of the complete

     psychological works of Sigmund Freud  (Vol. 5, pp. 629–714). London: Hogarth.

    Freud, S. (1905a). Fragment of an analysis of a case of hysteria. In J. Strachey (Ed. & Trans.),  The

    standard edition of the complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud   (Vol. 7, pp. 7–122).

    London: Hogarth.

    Freud, S. (1905b). Jokes and their relation to the unconscious. In J. Strachey (Ed. & Trans.),  The

    standard edition of the complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud   (Vol. 8, pp. 1–247).

    London: Hogarth.

    Freud, S. (1910). Five lectures on psycho-analysis. In J. Strachey (Ed. & Trans.),   The standard 

    edition of the complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud   (Vol. 11, pp. 1–55). London:

    Hogarth.

    Freud, S. (1911a). The handling of dream-interpretation in psycho-analysis. In J. Strachey 

    (Ed. & Trans.),   The standard edition of the complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud 

    (Vol. 12, pp. 89–96). London: Hogarth.

    Freud, S. (1911b). Psycho-analytic notes on an autobiographical account of a case of paranoia

    (dementia paranoides). In J. Strachey (Ed. & Trans.),   The standard edition of the complete

     psychological works of Sigmund Freud  (Vol. 12, pp. 3–82). London: Hogarth.

    Freud, S. (1913). On beginning the treatment (Further recommendations on the technique of 

    psycho-analysis I). In J. Strachey (Ed. & Trans.),   The standard edition of the complete

     psychological works of Sigmund Freud  (Vol. 12, pp. 121–144). London: Hogarth.

    Freud, S. (1914a). On narcissism: An introduction. In J. Strachey (Ed. & Trans.),  The standard edition of the complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud   (Vol. 14, pp. 73–102). London:

    Hogarth

    534   N. Matalon

  • 8/17/2019 The Riddle of Dreams. Nadav Matalon

    19/21

    Freud, S. (1914b). Remembering, repeating and working-through. In J. Strachey (Ed. & Trans.),

    The standard edition of the complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud  (Vol. 12, pp. 147–156).

    London: Hogarth.

    Freud, S. (1916–1917). Introductory lectures on psycho-analysis. In J. Strachey (Ed. & Trans.),

    The standard edition of the complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud   (Vols. 15–16,pp. 1–463). London: Hogarth.

    Freud, S. (1918). From the history of an infantile neurosis. In J. Strachey (Ed. & Trans.),

    The standard edition of the complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud  (Vol. 17, pp. 1–122).

    London: Hogarth.

    Freud, S. (1919). Lines of advance in psycho-analytic therapy. In J. Strachey (Ed. & Trans.),  The

    standard edition of the complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud  (Vol. 17, pp. 157–168).

    London: Hogarth.

    Freud, S. (1923). Remarks on the theory and practice of dream–interpretation. In J. Strachey 

    (Ed. & Trans.),   The standard edition of the complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud 

    (Vol. 19, pp. 107–121). London: Hogarth.

    Freud, S. (1925a). An autobiographical study. In J. Strachey (Ed. & Trans.),  The standard edition of the complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud  (Vol. 20, pp. 5–74). London: Hogarth.

    Freud, S. (1925b). Some additional notes on dream-interpretation as a whole. In J. Strachey 

    (Ed. & Trans.),   The standard edition of the complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud 

    (Vol. 19, pp. 125–138). London: Hogarth.

    Freud, S. (1926). The question of lay analysis. In J. Strachey (Ed. & Trans.),   The standard 

    edition of the complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud  (Vol. 20, pp. 183–258). London:

    Hogarth.

    Freud, S. (1937). Constructions in analysis. In J. Strachey (Ed. & Trans.),  The standard edition of the

    complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud  (Vol. 23, pp. 255–269). London: Hogarth.

    Freud, S. (1940). An outline of psycho-analysis. In J. Strachey (Ed. & Trans.),  The standard edition

    of the complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud  (Vol. 23, pp. 141–208). London: Hogarth.Grimm, J., & Grimm, W. (1987).   The complete fairy tails of the brothers Grimm. Toronto & 

    New York: Bantam.

    Hobson, J. A. (2005). Sleep is of the brain, by the brain and for the brain.  Nature, 437 , 1254–1256.

    Hobson, J. A. (2007). Wake up or dream on? Six questions for Turnbull and Solms.  Cortex ,  43,

    1113–1115.

    Hobson, J. A., & Pace-Schott, E. F. (2002). The cognitive neuroscience of sleep: Neuronal systems,

    consciousness and learning.  Neuroscience,  3, 679–693.

    Hobson, J. A., Pace-Schott, E. F., & Stickgold, R. (2000). Dreaming and the brain: Toward a

    cognitive neuroscience of conscious states. Behavioral and Brain Sciences,  23, 793–1121.

