ssrn-id2326987

19
Electronic copy available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2326987 Further information about the University of Cambridge Faculty of Law Legal Studies Research Paper Series can be found at http://www.law.cam.ac.uk/ssrn/ Proportionality and deference: the Importance of a structured approach Mark Elliott PAPER NO. 32/2013 SEPTEMBER 2013

Upload: penguinpowerrrr

Post on 19-Dec-2015

216 views

Category:

Documents


2 download

DESCRIPTION

SSRN-id2326987

TRANSCRIPT

Electronic copy available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2326987

Further information about the University of Cambridge Faculty of Law Legal Studies

Research Paper Series can be found at http://www.law.cam.ac.uk/ssrn/

Proportionality and deference: the

Importance of a structured approach

Mark Elliott

PAPER NO. 32/2013

SEPTEMBER 2013

Electronic copy available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2326987

Elliott,  ‘Proportionality  and  deference:  the  importance  of  a  structured  approach’       1  

Proportionality  and  deference:  the    importance  of  a  structured  approach  

Mark  Elliott*  

Introduction  

In  the  closing  decades  of  the  last  century,  when  one  of  the  questions  at  the  forefront  of  English  administrative  lawyers’  minds  was  whether  proportionality  should  be  embraced  as   a   ground  of   judicial   review,   the   two   factors   upon  which  debate   principally   centred  were  the  structured  nature  of  the  test  and  its  likely  impact  upon  the  breadth  of  executive  discretion  (and,  correlatively,  judicial  power).  Unsurprisingly,  the  former  was  generally  seen  as  a  good  thing,  and  as  welcome  relief  from  the  palm-­‐tree  quality  of  the  tautologous  Wednesbury  doctrine.1  However,  there  was  great  concern  in  certain  quarters  about  the  latter,   the   perceived   difficulty   being   that   adopting   the   proportionality   test   would  eviscerate   the   hallowed   distinction   between   appeal   and   review,   resulting   in   judicial  usurpation   of   administrative   functions.   Against   that   background,   the   purpose   of   this  paper  is  twofold.  It  argues  that  the  structured  nature  of  the  proportionality  test  is  one  of  its   principal   virtues,   but   that   English   courts   have   some   distance   to   go   before   fully  capitalising  on  this;  and  that  this  failure  in  turn  is  inhibiting  the  emergence  of  a  coherent  doctrine   of   judicial   deference   to   the   administrative   and   legislative   branches   which   is  intended  to  ensure  that  a  distinction  remains  between  the  respective  roles  of  courts  and  primary  decision-­‐makers.    

The  distinction  between  necessity  and  narrow  proportionality  

There  are  many  formulations  of  the  proportionality  test.2  The  version  that  is  advocated  in  this  paper,  for  reasons  which  will  be  defended  in  due  course,  is  as  follows:3    

(i) Does  the  measure  impinge  upon  a  highly-­‐regarded  interest  (eg  a  human  right)?    

(ii) Does  the  measure  pursue  a  legitimate  objective?    

(iii) Is  the  measure  capable  of  securing  that  objective?    

(iv) Is  the  adoption  of  the  measure  necessary  in  order  to  secure  that  objective?  

(v) Are  the  losses  inflicted  by  the  measure  (eg  in  terms  of  the  restriction  of  human  rights)  justified,  or  outweighed,  by  the  gains  which  it  purchases  (eg  in  terms  of  benefits  which  flow  from  securing  the  legitimate  objective)?    

While  it  is  now  well-­‐established  that  English  courts  can  and  do  apply  the  proportionality  test,   at   least   in   cases   concerning   human   rights,4   the   precise   content   of   the   test  which  

                                                                                                                         *  Senior  Lecturer  in  Law,  University  of  Cambridge;  Fellow,  St  Catharine’s  College,  Cambridge.  I  am  indebted   to   Julian   Rivers   for   his   invaluable   comments   on   earlier   drafts   of   this   paper   and   for  discussion  of  the  ideas  upon  which  it  is  based.    1  Associated  Provincial  Picture  Houses  Ltd  v  Wednesbury  Corporation  [1948]  1  KB  223.      2  See  further  Hickman,  ‘Proportionality:  Comparative  Law  Lessons’  [2007]  JR  31.  3  This  is  similar  to  the  version  of  the  test  preferred  by  Craig,  Administrative  Law  (London  2008)  at  628.    4  See  R  (Daly)  v  Secretary  of  State  for  the  Home  Department  [2001]  UKHL  26,  [2001]  2  AC  532.    

Elliott,  ‘Proportionality  and  deference:  the  importance  of  a  structured  approach’       2  

they  apply  is  far  from  clear.  The  leading  formulation,  set  out  by  the  Privy  Council  in  De  Freitas   v   Permanent   Secretary   of  Ministry   of   Agriculture,   Fisheries,   Lands   and  Housing5  and  adopted  by  the  House  of  Lords  in  Daly,6  does  not  unambiguously  incorporate  stage  (v)   of   the   analysis   (which   will   be   referred   to   in   this   paper   as   ‘proportionality   in   the  narrow   sense’   or   ‘narrow   proportionality’).   Whereas   that   stage   is   recognised   very  clearly   in   the   Canadian   jurisprudence,   which   requires   ‘a   proportionality   between   the  effects   of   the   measures   which   are   responsible   for   limiting   the   …   [relevant]   right   or  freedom,  and  the  objective  [in  question]’,7  and  is  also  evident  to  some  extent  in  the  case  law  of  the  European  Court  of   Justice,8  the  De  Freitas   inquiry  appears  to  end  with  stage  (iv)  (‘the  necessity  question’).9    

Although  some  English  cases  have  acknowledged  that  the  proportionality  test  requires  ‘the  striking  of  a  fair  balance  between  the  rights  of  the  individual  and  the  interests  of  the  community’,10   this   notion   is   deeply   ambiguous.   In   some   manifestations   it   appears   to  take   the   form   of   an   independent   requirement   over   and   above   that   of   necessity,   thus  suggesting   that   the  English  doctrine  of  proportionality   includes  a   fifth  stage,   requiring  analysis  of  proportionality  in  the  narrow  sense,  that  is  clearly  distinct  from  the  question  of  necessity.11  However,  the  fair  balance  requirement  has  also  been  characterised  as  one  which   is   synonymous   with   proportionality12   or   which   encompasses   the   whole   of   the  proportionality  analysis,  such  that  the  single  question  whether  a  given  measure  strikes  a  fair  balance  can  be  asked  in  place  of  the  distinct  questions  set  out  above.13  Meanwhile,  the   European   Court   of   Human   Rights   has   used   the   term   fair   balance   to   describe   a  requirement  which  operates  (in  relation  to  certain  ECHR  provisions)  in  place  of  stages  (iv)  and  (v),   thus  entirely   fusing   the  necessity  and  narrow  proportionality  questions.14  Moreover,   the   nature   of   the   necessity   test   is   itself   ambiguous.   In   some   contexts,   it   is  taken  to  mean  that  a  measure  may  not  lawfully  be  adopted  unless  it   imposes  upon  the  relevant   right   the   minimum   restrictions   which   are   consistent   with   achieving   the  legitimate   objective;15   yet   in   other   circumstances   it   is   characterised   in   less   exacting                                                                                                                            5  [1999]  1  AC  69  at  80.    6  Op  cit  n  4  at  [27].  7  R  v  Oakes  [1986]  1  SCR  103  at  [70].    8  Eg  Case  C-­‐331/88,  R  v  Ministry  of  Agriculture,  Fisheries  and  Food,  ex  parte  Federation  Europeene  de   la   Sante   Animale   [1991]   1   CMLR   507   at   522-­‐3,   per   Advocate-­‐General   Mischo.   However,  Tridimas,   The   General   Principles   of   EU   Law   (Oxford   2006,   2nd   ed)   at   139,   points   out   that   in  practice   the   ECJ   does   not   distinguish   between   the   necessity   and   narrow   proportionality  questions.    9   The  De   Freitas   test   does   require   the   court   to   determine   whether   the   objective   is   important  enough  to  justify  limiting  a  fundamental  right,  but  does  not  explicitly  require  the  court  to  decide  whether   the   objective   is   sufficiently   important   to   justify   the  particular   limitation   to  which   the  claimant  objects.  This  implies  the  sort  of  scrutiny  involved  in  stage  (ii)  rather  than  that  which  is  supplied  at  stage  (v).    10  R  (Razgar)  v  Secretary  of  State  for  the  Home  Department  [2004]  UKHL  27,  [2004]  2  AC  368  at  [20];  Huang  v  Secretary  of  State  for  the  Home  Department  [2007]  UKHL  11,  [2007]  2  AC  167.    11  R  (Baker)  v  First  Secretary  of  State  [2003]  EWHC  2511  (Admin)  at  [45];  Razgar,  op  cit  n  10  at  [17].    12  Kay  v  Lambeth  London  Borough  Council  [2006]  UKHL  10  [2006]  2  AC  465.    13  R  (Baiai  and  another)  v  Secretary  of  State  for  the  Home  Department  (Nos  1  and  2)  [2007]  EWCA  Civ  478  [2008]  QB  143  at  [37].    14  James  v  UK  (1986)  8  EHRR  123  at  [51].  15   A   v   Secretary   of   State   for   the   Home   Department   [2004]   UKHL   56   [2005]   2   AC   68   at   [231].  Admittedly,   this   case  concerned  Article  15  ECHR  which  refers   to   the   taking  of  measures  which  are  ‘strictly  required  by  the  exigencies  of  the  situation’—although  it  is  clear  that  the  ECtHR  does  not  itself  treat  this  requirement  as  equating  to  a  test  of  least  restrictive  means:  see,  eg,  Brannigan  v  United  Kingdom  (1994)  17  EHRR  539.    

Elliott,  ‘Proportionality  and  deference:  the  importance  of  a  structured  approach’       3  

terms;16   and   indeed   the   ECtHR’s   standard   formulation—that   ‘the   notion   of   necessity  implies  that  an  interference  corresponds  to  a  pressing  social  need  and,  in  particular,  that  it  is  proportionate  to  the  legitimate  aim  pursued’—suggests  that  the  necessity  question  has  no  meaning  independent  of  or  distinct  from  stages  (ii)  and  (v)  of  the  scheme  set  out  above.17  This  lack  of  clarity  about  both  the  structure  of  the  proportionality  doctrine  and  the   content   of   the   tests   of   which   it   is   comprised   is   problematic   for   several   (related)  reasons.    

