social brains, simple minds: does social complexity really ...people.exeter.ac.uk/jfh206/abh...

16
Social Brains, Simple Minds: Does Social Complexity Really Require Cognitive Complexity? Author(s): Louise Barrett, Peter Henzi and Drew Rendall Source: Philosophical Transactions: Biological Sciences, Vol. 362, No. 1480, Social Intelligence: From Brain to Culture (Apr. 29, 2007), pp. 561-575 Published by: The Royal Society Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/20209869 . Accessed: 13/02/2014 03:57 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. . The Royal Society is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Philosophical Transactions: Biological Sciences. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 144.173.6.145 on Thu, 13 Feb 2014 03:57:51 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Upload: vonga

Post on 06-Mar-2018

223 views

Category:

Documents


1 download

TRANSCRIPT

Social Brains, Simple Minds: Does Social Complexity Really Require Cognitive Complexity?Author(s): Louise Barrett, Peter Henzi and Drew RendallSource: Philosophical Transactions: Biological Sciences, Vol. 362, No. 1480, Social Intelligence:From Brain to Culture (Apr. 29, 2007), pp. 561-575Published by: The Royal SocietyStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/20209869 .

Accessed: 13/02/2014 03:57

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

.JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range ofcontent in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new formsof scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

.

The Royal Society is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to PhilosophicalTransactions: Biological Sciences.

http://www.jstor.org

This content downloaded from 144.173.6.145 on Thu, 13 Feb 2014 03:57:51 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

PHILOSOPHICAL TRANSACTIONS

_OF_yj^N Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B (2007) 362, 561-575

THE ROYAL Mrs doi: 10.1098/rstb.2006.1995 SOCIETY JUJ Published online 24 January 2007

Social brains, simple minds: does social complexity really require cognitive complexity?

Louise Barrett1'2,3'*, Peter Henzi1'2'3 and Drew Kendall3 1 Department of Psychology, Darwin Building, University of Central Lancashire, Preston PR1 2HE, UK

2Behavioural Ecology Research Group, University of KwaZulu Natal, Durban 4041, South Africa 3Behavioural Ecology Research Group, Department of Psychology, University of Lethbridge,

Alberta AB T1K3M4, Canada

The social brain hypothesis is a well-accepted and well-supported evolutionary theory of enlarged brain size in the non-human primates. Nevertheless, it tends to emphasize an anthropocentric view of social life and cognition. This often leads to confusion between ultimate and proximate mechanisms, and an over-reliance on a Cartesian, narratively structured view of the mind and social life, which in turn lead to views of social complexity that are congenial to our views of ourselves, rather than

necessarily representative of primate social worlds. In this paper, we argue for greater attention to embodied and distributed theories of cognition, which get us away from current fixations on 'theory of mind' and other high-level anthropocentric constructions, and allow for the generation of testable

hypotheses that combine neurobiology, psychology and behaviour in a mutually reinforcing manner.

Keywords: social complexity; primates; anthropocentrism; social brain; distributed cognition; embodied cognition

1. INTRODUCTION The social intelligence (social brain) hypothesis states that the demands of social life selected for large brains

within the primate order (Humphrey 1976; Byrne & Whiten 1988; Dunbar 1998). This rests, necessarily, on the assumption that social life is complex, where this

complexity makes demands that can only be solved with the use of flexible, cognitive strategies in real-time, rather than evolved 'rules-of-thumb5 (Byrne & Whiten

1988; Dunbar 1998). The evidence in favour of the social brain hypothesis is persuasive, but based

largely on proxy measures for both intelligence and social complexity, such as brain size and group size

(e.g. Dunbar 1992a, 1995, 1998; Joffe 1997; Byrne &

Corp 2004). While the social intelligence hypothesis is not solely

directed at primates?it hypothesizes that all socially living species should show enlarged brain sizes relative to more solitary congeners?it nonetheless implies that

primate social groups will, in some way, be more

complex than those of other socially living animals: since primates have disproportionately large brains, the selection pressures coming from the social environment

must therefore have been stronger. There are a number of hypotheses and explanations

as to what might increase the complexity of primate groups. All of these have hinged, in one way or another, on the view that primates are more 'political' than other animals?more Machiavellian?such that their interactions occur at a number of different levels,

within individualized societies, and involve more

* Author for correspondence ([email protected]).

One contribution of 19 to a Dicussion Meeting Issue 'Social

intelligence: from brain to culture'.

complex, polyadic forms of social engagement (de Waal 1982, 1986; Byrne & Whiten 1988; Cords 1997; Dunbar 1998). Here, we argue that evidence in support of this assumption reflects our own unspoken, and often unrecognized, anthropocentric commitments.

These commitments lead us to confuse proximate and ultimate explanations and to endorse a Cartesian and propositional view of the mind generally, and of social cognition in particular. We believe that there is

merit in considering primates, not as hermetically sealed cogitators, but as agents whose social cognition is determined, at least in part, by their being both 'embodied5 and socially 'situated5 (Clark 1997; Anderson 2003).

2. SOCIAL LIFE AND SOCIAL COMPLEXITY It is undoubtedly true that the diurnal anthropoid primates, monkeys in particular, are intensely social.

They form permanent groups in which one sex or another generally spends its entire life, with the result that groups are composed of extended networks of both

matrilineal and patrilineal kin (Dunbar 1988; Strier

1990). Group living is thought to represent an

evolutionary response to pr?dation risk (and infanti

cide; van Schaik & Rappeler 1997), while the internal structure of groups?the degree to which the sexes are

related, the nature of dominance hierarchies, the

patterning of grooming interactions between individ

uals, particularly females?is argued to be a response to

ecological constraints, specifically to the level of

competition for food within and between groups (van Schaik 1983; Dunbar 1988). Group size and structure therefore represent a balance between the centripetal force of pr?dation risk and the centrifugal force of

competition. This is assumed to have created a

561 This journal is ? 2007 The Royal Society

This content downloaded from 144.173.6.145 on Thu, 13 Feb 2014 03:57:51 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

562 L. Barrett et al. Social cognition in primates

selection pressure on individuals to evolve strategies and tactics that alleviate the negative effects of

competition on reproductive success. The social brain

hypothesis dovetails neatly with this, since the

proposed strategies involve the formation of 'coalitions and alliances' (Harcourt & de Waal 1992) that enable individual animals to combine forces and prevent other individuals from monopolizing resources.

Socio-ecological models are generally silent on whether such strategies represent some form of conscious cognitive processing (although see Dunbar

1984) or if they represent evolved strategies, where action derives from some rule-of-thumb that does not

require overt, conscious calculation of goals and

consequences. Nevertheless, the incorporation of the social brain hypothesis into socio-ecological expla nations does weight them in favour of the former: the

complexity of social life in primate groups must require some more complex form of cognitive assessment if the links between social life and behaviour are to underpin

brain size.

This comes about, at least partly, because our

reasoning runs from brains to behaviour, rather than the reverse: since we know that primates have big brains, it follows that they should be doing more with them than other animals. This being so, the social behaviours that we see are assumed to be built on high level, flexible cognitive assessment, where driving selection has ratcheted up the capacity to meet strategy

with counter-strategy, thereby establishing the relative

complexity of primate groups. These more complex mechanisms are therefore assumed to require more

brain tissue.

Coalition formation is commonly invoked to explain complexity of this kind because it decouples rank and

power (de Waal 1982; Datta 1983). Although rank

might derive initially from intrinsic resource holding potential, it can be augmented, and the decline of intrinsic ability compensated for, by the 'extrinsic5

power acquired through coalitionary relationships (Datta 1983; Chap?is 1992). This makes life inherently

more complex because strategizing individuals must

then base their decisions not only on observables, such as the body size or the current whereabouts of others, but also on details of the differentiated relationships between individuals within the group.

Coalitions are thought to be cultivated and main tained through allogrooming (Dunbar 1998). Groom

ing represents an investment of time and effort by one individual in another that establishes a special relation

ship among associating animals and increases the

probability of coalitionary support at some indetermin able point in the future. Strong grooming bonds are

signals of the likelihood of 'unstinting mutual support' (Dunbar 1988, 1998, see also Kummer 1968). As this is 'the core process that gives primate social groups their internal structure and coherence' (Dunbar 1998, p. 186), and because both grooming clique size and

group size correlate with neocortex ratio (Dunbar 1998; Kudo & Dunbar 2001), it follows that cognitive complexity has been selected by the need to monitor and sustain one's own grooming relationships, while

simultaneously monitoring those of others across time in order to keep a running tally of their levels of

extrinsic power (Dunbar 1988, 1998; Kudo & Dunbar

2001). This is a compelling proposition, supported by the apparently superior ability of higher primates to detect and identify third-party relationships (Dasser 1988; Cheney & Seyfarth 1990; Tomasello & Call

1997; Bergman et al 2003).

3. COALITIONS AND RELATIONSHIPS However, as we have argued elsewhere (Henzi & Barrett 1999; Barrett & Henzi 2002; Barrett & Henzi

2005, 2006), there is only equivocal evidence, at best, to support any causal link between grooming and coalition formation, while the formation of coalitions

by adults against other adults is also rare in wild

populations (Henzi & Barrett 1999; Silk et al. 2004). This is unexpected, given that such coalitions define the complexity of primate groups (Henzi & Barrett

1999). However, while the counterargument?that the

rarity of coalitions belies their central importance (Silk et al. 2004)?works for other rare events, like pr?dation or infanticide, it does not hold here. The risks of infanticide and pr?dation form the selection pressures to which primates are thought to have evolved specific countermeasures, such as group-living itself

(van Schaik 1983) and female promiscuity (Hrdy 1977). Female promiscuity and group-living are there fore common, which is why infanticide and pr?dation are rare (Dunbar 1988). Coalitions, however, are not the selection pressure, but the evolved response to the selection pressure generated by resource competition. Coalitions should therefore be common and compe tition rare, whereas the reverse is actually the case: there are many studies demonstrating the existence and extent of competition (see Strier 2002 for review), but

very few establish a reliable, causal link between

grooming and coalition formation in either the wild or captivity (see Cords 1997; Henzi & Barrett 1999). A recent study that explicitly set out to do so found no evidence of a direct link between the two (Silk et al.

2004), while grooming persists in the absence of coalitions (Barrett & Henzi 2006). This rarity of coalition formation, and the lack of a well-established link between coalitions and grooming, suggests that this behaviour is unlikely to represent a general explanation for the social complexity of primates and their groups.