    Kandel, E. R. (1999). Biology and the future of psychoanalysis: A new intellectual framework for

    psychiatry revisited.  American Journal of Psychiatry ,  156 , 505–524.Laplanche, J., & Pontalis, J. B. (1973).  The language of psychoanalysis. New York: Norton.

    Lear, J. (1998).  Open minded . Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Lear, J. (2005).  Freud . New York: Routledge.

    Macalpine, I., & Hunter, R. A. (1953). The Schreber case: A contribution to schizophrenia,

    hypochondria and psychosomatic symptom-formation.   The Psychoanalytic Quarterly ,   22,

    328–371.

    Puhl, K. (2004). Rule-following: Difference and repetition. In T. Demeter (Ed.),   Essays on

    Wittgenstein and Austrian Philosophy   (pp. 155–166). Amsterdam: Rodopi.

    Putnam, H. (2000). Rethinking mathematical necessity. In A. Crary & R. Read (Eds.),   The new 

    Wittgenstein   (pp. 218–231). London: Routledge.

    Read, R. (2005). Throwing away ‘the bedrock’.  Proceeding of the Aristotelian Society ,  105, 81–98.Schorske, C. E. (1973). Politics and practice in Freud’s  Interpretation of dreams. American Historical 

    Review ,  78, 328–347.

    Philosophical Psychology    535

  • 8/17/2019 The Riddle of Dreams. Nadav Matalon

    20/21

    Shevrin, H., & Eister, A. S. (2000). Continued vitality of the Freudian theory of dreaming.

    Behavioral and Brain Sciences,  23, 1004–1006.

    Solms, M. (2000). Dreaming and REM sleep are controlled by different brain mechanisms.

    Behavioral and Brain Sciences,  23, 843–850.

    Solms, M. (2001). The interpretation of dreams and the neurosciences.  Psychoanalysis and History ,3, 79–91.

    Solms, M., & Turnbull, O. (2002). The brain and the inner world: An introduction to the neuroscience

    of subjective experience. New York: Other Press.

    Solms, M., & Turnbull, O. (2007). Awareness, desire, and false beliefs: Freud in the light of modern

    neuropsychology. Cortex ,  43, 1083–1090.

    Spence, D. P. (1981). Toward a theory of dream interpretation.  Psychoanalysis and Contemporary 

    Thought ,  4, 383–405.

    Spence, D. P. (1982).   Narrative truth and historical truth: Meaning and interpretation in

     psychoanalysis. London: Norton.

    Spence, D. P. (1983a). Narrative persuasion. Psychoanalysis and Contemporary Thought , 6 , 457–481.

    Spence, D. P. (1983b). Narrative truth and theoretical truth.   Psychoanalytic Quarterly ,  51, 43–69.Spence, D. P. (1986). When interpretation masquerades as explanation.   Journal of the American

    Psychoanalytic Association,  34, 3–22.

    Spence, D. P. (1991). Saying good-bye to historical truth.   Philosophy of the Social Sciences,   21,

    245–252.

    Spence, D. P. (2001). Filling the gap.   Psychological Inquiry ,  12, 148–150.

    Wallerstein, R. S. (2006). The relevance of Freud’s psychoanalysis in the 21st century: Its science

    and its research.   Psychoanalytic Psychology ,  23, 302–326.

    Webster’s Encyclopedic Unabridged Dictionary of the English Language  (1994). New York: Gramercy.

    Wittgenstein, L. (1963). Tractatus logico-philosophicus.  London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. (Original

    work published 1922.)

    Wittgenstein, L. (1976).  Wittgenstein’s lectures on the foundations of mathematics: Cambridge 1939 .Hassocks: Harvard University Press.

    Wittgenstein, L. (1993).   Philosophical grammar . Oxford: Basil Blackwell. (Original work published

    1974.)

    Wittgenstein, L. (1994).   Lectures and conversations on aesthetics, psychology, and religious belief.

    Oxford: Blackwell. (Original work published 1966.)

    Wittgenstein, L. (1998).   Philosophical remarks. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. (Original work published

    1975.)

    Wittgenstein, L. (1998).   Remarks on the foundations of mathematics. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    (Original work published 1956.)

    Wittgenstein, L. (1998).  Zettel . Oxford: Basil Blackwell. (Original work published 1967.)

    Wittgenstein, L. (1999).   Philosophical investigations  (2nd ed.). Oxford: Blackwell. (Original work 

    published 1953.)

    536   N. Matalon

  • 8/17/2019 The Riddle of Dreams. Nadav Matalon

    21/21

    Copyright of Philosophical Psychology is the property of Routledge and its content may not be copied or

    emailed to multiple sites or posted to a listserv without the copyright holder's express written permission.

    However, users may print, download, or email articles for individual use.