First,  as  noted  above,  one  of  the  much-­‐vaunted  benefits  of  the  proportionality  test  is  its  greater  potential   for  analytical   clarity   than   the  Wednesbury   test.  That  potential   can  be  realised  only   if  courts  are  clear  about  what  elements  the  test  comprises  and  about  the  role  played  by  each.  In  this  regard,  distinguishing  clearly  between  stages  (iv)  and  (v)  is  essential.  The  fact  that  a  right  has  been  restricted  to  the  minimum  extent  necessary  to  secure   a   particular   objective   does   not   mean   that   the   disbenefit   arising   from   that  limitation  is  proportionate  to—in  the  sense  of  being  adequately   justified  by—the  good  that  will  flow  from  securing  the  relevant  objective.  For  example,  it  may  be  impossible  to  realize  a  particular  level  of  economic  well-­‐being  without  enacting  sweeping  limitations  upon   the   right   to   respect   for   private   life;18   such   restrictions   would   therefore   be  necessary  for  the  achievement  of  the  objective  in  question.  Yet  it  does  not  follow  that  the  resulting  loss  to  privacy  would  be  proportionate  (in  the  narrow  sense)  to  the  gain  which  it  would  purchase  in  terms  of  economic  well-­‐being:  the  gain  might  be  thought  too  small  to  justify  the  loss;  and  even  a  large  economic  gain  might  be  thought  insufficient  to  justify  a  small  privacy  loss   if   the   latter   is  regarded  as  a  much  more  valuable   interest  than  the  former.   The   necessity   and   narrow   proportionality   questions   thus   constitute   distinct  criteria—and  this  should  be  reflected  in  the  judicial  reasoning  process  in  the  interests  of  analytical  clarity  and  transparency.    

Secondly,   precisely   because   they   are   distinct   criteria,   the   consequences   of   their  enforcement  are  different.  The  necessity  test  implies  that  public  authorities  may  impair  highly-­‐regarded   interests   such   as  human   rights   only   insofar   as   that   is   essential   to   the  realisation  of   some   legitimate  policy  objective.19  Because  necessity   review   is   therefore  concerned   exclusively  with   the  decision-­‐maker’s   choice  of  means,   review  at   this   stage  will  only  ever  directly  constrain  how  a  decision-­‐maker  is  entitled  to  realise  its  legitimate  objective,   not   whether   it   is   able   to   do   so.   In   contrast,   if   a   measure   is   judged   to   be  necessary   but   disproportionate   in   the   narrow   sense,   this  means   that   the   objective   in  question  cannot   lawfully  be  achieved,  because  the   least  restrictive  way  of  securing  the  objective   constitutes   an   unacceptable   restriction   on   rights   judged   by   reference   to   the  benefits   it   would   secure.   So,   whereas   the   necessity   test   is   ultimately   concerned   with  whether   a   given   policy   objective   may   be   pursued   in   a   particular   way,   the   narrow  proportionality  test  determines  whether  it  may,  given  its  impact  on  rights,  be  pursued  at  all.20  

                                                                                                                         16  R   (Clays   Lane   Housing   Co-­‐Operative   Ltd)   v   The   Housing   Corporation   [2004]   EWCA   Civ   1658  [2005]  1  WLR  2229  at  [  ].    17  See,  eg,  Olsson  v  Sweden  (1989)  11  EHRR  259  at  [67].    18  Article  8(2)  of  the  European  Convention  on  Human  Rights  indicates  that  the  promotion  of  the  economic  well-­‐being  of   the  country   is  a   legitimate  objective  capable  of   justifying  restrictions  of  the  right  to  respect  for  private  life.    19  For  the  time  being,  it  is  assumed  that  the  necessity  test  compels  choice  of  the  least  restrictive  means.  This  position  is  defended  below.    20  Of  course,  a   logically  prior  question  which  forms  part  of  the  proportionality  test,  viz  whether  the  measure   under   review   pursues   a   legitimate   objective,   also   impacts   on  whether   the   policy  may  be  pursued  at  all:  rights-­‐infringing  measures  cannot  lawfully  be  adopted  except  in  pursuit  of  

Elliott,  ‘Proportionality  and  deference:  the  importance  of  a  structured  approach’       4  

Thirdly,   it   follows   from  what   has   just   been   said   that   perceptions  may   differ   as   to   the  legitimacy   of   judicial   enforcement   of   the   necessity   criterion   on   the   one   hand   and   the  narrow   proportionality   criterion   on   the   other.   The   necessity   criterion   regulates   only  means  and  requires  the  reviewing  court  to  ask  an  essentially  factual  question:  could  the  objective   have   been   achieved   in   some   other   way  which   would   have   involved   a  more  modest   restriction   of   the   right?   In   contrast,   the   narrow   proportionality   test   may  preclude   the   realisation  of   legitimate  objectives  and  reduces   to  a  value-­‐judgment:   is   it  worth  paying  a  given  price  in  order  to  secure  a  particular  gain?  Therefore,  in  terms  both  of   issues   raised   (factual   versus   value-­‐judgment)   and   consequences   (choice   of   means  versus  outcomes)  narrow  proportionality  review  represents  a  bolder  judicial  endeavour  than  necessity  review:  it  takes  courts  closer  to  the  merits  of  decisions  and  has  a  greater  impact   on   decision-­‐makers’   discretion.   Arguments   about   deference   therefore   play   out  differently  in  relation  to  necessity  and  narrow  proportionality,  such  that  a  fully  coherent  concept  of  deference  cannot  emerge  unless  courts  adopt  a  clearly  structured  approach  to  proportionality  review,  carefully  distinguishing  between  the  different  tasks  involved  in  assessing  the  necessity  and  narrow  proportionality  of  impugned  measures.    

Deference    

In  order  to  substantiate  this  proposition,  it  is  necessary  to  be  clear  about  what  is—and  what   ought   to   be—meant   by   ‘deference’.   Although   not   everyone   agrees   that   term   is  appropriate  in  the  present  context,21  it  is  generally  used  in  a  fairly  loose  way  to  describe  a   range   of   judicial   techniques   which   have   the   effect   of   increasing   decision-­‐makers’  latitude.  In  contrast  to  the  inherently  deferential  Wednesbury  doctrine,  which  is  phrased  in   such   a   way   as   to   preclude   judicial   intervention   unless   the   decision-­‐maker   has  exceeded   the   widely-­‐drawn   bounds   of   reasonableness,22   the   necessity   and   narrow  proportionality   tests   are,   at   least   prima   facie,   hard-­‐edged.   Requiring   courts   to   ask  whether   a   given   measure   is   necessary   and   whether   it   imposes   burdens   which   are  disproportionate   to   its   putative   benefits   implies   that   it   is   for   the   court   to   arrive   at   a  primary  judgment  on  these  matters,  rather  than  to  form  a  merely  secondary  judgment  about   the   reasonableness   of   the   decision-­‐maker’s   view.   If   the   court   believes   that   less  restrictive  means  could  have  been  adopted,  or  that   the  burdens  outweigh  the  benefits,  then   it   seems   that   the   court   should   strike   down   the   impugned  measure.   Prima   facie,  such  judicial  methodology  leaves  little  room  for  administrative  or  legislative  discretion  in  situations  where  rights  are  at  stake.    

It   was   perceptions   of   the   proportionality   test   such   as   these   which,   prior   to   the  enactment   of   the   Human   Rights   Act   1998,   led   certain   English   judges   to   view   it   with  considerable   suspicion.   Lord  Ackner,   for   instance,   feared   that   its   use  would   inevitably  ‘involve   a   review   of   the   merits   of   the   decision’,   risking   ‘an   abuse   of   power   by   the  judiciary’.23  The  doctrine  of   deference  has  been  developed   in   order   to   assist   courts   to  engage   in   proportionality   review   without   threatening   the   collapse   of   the   distinction  between   appeal   and   review,   by   creating   the   possibility   of   what   Laws   LJ   has   called   ‘a  principled   distance   between   the   court's   adjudication   …   and   the   [decision-­‐maker’s]  

                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                           legitimate  aims.  The  significance  of  the  narrow  proportionality  test  is  that  it  may  render  unlawful  the  only  possible  way  of  achieving  what  has  already  been  judged  to  be  a  legitimate  aim.    21  See,  eg,  R  (Prolife  Alliance)  v  British  Broadcasting  Corporation  [2003]  UKHL  23  [2004]  1  AC  185  at  [75],  per  Lord  Hoffmann.    22   Albeit   that,   in   practice,   courts  may   be  more  willing   to   intervene   than   the   rubric   of   the   test  implies.      23  R  v  Secretary  of  State  for  the  Home  Department,  ex  parte  Brind  [1991]  1  AC  696  at  758  and  763.    

Elliott,  ‘Proportionality  and  deference:  the  importance  of  a  structured  approach’       5  

decision,  based  on  his  perception  of  the  case's  merits’.24  Deference  therefore  makes  the  tests  which  comprise  the  proportionality  doctrine  less  hard-­‐edged,  blunting  them  such  that   the  defendant’s  decision  may  pass  muster  without  precisely  mirroring   the  court’s  view.  However,  while  this  much  is  apparent  from  existing  case  law,  there  are  three  other  important   issues   about   which,   it   will   be   argued   in   subsequent   parts   of   this   paper,  greater  clarity  is  needed.    

First,   there   are   two  ways   in   which   deference   can   operate.   One   possibility   is   that   the  questions   the   court   asks   of   the   decision-­‐maker   are   rendered   less   demanding.   For  example,   at   the   narrow   proportionality   stage,   the   court   might   limit   itself   to   ruling   a  measure   unlawful   only   if   the   human   rights   loss   significantly   exceeds   the   public   policy  gains.  Alternatively,  the  court  might  pose  the  questions  in  their  most  rigorous  form—for  example,  asking  (at  the  necessity  stage)  whether  the  measure  is  strictly  necessary—but  may  make  it  easier  for  the  decision-­‐maker  to  satisfy  the  court  that  the  answers  are  such  as   to   render   the   measure   lawful.   This   might   be   achieved   by   attaching   respect   to   the  decision-­‐maker’s  view—by,  for  example,  ascribing  considerable  weight  to  its  view  about  whether   the   desired   objective   could   have   been   successfully   achieved   via   other,   less  restrictive  means.    