It remains possible, of course, that monkeys sustain and monitor relationships for other valuable reasons besides coalition formation (see Silk et al. 2003a). Even so, the implicit assumption on which the argument rests?that monkeys can track their own and other

relationships through time?has not been tested

adequately (Cords 1997; Barrett & Henzi 2002). The

point about tracking time is central to this argument because it is assumed that the obligate sociality imposed by pr?dation risk entails, for each participant, a future in which competition is certain but its precise timing is unknown. Selection then favours a prospec

tive cognition that can prepare for this uncertainty. Of course, this ability is not necessary for relation

ships to be adaptive, as individuals could, in principle, achieve the same result with evolved rules-of-thumb that do not involve cognitive assessment. However, the

Phil Trans. R. Soc. B (2007)

This content downloaded from 144.173.6.145 on Thu, 13 Feb 2014 03:57:51 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Social cognition in primates L. Barrett et al. 563

social brain hypothesis needs more than this, since non

cognitive, evolved rules-of-thumb do not require particularly large brains. The problem with assuming cognitive solutions that rely on some form of temporal projection is that monkeys, at least, despite large brains, seem to live very much in the here and now, and have yet to provide evidence that they can plan for future contingencies (Roberts 2002), inhibit inap propriate pre-potent responses (Chap?is 1992) or remember when an event happened, in addition to what happened and where (Hampton et al. 2005).

There is also a lack of evidence to show that they can reason in a truly analogical, conceptual fashion (i.e. understand relations between relations), which would limit their ability to understand the equivalence between their own bonds and those of others

(Thompson & Oden 2000). Dasser's (1988) classic

study, indicating that female macaques can understand bonds conceptually, does not rule out some form of

perceptual matching between individuals, nor are the

simple discrimination testing and match-to-sample designs sufficient to show relational matching (Thompson 1995; Thompson & Oden 2000). The two successful monkeys in Dasser's (1988) study were not asked to match mother-offspring pairs with other

mother-offspring pairs (i.e. to judge relations between relations by first identifying identity versus non-identity pairs and then matching appropriately on the basis of these relations), but only to match a picture of a mother

with one of the two potential offspring, or to discriminate between a picture of a mother-offspring pair and a non-mother-ofifspring pair. The finding that

chimpanzees can accurately match unfamiliar mothers with their offspring suggests that perceptual matching is a possible explanation for Dasser's results (Vokey et al. 2004), while subsequent studies of monkeys using the appropriate relational tasks have not found evidence of analogical reasoning, although they used

only physical matching tasks (geometric shapes) and not social ones (Thompson & Oden 2000). These

findings contrast with observational and field experi mental evidence, indicating that monkeys behave as

though they do recognize third-party relationships (Tomasello & Call 1997), but whether this amounts to true conceptual, abstract understanding has not

specifically been addressed. At least one study demon

strates that simple, associative rules-of-thumb can

underpin this ability (Range & No? 2005). When Humphrey (1976, p. 309) originally proposed

the evolution of a specifically social intelligence, he

suggested that primates inhabit a world 'where the evidence on which their calculations are based is

ephemeral, ambiguous and liable to change, not least as a consequence of their own actions'. Here, as

Carrithers (1991) notes, use of words like 'ephemeral' serve to emphasize the close temporal horizons over which monkeys must perceive and act on events, and does not argue specifically for foresight and intentional

planning. There is little doubt that selection has

produced cognitive abilities that allow individuals to

perceive and respond appropriately to fast-acting dynamic changes in others' behaviour (Barrett & Henzi 2005), but there is no a priori reason why selection should have acted to extend these abilities in

time. The ability to respond flexibly and expediently to others5 behaviour does not demand the ability to plot and plan in any meta-representational fashion.

This all raises an obvious question: given the lack of clear empirical support, why do we persist with this

particular view of primate complexity and the social brain? It seems to us that there is something unusually beguiling about the structure and form of the social brain

hypothesis that has led us all to take a good deal of it on trust. One reason for this, of course, is that it possesses a

very coherent internal logic that binds together two

empirically undisputed endpoints (forced sociality; large brains) by means of some direct and intuitively appealing links between behavioural complexity and cognition.

There is a clear, if implicit, equation of functional behavioural complexity with underlying mechanistic

cognitive complexity, without demonstration (or even

argument) of what kinds of mechanistic complexity are

actually needed to produce behavioural complexity (or that they are needed at all). If so, it might be useful to ask

why these links are so appealing. Our answer to this question is that the reassuring

congeniality of the social brain hypothesis is a direct

consequence of the manner in which our own social

cognition is built, i.e. we somehow see our former selves

very clearly in this picture of primate social life. Indeed, it is our attempt to explain the evolution of human brains that drives, in part at least, the whole social brain project. Crucially, as is often pointed out (inter alia Wittgenstein 1968), although we ostensibly look on dispassionately, we can actually do so only through our own socio-cognitive spectacles. There is abundant evidence that we are

heavily prone to perceiving and interpreting other

components of the world, besides ourselves, in anthro

pocentric terms. As a result, we may impose complexity on a system that lacks it (or at least lacks the kind of

complexity we usually attribute to it). In the case of the social brain hypothesis, we may inadvertently have used

primates as a kind of tautological instrument: we have told them what we want them to be in order to validate our own view of who we think we are.

So what facets of human social cognition are

important and into what assumptions are we conse

quently tempted? Answers to these questions may both reveal the commitments that certain arguments and hypotheses entail with respect to social complexity and illustrate how they might mislead us if they remain subliminal and unacknowledged. There are three

particular facets of human cognition that we should consider: our inevitably anthropocentric attitude to the

world; the way in which this leads us to view other

species anthropomorphically; and the manner in which we structure our world as narrative. The first two lead us to view the worlds of other primates, and other

species in general, in ways that resonate for us, while we

artificially impose an extra layer of order on their worlds

by means of the latter.

4. ANTHROPOCENTRISM AND ANTHROPOMORPHISM An anthropocentric stance is something from which, to a large degree, we cannot retreat: by definition, neither can we see the world in anything other than human

Phil Trans. R. Soc. B (2007)

This content downloaded from 144.173.6.145 on Thu, 13 Feb 2014 03:57:51 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

564 L. Barrett et al. Social cognition in primates

terms nor can we describe or discuss it in anything other than ordinary human language. It also means that

we have a natural consequent tendency to anthro

pomorphize and attribute human characteristics to other animals (Guthrie 1993). It is clear, moreover, that we are prone to do so on the basis of the quite simple perception-action mechanisms that form the foundations of our folk psychology and which are

cognitively impenetrable. We perceive, tellingly, ani

macy and goal-directedness in a single white dot as it moves across a background, despite the fact that this is induced by nothing more than the way in which it

changes speed and direction (Scholl & Tremoulet

2000; Tremoulet & Feldman 2000). We also attribute motives and personality traits to simple geometric shapes on the basis only of the way they move in relation to each other (Heider & Simmel 1944) and, as a by-product of selection for such pattern recognition, we have an overwhelming and automatic urge to see human faces and forms in the most unlikely objects (Guthrie 1993). These basic, apparently evolved

mechanisms, on which our sophisticated and culturally constructed understanding of ourselves and other human beings is based (Tomasello 1999), mean that we need to take care to avoid being led astray by our folk psychological understanding of ourselves and other people: the more something resembles us, or the more familiar it is, the more likely its behaviour will

trigger these mechanisms, leading us to interpret it as human-like (Eddy et al. 1993; Povinelli et al. 2000).

The debate regarding the appropriateness of anthro

pomorphism as a scientific research strategy waxes and wanes regularly. There is, however, an overall sense that it is always a mistaken approach for scientists to take (e.g. Wynne 2004). As Tyler (2003, p. 270) notes, 'the very suggestion that a theory or approach is

anthropomorphic is, implicitly, always an objection or an accusation'. Those who employ such a strategy are

inevitably required to defend a deeply suspect position. By the same token, however, there is also an argument to the effect that anti-anthropomorphism is equally suspect, since it assumes implicitly that there are

unique human traits, identifiable a priori, and that these should not be attributed to creatures to which

they do not 'belong' (Sheets-Johnstone 1992; Sober

1998; de Waal 2001; Tyler 2003; Keeley 2004). Whether any 'anti-anthropomorphites' actually

hold such a philosophical position is moot and a more realistic characterization of this stance might be that we simply do not know whether other animals have human-like traits (and, if one's outlook is

particularly bleak, is something that we can never

know; e.g. Nagel 1974). Attributing human-like traits to other animals is inappropriate because it has the effect of sealing the matter before it has been properly studied. Even worse, it is likely that we have

mischaracterized the nature of at least some of those human traits in the first place (Tyler 2003; Fernandez-Armesto 2004; Rendall et al. 2007), so

applying human traits to other animals merely results in a layering of confusion: we are confused about ourselves and if we then apply that confused view to other animals, we compound the error (Andrews

2005; Rendall et al. 2007).

This bias can work both ways. In addition to

ascribing human attributes to other animals inappro priately, we can also deny them certain cognitive capacities in an equally inappropriate manner, because we confuse what is necessarily required with the

specific form these capacities happen to take in humans. The objections raised with respect to episodic memory in non-human animals are a case in point

(Suddendorf & Busby 2003). Here, aspects of episodic memory, such as autonoesis, which can only ever be demonstrated empirically in humans, were made an

integral and essential part of its definition. To criticize

any claims for avian episodic memory (Clayton et al.

2003a) by arguing that episodic memory is partly defined by elements that 'belong5 to humans necess

arily prescribes the investigation. The real issue, of course, is whether episodic memory is a cognitive

mechanism available to other species, not whether other animals have a specifically human episodic

memory. It should be obvious that they do not, since

they are not human and, as Clayton et al. (2003a, p. 437) point out, it is inappropriate to insist that

episodic memory should be defined by 'the phenom enology of the modern human mind, rather than in terms of core cognitive capacities5: to do so is just anthropocentric narrow-mindedness.

The argument that anthropocentrism obscures the social lives of primates is not, therefore, a simple criticism of an 'anthropomorphic5 approach per se: there is no reason why, taking an evolutionarily grounded view of cognition, other species should not also manifest some of the same cognitive capacities as

humans, either by descent or convergence. This being so, we need to avoid an approach to animal sociality that places humans at the comparative centre. We

should, instead, ask questions about what it means to be a living being of any kind, rather than immediately restricting ourselves to some comparison with humans. The proposition is, then, that anthropocentrism, whether positively or negatively anthropomorphic, needs to be acknowledged and contained because it denies animals their own voices.

In the case of social cognition, anthropocentrism leads us to ask questions about other primates5 social

cognition from an unduly distorted perspective. This is one that privileges conscious, 'higher5 forms of cogni tion, based on language and meta-representational 'theory of mind5 (ToM) skills, because we think of these as essential and fundamental to the understanding of the behaviour of other humans, even though this is not

generally the case (Liberman et al. 2002; Hutto 2004; Andrews 2005; Gallagher 2005). We consequently gear our research efforts explicitly to detecting these abilities or, more commonly, their precursors, in monkeys and

apes, either as a check on our own uniqueness and/or as a

means of identifying how our own skills in these domains have been derived from evolutionarily simpler mechanisms (e.g. Dunbar 1996; Bergman et al. 2003; Povinelli & Vonk 2003; Tomasello et al. 2003; Zuberbuhler 2003; Cheney & Seyfarth 2005).