Secondly,  there  two  principal  grounds  on  which  deference  may  be  exhibited.  A  court  may  defer   to  a  decision-­‐maker’s  superior  expertise   in  relation   to  certain  matters.  The  most  natural  way  for  such  deference  to  be  exhibited  is  by  the  ascription  of  particular  weight  to   the   decision-­‐maker’s   view.   For   example,   if   the   question   for   the   court   is   whether   a  given  measure   is   the   least  restrictive  way  of  securing  a  particular  policy  objective,   the  court  may  not  be  institutionally  well-­‐placed  to  determine  whether  some  other  measure  would  be  capable  of  securing  that  objective  but  in  a  manner  less  restrictive  of  the  rights  concerned.   If   the   decision-­‐maker   is   better   placed   to   do   so,   the   court   may   therefore  attach  weight   to   its   view,  making   it   more   likely   that   the   court   will   conclude   that   the  measure   adopted   has   been   shown   to   be   the   least   restrictive.   In   addition,   a   court  may  defer   to  a  decision-­‐maker   in   light  of   its   superior  democratic   legitimacy.  Whether   such  deference   is   appropriate   is   a   controversial   matter   which   is   discussed   below.   For   the  time  being,   it   is  simply  noted  that  such  deference  can,   if  desired,  be  achieved  either  by  ascribing  weight   to   the   decision-­‐maker’s   view   (eg   that   a   particular   trade-­‐off   between  rights   and   public   policy   is   appropriate)   or   by   making   the   test   less   onerous   (eg   by  accepting   a   trade-­‐off   between   rights   and   public   policy   which   the   court   accepts   is  reasonably  if  not  strictly  proportionate  in  the  narrow  sense).    

Thirdly,  there  are  two  principal  questions  upon  which  deference  may  bite.  Deference  may  be  exhibited  in  relation  to  the  necessity  question:  as  noted  in  the  previous  paragraph,  a  court  may,  for  example,  ascribe  particular  weight  to  the  decision-­‐maker’s  view  that  the  desired  objective  cannot  be  achieved  through  the  adoption  of  any  other,  less  restrictive  measures.   Instead,   or   in   addition,   deference   may   be   exhibited   in   relation   to   narrow  proportionality:   a   court  may   think   it   appropriate   to   grant   the  decision-­‐maker   latitude  vis-­‐à-­‐vis   the  question  whether  a  given   trade-­‐off  between  rights  and  public  policy   is   an  acceptable  one.    

It   is   argued   in   the   remainder   of   this   paper   that   acknowledging   the   three   sets   of  distinctions  set  out  above  is  imperative  if  the  courts  are  to  develop  a  coherent  doctrine  of   deference—and   that   this,   in   turn,   requires   a   structured   approach   to   the  proportionality  doctrine  itself.    

                                                                                                                         24  R  (Mahmood)  v  Secretary  of  State  for  the  Home  Department  [2001]  1  WLR  840  at  855,  per  Laws  LJ.    

Elliott,  ‘Proportionality  and  deference:  the  importance  of  a  structured  approach’       6  

The  necessity  question  

The   necessity   question   is,   or   at   least   appears   to   be,   a   question   of   fact:   could   the  administrative   or   legislative   objective   in   question   have   been   secured   by   taking   steps  involving  a  more  modest   (or  no)  restriction  upon  the  relevant  right?  Looked  at   in   this  way,  it  appears  that  the  court  should  simply  answer  this  question  for  itself:  taking  all  the  evidence   into  consideration,  does   it   think  that   the  government  could  have  achieved   its  objective  in  a  manner  less  restrictive  of  the  right?  However,  two  questions  arise.  Should  decision-­‐makers   ever   be   allowed—in   other   words,   granted   discretion—to   choose  something  other  than  the  least  restrictive  measure?  And,  even  if  the  court  insists  upon  the   least   restrictive  measure,   should   it   ever   extend   latitude   to   the   decision-­‐maker   by  respecting   its   view   about   what   that   measure   is?25   We   begin   by   exploring   the   latter  question   on   the   assumption   that   the   necessity   requirement   equates   to   one   of   least  restrictive  means;  the  former  question  is  addressed  in  a  later  section.    

In   a   typical   case,   the   claimant   argues   that   the   government   could   have   achieved   its  objective  without  infringing  his  right  to  the  extent  that  it  was  actually  infringed,  because  some  other  measure,  less  restrictive  of  the  right  in  question,  would  have  been  an  equally  effective   means   by   which   the   government   could   have   secured   its   policy   objective.   In  defence,  the  government  is  likely  to  contend  that  while  other,  less  restrictive  measures  could   have   been   adopted,   they   would   not   have   realized   its   objective   to   the   desired  extent,  such  that  nothing  short  of  the  measures  actually  adopted  will  suffice.  The  court,  of   course,  has   to  choose  between   these  competing   interpretations  of   the  situation,  but  may  consider   itself   ill-­‐equipped  to  do  so.   In  order  to  decide  whether  the  government’s  policy  was   the   least   restrictive  way   of   securing   its   objective,   the   court  must,   in   logic,  determine   whether   any   other   less   restrictive   measures   would   have   been   equally  effective  in  achieving  the  objective  in  question.  The  court  is  therefore  required  to  make  predictions  about  the  likely  effectiveness  of  both  the  measure  actually  adopted  and  rival,  less  restrictive  measures.  Whether   the  court  can  meaningfully  undertake   this   task  will  depend  on  the  precise  nature  of  the  issue  which  confronts  it.    

For   example,   in   the   Belmarsh   case,26   the   House   of   Lords   was   required   to   determine  whether   a   scheme   involving   extra-­‐judicial   detention   of   foreign   nationals   suspected   of  involvement   in   international   terrorism  was   a   necessary  means   by  which   to   safeguard  public  safety  in  the  face  of  the  threat  evidenced  by  the  9/11  attacks  in  the  United  States  of  America.  Their  Lordships  had   little  difficulty   in   concluding   that   it  was  not.  The   fact  that  the  scheme  did  not  apply  to  British  nationals  implied  that  the  government  did  not  consider   it   necessary   to   detain   them:   as   Baroness  Hale   put   it,   ‘Other  ways  must   have  been  found  to  contain  the  threat  which  they  present.  And  if  it  is  not  necessary  to  lock  up  the  nationals   it  cannot  be  necessary  to   lock  up  the   foreigners.’27  The  court  was  able  to  reach   this   conclusion   without   having   to   attempt   to   make   difficult   predictions   about  whether  the  government’s  public  safety  objective  could  have  been  met  by  adopting  less  draconian   measures   precisely   because   the   government   had—by   not   extending   the  scheme   to   nationals—effectively   conceded   the   point.   It  was   therefore   possible   for   the  court   to   deduce   that   the   detention   of   foreign   suspects  was   not   necessary—something  

                                                                                                                         25  These   two  questions   reflect   the   two  ways   in  which  deference  can  be  exhibited—viz  relaxing  the  test  (eg  reasonable  rather  than  strict  necessity)  and  ascribing  weight  to  the  decision-­‐maker’s  view.    26  A  v  Secretary  of  State  for  the  Home  Department  [2004]  UKHL  56  [2005]  2  AC  68.    27  Ibid  at  [231]    

Elliott,  ‘Proportionality  and  deference:  the  importance  of  a  structured  approach’       7  

which   the   court   could   do   without   the   need   for   any   special   expertise   in   relation   to  security  or  other  matters.28    

The  position  would  have  been  different  if  the  detention  regime  had  applied  to  nationals  and  non-­‐nationals  alike.   It  would  then  have  been  necessary  to  examine  whether  other,  less   restrictive   measures—such   as   close   monitoring   by   law   enforcement   agencies,  electronic   tagging,  curfews,  and  prohibitions  on   freedom  of  movement  and  association  falling   short   of   detention—would   have   been   sufficient   to   achieve   the   government’s  objective   of   ‘protecting   the   British   people   against   the   risk   of   catastrophic   Al-­‐Qaeda  terrorism’   (as   the   appellants   in  Belmarsh   put   it).29   Indeed,   a   similar   question   recently  arose   in   the  AP   case,30  which   concerned   a   challenge   to   a  measure   imposed   under   the  Prevention   of   Terrorism   Act   2005   placing   substantial   restrictions   falling   short   of  detention   on   a   terrorist   suspect’s   freedoms   of   (inter   alia)   movement,   expression   and  association.  The  view  was  taken—in  relation  to  both  whether  it  was  necessary  to  make  a   control   order   and,   if   so,   what   restrictions   it   should   impose—that   ‘the   court   should  accord  a  degree  of  deference  to  the  Secretary  of  State,  because  she  is  better  able  than  the  court  to  decide  what  measures  are  necessary  to  protect  the  public  from  the  activities  of  someone   suspected   of   terrorism’.31   Although   he   did   not   spell   out   the   reasons  underpinning  this  conclusion,  the  judge  was  presumably  of  the  view  that  the  Secretary  of  State—and  her  departmental  officials  and  advisers—were  better-­‐placed   to  make  an  assessment  of  the  likely  efficacy  of  the  range  of  possible  measures  that  could  have  been  taken   against   the   appellant,   and   to   identify   the   least   restrictive   method   by   which   to  secure   the   statutory   objective   of   ‘protecting   members   of   the   public   from   a   risk   of  terrorism’.32      

Expertise-­‐based  deference  

Such   deference   on   the   grounds   of   the   executive’s   superior   expertise   in   relation   to  certain   matters   is   broadly,   but   not   universally,   recognised   as   legitimate.33   As   Rivers  points   out,   ‘In   order   to   know   how   effective   a   policy   might   be’—and,   in   particular,  whether   the  desired  objective  could  have  been  achieved  via  a  policy   less  restrictive  of  rights—‘the  court  is  reliant  on  others  …  To  the  extent  that  there  is  expertise,  judges  are  correct   to   rely   on   the   executive   as   part   of   ‘‘getting   it   right”.’34   Viewed   in   this   way,  deference  takes  effect  as  the  ascription  of  particular  weight,  or  respect,  to  the  decision-­‐maker’s  view.  However,  it  is  important  to  recognise  that  there  are  limitations  upon  the  role  which  such  deference  can  properly  play.  Six  points  should  be  noted  in  this  regard.    