A research strategy of this kind requires commit ments that, on reflection, might be problematic. Looking explicitly for precursors of human socio

cognitive attributes, for one, judges primate capacities

Phil Trans. R. Soc. B (2007)

This content downloaded from 144.173.6.145 on Thu, 13 Feb 2014 03:57:51 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Social cognition in primates L. Barrett et al. 565

against a human standard and therefore necessarily sees in them some fraction of this standard at best, where these might better be regarded as adaptations in their own right (Tyler 2003). Adopting a 'folk theoretic' stance that places unobservable mental states to the fore, for another, creates all kinds of problems about how to define such states and justify their inference on the basis of observable behaviour

(Johnson & Oswald 2001, p. 454; Povinelli & Vonk

2003; Andrews 2005). Finally, an emphasis on higher cognition leads to a neglect of the perception-action

mechanisms by which animals actually engage with the

world, on which selection has acted for a much longer period, and from which these higher-level processes emerge (Brooks 1999). This is the most relevant

problem from our point of view because, by placing social cognition firmly 'in the head' as an abstract, logical, disembodied process, we ignore differences in

active, bodily engagement with the world. So, when de Waal (2005) argues that Georgia, the chimpanzee, should be regarded as possessing a 'complex and familiar inner life' because her behaviour looks so

very similar to our own, it disregards the fact that her

body interacts with the world very differently from the

ways that ours do. How might our own physical grounding of concepts differ if we could use our feet as effectively as our hands (or if we had flippers or a

wholly carnivorous diet)?

5. NARRATIVE INTELLIGENCE We distort our view of other animals further by virtue of a particular anthropocentric tendency to construct

meaning through narrative. Humans are a literary and

story-telling species (Turner 1996). Like those of all other animals, human brains are, generally speaking, machines for distilling pattern from the world. Chaotic randomness does not appeal to us, and our particular

means of extracting meaning and purpose from the events in our lives is to form them into narratives that, owing to the strictures of language, are linearly conceived and structured. To do so, we rely on

abstraction, the specific form of which depends on what we are trying to convey: stories told to entertain involve elaboration and sometimes exaggeration, while stories told to inform omit unnecessary detail and follow more direct linear trajectories (Tversky 2004). In addition, and importantly, 'stories have an extended

temporal horizon, they relate to past and future, and

they are created depending on the social context'

(Dautenhahn 2002, p. 111). Stories are formed by events that, in turn, can only be understood in relation to the story as a whole (Carrithers 1991). This natural

story-telling ability, like our tendency to anthropomor phize, is indiscriminate and promiscuous: we are

obliged to tell stories about everything we see and we structure narratives around both ourselves and other

living creatures.

Understanding narrativity is argued to be crucial to

understanding human cognition, generally (Bruner 1990, 1991; Carrithers 1991; Turner 1996), and the evolution of human social cognition in particular (Read &

Miller 1995; Dautenhahn 2001, 2002). Dautenhahn's

(2001) Narrative Intelligence hypothesis, for example,

argues that the evolutionary origin of communicating using stories reflects the increasingly complex social

dynamics that evolved among our early human ancestors. The point here is that, even when we are not explicitly assuming that other animals have minds like our own, our natural tendency to understand the world through narrative means that we may nevertheless observe,

experiment on and interpret their behaviour in narrative forms that rely on an essential anthropocentrism.

6. WHOSE COMPLEXITY IS IT? With respect to primate sociality, our narrative tendencies are most clearly revealed by the fact that

anybody who has worked on primates will have found

themselves, at one time or another, describing the life of a primate group as a 'soap opera5?an on-going

open-ended narrative involving a familiar set of characters (e.g. Dunbar 1996, p. 28). The question, of course, is: do other animals see themselves in this

way? It is our view that narrative structuring is not part of the world of at least one primate group?the

monkeys?and that when we impose a narrative structure on their social interactions, we make their

worlds more complex than is warranted. Hinde (1976, 1983) identified three levels of social

structure: interactions (between particular individuals), relationships (the frequency, quality and patterning of these interactions over time) and social structure (the overall patterning of relationships within the group). Although he saw relationships as emergent, irreducible

phenomena, Hinde also emphasized their fluidity, regarding them as dynamic equilibria in which an

impression of stability can be created by the contingent shifts and adjustments in interactions. As Silk (2002) suggests, however, we have largely assumed that such irreducible social relationships exist, rather than provid ing well-defined, rigorous means of identifying them

(see also Cords 1997). Despite this, they have come

increasingly to be seen as evermore stable entities that, as we know, can be subdivided into such forms as

'friendships' (Silk 2002), 'coalitions' (Dunbar 1984, 1988) or 'alliances5 (Harcourt & de Waal 1992) that animals sustain consistently and cooperatively. Conse

quently, whereas grooming and proximity maintenance (two measures of affiliation) might once have been viewed as constituting the relationship in and of

themselves, they are now more often regarded as an

index of some underlying bond that exceeds the sum of its parts. This, in turn, may reflect the fact that, to

identify relationships, we abstract many interactions over time, therefore adding a temporal component, and

temporal consistency, to our analyses of monkey life

(which actually reflects an arbitrary, human-relative time frame, rather than one relevant to the animals

themselves). In this way, the grooming we record between animals now can token 'unstinting mutual

support5 in the future (Harcourt 1992; Dunbar 1998). This, however, amounts to the reification of a relation

ship concept that we still need to show has more than human significance (Barrett & Henzi 2002; Silk 2002).

The well-documented demonstration that social animals can reconcile after aggression (de Waal & van Roosmalen 1979; de Waal 1989) has helped bed down

Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B (2007)

This content downloaded from 144.173.6.145 on Thu, 13 Feb 2014 03:57:51 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

566 L. Barrett et al. Social cognition in primates

this supposition that individuals service and repair their

relationships in order to sustain them (Aureli & de Waal

2000). The recent finding that the lifetime reproductive success of female baboons increases with their socia

bility links all these elements together evolutionarily, and further suggests that selection could act on the

psychological mechanisms that support these differing forms of association (Silk et al. 2003a). This, as already

mentioned, is argued to drive complexity: the cultiva tion of relationships, while simultaneously monitoring those of others, places a significant cognitive burden on

participants who track their status through time, and who pick up social knowledge and information that is not vital at the time, but can be used adaptively later on

(Harcourt 1988, 1989, 1992; Whiten 2000). If this is so, how might this social knowledge be

constructed? Cheney & Seyfarth (2005, p. 152), for

example, have used a suite of rigorous playback experiments to argue that wild female baboons'

'...knowledge is propositional'. By this, apparently they mean that it is a declarative, explicit form of

knowledge (i.e. 'knowing that' an individual A has a

relationship with B), rather than an implicit, procedural knowledge of others (i.e. 'knowing how' to

engage with others, without any explicit understanding of their relationships). The empirical data comprise the time an animal spends looking towards a hidden

speaker. Longer looking times are said to indicate that 'listeners responded as if they parsed a call

sequence as a dramatic narrative: Hannah is threatening

Sylvia and Sylvia is screaming. But Sylvia belongs to the

alpha-matriline and Hannah belongs to the beta. This can

only mean that the beta-family is attempting to depose the

alpha' (p. 152). This is a rich interpretation, given the nature of the data, and is really only possible because the 'parsing of narratives' is already built into the

experimental design and the baboons cannot do otherwise. The questions concern whether monkey narratives are hierarchically organized by kin and rank, but beg the question of whether such narratives exist at

all, which seems crucial. More importantly, the actual

cognitive mechanism underlying this looking time

response remains opaque. The design of the experi ment, which uses an introspective consideration of our own folk psychological mechanisms to rationalize the behaviour of the animals, probably tells us more about how we think our own minds work, as opposed to revealing anything significant about the mind of the baboon.

There is further reason to suspect that monkeys may not view their interactions as relationships with an

inherently temporal, narrative format. Long-term data from baboons reveal that there is a good deal of

variability in partner choice over time, with changes in

preference associated strongly with reproductive events

(Barrett & Henzi 2002). This, in itself, can explain why more sociable females are more reproductively success

ful: females with young infants attract significantly more social attention than non-lactating females

(Altmann 1980; Henzi & Barrett 2002; Silk et al.

2003&), with the result that those females who give birth more often experience increased levels of social interaction. Here, therefore, causality may run

in the direction opposite to that which is assumed

(Silk et al. 2003a). In addition, it is probable that individuals groom and maintain proximity to others

owing to short-term concerns, such as access to infants

or to 'skilled5 individuals, tolerance around resources and avoidance of aggression (Silk 1982; Stammbach

1988; Muroyama 1994; Barrett & Henzi 2001; Henzi & Barrett 2002; Chap?is 2006; No? 2006).

Data from samango monkeys also show that when the opportunity exists for increased social investment, females allocate the time to resting instead (Payne et al.

2003, Pazol & Cords 2005). Similarly, while Dunbar & Dunbar (1988) suggested that weaning behaviour in

gelada was prompted by the stresses placed on female social relationships (due to an increase in feeding time to fuel lactation), and the need to ensure relationship integrity could be maintained over time, analyses of two Papio baboon populations have found that, when

possible, females actively reduce social time as part of an energy-sparing strategy, but show no changes in the

diversity of their grooming partners as a consequence (Kenyatta 1995; Barrett et al. 2006).

Finally, recent analyses of baboon social networks show that these do not have the temporal durability that is usually assumed. When food is abundant, females from two markedly different environments

forego 'companionships5 (sensu Whitehead 1995) and like herding antelope are perhaps better regarded as

merely gregarious. Only when food is scarce do the 'constant companionships' indicative of strong, differ entiated relationships emerge. For part of each year, then, adult female baboons downgrade the qualitative status of their associations from what we would see as

relationships to what network analysis reveals as 'casual

acquaintances5 (Henzi et al, Submitted). There is no

suggestion that the phases without companionships trigger either temporary or permanent fission. This

being so, models of social life that are predicated on the value of grooming effort as a bonding agent may benefit from reconsideration (Dunbar 19926). If

relationships can regularly dissolve without affecting group integrity, it is hard to see why imposed reductions in social time should inevitably lead to

group fission as these models predict, and why group size should necessarily be limited by cognitive constraints on relationship tracking.

Overall, then, these findings suggest that the need for individuals to service, protect and repair relationships through time may have been overestimated, for wild

populations at least. This is reinforced by the fact that most data in support of grooming bonds come from Old World monkeys; studies of New World primates have shown that grooming is much less common, despite group and brain sizes similar to those found in Old

World species (Strier 2002). In captivity, from where much of the data on relationship value come (e.g. Cords

1997; de Waal 2003 for reviews), individuals may well need to ensure that they sustain contact with others

owing to an absence of alternative responses to

aggression. At the same time, of course, they have

more time to engage in social interaction and little else to

occupy them. This, in itself, is interesting and shows that

primates have the flexibility to adopt a variety of social solutions to their quotidian problems. We argue, in fact, that this kind of behavioural flexibility is the key to

Phil Trans. R. Soc. B (2007)

This content downloaded from 144.173.6.145 on Thu, 13 Feb 2014 03:57:51 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Social cognition in primates L. Barrett et al. 567

understanding primate social adaptation (Barrett & Henzi 2005). The construal of primate social engage ment in terms of narrative relationships, on the other

hand, seems comparatively less secure. At the very least, these concerns suggest that we should be sceptical about assuming that monkeys see their relationships as

we see them.

7. THE INTERPRETATIVE GAP If we cannot avoid our own socio-cognitive biases, and

acknowledge that they might lead us astray, we are

obliged to find a way to proceed. The most sensible

approach is probably to acknowledge the gravitational pull of an anthropocentric narrative and to ask

explicitly how something might be achieved if it is not

being achieved in a human-like way. What we have to

do, in other words, is to deal with Dennett's

'interpretative gap'. As Dennett (1989) has made clear, we adopt a

stance when we predict or explain a system. Whereas we might accurately predict the behaviour of a baboon

by ascribing reason to its actions (the 'intentional

stance'), which natural selection licenses us to do, this does not naturally entitle us to use reason as an

explanation of the action (see also Kennedy 1992). Or to put it more simply, it is not necessarily the case that an animal which behaves 'as if it is thinking, actually is. Or if it is, there is no need for it to be doing so in the way that we do (Povinelli et al. 2000). Although the intentional stance is unavoidable (Dennett 1989), it

necessarily opens up an interpretative gap?between prediction and explanation, and between function and mechanism?that must be closed. Our argument, then,

is that the current conception of the social intelligence/ social brain hypothesis inevitably opens up the

interpretative gap because it is a hypothesis that elides

evolutionary response with proximate mechanism, and allows evidence for the former to be taken as support for the latter.

The original social intelligence hypothesis, as put forward by Jolly (1966) and Humphrey (1976), was a

strongly evolutionary hypothesis, which aimed to

explain why primates were more brainy than other

animals, despite the fact that the environmental

challenges facing them were no more taxing, and sometimes considerably less so, than those that faced other species. The hypothesis put forward was that the social environment provided the cognitive challenges, so that improvement in cognitive ability in one part of the population would over time ratchet up the level in the rest of the population due to the interactive and

dynamic nature of social engagement, with the smartest animals enjoying increased survival and reproductive success. As we have shown, the behaviours assumed to have been selected were those associated with relation

ship formation, maintenance and protection (which were also seen as characteristic of primates), and these in turn were assumed to require certain sophisticated cognitive capacities, based largely on a folk psycho logical projection of our own abilities in these domains

(see also Silk (2002) for a similar argument with respect to the evolution of reconciliation).

Consequently, evidence in support of the evolution

ary argument, such as the correlation between group size and brain size across the primate order (Dunbar 1995), has also been taken as implicit support for the

postulated proximate behavioural and cognitive mechanisms by which individual animals increase survival and reproductive success. But such evidence does not, and cannot, tell us anything directly about

proximate mechanisms. Moreover, the same is true even if we move down a level and show that the behaviours themselves are deployed by females in a way that is directly fitness enhancing (e.g. Silk et al. 2003a).

This is because females that act as if they know their

relationships are valuable and worth protecting may well be doing so in an evolutionary sense, but not

necessarily at a more proximate level: the selection

pressures acting on the actual cognitive mechanisms by which females engage with each other may be very different from the evolutionary forces that have shaped fitness-enhancing sociality in general. The successful

application of our own folk psychological understand

ing of primates to generate functional hypotheses and

explanations of behaviour cannot, therefore, be taken to indicate that we understand anything about the

psychological mechanisms that primates might use to understand each other.

One way that researchers have used to get around the

problem of the interpretative gap is by appealing to

phylogenetic similarity and, in essence, closing the gap by fiat. Consequently, de Waal (2001, p. 70), for one of

many examples, argues that the 'mere five to six million

years5 which separate chimpanzees and humans shift the burden of proof (concerning behavioural or cognitive similarities) to those who deny the relevance of this fact: 'But doesn't ...parsimony argue against assuming a

huge cognitive gap when the evolutionary distance between humans and apes is so small?' (de Waal 1997, p. 53). Interestingly, in this regard, baboons emerged as a species only some 2.5 Myr ago. Nevertheless, they have subsequently differentiated into a number of forms that are distinctively different in behaviour. Here, an

assumption of interpretative continuity can?and has?lead to misinterpretation (Henzi & Barrett

2003). In truth, as Dennett has indicated, the interpret ative gap is only narrowed by adopting the intentional stance and then setting out specifically to test its starting assumptions. The burden of proof, therefore, falls

squarely on all of us, all of the time.

Therefore, if we begin by acknowledging explicitly our anthropocentric perspective, our objective must be an examination of the mechanisms by which we and other animals do the things that we do. In other words, our questions must become explicitly proximate mechanistic, and not evolutionary functional. We cannot use the 'as if reasoning of functional hypotheses when asking questions about cognition because it blurs the distinction between proximate and ultimate expla nation and makes it possible to slide between

evolutionary and cognitive causes of action (Kennedy 1992). Arguing that baboons act 'as if they are parsing calls into narratives or that Diana monkeys act '...as if

they recognized that chimpanzee alarm screams

signalled the presence of a leopard' (Zuberbuhler 2003, p. 283), actively avoids considering mechanism.

Phil Trans. R. Soc. B (2007)

This content downloaded from 144.173.6.145 on Thu, 13 Feb 2014 03:57:51 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

568 L. Barrett et al. Social cognition in primates

This is fine if our concerns are the assessment of functional (fitness-based) outcomes, but clearly pro blematic for an elaboration of cognitive evolution, which is the ostensible intention of many of these studies. Merely arguing that monkeys act 'as if they understand the chimpanzee calls, for example, does not

really get us anywhere because the 'meaning' of the

vocalization, in this instance, is neither its function nor the proximate mechanism giving rise to it. It sits

uneasily somewhere in between as an intentional heuristic that, sooner or later, has to get cashed out for a concrete explanation in terms of mechanism, as well as function.

It is important to stress that this pursuit of mechanism is not in any way a caricatured, radical behaviourist denial of higher-order cognition. Analyti cally, since it is the comparison of plausible competing hypotheses concerning the nature of underlying mechanisms, it would have, in fact, the welcome and

opposite effect of ending the use of statistical null models as the benchmark against which ideas or

propositions are assessed (see also Gigerenzer 2004). At present, highly cognitive hypotheses are tested

against null models, which is the equivalent of saying: 'we are testing whether something is happening in these animals' heads, rather than nothing'. Rejecting the null

hypothesis, then, does not mean that the postulated cognitive mechanism has been shown to exist, only that a cognitive mechanism of some kind is operating, rather than a simple stimulus-response link. Identifying and

pitting alternative cognitive mechanisms against each other is the only way to establish what kind of cognitive mechanism is actually being used, as studies of memory development in children (Russell & Thompson 2003) and prospective cognition in jays (Clayton & Dickinson

1999) illustrate to great effect. Given this, the question then arises as to where

these alternative kinds of plausible mechanisms might come from. Our approach in what follows is to suggest that apparent cognitive complexity may emerge from the interaction of brain, body and world, and is not

merely due to the level of internal complexity the animal itself possesses.

8. COMPLEX SOCIAL SPACE With respect to monkeys, and their social interactions, this means recognizing, first of all, that the shifting and varied encounters which we view anthropocentrically as the evolutionary precursors to human relationships, and

which we have assumed to possess a significant temporal component, may, from the monkey's perspective, be better conceptualized as a form of spatial pattern recognition. In other words, monkeys may engage each other in a highly action-centred, continuous, spatial jockeying for position and influence within the confines of the group, using social contact and proximity as a means to achieving immediate goals, and moni

toring the concurrent actions of others, but without any conceptual, representational knowledge of what they are

doing, or any projection of this through time. If this is the case, then fission may not be the result

of weakening and fragmentation of relationships, followed by fracturing along lines of least resistance

(Dunbar 19926), but may simply reflect the inability to maintain ongoing contact with all other group members as groups become larger and more spatially dispersed. Where animals are frequently separated by the need to find food, fission can emerge as a gradual

mechanical process in which subgroups become

increasingly spatially disjunct. The formation of new

groups is likely to be hastened where sleeping sites are

readily available and where perceived pr?dation risk does not set a high lower limit on the size of foraging group an individual feels comfortable in.

Similarly, we can view coalitions as only one

component of a suite of tactics that monkeys use when

they offer immediate benefits for both parties, i.e. as short-term mutualism (e.g. Silk et al. 2004) and not as

prospective investment governed by reciprocal altruism

(e.g. Seyfarth & Cheney 1984). Reconfigured in this

way, they can be seen as the presentation of a spatially integrated 'united front' by two or more animals, where current need drives conjoint action and reduces the social stress experienced by the participants. Mainten ance of spatial proximity may, by the same token, function as a more 'passive' form of coalitionary support reducing the likelihood of displacement or aggression and reflecting an immediate, dynamic response to

changes in spatial positioning. The tendency of many female-bonded species to groom up the dominance

hierarchy may involve a similar tendency to seek tolerance around higher-ranked animals both for the benefits this may offer directly and to reduce the likelihood of interference by third parties while in a dominant's zone of tolerance (e.g. Silk 1982).

Under these conditions, individuals do not need to hold abstract conceptual notions of 'bonds' or track others' relationships because they can gauge circum stances directly by looking at what is happening around them: the spatial structuring of the animals in their environment may obviate the need for certain kinds of

high-level processing in the animals themselves, and

they can 'use the world as its own best model5 as Brooks

(1999) suggests (see also Gibson 1979). This kind of

'just in time5 learning is both less costly and time

consuming than the 'just in case5 learning proposed by Whiten (2000), which requires much more complex internal models of the world for efficient functioning. It

fits, too, with Silk's (1996) proposal that reconciliation acts fundamentally as a short-term signal of benign intent. In all cases, such manoeuvring is performed in the 'here and now5 and we do not need to infer any form of planning or anticipation of the future.

Rejection of a narrative component to primate relationships is not a rejection of the possibility of

complex social engagement per se, but an expectation that any complexity will be dynamic and result from

on-going spatial engagement in real-time. It need not be a consequence of the integration of information across many social events and many actors. New World

primates, incidentally, are among the beneficiaries of this conception since the absence of a strong relation

ship between group size and grooming time in the

platyrrhines (Dunbar 1991) has led to suggestions that

they may lack the strategic capabilities of the catar rhines. Thinking in terms of space, from a highly action-centred perspective, rather than about time and

Phil Trans. R. Soc. B (2007)

This content downloaded from 144.173.6.145 on Thu, 13 Feb 2014 03:57:51 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Social cognition in primates L. Barrett et al. 569

representations, may give us new insights into the social

engagement of all primates, while also shedding light on the differences between monkey and ape cognition (Barrett et al. 2003).