                                                                                                                         28  Belmarsh  may   therefore   be   said   to   fall   into   the   category   of   cases,   identified   by  Buxton   LJ   in  Southampton  Port  Health  Authority  v  Seahawk  Marine  Foods  Ltd  [2002]  EWCA  Civ  54  at  [34],   in  which  ‘it  will  be  possible  for  a  court  to  reach  a  conclusion  on  an  issue  of  proportionality  on  the  basis   of   commonsense   and   its   own   understanding   of   the   process   of   government   and  administration’.    29  Op  cit  n  26  at  [30].    30  Secretary  of  State  for  the  Home  Department  v  AP  [2008]  EWHC  2001  (Admin).  This  case  was  an  appeal   under   s   10   of   the   Prevention   of   Terrorism   Act   2005,   rather   than   a   claim   for   judicial  review.  However,  it  is  relevant  here  since  court  are  required  by  s  10(6)  when  hearing  such  claims  to   ‘apply   the   principles   applicable   on   an   application   for   judicial   review’   and   are   specifically  required  by  s  10(4)  to  consider  whether  the  measures  adopted  were  necessary.      31  Ibid  at  [66];  see  also  [74].    32  Prevention  of  Terrorism  Act  2005,  s  2(1)(b).    33  Cf  n  45  and  text  thereto.    34  Rivers,  ‘Proportionality  and  Variable  Intensity  Review’  [2006]  CLJ  174  at  200.    

Elliott,  ‘Proportionality  and  deference:  the  importance  of  a  structured  approach’       8  

First,  and  perhaps  most  obviously,  deference  on  expertise  grounds   is  appropriate  only  where   the   matter   in   question   engages   issues   that   call   for   expertise—a   point   which   is  illustrated  by  the  distinction  between  the  Belmarsh  case,  in  which  the  court  was  able  to  deduce   that  detention  of   foreign  nationals  was  not   (or  at   least  had  not  been  shown  to  be)  necessary,  and  AP,  in  which  the  likely  effect  of  different  forms  of  control  involved,  as  Rivers  puts   it,   a   ‘factual  prognosis’  which   the  Secretary  of  State  was  better-­‐situated   to  make.35    

Secondly,   deference   to   executive   judgment   is   only   appropriate—indeed,   is   only  possible—if  such  a  judgment  exists  in  the  first  place.  It  is  now  clear  that  proportionality  is  concerned  with  the  outcome  of  the  decision-­‐making  process,  such  that  a  decision  is  not  per  se  disproportionate  simply  because  a  decision-­‐maker  failed  explicitly  to  address  the  various  questions  which  comprise  the  proportionality  test.36  However,  it  is  equally  clear  that  if  a  decision-­‐maker  entirely  fails  to  address  the  question  whether  a  given  measure  is   necessary—in   the   sense   of   whether   the   objective   in   question   could   have   been  achieved  by  other,  less  restrictive  means—then  it  is  impossible  for  the  court  to  defer  to  its  view  on  that  point,  even  if,  had  a  view  existed,  it  might  been  entitled  to  respect  as  an  expert   view.37   The   reverse   proposition   is   also   true.   For   example,   in   the  Denbigh  High  School   case,   which   involved   a   challenge   on   freedom   of   religion   grounds   to   a   school’s  policy  of  prohibiting  the  wearing  of  certain  but  not  all  forms  of  Muslim  dress,  the  school  had—as  Lord  Bingham  put   it—‘taken  immense  pains  to  devise  a  uniform  policy  which  respected  Muslim   beliefs   but   did   so   in   an   inclusive,   unthreatening   and   uncompetitive  way’.38  It  would  therefore,  he  said,  be  ‘irresponsible  of  any  court,  lacking  the  experience,  background   and   detailed   knowledge   of   the   head   teacher,   staff   and   governors,   to  overrule   their   judgment   on   a   matter   as   sensitive   as   this’.39   This   suggests—quite  rightly—that  where  a  decision-­‐maker  with  relevant  expertise  exercises  it,  considerable  weight  should  be  attached  to  its  view.  However,  Lord  Bingham  is  surely  wrong  to  imply  that,   in  such  circumstances,   the  court  should  simply  acquiesce   in   that  opinion.  A  more  subtle  view  was  advanced  by  Lord  Hoffmann,  who  said  that  ‘the  way  in  which  the  school  approached   the  problem  may  help   to   persuade   a   judge   that   its   answer   fell  within   the  area  of  judgment  accorded  to  it  by  the  law’.40    

Thirdly,   however,   this,   too,   is   problematic.   If   the   necessity   question   involves   asking  whether   the  measure   adopted—in   this   case,   banning   the  wearing   of   certain   forms   of  Muslim   dress—is   the   least   restrictive   way   of   achieving   the   desired   objective   of  protecting   other   pupils’   rights   and   freedoms,41   in   what   sense   does   the   decision-­‐maker  have   an   ‘area   of   judgment’?42   Surely   the   question   admits   of   only   one   correct   answer  (unless   there  are  several  ways  of  achieving   the  objective,  all  of  which  are  equally,  and  minimally,  restrictive  of  the  right).  Here  we  see  the  confusion  which  is  introduced  when  courts  fail  to  adopt  a  sufficiently  structured  approach  to  proportionality  and  deference.                                                                                                                            35  Ibid  at  199.    36  R  (SB)  v  Governors  of  Denbigh  High  School  [2006]  UKHL  15,  [2007]  1  AC  100.    37  See,  eg,  Belfast  City  Council  v  Miss  Behavin'  Ltd  [2007]  UKHL  19,  [2007]  1  WLR  1420  at  [37],  per  Baroness  Hale.    38  Op  cit  n  36  at  [34].    39  Ibid.    40  Ibid  at  [68].    41  The  argument  was  that  allowing  the  wearing  of  certain  strict  forms  of  Muslim  dress  would  be  divisive;   it  might,   as   Lord   Bingham   put   it   at   [18],   lead   to   ‘undesirable   differentiation   between  Muslim  groups  according  to  the  strictness  of  their  views’  with  adverse  consequences  in  terms  of  inclusion  and  social  cohesion.    42  This  part  of  Lord  Hoffmann’s  speech  is  also  problematic  because  it  is  not  entirely  clear  whether  he  is  discussing  necessity,  narrow  proportionality  or  both  questions.    

Elliott,  ‘Proportionality  and  deference:  the  importance  of  a  structured  approach’       9  

There   might   be—indeed   it   is   argued   below   that   there   is—a   case   for   relaxing   the  standard  of  review  in  certain  circumstances  so  as  to  recognise  the  superior  democratic  legitimacy   of   the   decision-­‐maker.   But   if   this   different   form   of   deference   is   to   be  exhibited,   it   is   incumbent   upon   the   court   to   say   so—and   to   make   it   clear,   as   Lord  Hoffmann  failed  to  do,  that  it  has  nothing  whatever  to  do  with  the  expertise,  as  distinct  from  the  democratic  credentials,  of  the  decision-­‐maker.    

Fourthly,  discussion  of  deference  on  grounds  of  expertise  usually  focuses  exclusively  on  the   relative   institutional   competence  of   the   court   and   the  decision-­‐maker.   It   is   clearly  arguable   that—as   in   the   AP   case,43   discussed   above—courts   should   attach   particular  weight   to   the   views   of   decision-­‐makers   who   are   better-­‐situated   to   determine   how   a  given  objective  can  most  efficiently  be  achieved  with  respect  to  the  cost  in  human  rights  terms.   However,   once  we   recognise   that   the   basis   on  which   deference   is   exhibited   in  relation   to   the   necessity   question   is   relative   expertise—rather   than,   say,   the   superior  democratic   credentials   of   the   decision-­‐maker—it   becomes   apparent   that   public  authority   defendants   cannot   legitimately   occupy   a   uniquely   privileged   position   in   this  regard.   If   another   party   to   the   proceedings   has   great   expertise,   and   argues   that   some  other,   less  restrictive  measures  would  have  been  equally  effective   in  terms  of  securing  the  government’s  objective,   it   is   surely   incumbent  upon   the  court   to  ascribe  weight   to  that   view   just   as   it   would   ascribe   weight   to   the   view   of   an   expert   public   authority  defendant.   This   is   true   whether   the   non-­‐defendant   expert   is   the   claimant   or   an  intervening   party—and   it   is   important   to   recognise   that   the   chances   of   such   expert  parties  being  before  the  court  are  greater  now  than  ever,  given  the  propensity  of  English  courts   to  confer  standing  upon  expert  groups  on  public   interest  grounds,  and   to  allow  intervention   by   third   parties   whose   expertise   means   that   they   are   likely   to   make   a  useful   contribution   to   the   proceedings.44   The   crucial   point   is   that   to   the   extent   that  deference   in   relation   to   the   necessity   question   is   motivated   by   the   decision-­‐maker’s  superior   expertise   rather   than   by   its   superior   democratic   legitimacy,   the   argument   is  equally  applicable  to  expert  defendants  and  interveners.    

Fifthly,   this   leads  on  to  the  point   that  not  everyone  agrees  that  deference  on  grounds  of  relative  expertise  is  an  appropriate  judicial  response.45  Other  responses  are  possible,  and  these   may   well   include   the   court   taking   steps   to   equip   itself   better   to   evaluate  arguments   about   the   likely   efficacy   of   measures   of   varying   levels   of   restrictiveness,  rather   than   simply   adopting—or   at   least   ascribing   considerable   weight   to—the  decision-­‐maker’s   expert   view.   Such   steps   might,   of   course,   include   courts   facilitating  intervention  by  third  parties  in  order  to  render  the  court  better-­‐informed  and  therefore  more   able   to   assess   the   parties’   arguments   about   rival   methods   of   securing   a   given  legitimate  objective.    

Sixthly,  and  finally,  the  scope  for  rigorous  review  of  a  decision-­‐maker’s  judgment  that  it  is   necessary   to   take   certain   rights-­‐infringing   steps   in   order   to   secure   a   particular  objective   is   likely   to   depend   on   the   terms   in   which   the   objective   is   cast.   Where   an  objective   is   formulated   in   precise   terms—for   example,   where   a   decision-­‐maker  contends   that   it   is   necessary   to   ban   rather   than   merely   regulate   a   particular   annual  march  which  in  the  past  has  ended  in  serious  violence  in  order  to  ensure  the  reasonable  

                                                                                                                         43  Op  cit  n  30.    44  See  Harlow,  ‘Public  Law  and  Popular  Justice’  (2002)  65  MLR  1.    45  See,  eg,  Allison,  ‘Fuller’s  Analysis  of  Polycentric  Disputes  and  the  Limits  of  Adjudication’  [1994]  CLJ  367  at  382-­‐3;  Hunt,   ‘Sovereignty’s  Blight:  Why  Contemporary  Public  Law  needs  the  concept  of   “Due  Deference”’   in   Bamforth   and   Leyland   (eds),  Public   Law   in   a  Multi-­‐Layered   Constitution  (Oxford,  Hart:  2003)  at  350.    