9. BEING IN THE WORLD The second means of dealing with the interpretative gap is to reject the Cartesian viewpoint that places an intentional (anthropomorphic) stance to the fore. If we assume that relationships are temporally constructed narratives in the heads of the animals, and use the intentional stance to make predictions about

behaviour, we are immediately drawn into a view of animals as 'thinking subjects' and so privilege questions that deal with how subjects gain knowledge of the

world, how they relate to it and how they acquire an

understanding of the social worlds of others. If instead we adopt a more embodied approach to cognition generally (Anderson 2003) and to primate social

cognition in particular (G?llese 2001, 2005, 2006, 2007; Barrett & Henzi 2005), we move from thinking of ourselves and other animals as detached observers of the world, but as beings situated in the world, and

inseparable from it (Heidigger 1927/1978). This

immediately gives us greater purchase on the mechanisms by which animals actively cope with the

world, because many of these will be visible to us in the form of perception-action loops, and not as invisible mental constructs.

This fits with findings from various areas of cognitive science, including computer science, artificial intelli

gence and robotics, which argue that we should think of brains and cognition as behaviour control systems, designed to help humans and other animals engage actively with the world, rather than reflect on it (Clark 1997; Brooks 1999). Representations of the world, therefore, will be grounded in an animal's physical skills and bodily experiences (Anderson 2003). Such a

perspective has a much stronger evolutionary flavour

(Damasio 1994) and, by focusing on the physical means by which an animal engages with the world, it

immediately reduces our anthropocentric tendencies. It allows us to discount the association of cognition

with high-level thought processes alone and to study perception, action and cognition as a functionally integrated system (Barrett & Henzi 2005; Barton

2006, 2007). In so doing, it returns us to Leslie Brothers' (1990) original concept of the social brain, where neural activity and bodily responses to social stimuli form the basic building blocks for participation in social acts, and therefore gets us away from the 'neuroist' approach that places all the important stuff

solely in the brain itself (Brothers 2001). As a consequence, embodied cognition (EC) places

a different emphasis on evolutionary continuity. It

proposes that we investigate the way in which

perception-action mechanisms, and bodily engage ment with the world, can exploit the structure of the environment (Gibson 1979) and so limit the need for expensive (often slow), high-level internal proces sing, as a cost-effective evolutionary process should

(Humphrey 1976). More importantly, it turns an

anthropocentric research strategy on its head by

proposing that, instead of looking for the cognitive precursors of sophisticated human cognition, we should investigate the ways in which perception-action

mechanisms constrain (in the sense of canalize) the evolution of high-level processes (Brooks 1999; Anderson 2003; see also Panksepp 1998).

An embodied perspective, therefore, moves us away from an anthropocentric, mentalistic view of cognition and extends it beyond 'skin and skull5 to the body and the world (Clark 1997), with the aim of understanding how cognitive processes are rooted in bodily experience and interwoven with bodily action and interaction with other individuals (Merleau-Ponty 1962/2002; V?rela et al. 1991; Damasio 1994; Clark 1997; Lakoff &

Johnson 1999; Anderson 2003; Garbarini & Adenzato

2004; Barrett & Henzi 2005). It is therefore an

approach that has much in common with the research

strategy that Shettleworth (1998) characterizes as

ecological; here the assumption is that evolution has selected for the behaviours and mechanisms that enable animals to cope with life in particular ecological niches. It acknowledges that animals may show skilled and sophisticated performance in specific domains, where they may be superior to humans, but that this need not manifest itself in other domains, indicate some general form of anthropocentrically defined

'intelligence5 or reflect phylogenetic proximity to humans (as implicitly assumed by anthropocentric imperatives such as Morgan's canon). The striking social and cognitive skills of corvids, for example (Clayton et al. 20036; Emery & Clayton 2004), expressed in the context of food caching, can therefore be seen in this light. Similarly, the inability of Old

World monkeys to match the cooperative behaviour and tool-use capacities of capuchin moneys (e.g.

Mendres & de Waal 2000; Moura et al. 2004) are a

puzzle only if we adopt an anthropocentric, phyloge netic perspective.

There is strong neurobiological support for an embodied primate cognition (Perrett et al. 1990; Barton 1996, 1998; Rizzolatti et al 1996; Gallese

2005, 2006, 2007; Gallese et al. 2004). This provides the necessary springboard from which to test the

'physical grounding hypothesis' (Brooks 1999), which is the central project of EC (Anderson 2003). G?llese

(2001, 2003, 2005, 2006, 2007; Gallese et al. 2004), in

particular, has presented an extremely compelling argument for mirror mechanisms (systems of motor and pre-motor neurons, activated by one's own

performance of action and the observations of others' actions) as the basis of an implicit, automatic and unconscious understanding of others as goal directed agents.

The fundamental ability of the motor system to resonate when viewing action (and that extends to emotions and sensations; see G?llese 2006, 2007, for a

review) suggests that primates can establish a mean

ingful understanding of others, and of themselves, without any need for mental state understanding or overt conscious simulation. This is therefore a basic form of inter-subjectivity or empathy (Preston & de

Waal 2002; G?llese 2005). As a result, individuals

automatically generate affordances?possibilities for action?for the animals that observe them and

Phil Trans. R. Soc. B (2007)

This content downloaded from 144.173.6.145 on Thu, 13 Feb 2014 03:57:51 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

570 L. Barrett et al. Social cognition in primates

afifordances that are built directly into an animal's

perceptual representations. Social engagement may not

therefore require the 'propositional' knowledge that is often assumed (Zuberbuhler 2003; Cheney & Seyfarth 2005). Social understanding may, instead, be a form of

pattern recognition involving 'active' perception (No? 2004). It will then be better modelled and understood as embodied in the patterns of activation of neuronal

units, linked in distributed networks, than as some form of logical, syntactically organized computation (Clark 1993). Mechanistic explanations of this type can explain

why kin recognition in primates appears to be based on

familiarity and not on more specialized mechanisms like phenotype matching (Rendall 2004). Since neural networks require experience, they have the flexibility to

cope with changes in cue features over time (as naturally happens as individuals develop and age) lacked by the other more deterministic processes. Indeed, neural networks are the 'cellular instantiation' of familiarity: what the network 'knows' is that with which it is most familiar. The experiential plasticity of neural networks also allows a continuous updating of social signals, which can account for the proficiency

with which animals can perceptually track changing social cues (Rendall 2004). This makes such

mechanisms potentially more powerful than highly specialized mechanisms, because they are robust to deviations in cues or context. By contrast, the narrowly

tuned, specialized mechanisms used by, e.g. ants and

digger wasps, work extremely well in the correct

context, but can be perturbed by the smallest deviation from normal triggering conditions, revealing them selves as robotic and 'stupid'. Generalized

mechanisms, as they are more flexible, allow for more

flexible, contingent behaviour. For long-lived social primates, for whom both

physical and social environments are inherently unstable, such mechanisms are arguably more adaptive than specialized cognitive routines, such that we should

expect flexible, experientially informed pattern-recog nition to form the basis for much of primate cognition. The potential downside of such mechanisms is that

they are tissue intensive: large-scale pattern recognizers

require a lot of connectivity to implement (Clark 1993). In this case, however, it adds strength to our

argument, since it is precisely this extra requirement for neural tissue that the social brain hypothesis must

explain. While evolution is cost-effective, as Humphrey (1976) originally argued, this does not mean that it

must also be an efficient engineer, as we tend to assume. Convoluted, messy solutions may be both

necessary due to inherent, physical constraints on neuronal functioning, and made possible by the fact that evolution is liberated by having the time in which to come up with non-obvious, but effective solutions

(Clark 2000). Our take-home message, therefore, is that primate

groups are not more socially complex than those of

other animals per se, and it is not social complexity alone that has selected for greater brain size. Rather, these long-lived, group-living animals face significant changes in both social and ecological environments over the course of their lifespan, and synergistic effects

between the two (Sterelny 2007). Consequently, they require high levels of behavioural flexibility ('quotidian cognition'; Barrett & Henzi 2005), instantiated in generalized pattern-recognition networks, in order to survive.

The generation of hypotheses and predictions linked to pattern recognition argues for an increased focus on

naturalistic, observational studies of primate social interaction?the manner in which individuals respond to the social cues of others, the cues they themselves

display and how this leads to forms of behavioural coordination?rather than observations and experi

ments designed to tap into abstract, conceptual knowl

edge. The classic demonstration that monkeys understand rank relations, for example, does so by showing how the lower ranking of two individuals retreats at the approach of a third, higher-ranking female (Cheney & Seyfarth 1990). This is usually interpreted as an indication that individuals compute the rank relationships of others and do not rely on a

purely egocentric assessment. It could equally, however, be achieved by a simpler embodied

mechanism, more related to 'intentional attunement'

(G?llese 2006, 2007) than to 'propositional knowledge' (Cheney & Seyfarth 2005). Individuals may attend to the salient features of the responses of others to

particular events, generating distributed networks that can match these patterns when they recur. If the

approaching female provides physical cues and directs her gaze more towards one female, the approached animals can respond in different ways, depending on whether they are the focus of attention and for how

long this lasts. The lower-ranking female may show

greater muscle tension, stiffen her posture, show facial

expressions or make preparatory movements all of which enable the other female to infer an intention to leave and respond accordingly by remaining. While this is crude conjecture, it is, in principle,

plausible and can be tested. Monitoring the attention structure of such triads may tell us more about how individuals manage social engagement than does

interpreting social responses in terms of abstract rank

structure alone (e.g. Johnson & Oswald 2001). The

study by Paukner et al. (2004) showing how pigtailed macaques preferred to watch a mimicking experimenter, despite no overt recognition of the

mimicry, is therefore very interesting in this regard, since it flags up, quite literally, the salience of close behavioural coordination among partners. The find

ings of Chartrand & Bargh (1999) that similar non conscious mimicry can facilitate intimacy in humans, perhaps forming the true 'social glue' which bonds

groups (Lakin et al. 2003), therefore generate a testable

prediction with regard to the behavioural coordination shown by monkey affiliates. Placing a stronger, more

ethological focus on how individuals coordinate their behaviour under various conditions, we can begin to

hypothesize and test how the mechanisms that govern how they perceive, act and move in such an environ

ment are linked to the internal representations they generate: as Anderson (2003) states, representations are more likely to be governed by these practical criteria than by abstract or logical ones. G?llese (2007) is

already making great strides in specifying how

Phil Trans. R. Soc. B (2007)

This content downloaded from 144.173.6.145 on Thu, 13 Feb 2014 03:57:51 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Social cognition in primates L. Barrett et al. 571

embodiment scaffolds representational schema and influences higher-order cognition (see also G?llese &

Goldman 1998; Gallese et al. 2004). If behavioural studies also begin to pay more attention to the details of how animals perceive and act in the world, rather than what we think they think about it, then we can begin to consider seriously how 'lower' faculties might relate to

'higher' ones. Alternatively, as we argued above, they may reveal how the interleaving of perception and action in response to environmental structures elimin ates the need for certain high-level forms of processing altogether (Brooks 1999), or at least greatly reduces the

complexity of internal mechanisms.

Again, it is important to stress that this emphasis on embodied behaviour is not a return to behaviourism. This is because perception and action form 'loopy structures', where action generates perceptual feedback

that, in turn, generates further action, so that outward behaviour becomes an important co-contributor to the

processes, including neural processes, which generate further behavioural response (Keijzer 2005). As Hurley (1998) notes, by contrast, behaviourism assumes a

linear, one-way process where perception causes action

(i.e. input to output), but there is no further feedback from action to perception (i.e. output to input).

An embodied perspective, then, is one that allows us to consider social cognition as an observable, distributed event (Hutchins 1985; Brothers 2001; Johnson 2001), rather than as purely invisible, private ones. This view owes much to Heidigger (1927/1978), and the rejection of a 'Cartesian homunculus peering out at the world and seeing what's there' (Dourish 2001, p. 108) in favour of a world that is already structured meaningfully through a process of common, social practice. By the same token, when monkeys are born into their groups, they encounter a world of common social practice and what they learn, over the course of development, is how to participate. This is

something that is learned through participation itself

(Dourish 2001; Anderson 2003). For psychologists, this view goes back at least to

Vygotsky (1978) and the idea that cognition initially begins by being social and visible and is only later internalized and invisible. Models of mental represen tation are not rejected by such a view, as some might suspect, but rather can 'inform models of mental

representation by charting ontogeny through embodied interactions in the infant and its caretaker, the juvenile and its cohorts and the adult and its society' (Johnson 2002, p. 628). A distributed view, therefore, empha sizes that behaviour?or more accurately interaction?

is the source and cause of what must ultimately end up inside the head (Johnson 2002). Moreover, despite reservations that a socially distributed view is only of

any real relevance to humans (Tomasello & Call 1997), Strum et al. (1997), Johnson (2001) and Johnson & Oswald (2001) illustrate how this can be applied to other primate species.

In addition to other individuals, the surrounding physical environment provides cognitive resources.

Objects in the environment present animals with certain

'possibilities for action' (Gibson 1979) and afford certain responses (e.g. for humans, a chair affords the

possibility of sitting down on it). These afifordances and

their relation to ongoing activity can help us to understand how and why certain behaviours are played out in certain ways at certain times. Strum et al. (1997), for example, show how consort takeovers among male baboons are structured by the properties of the sleeping cliffs where these take place: the limits they place on

movement can be used to a male's advantage and lead to an unfolding of events quite different to those on the

plains (see also Johnson & Oswald 2001 on 'social tool use' in bonobos). In this way, Machiavellian intelligence need not be Machiavellian in the sense that currently holds sway, because the flexibility, unpredictability and

ingenuity shown by animals is due to processes that are distributed across brain, body and world.

The basic tenet of a distributed approach, therefore, is that dynamic social interactions do not merely point to internal cognitive acts but are cognitive acts in themselves (Kirsh 1996; Johnson 2001). Kirsh (1996) in particular distinguishes between 'pragmatic acts' that move an individual closer to a better state in the external environment, and 'epistemic acts5 that move

an individual to a better state in its cognitive environment. Epistemic acts, therefore, change the world in order to have useful cognitive effects on the

actor; they create cognitive affordances that help improve the speed, accuracy or robustness of cognitive processes, rather than enable the agent to make literal

progress in a task (Kirsh 1996). In humans, for

example, moving Scrabble tiles around makes it easier to see the potential words that can be formed, and can therefore be considered an epistemic act. This close

interleaving of physical and mental actions to reduce the complexity of a task means that it becomes

important to pay attention to the means by which an individual tackles a particular task, because the task is carried out partly in the individual's head and partly in its environment. The degree to which primates and other species engage in any kind of epistemic action is an empirical issue at present, largely because we have not looked for these kinds of behaviours in order to understand cognitive processes.

It should be readily apparent how this kind of

behaviourally oriented approach can also be used to test and develop the theories of intentional attunement and embodied simulation that emanate from neuro

biology (G?llese 2006, 2007). Mirror systems, in

particular, show us how, at the most fundamental neuronal level, our understanding of others is a distributed process that requires action in the world.

Hopefully, a better understanding of the embodied and distributed nature of social cognition in our fellow

primates will enable us to understand them on their own terms. Tying this to work demonstrating the embodied and distributed nature of cognition in humans (e.g. V?rela et al. 1991; Vygotsky 1978; Fogel 1993; Gallagher 2005) may then enable us to identify true commonalities across species, rather than anthro

pocentric chimera.

We would like to thank the organisers of the discussion meeting, Chris Frith, Nicky Clayton and Nathan Emery, for inviting us to participate. We are also grateful to John Vokey for many enlightening discussions of the issues presented here, and an anonymous reviewer for helpful comments on a

previous draft.

Phil Trans. R. Soc. B (2007)

This content downloaded from 144.173.6.145 on Thu, 13 Feb 2014 03:57:51 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

572 L. Barrett et al. Social cognition in primates

REFERENCES Altmann, J. 1980 Baboon mothers and infants. Cambridge,

MA: Harvard University Press.

Anderson, M. L. 2003 Embodied cognition: a field guide. Artif. Intell. 149, 91-130. (doi:10.1016/S0004-3702(03) 00054-7)

Andrews, K. 2005 Chimpanzee theory of mind: looking in all the wrong places? Mind Lang. 20, 521-536.

Aureli, F. & de Waal, F. B.M 2000 Natural conflict resolution.

Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

Barrett, L. & Henzi, S. P. 2001 The utility of grooming in baboon troops. In Economics in nature: social dilemmas, mate

choice and biological markets (eds R. No?, J. A. R. A. M.

van Hooff & P Hammerstein), pp. 119-145. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

Barrett, L. & Henzi, S. P. 2002 Constraints on relationship formation among female primates. Behaviour 139,

263-289. (doi: 10.1163/156853902760102672) Barrett, L. & Henzi, S. P. 2005 The social nature of primate

cognition. Proc. R. Soc. B 272, 1865-1875. (doi:10.1098/

rspb.2005.3200) Barrett, L & Henzi, S. P. 2006 Monkeys, markets and minds:

biological markets and primate sociality. In Cooperation in

primates and humans: mechanisms and evolution (eds P. M.

Rappeler & C. P. van Schaik), pp. 209-232. New York, NY: Springer.

Barrett, L., Henzi, S. P. & Dunbar, R. I. M. 2003 Primate

cognition: from what now to what if? Trends Cogn. Sei. 7,

494-497. (doi:10.1016/j.tics.2003.09.005) Barrett, L., Halliday, J. & Henzi, S. P. 2006 The ecology of

motherhood: structuring lactation costs in chacma

baboons. J. Anim. Ecol. IS, 875-886. (doi:10.1111/ j.1365-2656.2006.01105.x)

Barton, R. A. 1996 Neocortex size and behavioural ecology in

primates. Proc. R. Soc. B 263, 173-177. (doi:10.1098/

rspb. 1996.0028) Barton, R. A. 1998 Visual specialisation and brain evolution

in primates. Proc. R. Soc. B 265, 1933-1937. (doi: 10.

1098/rspb. 1998.0523) Barton, R. A. 2006 Primate brain evolution: integrating

comparative, neurophysiological and ethological data.

Evol. Anthropol. 15, 224-236.

Barton, R. A. 2007 Evolution of the social brain as a

distributed neural system. In The Oxford handbook of evolutionary psychology (eds R. I. M. Dunbar & L. Barrett),

pp. 129-144. Oxford, UK: Oxford University.

Bergman, T. J., Beehner, J. C, Cheney, D. L. & Seyfarth, R. M. 2003 Hierarchical classification by rank and kinship in baboons. Science 302, 1234-1236. (doi: 10.1126/science.

1087513) Brooks, R. A. 1999 Cambrian intelligence: the early history of the

new A.I. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Brothers, L. 1990 The social brain: a project for integrating

primate behaviour and neurophysiology in a new domain.

Concepts Neurosa. 4, 107-118.

Brothers, L. 2001 Mistaken identity: the mind-brain problem reconsidered. New York, NY: State University of New York

Press.

Bruner, J. 1990 Acts of meaning. Cambridge, MA: Harvard

University Press.

Bruner, J. 1991 The narrative construction of reality. Crit.

Inq. 18, 1-21. (doi: 10.1086/448619) Byrne, R. W. & Corp, N. 2004 Neocortex size predicts

deception rate in primates. Proc. R. Soc. B 271, 1693-1699. (doi: 10.1098/rspb.2004.2780)

Byrne, R. W. & Whiten, A. 1988 Machiavellian intelligence: social expertise and the evolution of intellect in monkeys, apes and humans. Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press.

Carrithers, M. 1991 Narrativity: mind reading and making societies. In Natural theories of mind: evolution, development and simulation (ed. A. Whiten), pp. 317-331. Oxford, UK:

Basil Blackwell.

Chap?is, B. 1992 The role of alliances in social inheritance of rank among female primates. In The role of alliances in social

inheritance of rank among female primates (eds A. H.

Harcourt & F. B. M. de Waal), pp. 29-59. Oxford, UK:

Oxford University Press.

Chap?is, B. 2006 Kinship, competence and cooperation in

primates. In Cooperation in primates and humans: mechanisms

and evolution (eds P. Rappeler & C. P. van Schaik), pp. 47-66. Berlin: Springer.

Chartrand, T. L. & Bargh, J. A. 1999 The chameleon effect: the

perception-behaviour link and social interaction. J. Per. Soc.

Psychol. 76,893-910. (doi:10.1037/0022-3514.76.6.893) Cheney, D. L. & Seyfarth, R. M. 1990 How monkeys see the

world: inside the mind of another species. Chicago, IL:

University of Chicago Press.

Cheney, D. L. & Seyfarth, R. M. 2005 Constraints and

preadaptations in the earliest stages of language evolution.

Linguistic Rev. 22, 135-159. (doi:10.1515/tlir.2005.22. 2-4.135)

Clark, A. 1993 Associative engines: connectionism, concepts, and

representational change. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Clark, A. 1997 Being there: bringing brain, body and world

together again. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Clark, A. 2000 Mindware: an introduction to the philosophy of

cognitive science. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

Clayton, N. S. & Dickinson, A. 1999 Memory for contents of

caches by scrub jays. J. Exp. Psychol Anim. Behav. Process

25, 82-91. (doi:10.1037/0097-7403.25.1.82) Clayton, N. S., Bussey, T. J., Emery, N. J. & Dickinson, A.

2003a Prometheus to Proust: the case for behavioural

criteria for mental time-travel. Trends Cogn. Sei. 1, 436-437. (doi:10.1016/j.tics.2003.08.003)

Clayton, N. S., Bussey, T. J. & Dickinson, A. 20036 Can

animals recall the past and plan for the future? Nat. Rev.

Neurosci. 4, 685-691. (doi:10.1038/nrnll80) Cords, M. 1997 Friendships, alliances, reciprocity and repair.

In Machiavellian intelligence. II. extensions and evaluations

(eds A. Whiten & R. W. Byrne), pp. 24-49. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

Damasio, A. R. 1994 Descartes3 error. Putnam.