Elliott,  ‘Proportionality  and  deference:  the  importance  of  a  structured  approach’       10  

safety   of   the   public—the   possibility   of   rigorous   review   arises.   The   court   would   be  entitled   to   ask   for   historical   evidence   tending   to   show   the   inadequacy   of   regulation  (what  measures  short  of  prohibition  have  been  taken  in  the  past,  and  why  did  they  fail?)  and   for   contemporary   evidence   of   the   same   (is   there   evidence   that   trouble-­‐makers  intend   to   ferment  violence  on  such  a  scale   this  year   that  prohibition   is   the  only  viable  option?)  However,  the  position  is  likely  to  be  different  if  the  objective  is  very  vague.  For  example,  the  AP  case,  considered  above,46  concerned  a  power  the  statutorily-­‐prescribed  objective   of   whose   exercise   was   ‘protecting   members   of   the   public   from   a   risk   of  terrorism’.47  The  very  wide  definition  of  terrorism48  combined  with  the  absence  of  any  requirement   that   the   risk   must   be   of   a   given   level   of   seriousness   means   that   the  objective   is   largely   open-­‐ended:   it   will   be   relatively   easy   for   the   decision-­‐maker   to  establish  that  more  severe  restrictions  are  necessary  in  the  sense  that  they  are  likely  to  involve   a   small   reduction   in   the   risk   posed   by   the   individual   concerned.   Where   the  objective   is   presented   merely   in   terms   of   reducing   a   risk,   rather   than,   say,   bringing  about  or  preventing  a  particular  state  of  affairs,  any  measure  will  be  necessary  if  it  goes  further  in  reducing  the  risk—even  if  it  is  so  draconian  that  it  would  have  overshot  if  the  objective  had  been  stated  in  more  precise  terms.49    

It   is   important,   however,   to   recognise   that   the   absence   of   intense   review   of   necessity  where  the  objective  is  vague  does  not  imply  deference.  The  court  is  not  ascribing  special  weight  to  the  decision-­‐maker’s  view  of  what  needs  to  be  done  if  the  desired  outcome  is  to  be  achieved:  rather,  the  ease  with  which  the  necessity  requirement  can  be  satisfied  in  such   circumstances   is   simply   a   function   of   the   breadth   of   the   terms   in   which   the  objective   is  cast.  This  begs  the  question  whether  decision-­‐makers  should  be  permitted  to   define   objectives   so   broadly   as   to   render   the   necessity   stage   of   the   proportionality  test   largely  nugatory.50  For  example,   if  a  decision-­‐maker  were  to  adopt  as   its  objective  ‘the  promotion  of   the  public   good’,   this  would  allow   it   to  establish   the  necessity  of   an  extremely   broad   range   of  measures,   thereby   circumventing   the   necessity   stage   of   the  proportionality  test.  Clearly,  courts  should  not  allow  decision-­‐makers  to  conceal  a  real,  more   specific   objective   behind   the   smokescreen   of   a   general   objective   designed   to  preclude   meaningful   scrutiny   of   a   measure’s   necessity.   In   applying   the   doctrine   of  proper  purposes,  courts  are  perfectly  willing  to  determine  whether  a  stated   legitimate  objective   is   the   true   (and   dominant)   one,51   and   there   is   no   reason   why   the   same  approach  should  not  be  adopted  here.  If,  on  such  an  analysis,  the  objective  is  genuinely  very   general,   then   although,   as   noted   above,   this  will   render   necessity   review   largely  meaningless,  it  is  important  to  recognise  that  this  is  not  determinative  of  the  legality  of  the  measure   in   question.   First,   the   objective—however   general—must   be   a   legitimate                                                                                                                            46  Op  cit  n  30.    47  Op  cit  n  32.    48  Terrorism  Act  2000,  s  1.    49   Of   course,   even   if   the  measure   is,   on   such   an   analysis,   necessary,   it   does   not   automatically  follow  that  it  is  lawful:  it  may  well  be  disproportionate  in  the  narrow  sense.    50  A  distinct  but  related  question  is  whether  the  decision-­‐maker  should  be  permitted  to  cast   its  objective  in  a  way  that  is  determinative  of  the  necessity  question.  For  example,  Rivers,  op  cit  n  34  at  188,  notes   the  possibility   (with  reference   to   the  Belmarsh  case,  op  cit  n  15)  of   the  executive  adopting   as   its   objective   ‘protecting   the   British   people   from   the   risk   of   catastrophic   Al-­‐Qaeda  terrorism  by  giving   the  Home  Secretary   the  power   to  detain   foreign   terrorist   suspects  without  trial’.  The  only  way,  of  course,  of  realising  such  an  objective  is  to  give  the  Home  Secretary  such  powers:  judicial  scrutiny  of  the  necessity  of  such  a  step  can  play  no  meaningful  role.  The  better  view,   it   is   submitted,   is   that   courts   must   prevent   decision-­‐makers   from   evading   review   of  necessity  by  refusing  to  allow  objectives  to  be  defined  in  terms  which  include  the  methodology  by  which  their  fulfilment  is  to  be  secured.    51  R  v  Governor  of  Brixton  Prison,  ex  parte  Soblen  [1963]  2  QB  243  at  302,  per  Lord  Denning  MR.  

Elliott,  ‘Proportionality  and  deference:  the  importance  of  a  structured  approach’       11  

one.  And,  secondly,  even   if  a  very  general  objective   is  deemed   lawful  and  the  measure  necessary,  the  decision-­‐maker  will  still  have  to  satisfy  the  court  that  it  is  proportionate  in  the  narrow  sense:  at  this  stage,  the  generality  of  the  objective  is  irrelevant,  since  the  question  is  simply  whether  the  specific  gains  which  the  measure  entails  are  sufficient  to  justify  whatever  losses  (in  terms  of  prejudice  to  human  rights  or  other  highly-­‐regarded  interests)  it  occasions.    

Legitimacy-­‐based  deference  

The   sort   of   deference   thus   far   considered   is   motivated   by   entirely   practical  considerations.   The   question   for   the   court   is   whether   the   measure   adopted   by   the  decision-­‐maker   represents   the   least   restrictive   way   of   achieving   its   objective.   If   the  court  can  make  that  assessment  unaided,  then  it  will  do  so;  if  it  cannot,  then  it  will  attach  weight  to  the  decision-­‐maker’s  (or  another  party’s)  opinion  in  the  course  of  arriving  at  a  view  about  whether  the  measure  is  necessary.  It  was  noted  above  that  deference  can  be  effected  either  by  diluting  the  question  the  court  asks  or  by  the  court  attaching  weight  to  others’  views    when  it  is  trying  to  work  out  the  answer  to  whatever  the  question  is.  It  is  important   to   note   that   the   sort   of   expertise-­‐based,   practically-­‐motivated   deference  considered   thus   far  can  only  properly   take  effect   in   the   latter  way.  Our  analysis   so   far  indicates   no   normative   reason   for   diluting   the   requirement   that   the   objective   be  pursued   in   the   manner   least   restrictive   of   the   right   in   question:   the   court’s   relative  institutional   incompetence  merely  ordains   that   it  may  be  appropriate   for   the   court,   in  attempting   to  determine  whether   that  requirement  has  been  met,   to  ascribe  weight   to  others’  expert  views.    

In  contrast,  deference  on  grounds  of  democratic  legitimacy  is  underpinned  by  normative  considerations:   such   deference   is   exhibited   because   the   court   takes   the   view   that,   in  relation   to   certain   questions,   the   decision-­‐maker   should   enjoy   a   degree   of   latitude   on  account  of  its  superior  democratic  credentials.  So  whereas  expertise-­‐based  deference  is  a  necessary  evil,  or   is  at   least  adopted  for  negative  reasons  based  on  the  limitations  of  the   court,   legitimacy-­‐based   deference   is   exhibited   (say   its   proponents)   because   it   is  normatively   right   that   the   decision-­‐maker   should,   in   certain   circumstances,   enjoy   a  degree  of  discretion.    

Two   questions   arise.   First,   is   legitimacy-­‐based   deference   ever   appropriate?   And,  secondly,   if   it   is,   at  what   stage  or   stages  within   the  proportionality   test  does   it  have  a  role   to   play   and   by   what   doctrinal   means   should   it   take   effect?   The   focus   of   the  remainder   of   this   paper,   in   line   with   its   central   objective   of   clarifying   the   doctrinal  structure   within   which   proportionality   review   should   be   undertaken   and   deference  exhibited,  is  on  the  second  of  those  questions—although,  in  the  course  of  addressing  it,  the   first   question,   which   has   been   explored   extensively   elsewhere,52  must   at   least   be  sketched.    

Prima  facie,  expertise-­‐  and  legitimacy-­‐based  deference  are  relevant  to  distinct  aspects  of  the  proportionality  test.  The  former,  as  we  have  already  seen,  clearly  has  a  role  to  play  in  relation  to  the  necessity  question.  In  contrast,  the  latter  is  more  obviously  relevant  at  the  narrow  proportionality  stage.  Whereas  there  is  an  objectively  correct  answer  to  the  necessity   question   (even   though   it   might   be   beyond   the   court’s—and   perhaps  anybody’s—expertise   to   identify   it),   the   same   is   not   obviously   true   of   the   question  whether   it   is  worth  sacrificing  a  given  amount  of  rights   in  order  to  secure  a  particular                                                                                                                            52   See,   inter  alios,  Hunt,  op  cit  n  45;   Jowell,   ‘Judicial  Deference:   servility,   civility  or   institutional  capacity?’  [2003]  PL  592.    

Elliott,  ‘Proportionality  and  deference:  the  importance  of  a  structured  approach’       12  

public  policy  gain.  This  necessarily  turns  on  the  value  which  is  ascribed  to  the  two  sets  of  variables  which  fall  to  be  weighed  against  one  another,  and  it  is  at  least  arguable  that  democratically-­‐accountable  decision-­‐makers   should  be  accorded  not  carte  blanche  but  some   latitude   in  deciding  upon   the   relative   importance  of   a   given   loss   of   rights   and   a  given  public  policy  gain.    

Legitimacy-­‐based  deference  at  the  necessity  stage?    

This   analysis   implies   a   straightforward   schema   as   far   as   deference   is   concerned:  expertise-­‐based  deference  is  relevant  to  the  necessity  question,  while  legitimacy-­‐based  deference   is   relevant   at   the   narrow   proportionality   stage.53   However,   the   position   is  actually  more   complex.   As  Maurice   Kay   J   pointed   out   in   Clays   Lane,   if   a   test   of   strict  necessity  inevitably  compels  adoption  of  the  least  restrictive  measure,  this  may  require  the  taking  of  decisions  which  are  ‘distinctly  second  best  or  worse’:  ‘A  decision  which  was  fraught  with  adverse  consequences  would  have  to  prevail  because  it  was,  perhaps  quite  marginally,   the  least   intrusive.’54  This  dictum  recognises  that  while  the   least  restrictive  measure   will   be   the  most   efficient   way   of   trading   off   the   right   against   the   legitimate  objective,   it  may  represent  a  suboptimal  solution  if  broader  public  policy  considerations  are  taken  into  account.  The  least  restrictive  measure  may  entail  negative  consequences  in  relation  to  interests—financial,  administrative,  environmental,  and  so  on—which  do  not   constitute   legitimate   objectives   capable   of   forming   the   primary   justification   for  limitation  of  the  right,  but  which  are  nevertheless  important.  Should  the  decision-­‐maker  be   allowed   to   trade   the   right   off   against   not   just   the   legitimate   objective   but   against  these  wider  considerations  too  by,  for  instance,  preferring  a  marginally  more  restrictive  measure  which  avoids   inflicting   the  serious  damage  to  broader   interests   that   the   least  restrictive  measure  would  have  caused?    

The   courts’   answer   to   this   question   is   in   the   affirmative,   but   the   doctrinal   means   by  which  decision-­‐makers  are  allowed  to  behave  in  this  way  are  far  from  clear.  A  common  judicial   technique   in   such   circumstances   is   dilution   of   the   necessity   requirement   by  requiring   the   decision-­‐maker   to   demonstrate   that   its   chosen   measure   is   reasonably,  rather   than   strictly,   necessary,   the   thinking   (apparently)   being   that   legitimacy-­‐based  deference   is   appropriate   because   the   decision-­‐maker   ought   to   have   some   latitude   to  decide   how   to   balance   the   right   against   a   broader   range   of   conflicting   policy  considerations.   For   example,   in  Handyside   v   UK,   the   ECtHR   stated   (with   reference   to  Article   10(2)   ECHR)   that   the   word   ‘necessary’   was   ‘not   synonymous   with  'indispensable’,   albeit   that   it   could   not   be   stretched   so   far   as   to   mean   merely  ‘reasonable’  or  ‘desirable’.55  The  concept  of  reasonable,  as  distinct  from  strict,  necessity  appears   to   be   helpful,   in   that   it   makes   it   possible   for   non-­‐minimally   but   not  unreasonably   restrictive  measures   to   be   chosen   so   as   to   facilitate   triangulation   of   the  right,  the  legitimate  objective  and  wider  public  policy  considerations.    

However,   further   reflection   indicates   that   the   notion   of   reasonable   necessity   is  problematic.   Although   it   is   used   to   facilitate   deference,   the   concept   actually   serves   to  obscure  the  subject-­‐matter  and  nature  of  such  deference.  As  argued  above,  necessity  is  about   the   efficiency   of  means:   is   this  measure   the  most   efficient  way,  with   respect   to  human   rights,   of   realising   the  decision-­‐maker’s   objective?   It   follows,   as  we  have   seen,  that  deference   in  relation  to  the  necessity  question   is  exhibited  (to  the  extent  that  any  deference   is   appropriate)   on   grounds   of   relative   expertise.   Yet   the   agenda   behind                                                                                                                            53  Cf  Rivers,  op  cit  n  34.      54  Op  cit  n  16  at  [25].    55  (1979-­‐80)  1  EHRR  737  at  [48].    

Elliott,  ‘Proportionality  and  deference:  the  importance  of  a  structured  approach’       13  

substituting  a  requirement  of  strict  necessity  with  one  of  reasonable  necessity  is  to  free  the   decision-­‐maker   to   trade   the   right   off   against   other   objectives,   allowing   it,   for  example,  to  adopt  means  which  are  more  restrictive  of  the  right  than  are  necessary  for  the  achievement  of  the  primary  legitimate  objective  so  as  to  enable  the  pursuit  of  wider  public  policy  aim  which  adoption  of   the   least   restrictive  means  may  unduly  prejudice.  This  is  ultimately  about  giving  the  decision-­‐maker  latitude  not  over  the  means  by  which  it  achieves   its  objective,   but  over   the  objectives  which   it   is  allowed   to  pursue   in   the   first  place.   The   difficulty   is   that   the   necessity   question   is   not   designed   to   assess   the  legitimacy   of   objectives—it   is   intended   to   assess   the   efficiency   of   means.   To   adopt   a  criterion  of   reasonable  necessity   is   therefore   to   conflate   the   concept  of  necessity  with  the   logically   prior   question  whether   the   factors   the   decision-­‐maker   seeks   to   trade   off  against   the   right   carry   sufficient   legitimacy   as   to   be   capable,   in   principle,   of   justifying  restriction  of  the  right,  and  the  logically  subsequent  question  whether  those  factors  are  actually   capable,   within   the   factual   matrix   of   the   case,   of   justifying   the   specific  infringement.  This  blurring  of  the  boundaries  between  the  different  stages  of  the  test  is  antithetical   to   the   structured   approach   to   proportionality   advocated   in   this   paper;   it  seeks  to  inject  deference  into  the  review  process  by  conferring  latitude  on  the  decision-­‐maker,   but   does   so   in   a   way   that   lacks   both   doctrinal   coherence   and   analytical  transparency;  and  it  confuses  the  kind  of  deference  (on  expertise-­‐based  grounds)  which  is  relevant  to  the  necessity  inquiry  with  the  kind  of  deference  (on  democratic  legitimacy  grounds)  which  is  relevant  to  the  choice  of  objectives  which  the  decision-­‐maker  wishes  to   pursue.   This   demonstrates   the   symbiotic   nature   of   the   relationship   between   the  structure  of  the  proportionality  test  and  the  doctrine  of  deference:  a  coherent  version  of  the  latter  is  impossible  if  the  former  is  not  taken  seriously.56  

It   follows   that   if  a  decision-­‐maker  wishes   to  attempt   to   justify  a  measure  which   is  not  the  least  restrictive  on  the  ground  that  it  represents  a  better  trade-­‐off  between  the  right  and  broad  public   policy   considerations,   its   argument  must   be   scrutinised   at   the   three  relevant  stages  of  the  proportionality  analysis.    

First,   although,   by   definition,   wider   policy   considerations   (eg   saving   money)   are   not  primary   legitimate   objectives   (eg   promoting   public   safety)   capable,   in   and   of  themselves,  of  justifying  restriction  of  rights,  it  is  clear  that  there  must  be  some  scrutiny  of  the  legitimacy  of  such  considerations.  Such  scrutiny  can  most  naturally  be  undertaken  alongside   scrutiny   of   the   legitimacy   of   the   decision-­‐maker’s   primary   objective.57  Whether  or  not  the  court  regards  a  secondary  set  of  policy  considerations  as  legitimate  will   turn  upon  the  sort  of  analysis  which  courts  deploy   in  order  to  determine  whether  the   decision-­‐maker   is   taking   into   account   relevant   (and   disregarding   irrelevant)  considerations.  In  this  way,  the  court  recognises  that,  on  democratic  legitimacy  grounds,  it   is   right   that   the   decision-­‐maker   has   a   degree   of   latitude   over   which   objectives   it  pursues,  albeit  that  such  latitude  is  bounded  by  the  terms  of  the  enabling  legislation  and  is  not  therefore  unlimited.    

                                                                                                                         56  Similar  difficulties  are  evident  in  the  case  law  of  the  ECtHR.  Eg  in  Brannigan  v  United  Kingdom  (1994)   17   EHRR   539   at   590,   Judge   Martens,   in   his   concurring   opinion,   suggested   that   the  requirement  in  Article  15  ECHR  that  the  measure  must  be  ‘strictly  required  by  the  exigencies  of  the  situation’calls  for  a  closer  scrutiny  than  the  words  “necessary  in  a  democratic  society”  which  appear   in   the   second  paragraphs   of  Articles   8–11’.   This   statement   is   based  on   the   assumption  that   there   are   degrees   of   necessity.   For   the   reasons   advanced   above,   it   is   submitted   that   this  notion  is  misconceived,  and  reflects  the  ECtHR’s  general  failure  (see  n  17  above  and  text  thereto)    to  distinguish  adequately  between  the  different  stages  of  the  proportionality  test.    57  Ie  stage  (ii)  within  the  scheme  set  out  above  at  p  1.    

Elliott,  ‘Proportionality  and  deference:  the  importance  of  a  structured  approach’       14  

Secondly,   at   the   necessity   stage,58   the   court   will   have   to   ask   whether   the   decision-­‐maker’s   chosen  measure   is   the  most   efficient  way   of   achieving   its   primary   legitimate  objective  while   also   realising   any   secondary   aims   that  withstood   scrutiny   at   the  prior  legitimacy  stage  of  the  analysis.  Since  the  necessity  analysis  is  concerned  solely  with  the  efficiency  of  means,  there  is  no  role  for  deference  on  anything  except  expertise  grounds;  and,   for   reasons   advanced   above,   the   question   must   be   whether   the   measures   are  strictly   necessary,   not   reasonably   necessary.   Importantly,   however,   if   wider  considerations  are  allowed  to  form  part  of  the  objective  against  which  the  necessity  of  the  measure   fall   to   be   tested,   it  may   survive   scrutiny   at   the   necessity   stage   even   if   it  would  have  failed  to  do  so  had  the  objective  been  cast  more  restrictively.    

Thirdly,  an  obvious  objection  to  the  foregoing  is  that  it  significantly  enhances  decision-­‐makers’   capacity   to   override   human   rights   by   allowing   legitimate   objectives   to   be  supplemented  by  wider  policy  concerns,  thereby  subjugating  rights  to  considerations  of  expediency  to  an  unacceptable  degree.  However,  even  if  the  court  concludes  that  taking  certain  wider   policy   interests   into   account   is   legitimate  and   that   the   decision-­‐maker’s  chosen   measure   is   the   most   efficient   way   of   realising   the   primary   objective   while  pursuing   those   wider   interests   (notwithstanding   that   it   restricts   the   right   more   than  would   be   necessary   if   the   primary   objective   alone   was   to   be   pursued),   this   merely  establishes  the  potential  lawfulness  of  the  measure.  Whether  or  not  it  is  actually  lawful  will   depend   on   the   court’s   decision   at   the   final,   narrow   proportionality   stage   of   the  analysis.59  Here,   the  court  must  examine  the   loss   to  human  rights  and  the  gains  which  flow   from   achieving   the   legitimate   objective   and   any   other   legitimate   policy   aims.   In  doing  so,  the  court  will  obviously  have  to  take  account  of  the  relative  weight  which  each  of   these   considerations   should   carry—and   the  distinction  between  primary   legitimate  objectives  and  wider  policy  considerations  is  very  likely  to  be  reflected  in  the  ascription  of  far  greater  weight  to  the  former  than  to  the  latter.  It  follows  that  while,  for  example,  financial   considerations   might   be   judged   to   be   relevant   matters   which   the   decision-­‐maker   can   legitimately   take   into   account,   relatively   little  weight  might   be   attached   to  them   at   the   balancing   stage.   So  while   substantial   financial   savings  may   justify   a   very  slightly  more  restrictive  measure,  a  significantly  more  restrictive  measure  is  unlikely  to  be  justified  by  financial  savings.    

In  conclusion  on  this  point,   it   is  submitted  that  courts  are  right  to  recognise  that  there  may  be  circumstances  in  which  the  decision-­‐maker  should  have  some  latitude  to  trade  qualified   rights   off   against   wider   policy   concerns   (not   just   primary   legitimate  objectives).  However,   for   the   reasons   advanced   above,   it   is   only  possible   to  develop   a  coherent  doctrinal  structure  within  which  courts  may  test  the  legality  of  such  decisions  if   proper   reliance   is   placed   on   each   of   the   relevant   parts   of   the   proportionality   test,  rather   than   relying   on   the   notion   of   deference   in   order   to   transform   the   necessity  question  into  one  which  is  ultimately  meaningless.    

Legitimacy-­‐based  deference  at  the  narrow  proportionality  stage  

Finally,  it  is  necessary  to  address  the  question  of  the  role  of  legitimacy-­‐based  deference  at   the   narrow   proportionality   stage   of   the   court’s   inquiry.  Whether   such   deference   is  ever   appropriate   has  been  discussed   at   length   elsewhere;60   the   focus  here   is   on  more  technical  questions  relating  to  the  stage  at  and  the  way  in  which  such  deference  might  take  effect.                                                                                                                            58  Ie  stage  (iv).    59  Ie  stage  (v).    60  Op  cit  n  52.    

Elliott,  ‘Proportionality  and  deference:  the  importance  of  a  structured  approach’       15  

At  the  beginning  of  this  paper,  it  was  suggested  that  the  proportionality  test  can  best  be  thought   of   in   terms   of   five   questions.   The   first,   third   and   fourth   questions—which  respectively  ask  whether  the  measure  infringes  a  highly-­‐regarded  interest,  is  capable  of  securing   a   given   objective   and   is   necessary—are  questions   of   fact.  We   have   seen   that  deference   in   relation   to   factual   questions—most   pertinently   the   necessity   question—may   be   appropriate   on   grounds   of   expertise.   This   is   motivated   by   purely   practical  concerns.  There  is  no  normative  reason  why  the  court  should  not,  when  equipped  to  do  so,   decide   for   itself   whether   the   decision-­‐maker’s   preferred   measure   is   the   least  restrictive;  deference  to  others’  views  is  only  exhibited  on  this  point  where  the  court  is  unable,  because  of  its  lack  of  expertise,  to  reach  a  judgment  unaided.  

In   contrast,   the   other   two   questions—whether   the  measure   pursues   a   legitimate   aim  and   strikes   an   acceptable   balance   between  human   rights   and   competing  public   policy  interests—call  for  value-­‐judgments.  Whereas,  for  instance,  whether  the  decision-­‐maker’s  chosen  measure  is  (in  human  rights  terms)  the  most  efficient  way  of  realising  its  aim  is  a  factual   question   with   a   right   answer,   there   is   no   objectively   correct   answer   to   the  question  whether  the  gains  that  result  from  securing  that  aim  are  sufficient  to  justify  the  corresponding  human  rights  loss.  The  latter  question  is  normative,  not  factual,  in  nature,  and   one’s   answer   to   it   will   necessarily   depend   upon   a   whole   series   of   underlying  assumptions  about   the  relative   importance  of   the  right  and  of  competing  public  policy  interests.   The   question   arises   whether   the   court’s   view   of   such   matters   should  necessarily  prevail,  or  whether  some   form  of   legitimacy-­‐based  deference—recognising  that   other   constitutional   branches’   views   may   be   deserving   of   respect   in   light,   for  example,  of  their  democratic  credentials—might  be  appropriate.    

Some  commentators  have  argued  that,  in  the  UK,  the  enactment  of  the  Human  Rights  Act  1998   means   that   no   such   deference   should   be   exhibited.   Jowell   has   contended   that  reviewing  courts  should  not   ‘prefer  the  authority  of  Parliament  or  other  bodies  on  the  ground   alone   that   they   represent   the   popular   will,   or   are   directly   or   indirectly  accountable  to  the  electorate’,61  while  Lord  Bingham,  pointing  out  that  the  Act  ‘gives  the  courts   a   very   specific,   wholly   democratic,   mandate’   to   review   on   proportionality  grounds,   was   at   least   sceptical   about   the   appropriateness   of   legitimacy-­‐based  deference.62  However,  many  cases  do  reveal  evidence  of  judges’  willingness  to  defer  on  such   grounds.63   Such   deference,   it   is   submitted,   is,   in   certain   circumstances,   entirely  appropriate.  Reasonable  minds  will  differ  as  to  what  represents  an  acceptable  trade-­‐off  between   individual   rights   and   wider   public   policy   interests,   and   there   is   no   a   priori  reason   why   judges   should   always   have   the   final   word.   However,   the   proper   role   of  deference  in  relation  to  the  narrow  proportionality  analysis  can  only  be  understood  by  reference  to  the  specific  and  distinct  tasks  which  courts  must  perform  in  that  sphere.    

The  first  matter  that  must  be  confronted  is  the  impact  of  the  measure:  what  is  the  scale  of  the  human  rights  loss  which  it  entails?  And  what  is  the  scale  of  the  public  policy  gain  resulting   from   the  measure?  These   are   questions   of   fact,   and   it   therefore   follows   that  expertise-­‐based  deference  may  be  relevant  here:  the  court  may  need  to  rely  on  others’                                                                                                                            61  Op  cit  n  52  at  597.    62  Op  cit  n  15  at  [42].    63   See,  eg,   R   (Prolife  Alliance)   v  British  Broadcasting  Corporation   [2003]  UKHL  23;   [2004]  1  AC  185  at  [76];  R  (Farrakhan)  v  Secretary  of  State  for  the  Home  Department   [2002]  EWCA  Civ  606;  [2002]  QB  1391  at  [74];  R  (Animal  Defenders  International)  v  Secretary  of  State  for  Culture,  Media  and  Sport  [2008]  UKHL  15  [2008]  2  WLR  781  at  [33];    Secretary  of  State  for  the  Home  Department  v  Rehman  [2001]  UKHL  47  [2003]  1  AC  153  at  [62];  R  (Alconbury  Ltd)  v  Secretary  of  State  for  the  Environment  [2001]  UKHL  23  [2003]  2  AC  295  at  [60],  [159];  Kay  v  Lambeth  LBC  [2006]  UKHL  10  [2006]  2  AC  465  at  [53].    

Elliott,  ‘Proportionality  and  deference:  the  importance  of  a  structured  approach’       16  

expertise  in  order  to  arrive  at  a  view  as  to  what  the  impact  of  the  measure  will  be.  The  scale  of  such  deference  will  depend  upon  the  extent  to  which  the  court,  relative  to  the  decision-­‐maker   or   other   parties,   is   under   institutional   inhibitions   which   affect   its  capacity  to  determine  the  measure’s  impacts  on  individual  rights  and  public  interests.    

Secondly,  value  must  be  ascribed  to  the  gains  and   losses.  Working  out  that  the  measure  produces  particular  public  policy  gains  on  the  one  hand  and  human  rights  losses  on  the  other  is  one  thing;  but  if  a  decision  is  to  be  made  about  whether  the  former  outweigh  the  latter,   some   sort   of   value   must   be   ascribed   to   them   first,   in   order   that   they   may   be  compared.  Thirdly,  a  decision  must  be  taken  about  whether  the  gains  outweigh  the  losses.  This   is,  prima   facie,  a  simple  matter  which  turns  on  whether   the  value  assigned  to   the  gains   at   the   previous   stage   of   the   analysis   is   greater   than   that   assigned   to   the   losses.  However,   the   relationship   between   the   second   and   third   stages   requires   further  consideration.  The   schema   suggested  above   implies   that   it   is,   in   effect,   possible   at   the  second  stage  to  assign  specific  (eg  numerical)  values  to  the  gains  and  the  losses  within  a  single   scale,   so   that   the   third   stage   reduces   to   asking   which   value   is   the   greater.  However,   it   is   obvious   that   assigning   value   to   the   gains   and   losses   is   a   far   from  straightforward  matter.  The  two  sets  of  factors  in  play—human  rights  on  the  one  hand,  the   public   interest   on   the   other—are   not   readily   commensurable.64   Rendering   them  commensurable   in   order   that   they  may  be   compared   at   the   third   stage   of   the   narrow  proportionality   analysis   necessarily   entails   a   value-­‐judgment:   it   requires   a   view   to   be  taken   about   the   relative   importance   of   the   right   (or,   more   specifically,   about   the  importance  of  the  particular  exercise65  of  the  right   in  question)  and  the  public   interest  which  its  limitation  secures.  There  are  two  (alternative)  ways  in  which  legitimacy-­‐based  deference  might  blunt  judicial  review  in  this  regard.    

On  the  one  hand,  the  court  may  insist  on  deciding  the  respective  values  to  be  ascribed  to  the  human  rights  loss  and  the  public  policy  gain,  but  may  then  avoid  full  substitution  of  judgment   where   appropriate   by   applying   a   more   relaxed   standard   of   review:   rather  than  insisting  that  the  measure  must  not  inflict  losses  which  are  greater  than  the  gains  it  purchases,   the   court   may   require   only   that   the   losses   do   not   exceed   the   gains   to   an  unacceptable   degree—‘reasonable   proportionality’   rather   than   ‘strict   proportionality’.    The  bounds  of  acceptability  would  reflect  the  court’s  view  of  the  appropriate  extent  of  the  discretion  which  the  decision-­‐maker  should  enjoy  in  the  circumstances.    

On  the  other  hand,  the  court  may  concede  latitude  to  the  decision-­‐maker  in  relation  to  the   ascription   of   value   to   the   gain   and   loss.   This  would   not   (in   contrast   to   expertise-­‐based  deference)  amount  to  the  court  attaching  weight  to  the  decision-­‐maker’s  view  in  the  course  of  coming  to  its  own  view  about  the  matter  at  hand;  since  the  whole  point  of  legitimacy-­‐based  deference  is  that  the  court  accepts  that  its  view  should  not  necessarily  prevail,   the   process   is   better   conceptualised   in   terms   of   the   court   permitting   the  decision-­‐maker  to  ascribe  any  value  to  the  gains  and  losses  within  a  judicially-­‐controlled  range.  This   reflects   the   fact   that  whereas  expertise-­‐based  deference   is  about   the  court  relying  on  others’  views  in  order  that  it  may  arrive  at  the  right  answer,  legitimacy-­‐based  deference   is   about   carving   out   a   sphere   of   administrative   or   legislative   discretion  because  there  is  no  right  answer  (or  at  least  no  demonstrably  right  answer).    

Although   it   perhaps   makes   little   practical   difference,   it   is   submitted   that   the   latter  approach   is,   for   the   following   reason,   to   be   preferred.   There   is   per   se   no   normative  reason  why  courts  should  allow  decisions  to  stand  which  inflict  human  rights  losses  that  

                                                                                                                         64  Cf  Rivers,  op  cit  n  34.    65  See  the  example  given  below  at  text  to  n  68.    

Elliott,  ‘Proportionality  and  deference:  the  importance  of  a  structured  approach’       17  

are   not   outweighed   by   public   policy   gains.   In   truth,   the   argument   against   judicial  enforcement  of  a  strict  rule  prohibiting  measures  where  the  losses  outweigh  the  gains  is  based   on   the   fact   that   reasonable   minds   might   differ   about   the   value   that   should   be  ascribed   to   those   gains   and   losses.   Arguments   based   on   democratic   legitimacy   and  separation  of  powers  theory  may  make  it  appropriate  in  some  circumstances  to  permit  the  decision-­‐maker’s  value-­‐judgments  to  stand  even  if  they  are  not  the  same  as  the  ones  the  court  would  have  formed  had  it  been  charged  with  making  the  decision.  Recognising  that   it   is  on  the  ascription  of  value  to  human  rights   losses  and  public  policy  gains   that  legitimacy-­‐based   deference   bites   is   therefore   helpful   because   it   pinpoints   not   just   the  precise  issue  upon  which  decision-­‐makers  are  allowed  a  degree  of  latitude  but  also  the  underlying  rationale.    

This  is  not,  however,  to  suggest  that  review  on  narrow  proportionality  grounds  should  be  uniformly  deferential.  The  court  must  decide  upon  how  much  latitude  the  decision-­‐maker  should  enjoy  reference  to  factors  which  are  specific  to  the  case.  Most  obviously,  if  concerns  pertaining  to  democratic  legitimacy  form  the  rationale  for  attaching  respect  to  certain   decision-­‐makers’   views   about   the   relative   importance   of   rights   and   public  interests,  greater  respect  will  be  due  to  the  views  of  decision-­‐makers  with  particularly  strong   democratic   credentials.   This   is   why,   for   instance,   courts   are   often   willing   to  accord  a  degree  of  deference  to  judgments  made  by  Parliament  (when  determining  the  compatibility   of   primary   legislation   with   Convention   rights)66   and   by   other   decision-­‐makers,   such   as   local   authorities   and   government   ministers,   who   are   clearly  democratically  accountable  for  their  actions.67    

The  fact  remains,  however,  that  the  decision-­‐maker’s  discretion  is  bounded  by  whatever  parameters  the  court   judges  to  be  appropriate.   It   is  well-­‐recognised  that  certain  rights  carry  greater  weight  than  others.  Indeed,  one  mode  of  exercise  of  a  given  right  may  be  regarded  as  much  more  important  than  another  mode  of  exercise  of  the  same  right.  For  example,   it   is   widely   acknowledged   that   the   communication   of   political   opinions  constitutes  a  particularly  valuable  exercise  of  the  right  of  freedom  expression,68  whereas  the   dissemination   of   some   other   sorts   of   information,   such   as   pornography,     may   be  regarded  as  a  less  valuable  exercise  of  the  right.69  While  a  decision-­‐maker  with  sufficient  democratic  credentials  might  be  recognised  by  a  reviewing  court  as  enjoying  a  degree  of  latitude  in  relation  to  the  precise  value  to  be  ascribed  to  each  of  those  exercises  of  the  right,   it   is  no  part  of  the  present  argument  that  decision-­‐makers  should  enjoy  so  much  latitude   as   to   be   free   to   treat   the   two   forms   of   free   speech   as   equivalent,   thereby  undermining   freedom  of  political   speech  by   rendering   its   limitation  much  more  easily  justifiable.  By  the  same  token,  the  present  argument  should  not  be  taken  to   imply  that  decision-­‐makers  enjoy  sufficient  discretion  as  to  treat  public   interest  arguments  based  on  administrative   convenience  or   financial   considerations   as  having   the   same  value—and  so  the  same  justificatory  capacity—as  the  public  interest  in  national  security  or  the  prevention  of  crime.  The  discretion  enjoyed  by  decision-­‐makers  vis-­‐à-­‐vis   the  ascription  of  value   to  human  rights  on   the  one  hand  and  public  policy   interests  on   the  other   is  a  

                                                                                                                         66   See,   eg,  R   (Animal   Defenders   International)   v   Secretary   of   State   for   Culture,  Media   and   Sport  [2008]  UKHL  15  [2008]  2  WLR  781  at  [33].    67  See,  eg,  Farrakhan,  op  cit  n  63  at  [74].    68  See,  eg,  Castells  v  Spain  (1992)  14  EHRR  445  at  [42];  Prolife  Alliance,  op  cit  n  21  at  [37]  (CA),  per  Laws  LJ  at  [97]  (HL),  per  Lord  Scott  (dissenting).  69  See,  eg,  Miss  Behavin’,  op  cit  n  37  at  [38],  per  Baroness  Hale.    

Elliott,  ‘Proportionality  and  deference:  the  importance  of  a  structured  approach’       18  

legal  construct,  and  it  is  therefore  for  the  court  to  decide  on  the  degree  of  latitude  which  the  decision-­‐maker  may  properly  enjoy  in  any  given  case.70  

Conclusions  

The  views  advanced  in  this  paper  may  be  overly  technical  for  some  tastes.  Yet  it  is  only  by  recourse  to  the  inherently,  but  too  frequently  overlooked,71  structured  nature  of  the  proportionality  test  that  a  coherent  jurisprudence  of  substantive  review  and  deference  can   be   developed.   This   follows   because,   in   truth,   the   proportionality   doctrine   is   a  portmanteau  term  which  is  used  as  convenient  shorthand  for  a  series  of  very  different  forms  of   judicial   scrutiny  of   legislative   and  administrative   action.   It   involves   courts   in  the  making  of  factual  assessments  about  what  the  decision-­‐maker  is  genuinely  trying  to  do  and  whether   it   is   trying   to  do   it   in   the  most   efficient  way;   yet  other   aspects  of   the  doctrine   require   courts   to   engage   with   and   carry   out   oversight   of   difficult   value-­‐judgments  about  whether  particular  objectives  are  legitimate  and,  if  so,  whether  on  the  facts   they   carry   sufficient   weight   to   justify   a   given   limitation   upon   a   human   right   or  some  other  highly-­‐regarded   interest.  Any  view  of  proportionality  which  overlooks   the  radically  different   types  of   judicial  endeavour  which  collectively  comprise   this   form  of  review  is  doomed  to  failure—at  least  if  success  is  defined  in  terms  of  the  emergence  of  a  transparent   jurisprudence   which   lays   bare   the   courts’   reasoning,   provides   reliable  guidance   to   individuals   and   public   authorities   about   the   legitimate   extent   of  governmental  power,  and  furnishes  a  basis  upon  which  to  build  a  coherent  doctrine  of  deference.    

Indeed,   the   bifurcated   nature   of   the   proportionality   doctrine—in   the   sense   that   it   is  concerned   both   with   judicial   scrutiny   of   factual   issues   and   value-­‐judgments—implies  that  to  speak  of  a  single  doctrine  of  deference  is  meaningless  and  ultimately  unhelpful.72  As  we  have  seen,  in  relation  to  factual  questions,  such  as  whether  a  given  measure  is  the  least   restrictive  way  of  securing   the   legitimate  objective,   there   is  no  normative  reason  for   the  court   to  concede  discretion   to   the  decision-­‐maker;   the  purpose  of  deference   in  these   circumstances   is   therefore   not   to   open   up   such   discretion,   but   simply   to   reflect  (where   appropriate)   the   superior   expertise   of   the   decision-­‐maker.   This   is   an   entirely  different  endeavour,  in  terms  of  both  execution  and  rationale,  from  deference  in  relation  to  value-­‐judgments  such  as  whether  the  means  justify  the  end.  Here,  the  raison  d’être  of  deference  is  to  afford  latitude  to  the  decision-­‐maker  so  as  to  confer  upon  it  a  measure  of  freedom  to  choose  the  trade-­‐off  between  rights  and  policy  objectives  which  it  regards  as  most   desirable,   there   being   no   single   correct   such   trade-­‐off.   These   distinct   senses   of  deference   mirror   the   distinct   judicial   tasks   of   which   the   proportionality   doctrine   is  comprised—and  it  follows  that  a  coherent  jurisprudence  in  this  sphere  is  possible  only  if   the  courts  adopt  a  suitably  structured  approach  to  both   the  proportionality   test  and  the  notions  of  deference  which  inform  is  application.    

 

                                                                                                                         70   This   reflects   the   view   expressed   by   Lord   Hoffmann   in   Prolife   Alliance,   op   cit   n   63   at   [76].  Although  his  Lordship  indicated  his  dislike  of  the  word  ‘deference’  in  this  context  because  of  its  ‘overtones   of   servility’   (ibid   at   [75]),   his   essential   point   was   that   it   is   for   the   court   to   decide,  according  to  the  circumstances,  how  wide  or  narrow  the  decision-­‐maker’s  discretion  should  be.  He  indicated,  for  instance,  that  discretion  should  be  broader  in  relation  to  decisions  about  policy  matters  and  resource-­‐allocation.  71  At  least  by  English  courts.    72  Cf  Rivers,  op  cit  n  34  at  177,  on  the  distinction  between  ‘deference’  and  ‘restraint’.