Dasser, V. 1988 A social concept in java monkeys. Anim. Behav.

36, 225-230. (doi:10.1016/S0003-3472(88)80265-3) Datta, S. 1983 Relative power and the acquisition of rank. In

Primate social relationships (ed. R. Hinde), pp. 91-103.

Oxford, UK: Blackwell Scientific Publications. Dautenhahn, K. 2001 The narrative intelligence hypothesis: in

search of the transactional formats of narratives in humans

and other animals. In Proc. Fourth Int. Cogn. Tech. Conference CT2001: instruments of mind (eds M. Beynon, C. L. Nehaniv

& K. Dautenhahn), pp. 248-266. New York, NY: Springer.

Dautenhahn, K. 2002 The origins of narrative: in search of

the transactional formats of narratives in humans and

other social animals. Int. J. Cogn. Technol 1, 97-123.

de Waal, F. B. M. 1982 Chimpanzee politics: power and sex

among primates. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press,

de Waal, F B. M. 1989 Peace-making among primates.

Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press,

de Waal, F B. M. 1997 Are we in anthropodenial? Discover

18, 50-53.

de Waal, F B. M. 2001 The ape and the sushi master. New

York, NY: Basic Books,

de Waal, F B. M. 2003 Social syntax: the 'if-then' structure of

social problem solving. In Animal social complexity:

Phil Trans. R. Soc. B (2007)

This content downloaded from 144.173.6.145 on Thu, 13 Feb 2014 03:57:51 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Social cognition in primates L. Barrett et al. 573

intelligence, culture and individualised societies (eds F. B. M.

de Waal & P. L. Tyack), pp. 230-248. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press,

de Waal, F. B. M. 2005 Animals and us: suspicious minds.

New Sei. 186, 48.

de Waal, F. B. M. & van Roosmalen, A. 1979 Reconcilia

tion and consolation among chimpanzees. Behav. Ecol.

Sociobiol. 5, 55-66. (doi:10.1007/BF00302695) Dennett, D. 1989 The intentional stance. Cambridge, MA:

MIT press.

Dourish, P. 2001 Where the action is: the foundations of embodied interaction. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Dunbar, R. I. M. 1984 Reproductive decisions. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

Dunbar, R. I. M. 1988 Primate social systems. London, UK:

Chapman & Hall. Dunbar, R. I. M. 1991 Functional significance of social

grooming in primates. Folia Primatol. SI, 121-131.

Dunbar, R. I. M. 1992a Neocortex size as a constraint on

group size in primates. J. Hum. Evol. 20, 469-493.

(doi:10.1016/0047-2484(92)90081-J) Dunbar, R. I. M. 19926 Time: a hidden constraint on the

behavioural ecology of baboons. Behav. Ecol. Sociobiol. 31, 35-49. (doi:10.1007/BF00167814)

Dunbar, R. I. M. 1995 Neocortex size and group size in

primates: a test of the hypothesis. J. Hum. Evol. 28, 287-296. (doi:10.1006/jhev.l995.1021)

Dunbar, R. I. M. 1996 Grooming, gossip and the evolution of

language. London, UK: Faber & Faber.

Dunbar, R. I. M. 1998 The social brain hypothesis. Evol.

Anthropol. 6, 178-190. (doi: 10.1002/(SICI) 1520-6505 (1998)6:5 <178::AID-EVAN5>3.0.CO;2-8)

Dunbar, R. I. M. & Dunbar, P. 1988 Maternal time budgets of gelada baboons. Anim. Behav. 36, 970-980. (doi: 10.

1016/S0003-3472(88)80055-l) Eddy, T. J., Gallup, G. G. & Povinelli, D. J. 1993 Attribution

of cognitive states to animals: anthropomorphism in

comparative perspective. J. Soc. Issues 49, 87-101.

Emery, N. J. & Clayton, N. S. 2004 The mentality of crows:

convergent evolution of intelligence in corvids and apes.

Science306, 1903-1907. (doi: 10.1126/science. 1098410) Fern?ndez-Armesto, F. 2004 So you think you're human?

Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Fogel, A. 1993 Developing through relationships: origins of self,

communication and culture. Chicago, IL: University of

Chicago Press.

Gallagher, S. 2005 How the body shapes the mind. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

G?llese, V. 2001 The 'shared manifold' hypothesis: from

mirror neurons to empathy. J. Conscious Stud. 8, 33-50.

G?llese, V. 2003 The roots of empathy: the shared manifold hypothesis and the neural basis of intersubjectivity.

Psychopathology 36, 171-180. (doi: 10.1159/000072786) G?llese, V. 2005 Embodied simulation: from neurons to

phenomenal experience. Phenomenol. Cogn. Sei. 4, 22-48.

Gallese, V. 2006 Intentional attunement: a neurophysiologi cal perspective on social cognition and its disruption in

autism. Brain Res. 1079, 15-24.

G?llese, V. 2007 Before and below 'theory of mind': embodied simulation and the neural correlates of social

cognition. Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B 362, 659-669. (doi: 10.

1098/rstb.2006.2002) G?llese, V. & Goldman, A. 1998 Mirror neurons and the

simulation theory of mind-reading. Trends Cogn. Sei. 12, 593-609.

Gallese, V., Keysers, C. & Rizzolatti, G. 2004 A unifying view

of the basis of social cognition. Trends Cogn. Sei. 8, 396-403. (doi:10.1016/j.tics.2004.07.002)

Garbarini, F. & Adenzato, M. 2004 At the root of embodied cognition: cognitive science meets neurophysiology. Brain

Cogn. 56, 100-106. (doi:10.1016/j.bandc.2004.06.003) Gibson, J. J. 1979 The ecological approach to visual perception.

Boston, MA: Houghton-Miller.

Gigerenzer, G. 2004 Mindless statistics. J. Soc. Econ. 33, 587-606. (doi:10.1016/j.socec.2004.09.033)

Guthrie, S. E. 1993 Faces in the clouds: a new theory of religion.

Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Hampton, R. R, Hampstead, B. M. & Murray, E. A. 2005

Rhesus monkeys (Macaca mulatto) demonstrate robust

memory for what and where, but not when, in an open field test. Learn. Motiv. 36, 245-259. (doi:10.1016/j.lmot. 2005.02.004)

Harcourt, A. H. 1988 Alliances in contests and social

intelligence. In Machiavellian intelligence: social expertise and the evolution of intellect in monkeys, apes and humans

(eds R. W. Byrne & A. Whiten), pp. 132-152. Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press.

Harcourt, A. H. 1989 Social influences on competitive ability: alliances and their consequences. In Comparative

socioecology (eds V. Standen & R Foley), pp. 223-242. Oxford, UK: Blackwell Scientific Publications.

Harcourt, A. H. 1992 Coalitions and alliances: are primates more complex than non-primates? In Coalitions and

alliances in humans and other animals (eds A. H. Harcourt

& F B. M. de Waal), pp. 445-471. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

Harcourt, A. H. & de Waal, F B. M. 1992. Coalitions and

alliances in humans and other animals. Oxford, UK: Oxford

University Press.

Heider, F & Simmel, M. 1944 An experimental study of apparent behaviour. Am. J. Psychol 57, 243-259. (doi: 10.

2307/1416950) Heidigger, M. 1927/1978. Being and time. Oxford, UK:

Blackwell.

Henzi, S. P. & Barrett, L. 1999 The value of grooming to female primates. Primates 40, 47-59.

Henzi, S. P. & Barrett, L. 2002 Infants as a commodity in a

baboon market. Anim. Behav. 63, 915-921. (doi: 10.1006/

anbe.2001.1986) Henzi, S. P. & Barrett, L. 2003 Evolutionary ecology, sexual

conflict and behavioral differentiation among baboon

populations. Evol. Anthropol 12, 217-230. (doi: 10.1002/ evan.10121)

Henzi, S. P., Lusseau, D, Weingrill, T., van Schaik, C. P. &

Barrett, L. Submitted. Qualitative variation in social

networks and social bond strength among female baboons.

Hinde, R. A. 1976 Interactions, relationships and social structure. Man 11, 1-17. (doi: 10.2307/2800384)

Hinde, R. A. 1983 A conceptual framework. In Primate social

relationships: an integrated approach (ed. R. A. Hinde), pp. 1-7. Oxford, UK: Blackwell Scientific Publications.

Hrdy, S. B. 1977 The langurs of Abu. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Humphrey, N. 1976 The social function of intellect. In

Growing points in ethology (eds P. P. G. Bateson & R. A.

Hinde), pp. 303-317. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

Hurley, S. 1998 Consciousness in action. Cambridge, MA:

Harvard University Press.

Hutchins, E. 1985 Cognition in the wild. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Hutto, D. H. 2004 The limits of spectatorial folk psychology. Mind Lang. 19,548-573.

Joffe, T. H. 1997 Social pressures have selected for an extended juvenile period in primates. J. Hum. Evol. 32, 593-605. (doi:10.1006/jhev.l997.0140)

Johnson, C. M. 2001 Distributed primate cognition: a review.

Anim. Cogn. 4, 167-183. (doi: 10.1007/s 100710100077)

Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B (2007)

This content downloaded from 144.173.6.145 on Thu, 13 Feb 2014 03:57:51 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

574 L. Barrett et al. Social cognition in primates

Johnson, C. M. 2002 The Vygotskian advantage in cognitive

modelling: participation precedes and thus prefigures

understanding. Behav. Brain Sei. 25, 628-629. (doi: 10.

1017/S0140525X02300116) Johnson, C. M. & Oswald, T. M. 2001 Distributed cognition

in apes. In Proc. 23rd Annual Conf. of the Cognitive Science

Society (eds J. D. Moore & K. Stenning), pp. 453^158.

Edinburgh, UK: Human Communication Research Centre.

Jolly, A. 1966 Lemur social behaviour and primate intelli

gence. Science 153, 501-506.

Keeley, B. L. 2004 Anthropomorphism, primatomorphism,

mammalomorphism: understanding cross-species compari sons. Biol. Philos. 19, 521-540. (doi: 10.1007/sBIPH-004

0540-4) Keijzer, F 2005 Theoretical behaviourism meets embodied

cognition: two theoretical analyses of behaviour. Philos.

Psychol. 18, 123-143.

Kennedy, J. S. 1992 The new anthropomorphism. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

Kenyatta, C. G. 1995 Ecological and social constraints on

maternal investment strategies. Ph.D. thesis, University of

London, London.

Kirsh, D. 1996 Adapting the environment instead of oneself.

Adapt. Behav. 4, 415-452.

Kudo, N. & Dunbar, R. I. M. 2001 Neocortex size and social

network size in primates. Anim. Behav. 62, 711-722.

(doi: 10.1006/anbe.2001.1808) Kummer, H. 1968 Primate social organisation. Chicago, IL:

University of Chicago Press.

Lakin, J. L., Jefferis, V. E., Cheng, C. M. & Chartrand, T. L.

2003 The chameleon effect as social glue: evidence for the

evolutionary significance of non-conscious imitation.

J. Non-Verbal Behav. 23, 145-162.

Lakofif, G. & Johnson, M. 1999 Philosophy in the flesh: the embodied mind and its challenge to western thought. New

York, NY: Basic Books.

Liberman, M. D, Gaunt, R., Gilbert, D. T. & Trope, Y. 2002

Reflection and reflexion: a social cognitive neuroscience

approach to attributional inference. Adv. Exp. Psychol. 34,

199-249. (doi: 10.1016/S0065-2601 (02)80006-5) Mendres, K. A. & de Waal, F. B. M. 2000 Capuchins do

cooperate: the advantage of an intuitive task. Anim. Behav.

60, 523-529. (doi:10.1006/anbe.2000.1512) Merleau-Ponty, M. 1962/2002 Phenomenology of perception.

London, UK: Routledge Classics.

Moura, A. C, de, A. & Lee, P. C. 2004 Capuchin stone tool

use in Caatinga dry forest. Science 306, 1909. (doi: 10.

1126/science. 1102558) Muroyama, Y. 1994 Exchange of grooming for allomothering

in female patas monkeys. Behaviour 128, 103-129.

Nagel, T. 1974 What is it like to be a bat? Philos. Rev. 83, 435-450. (doi:10.2307/2183914)

No?, A. 2004 Action in perception. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

No?, R. 2006 Digging for the roots of trade. In Cooperation in primates and humans: mechanisms and evolution (eds P. Rappeler & C. P. van Schaik), pp. 233-262. New York, NY: Springer.

Panksepp, J. 1998 Affective neuroscience: the foundations of human and animal emotions. Oxford, UK: Oxford

University Press.

Paukner, A., Anderson, J. R., Borelli, E., Visalberghi, E. &

Ferrari, P. F 2004 Macaques (Macaca nemestrina) recognise when they are being imitated. Biol. Lett. 1, 219-222. (doi:10.1098/rsbl.2004.0291)

Payne, H. F. P., Lawes, M. J. & Henzi, S. P. 2003 Competition and the exchange of grooming in female samango monkeys

(Cercopithecus mitis erytharcus). Behaviour 140, 453-471.

(doklO.l 163/156853903322127931) Pazol, K. & Cords, M. 2005 Seasonal variation in feeding

behaviour, competition and female social relationships in a

forest-dwelling guenon, the blue monkey (Cercopithecus mitis stuhlmanni) in the Kakamega Forest, Kenya. Behav.

Ecol. Sociobiol 58, 566-577. (doi:10.1007/s00265-005 0953-3)

Perrett, D. et al 1990 Social signals analyzed at the single cell

level: someone is looking at me, something touched me,

something moved! Int. J. Comp. Psychol. 4, 25-55.

Povinelli, D. J. & Vonk, J. 2003 Chimpanzee minds: suspiciously human? Trends Cogn. Sei. 1, 157-160. (doi:10.1016/S1364 6613(03)00053-6)

Povinelli, D., Bering, J. & Giambrone, S. 2000 Toward a science of other minds: escaping the argument by analogy.

Cogn. Sei. 24, 509-541. (doi:10.1016/S0364-0213(00) 00023-9)

Preston, S. D. & de Waal, F B. M. 2002 Empathy: its

ultimate and proximate bases. Behav. Brain Sei. 25, 1-72.

(doi: 10.1017/SO140525X02000018) Range, F & No?, R. 2005 Simple rules account for the

pattern of triadic relations in juvenile and adult sooty

mangabeys. Anim. Behav. 69, 445-452. (doi: 10.1016/

j.anbehav.2004.02.025)

Read, S. J. & Miller, L. C. 1995 Stories are fundamental to

meaning and memory: for social creatures could it be

otherwise? In Knowledge and memory: the real story (ed. R. S. Wyer), pp. 139-152. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence

Erlbaum Associates.

Rendall, D. 2004 "Recognizing" kin: mechanisms, media,

minds, modules and muddles. In Kinship and behaviour in

primates (eds B. Chap?is & C. Berman). Oxford, UK:

Oxford University Press.

Rendall, D., Notman, H. & Vokey, J. R. 2007 Homologizing the mind. In The Oxford handbook of evolutionary psychology (eds R. I. M. Dunbar & L. Barrett), pp. 59-70. Oxford,

UK: Oxford University. Rizzolatti, G., Fadiga, L., G?llese, V. & Fogassi, L. 1996

Premotor cortex and recognition of motor actions. Cogn. Brain Res. 3, 131-141. (doi: 10.1016/0926-6410(95) 00038-0)

Roberts, W. A. 2002 Are animals stuck in time? Psychol. Bull.

128, 473-489. (doi: 10.1037/0033-2909.128.3.473) Russell, J. & Thompson, D. 2003 Memory development in

the second year: for events or locations? Cognition 87, B97-B105. (doi:10.1016/S0010-0277(02)00238-X)

Scholl, B. J. & Tremoulet, P. D. 2000 Perceptual causality and

animacy. Trends Cogn- Sei. 4, 299-309. (doi: 10.1016/ S1364-6613(00)01506-0)

Seyfarth, R. M. & Cheney, D. L. 1984 Grooming, alliances

and reciprocal altruism in vervet monkeys. Nature 308, 541-543. (doi: 10.1038/30854laO)

Sheets-Johnstone, M. 1992 Taking evolution seriously. Am.

Philos. Q. 29, 343-352.

Shettleworth, S. 1998 Cognition, evolution and behaviour.

Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

Silk, J. 1982 Altruism among female Macaca radiata:

explanations and analysis of patterns of grooming and

coalition formation. Behaviour 79, 162-168.

Silk, J. B. 1996 Why do primates reconcile? Evol Anthropol 5, 39-42. (doi:10.1002/(SICI)1520-6505(1996)5:2<39:: AID-EVAN2>3.0.CO;2-R)

Silk, J. B. 2002 Using the F-word in primatology. Behaviour

139, 421-446. (doi:10.1163/156853902760102735) Silk, J. B., Alberts, S. C. & Altmann, J. 2003a Social bonds of

female baboons enhance infant survival. Science 302, 1231-1234. (doi: 10.1126/science. 1088580)

Silk, J. B., Rendall, D., Cheney, D. L. & Seyfarth, R. M.

20036 Natal attraction in adult female baboons (Papio

cycnocephalus ursinus) in the Moremi Reserve, Botswana.

Ethology 109, 627-644. (doi:10.1046/j.l439-0310.2003. 00907.x)

Phil Trans. R. Soc. B (2007)

This content downloaded from 144.173.6.145 on Thu, 13 Feb 2014 03:57:51 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Social cognition in primates L. Barrett et al. 575

Silk, J. B., Alberts, S. C. & Altmann, J. 2004 Patterns of

coalition formation by adult female baboons in Amboseli, Kenya. Anim. Behav. 67, 573-582. (doi:10.1016/j.anbe

hav.2003.07.001)

Sober, E. 1998 Morgan's canon. In The evolution of mind (eds C. Allen & D. Cummins), pp. 224-242. Oxford, UK:

Oxford University Press.

Stammbach, E. 1988 Group responses to specially skilled

individuals in a Macaca fascicularis group. Behaviour 107, 241-266.

Sterelny, K. 2007 Social intelligence, human intelligence and niche construction. Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B 362, 719-730.

(doi:10.1098/rstb.2006.2006) Strier, K. B. 1990 New world primates, new frontiers:

insights from the woolly spider monkeys, or muriqui

(Brachyteles arachnoids). Int. J. Primatol. 11, 7-19. (doi: 10.

1007/BF02193693) Strier, K. B. 2002 Primate behavioural ecology, 2nd edition

Boston, MA: Allyn & Bacon. Strum, S. C, Forster, D. & Hutchins, E. 1997 Why

Machiavellian intelligence may not be Machiavellian. In

Machiavellian intelligence. II. extensions and evaluations (eds A. Whiten & R. W. Byrne), pp. 50-87. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

Suddendorf, T. & Busby, J. 2003 Mental time travel in animals? Trends Cogn. Sei. 7, 391-396. (doi: 10.1016/ S1364-6613(03)00187-6)

Thompson, R. K. R. 1995 Natural and relational concepts in

animals. In Comparative approaches to cognitive science (eds H. L. Roitblat & J.-A. Meyer), pp. 175-224. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Thompson, R. K. R. & Oden, D. L. 2000 Categorical perception and conceptual judgments by non-human primates: the

paleological monkey and the analogical ape. Cogn. Sei. 24, 363-396. (doi:10.1016/S0364-0213(00)00029-X)

Tomasello, M. 1999 The cultural origins of human cognition.

Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Tomasello, M. & Call, J. 1997 Primate cognition. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

Tomasello, M., Call, J. & Hare, B. 2003 Chimpanzees understand psychological states?the questions is which

ones and to what extent. Trends Cogn. Sei. 7, 153-156.

(doi:10.1016/S1364-6613(03)00035-4) Tremoulet, P. D. & Feldman, J. 2000 Perception of animacy

from the motion of a single object. Perception 29, 943-951.

(doi:10.1068/p3101) Turner, M. 1996 The literary mind: the origins of thought and

language. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

Tversky, B. 2004 Narratives of space, time and life. Mind

Lang. 19, 380-392.

Tyler, T. 2003 If horses had hands. Soc. Anim. 11, 267-281.

(doi:10.1163/156853003322773069) van Schaik, C. P. 1983 Why are diurnal primates living in

groups? Behaviour 87, 120-144.

van Schaik, C. P. & Kappeler, P. 1997 Infanticide risk and the evolution of permanent male-female association in non

human primates: a new hypothesis and comparative test.

Proc. R. Soc. B 264, 1687-1694. (doi: 10.1098/rspb. 1997.

0234) V?rela, F. J., Thompson, E. & Rosch, E. 1991 The embodied

mind: cognitive science and human experience. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Vokey, J. R, Rendall, D, Tangen, J. M., Parr, L. A. & de

Waal, F B. M. 2004 On visual kin recognition and family resemblance in chimpanzees. J. Comp. Psychol. 118, 194-199. (doi: 10.1037/0735-7036.118.2.194)

Vygotsky, L. 1978 Mind in society. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Whitehead, H. 1995 Investigating structure and temporal scale in social organisations using identified individuals.

Behav. Ecol. 6, 199-208.

Whiten, A. 2000 Social complexity and social intelligence. In The nature of intelligence, pp. 185-201, New York, NY:

Wiley (Novartis Foundation Symposium 233). Wittgenstein, L. 1968/1999 Philosophical investigations, 3rd

edn. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall. Wynne, C. 2004 The perils of anthropomorphism. Nature

428, 606. (doi:10.1038/428606a) Zuberbuhler, K. 2003 Referential signalling in non-human

primates: cognitive precursors and limitations for the

evolution of language. Adv. Study Behav. 33, 265-308.

Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B (2007)

This content downloaded from 144.173.6.145 on Thu, 13 Feb 2014 03:57:51 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions