shanon, b. 2003, hallucinations

29
Benny Shanon Hallucinations This paper examines the standard conceptualizations of the notion of hallucination in light of various non-ordinary phenomenological patterns associated with altered states of consciousness induced by psychoactive agents. It is argued that in general, the conceptualizations encountered in the literature do not do justice to the richness and complexity that the psychological phenomenology actually exhib- its. A close inspection of this phenomenology reveals some pertinent distinctions which are usually not made in the scientific literature. On the one hand, the discus- sion is based on first-hand experiences and, on the other hand, it is grounded in empirical and theoretical cognitive investigations of the phenomenology of human consciousness. Theoretically, the discussion is grounded in an approach highlight- ing the centrality of experience, meaning and action in cognition. Introduction Let us start with some definitions found in the literature. 1 The classical defini- tion of hallucination is often attributed to Esquirol (1845/1965): A man . . . who has the inward conviction of a presently perceived sensation at a moment when no external capable of arousing this sensation is within the field of his sense, is in a state of hallucination. (p. 93) Journal of Consciousness Studies, 10, No. 2, 2003, pp. 3–31 Correspondence: Benny Shanon, Psychology Dept, The Hebrew University, Jerusalem, Israel. Email: [email protected] [1] I do not include William James in this survey of standard definitions. This calls for an explanation, for in the Principles of Psychology, James (1890/1950) observes that ‘In hallucination there is no objec- tive stimulus at all’ (p. 115). On the other hand, James further argues that ‘An hallucination is a strictly sensational form of consiousness, as good and true a sensation as if there were a real object there’ (p. 115). He also emphasizes that there are various kinds and degrees of hallucinations. Indeed, in other, less known, texts James (see Burkhardt and Bowers, 1986) explicitly acknolwedges the problematic nature of the term ‘hallucination’. In part, the problems have to do with reasons similar to those indi- cated in this paper. Specifically, James (1890/1986; see also the long citation from a text by Sidgwick) objects to the various pejorative connotations people usually associate with the term — of these he critically mentions falsity, lack of meaning and value, and morbidity. Appreciating both the heteroge- neity of the phenomenon of hallucination and the connotation which he does not share, and consider- ing several alternatives, for lack of a better alternative, James decides to hold to the term ‘hallucina- tion’. Thus, it appears that despite the definition James offers in the Principles, which seems to be in line with the establishment view of hallucination, a broader inspection of James’ writings presents a view much more in line with the alternative picture presented in this paper. Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013 For personal use only -- not for reproduction

Upload: khriniz

Post on 12-May-2017

236 views

Category:

Documents


1 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Shanon, B. 2003, Hallucinations

Benny Shanon

Hallucinations

This paper examines the standard conceptualizations of the notion of hallucination

in light of various non-ordinary phenomenological patterns associated with

altered states of consciousness induced by psychoactive agents. It is argued that in

general, the conceptualizations encountered in the literature do not do justice to

the richness and complexity that the psychological phenomenology actually exhib-

its. A close inspection of this phenomenology reveals some pertinent distinctions

which are usually not made in the scientific literature. On the one hand, the discus-

sion is based on first-hand experiences and, on the other hand, it is grounded in

empirical and theoretical cognitive investigations of the phenomenology of human

consciousness. Theoretically, the discussion is grounded in an approach highlight-

ing the centrality of experience, meaning and action in cognition.

Introduction

Let us start with some definitions found in the literature.1 The classical defini-

tion of hallucination is often attributed to Esquirol (1845/1965):

A man . . . who has the inward conviction of a presently perceived sensation at a

moment when no external capable of arousing this sensation is within the field of his

sense, is in a state of hallucination. (p. 93)

Journal of Consciousness Studies, 10, No. 2, 2003, pp. 3–31

Correspondence: Benny Shanon, Psychology Dept, The Hebrew University, Jerusalem, Israel.Email: [email protected]

[1] I do not include William James in this survey of standard definitions. This calls for an explanation, forin the Principles of Psychology, James (1890/1950) observes that ‘In hallucination there is no objec-tive stimulus at all’ (p. 115). On the other hand, James further argues that ‘An hallucination is a strictlysensational form of consiousness, as good and true a sensation as if there were a real object there’ (p.115). He also emphasizes that there are various kinds and degrees of hallucinations. Indeed, in other,less known, texts James (see Burkhardt and Bowers, 1986) explicitly acknolwedges the problematicnature of the term ‘hallucination’. In part, the problems have to do with reasons similar to those indi-cated in this paper. Specifically, James (1890/1986; see also the long citation from a text by Sidgwick)objects to the various pejorative connotations people usually associate with the term — of these hecritically mentions falsity, lack of meaning and value, and morbidity. Appreciating both the heteroge-neity of the phenomenon of hallucination and the connotation which he does not share, and consider-ing several alternatives, for lack of a better alternative, James decides to hold to the term ‘hallucina-tion’. Thus, it appears that despite the definition James offers in the Principles, which seems to be inline with the establishment view of hallucination, a broader inspection of James’ writings presents aview much more in line with the alternative picture presented in this paper.

Cop

yrig

ht (

c) Im

prin

t Aca

dem

ic 2

013

For

per

sona

l use

onl

y --

not

for

repr

oduc

tion

Page 2: Shanon, B. 2003, Hallucinations

Practically all the definitions in the literature are variants of this old definition.

Thus, the Encyclopaedia Britannica (1971) defines hallucinations as:

The perception of objects with no reality or the experiencing of sensations in the

absence of the usual cause. In effect, a hallucination is a perception within or of a

person’s fantasy that is mistakenly ascribed, by the person who experiences it, to

sources outside.

Essentially identical definitions appear in the Grand Larousse and in many other

lexicons and dictionaries. For instance, Webster’s Third New International Dic-

tionary (1975) specifies that hallucination is:

Perception of objects with no reality; experience of sensations with no external

cause usually arising from disorder of the nervous system (as in delirium tremens or

in functional psychosis without known neurological disease).

Similarly, Reber (1984), in The Penguin Dictionary of Psychology, explains that

hallucination is:

A perceptual experience with all the compelling subjective properties of a real sen-

sory impression but without the normal physical stimulus for that sensory modality.

Hallucinations are taken as classic indicators of a psychotic disturbance and are a

hallmark of various disorders like schizophrenia.

Definitions in the medical and scientific literature are similar. Here is that given

by the DSM, the standard manual of the American Psychiatric Association (1994):

A sensory perception that has the compelling sense of reality of a true perception but

that occurs without external stimulation of the relevant sensory organ. (p. 767)

Likewise, a leading psychiatric textbook, Schrafetter (1980), explains that:

Hallucinations, or false perceptions, are diagnosed when someone hears, sees,

smells or tastes something, or feels something on or in his body, for which other peo-

ple can find no objective basis (p. 136)

Similar definitions are found in standard psychiatric lexicons (see, for example,

Campbell, 1981, and Noll, 2000).

A definition framed in cognitive–psychological thinking of the information-

processing orientation is that offered by Horowitz (1975):

Hallucinations are images based on immediately internal sources of information,

which are appraised as if they came from immediately external sources of informa-

tion (p. 165).

This definition differs from those cited above in its theoretical orientation, which

is more technical cognitive rather than epistemological or clinical. Yet, as far as

the basic view of hallucination it presents — as with respect to all issues to be dis-

cussed below — it is not essentially different from them.

The most extensive and thoughtful analysis of the phenomenon of hallucina-

tion in the literature is, I find, that presented by Slade and Bental (1988).

Grounding their discussion in a comprehensive empirical survey, these investi-

gators examine hallucinations from both a psychological and a clinical–psychi-

atric point of view and they also present an extensive theoretical analysis. They

offer the following threefold definition:

4 B. SHANON

Cop

yrig

ht (

c) Im

prin

t Aca

dem

ic 2

013

For

per

sona

l use

onl

y --

not

for

repr

oduc

tion

Page 3: Shanon, B. 2003, Hallucinations

Any percept-like experience which (a) occurs in the absence of an appropriate stim-

ulus, (b) has the full force or impact of the corresponding actual (real) perception,

and (c) is not amenable to direct and voluntary control by the experiencer (p. 23).

The first two criteria of the definition are in line with those of the various defini-

tions considered above, the third adds to them.

Summing up the survey of the literature, we note that a substantive consensus pre-

vails. By it, hallucinations are defined by the following cluster of characteristics:

i. Vividness: Subjectively, the experience is that of vivid perception.

ii. Non-correspondence: Factually, the experience does not correspond to any

real objects or state of affairs in the real world.

iii. Ignorance: The cognitive agent, however, is not cognizant of (ii).

iv. False judgement: Hence, the hallucinatory experience involves false judge-

ment on the part of the cognitive agent.

v. Negative evaluation: Thus, overall, the hallucinatory experience is evaluated

pejoratively, and it is assumed that it is of no positive import. Typically, the

experience is taken to be indicative of some psychological impairment.

vi. Dismissal: Implied in all this is the assessment that any person other than the

one having the hallucinatory experience will adhere to the negative evalua-

tion indicated in (v).

In this paper I would like to show that the common definitions of hallucination

and the conceptualizations on which they are based do not do justice to the perti-

nent psychological facts. It seems to me that the actual phenomenology of hallu-

cinations that human beings may experience is both richer and more complex

than these definitions may suggest. Highlighting these definitions, I shall point

out some cognitive distinctions which, to my mind, are central for any psycho-

logical study of the phenomenon of hallucinations. With this, I hope, new lines

for such a study may be charted.

Lest I be misunderstood, let me make a further clarification. Obviously,

simpliciter hallucination is, indeed, a perceptual experience in which lack of cor-

respondence to states of affairs in the real world is noted. The main aim of this

paper is not to debate with the simple, and obviously valid, core of the standard

definition but rather to point out that instead of opening the cognitive psycholog-

ical investigation of hallucination, this definition closes it. The goal of cognitive

research is to investigate the phenomenology of human mental life empirically in

a manner not constrained or bounded by prior preconceptions be they com-

mon-sensical or philosophical. The standard definition of hallucination is, I

believe, constrained in this manner. Only when this is appreciated can the per-

spective of investigation be changed and fruitful empirical research proceed.

Thus, I hope, the critical conceptual analysis will eventually bear concrete con-

structive consequences.

HALLUCINATIONS 5

Cop

yrig

ht (

c) Im

prin

t Aca

dem

ic 2

013

For

per

sona

l use

onl

y --

not

for

repr

oduc

tion

Page 4: Shanon, B. 2003, Hallucinations

Fundamental to the discussion to be pursued here is that to a great extent it is

based on first-hand experiences I myself have had with South American

psychotropic agents, all consumed in traditional contexts in Brazil and Peru.

Indeed, the distinctions and the various possible cognitive states of affairs indi-

cated below would not have occurred to me had I not had such experiences. It is

my firm belief that just as one cannot talk of music if one had not experienced

music first-hand, one cannot seriously discuss the phenomenology of the

so-called altered states of consciousness without actually having had a first-hand

feel of the non-ordinary experiences associated with these states. Being more

blunt, I would thus venture saying that, to a great extent, most scientists — phi-

losophers, psychologists and psychiatrists — who talk of hallucinations do not

know what they are talking about and that, in fact, what they say is more a reflec-

tion of their conceptual presuppositions with regard to this subject matter than a

fair characterization of the psychological phenomenology at hand.

Background Information

Before turning to the specific subject matter of this paper, let me present some

background information about the psychotropic substances I shall mention here

and about the context of their use.

Three substances will be mentioned in this discussion. All are very powerful,

and all induce vivid visual hallucinations. Hallucinatory effects in other sensory

modalities as well as marked ideational and affective effects are also common.

All three have been used by the Amerindians for millennia and have been at the

centre of their cultures. In particular, these substances have been pivotal in both

religious rites and shamanistic practices, and much of the artistic and cultural

creations of the indigenous societies in question — e.g., mythologies, music,

drawings and graphic decorations — were directly related to them. The primary

raison d’être for the use of these substances is the appraisal that they allow

human beings to transcend their daily existence and thus bring them in contact

with the Gods or the ultimate energies of Nature and Life (for a general discus-

sion, see La Barre, 1972). The healing effects of these substances are taken to be

a corollary of this.

The first substance, Ayahuasca2, is a brew consumed throughout the entire

upper Amazon, the main active ingredients of which are the alkaloids

N,N-Dimethyltryptamine or DMT, harmine and harmaline (for general discus-

sion, see Reichel-Dolmatoff, 1975; 1978; the various contributions in Harner,

1973; Luna, 1986a; Langdon, 1979; 1992; for a comprehensive bibliography see

Luna, 1986b). The brew is made out of two plants — Banisteriopsis caapi, a

liana, and Psychotria viridis, a bush (or rather, the leaves thereof). The indige-

nous peoples of the Amazon region have used Ayahuasca for millennia, and in

the past, the brew was the pillar of their cultures and used in all religious rites and

tribal ceremonies. Nowadays, Ayahuasca is still the basic instrument of shamans

6 B. SHANON

[2] I prefer to use the traditional, vernacular, names to refer to these substances, as the botanical ingredi-ents may at times slightly vary.

Cop

yrig

ht (

c) Im

prin

t Aca

dem

ic 2

013

For

per

sona

l use

onl

y --

not

for

repr

oduc

tion

Page 5: Shanon, B. 2003, Hallucinations

and medicine men in the entire region: it is said to enable healers to see the inner

constitution of their patients, and thus establish a diagnosis and perform treat-

ment (for general discussions of the healing practices associated with

Ayahuasca, see Dobkin de Rios, 1972; Langdon, 1992; Luna, 1986a). In this cen-

tury, in Brazil, a number of syncretic religious groups have been founded that

employ the brew in rites bringing together Christian and Amerindian traditions;

in some, Afro-Brazilian elements are incorporated as well. For further anthropo-

logical information the reader is referred to the works of Dobkin de Rios (1972);

Reichel-Dolmatoff (1975; 1996), Luna (1986a) and the anthology edited by

Luna and White (2000). For botanical, pharmaceutical and medical information

see Schultes (1972) and Ott (1993; 1994); for excellent artistic depictions of

Ayahuasca visions, the reader is referred to Luna and Amaringo (1993).

The second substance I shall mention is San Pedro (Trichocereus pachanoi),

an Andean cactus, the main psychotropic ingredient of which is mescaline. It,

too, has a long tradition of indigenous use. Nowadays, however, by and large this

use is confined to folk medicine. For Western accounts of mescaline-induced

experiences the reader is referred to Klüver (1928; 1966), Michaux (1972) and

Huxley (1971).

Toé, the third substance, is both the most powerful of the three and also that

whose use is the rarest. It is made from Brugmansia suaveolens (Floripondio, in

Spanish), a plant related to the Daturas. Unlike the two other plants noted above,

toé may be physiologically (as distinct from psychologically) dangerous. For this

reason, its use is much less common than that of the other substances mentioned

here (for a first-hand report, see Chango, 1984).

Personally, I have had extensive experience with Ayahuasca — I have partaken

of this brew about 140 times in various contexts and locales, both indigenous and

non-indigenous, throughout the Amazon region and elsewhere. With the other two

substances, San Pedro and toé, I have had only occasional first-hand experience.

Specifically, I have partaken of San Pedro four times and have inadvertently con-

sumed toé twice, in both cases as an admixture to Ayahuasca which was adminis-

tered by indigenous shamans in the Peruvian Amazon.

Finally, let me explain my own professional involvement with the study of psy-

choactive substances and altered states of consciousness. For the past decade I

have been engaged in a project concerned with the cognitive–psychological

aspects of the Ayahuasca experience. This is the first cognitive–psychological, as

distinct from physiological, medical, anthropological or applied psychological,

study of this brew. Its aim is to draw a systematic, comprehensive chart of the psy-

chological phenomenology of the state of mind induced by Ayahuasca and gain a

cognitive theoretical understanding thereof. Empirically, my research is based on

the analysis of both the records my own first-hand experiences and on interviews I

conducted with a large number of informants. The latter included indigenous and

non-indigenous individuals, coming from different personal and socio-cultural

backgrounds, who partook of Ayahuasca in different places and contexts through-

out South America. Preliminary reports of this research appear in Shanon (1997a,b;

1998a; 2001; 2002a); a full account of my work appears in Shanon (2002b).

HALLUCINATIONS 7

Cop

yrig

ht (

c) Im

prin

t Aca

dem

ic 2

013

For

per

sona

l use

onl

y --

not

for

repr

oduc

tion

Page 6: Shanon, B. 2003, Hallucinations

A Series of Examples

As noted, it is my firm belief that the topic of hallucination — like any other

aspect of the phenomenology of human cognition and consciousness — cannot

be studied in the abstract. It has to involve careful observations, and these have to

be collected first-hand. Thus, by way of setting the empirical grounds for the pro-

gression of our discussion, I shall recount some personal experiences. The spe-

cific reports were chosen because they exemplify what seem to me to be several

very different types of hallucination. In order to facilitate the reading, I assign a

label to each example; this label will serve for later reference.

Example 1: The golden city

This is one of the very first, and most powerful, experiences I have had with

Ayahuasca. It took place during day time when I was sitting on a small bench

looking at a grove of the Amazonian forest. When the brew had its effect, I saw

an enchanted city, all constructed of gold and precious stones. It was of inde-

scribable beauty. The scene that I was seeing appeared to be in front of my eyes

and, at the same time, separated from me — just as a scene in the theatre would

be. Every now and then I would turn my head aside and away from the scene of

the vision. Returning my gaze, I would come back to the same visionary scene I

had inspected before this turn.

Example 2: The enchanted forest

The occasion was the same as described in Example 1. Sitting there by the Ama-

zonian grove, I saw the forest in front of me full of animals — both zoological

and mythological. Amongst others, these included dragons, tigers and big birds.

With my eyes open, I was sitting viewing the forest as if it were a stage. It was as

if a screen were raised and another world made its appearance. Indeed, it was as if

the forest was revealing its mysteries to me. It was all blissful, and very real. The

experience coupled together exquisite aesthetic gratification, a profound sense of

personal well-being and a feeling that a new dimension of reality was revealed to

me. Now, almost ten years after this has taken place, I still consider this experi-

ence as one of the most beautiful, most enriching ones of my entire life.

While I was enjoying this spectacle, a group of young women were standing

off to one side singing. From time to time, I would turn my head and observe

these women. Returning my head to the fore, the same spectacle of the enchanted

forest would still be there in front of me. Once, I also nodded my head to the

women expressing my appreciation for their singing (this gesture, I shall note,

was socially appropriate, and acknowledged as such by the women). The distinc-

tion between what pertained to the hallucination and what pertained to ordinary

reality was clear-cut, evident and effortless. Just as a person in the theatre does

not confuse what he sees on the stage and in the hall (his companion sitting next

to him, say) so too here I did not confuse the creatures seen in the vision with the

real women standing nearby. On the one hand, my eyes were open and what I saw

in front of me seemed to be so very real; on the other hand, my perception of the

8 B. SHANON

Cop

yrig

ht (

c) Im

prin

t Aca

dem

ic 2

013

For

per

sona

l use

onl

y --

not

for

repr

oduc

tion

Page 7: Shanon, B. 2003, Hallucinations

physical environment, the (real) people and the (real) objects was totally normal

and I had no problem whatsoever in ascertaining who they were and to act prop-

erly towards them.

Example 3: The cosmic lottery

This too is an experience I have had with Ayahuasca. It took place in an indige-

nous Amazonian hut, in full darkness, and with my eyes closed. The effect of the

brew was very strong. In my vision I was thrown up into a realm high above the

planet and found myself in the midst of what I interpreted to be a cosmic lottery.

My understanding was that my entire existence, both physical and mental, was at

stake: If I played it right, I would be saved, if not, I would lose everything and

perish. In order to redeem myself, I began to sing. There was no reflection

involved in this decision, nor any recourse to past experience with Ayahuasca (as

would be the case today). For six or eight hours I continuously sang the praises of

God. The words that spontaneously came out of my mouth were Gloria a Dios

(in English, Glory to God); the melody was being composed as it was being sung.

As I was singing, I found myself to be surrounded by an immense choir of angels

— I was taking the leading role and they were accompanying me. The music was

exceedingly beautiful. Every now and then the choir was joined by guest groups

that came in, performed, and then left. Especially impressive was an orchestra of

Black players whose playing was very rhythmic and exceedingly sensual. Expe-

rientially, the vision was very real and I was a full participant in the act that was

unfolding. In the morning, when the session was over, the other persons present

told me that they were deeply affected by my singing.

Example 4: The rock lions

This Ayahuasca experience took place in the course of a religious ritual con-

ducted in a large circular building during the daytime. The building consisted of

pillars and a roof, but it lacked walls, so that nature was seen all around. The par-

ticipants in the session were all singing. At one point I looked outside and carved

out of the rocky hills surrounding the building, there were lions. The rock lions

were looking attentively, with interest and appreciation, to what was going on

inside the hall. When I would move my gaze to the inner part of the hall I would

no longer see the lions. Whenever my gaze returned to the hills, the very same

lions were there — just as I had seen them before. I wondered — are the rock

lions really there or are they just the fancy of my imagination? The answer that

came to my mind was that they were both. The animals I was seeing could not be

there without there being the rocks from which they were made. At the same

time, they could not be without my being there, me with my power of imagina-

tion. And it further occurred to me that, in fact, there was a third agent involved in

what was happening, namely, whatever was linking me to the world. When this

was appreciated, the dichotomous division between the internal and the external

seemed to lose much of its relevance.

HALLUCINATIONS 9

Cop

yrig

ht (

c) Im

prin

t Aca

dem

ic 2

013

For

per

sona

l use

onl

y --

not

for

repr

oduc

tion

Page 8: Shanon, B. 2003, Hallucinations

Example 5: The dilapidated house

This example was reported to me by an informant, a patient in the Takiwasi reha-

bilitation centre in Peru.3 The man was shown a dilapidated house. The house

was poorly maintained and piles of rubbish were all over it. A guide appeared and

explained that actually, when the house was built it was of good construction and

appearance. Only because it was not taken care of did the house reach its present

desolate state. The guide further explained that ‘The house is you’. ‘It is up to you

how your life would proceed: If you take care, you can make it into a good life.’

The informant explained to me that this vision had a deep effect on him, and that

it played a crucial transformative role in the further conduct of his life. I have no

way to verify the long-term effects of this vision, but I know of other persons

whose life was drastically changed for the better through similar experiences. In

many instances, the beneficiary effects of the visionary experience are very long

lasting and clearly observed by other people.4

Example 6: Insights

The last piece of data pertaining to Ayahuasca visions I shall offer does not pres-

ent the story of any specific visionary experience, but rather a summary state-

ment regarding insights gained in conjunction with such experiences. Insights

both I and my informants had involved themes of personal, psychological con-

cern, topics of special intellectual or professional interest, and ideas of general

philosophical nature (for a review of the latter, see Shanon, 1998b). In the indige-

nous Amerindian context insights pertaining to healing are especially valued. As

noted above, medicine men use Ayahuasca to diagnose their patients and to know

how to treat them. It is for this that Ayahuasca (along with other plants) is

referred to as a ‘master’ or a ‘teacher’ (see Luna, 1984; the notion of master

plants). Personally, with Ayahuasca I had various new ideas regarding my pro-

fessional concerns in the study of human cognition and consciousness. The

insights I gained in this fashion were novel to me and I considered them interest-

ing even when I returned to the ordinary state of consciousness; I still do. Similar

experiences were reported to me by my informants.

Example 7: The hippy

In a remote Indian village in the upper Amazon, an old indigenous healer admin-

istered Ayahuasca to me; the session took place at the inner yard of a house in

which his entire extended family resided. Unbeknownst to me the brew also con-

tained some toé as an admixture; only I partook of it. In the beginning, the session

proceeded in a manner which I recognized to be totally standard and rather

uneventful (this episode took place when I already had quite extensive experi-

ence with Ayahuasca). At a certain point the healer retired to sleep and I

10 B. SHANON

[3] In this centre cocaine addicts are treated with Ayahuasca. By comparision to other treatment of drugaddiction, the success rate of the treatment is high (see Mabit, 1996).

[4] Note the similarity between this kind of vision to parables, especially those of the Prophets of the OldTestament.

Cop

yrig

ht (

c) Im

prin

t Aca

dem

ic 2

013

For

per

sona

l use

onl

y --

not

for

repr

oduc

tion

Page 9: Shanon, B. 2003, Hallucinations

remained in the yard stretching myself out on a long wooden log and half sleep-

ing for, I gather, the last two hours of the night. When I opened my eyes it was the

beginning of day and I discovered that I was having great difficulty pulling

myself up from my prostrate position. Eventually, I managed — only to see, at

the corner of the yard, behind a door, a young man. He was a Caucasian, looked

like a hippy, and had what seemed to me an overall suspicious presence. Around

that time, the house began to fill with movement. The members of the family

were getting up and preparing for the day. Children were criss-crossing the court-

yard and their mother, the healer’s daughter, was helping them get ready for the

day. Whenever this woman passed, the suspicious looking man withdrew and hid

in a small space between the door and the wall. In that position he could not be

seen by anyone but me. He stared at me, and it was clear he was indicating that I

should not say anything about his presence. I did my best to avoid his look. I was

also preparing to leave and go back to the village hospice where I resided. As I

was doing this, however, I realized that one of my bags was gone. I had three

items with me when I arrived, I reckoned — two shoulder bags that contained

clothes and other personal effects and one smaller blue bag with all my guide

books, diaries and phone booklets. My legal travel documents and money were

tucked underneath my clothes on my body, but the material in the blue bag was

my actual connecting line to the world, and without the information contained in

it I could not go on with my journey nor establish contact with the many persons I

was planning to meet in the next stops of my planned itinerary throughout South

America. In addition to these three items, I had a plastic bag that contained a

flashlight, a bottle of mineral water and a roll of toilet paper. So, here I was —

getting up only to realize that one of my shoulder bags was gone. I looked

around, the hippy man was gone too. Evidently, he had stolen my bag. I went out-

side intending to alert someone, but all the people present were too busy with

their preparations for the new day. I tried to tell them that there was a suspicious

person in the house, but no one would pay any attention to me. I stepped back into

the inner yard, and I saw that now the second of my large bags had disappeared.

In my distress, I sat down on the log. And then I saw him again — that man. He

was looking at me half maliciously, half in a friendly manner. It was clear to me

that he was attempting to make a pact with me. If I collaborated, my belongings

would be given back to me. At any rate, I knew that I should beware and not tell

anyone of his presence. By now I was determined to get some help. I got up and

looked for the owner of the house. I stepped out of the house and tried to explain

what was going on, but, again, no one would pay attention to me. When I got

back to the inner yard, only the plastic bag was there. I could have managed with-

out my clothes and various travelling items, but with my blue bag gone I was

completely lost. What happened later is not of relevance here. Let me just point

out that in reality, all my personal possessions had been left securely in the lodg-

ing place where I was staying; when I got to the healer’s house, I only brought

along the plastic bag that contained those items that I deemed to be of potential

use for me during the session.

HALLUCINATIONS 11

Cop

yrig

ht (

c) Im

prin

t Aca

dem

ic 2

013

For

per

sona

l use

onl

y --

not

for

repr

oduc

tion

Page 10: Shanon, B. 2003, Hallucinations

I have described this episode at length, for toé intoxications are very rarely

described in the literature. I shall further emphasize that this experience was

totally different from those usually induced by Ayahuasca. First, it lacked any

fantastic allure. With Ayahuasca I have very seldom seen ‘regular’ persons — the

persons I have normally seen were royalty, historical figures, people of other

lands and other times. In the episode just described, the person I saw was a man

of our time that I could have met on the street. Second, the hallucination was

completely incorporated within the perception of the veridical world around and

there was no separation or distinction between them whatsoever. Indeed, and this

is a third point to be noted, I took the hallucination to be real, never suspecting

that it was not. With Ayahuasca this was never the case for me.

Example 8: The starry night

I was partaking of San Pedro in a session administered by a traditional Peruvian

healer; three other persons participated in the session. Apparently, on me the

effect was strongest and the other participants urged me to go out from the closed

hall in which I was sitting and join them outside around a campfire that the leader

of the session had set up. I had difficulty in motor coordination and one fellow

participant assisted me in my walk and placed me on a bench. There I was, in the

middle of the warm starry night, seeing the pastoral landscape around: There was

the campfire in front of me and several individuals, all of whom I recognized,

around it. By any external criterion, all that I have perceived was real; yet, to me,

experientially, it was all a dream.

Phenomenological Analysis — A First Round

Let me begin my analysis by examining the foregoing nine examples in light of

the specifications of the ‘consensus’ listed on p. 5 above.

Example 1 (The golden city) fully satisfies specifications (i) [vividness] and

(ii) [non-correspondence]. Clearly, neither specification (iii) [ignorance] nor

specification (iv) [false judgement] is met and in contrast to the stipulation of (v)

[negative evaluation], subjectively, the experience at hand is deemed, by the per-

son having it (me), to be a most rewarding one. Furthermore, the example shows

that the person experiencing the hallucination can effortlessly make a clear-cut

distinction between what pertains to the hallucination and what does not.

The example further indicates that, contrary to what is normally stated in the

literature, hallucinatory contents can have stability and experientially they can

be perceived as independent of the hallucinating person: the vision was not

affected by the movement of the subject’s head and gaze.

Example 2 (The enchanted forest) is, from a phenomenological point of view,

similar to Example 1 (The golden city). (As noted, the episodes described in the

two examples took place in the same afternoon.) I cite it in order to underscore a

difference with respect to specification (ii) [non-correspondence]: In the case of

Example 1 there was no correspondence between the vision and the world; in the

case of Example 2 there was partial correspondence between items in the vision

12 B. SHANON

Cop

yrig

ht (

c) Im

prin

t Aca

dem

ic 2

013

For

per

sona

l use

onl

y --

not

for

repr

oduc

tion

Page 11: Shanon, B. 2003, Hallucinations

and objects in the world (i.e., the trees). Furthermore, contrary to specification

(iii) [ignorance], the subject (myself) appreciated that he is hallucinating and was

cognizant of the correspondences (or lack thereof) just discussed. Significantly,

although from an analytical, external point of view, the difference between the

two examples with respect to specification (ii) [non-correspondence] may seem

categorical, it is not so from the experiential, internal point of view of the subject.

Indeed, experientially, the two episodes seemed to be on a par: both were very

vivid and in both the subjective feeling was that of a marvellous other reality

being revealed. Along with specification (iii) [ignorance], specification (iv)

[false judgement] is not met either. While the scene of the vision was vivid to the

utmost, it was clearly distinct and well segregated from the things that sur-

rounded me in the real world. The physical environment, the people, the objects

— I perceived them all in a totally normal manner, knowing exactly what they

were and how to act and interact with them. It was not unlike the situation in a

theatre hall or in the cinema. The curtain is lifted and one sees a scene depicting

other people, other places, other times. These scenes may strike one as very real

and they may strongly take hold of one both cognitively and emotionally. In the

case of the theatre, the people on the stage are indeed real. Yet in no way does one

confuse whatever one has seen either on the screen or on the stage with what is

there in the hall. Furthermore, one fully knows that what one sees is not reality in

the ordinary sense of the term.

Example 3 (The cosmic lottery) satisfies both (i) [vividness] and (ii) [non-

correspondence]. Specifications (iii) [ignorance] and (iv) [false judgement]

seem to be irrelevant — as the subject experiences himself being in a different

reality. It is not that the hallucinatory person misjudged reality; rather,

experientially he finds himself situated in a domain which is completely different

and separated from the ordinary world. Again, in contrast to what is stipulated by

(v) [negative evaluation], the experience is valued very positively. Furthermore,

contrary to what is indicated by (vi) [dismissal], the overt expression of the expe-

rience (i.e., my singing) was also held in high regard by other people.

Example 4 (The rock lions) is presented in order to further emphasize how

unsuitable for the characterization of the hallucinatory experience are seemingly

objective distinctions such as that differentiating between internal and external

realities (in contrast to (ii) [non-correspondence]).

Example 5 (The dilapidated house) and the insights subsumed under Example

6 are mentioned so as to present the long-term positive effects of the hallucina-

tory experience. These effects may be cognitive, affective, behavioural, spiritual

and transformative–psychological ones. In particular, it will be noted that the

insights gained during the so-called hallucinatory experience can be of value to

the subject and be deemed so even when he/she is no longer under the influence

of the psychotropic substance. The orientation adopted by the consensus would

dictate the opposite: By it, once an ordinary, non-hallucinatory stance is adopted,

the hallucinatory experience should be regarded as false and the insights drawn

on its basis would be dismissed. Surely, no positive import will be associated

with the hallucination, let alone a significant, long-term one.

HALLUCINATIONS 13

Cop

yrig

ht (

c) Im

prin

t Aca

dem

ic 2

013

For

per

sona

l use

onl

y --

not

for

repr

oduc

tion

Page 12: Shanon, B. 2003, Hallucinations

Example 7 (The hippy) is the only one in which all the specifications of the

consensus are met. In the episode it presents I had a false evaluation of reality

without being cognizant that this was the case. The experience was far from

pleasant, and the people around regarded my behaviour as disturbed. I should

note that this kind of experience never happened to me with Ayahuasca.

Example 8 (The starry night) is special because, by the standard definitions

encountered in the literature, it would not be deemed as hallucinatory at all. Spe-

cifically, the experience in question does not satisfy the crucial specification (ii)

[non-correspondence]. What the cognitive agent under the intoxication sees is

precisely what is there in the world. Yet, for him/her, what s/he sees is not real.

The perception is most vivid, yet is experienced as a dream. Furthermore, even

though specification (ii) [non-correspondence] is not met, the false judgement

indicated by specification (iv) [false judgement] is actually made and, in line

with specification (iii) [ignorance], the person at hand is not cognizant of that.

However, an external observer adopting the general orientation of the consensus

and of the definitions associated with it will not be aware of all this.

Let us take stock. Taken in unison, the foregoing examples demonstrate how

inappropriate the consensus is. Except for the first specification, which is neces-

sary for the discussion to proceed, all of them may be violated and yet, a radically

non-ordinary perceptual experience will still take place. Remarkably, Example 8

(The starry night) presents a case in which none of the specifications of the

consensus is met, yet from both a subjective experiential point of view and as far

as any meaningful cognitive–psychological analysis is concerned, the experi-

ence is definitely hallucinatory. Taken together, the examples discussed show

that the specifications are either inapplicable or irrelevant. Often, these specifi-

cations fail to capture those distinctions that are actually meaningful to the per-

sons having the experiences under consideration. Alternatively, they might force

differential categorization when as far as the substance of the matter is concerned

there is no real distinction (viz. Examples 1 and 2).

In conclusion, all this is tantamount to saying that the consensus and the defi-

nitions associated with it are neither empirically valid nor theoretically produc-

tive. In other words, these definitions and the specifications made by them do not

capture the interesting distinctions actually manifested by the psychological phe-

nomenology at hand, they do not capture the richness and complexity of the

domain under investigation, and they do not offer the proper framework for its

cognitive analysis.

With this critical conclusion in mind, we shall now turn to a more constructive

discussion and see how the foregoing analysis may further our understanding of

the cognitive–psychological phenomenon of hallucination.

Further Examination of the Definitions

Guided by the foregoing critical observations, let us take a further look at the def-

initions of hallucination cited in the opening section of this paper. Why are they

lacking? It seems to me that this is due to several basic features of these defini-

tions and some underlying assumptions on which they are based.

14 B. SHANON

Cop

yrig

ht (

c) Im

prin

t Aca

dem

ic 2

013

For

per

sona

l use

onl

y --

not

for

repr

oduc

tion

Page 13: Shanon, B. 2003, Hallucinations

First, the definitions are content-free. In them, the characterization of a mental

state as hallucinatory does not depend on the types of content experienced to be

seen during that state. In other words, the definitions pertain solely to the

epistemic status of the perceptual experience, not its semantics (nor, as shall be

noted below, their pragmatic). In this sense, they may be regarded as being struc-

tura–functional and not semiotic. Incidentally, this was not true of the original

use of the term ‘hallucination’, when first introduced into the English language

(at the beginning of the sixteenth century; see Sarbin and Juhasz, 1967). Then,

the term was used in conjunction with particular contents of false perception,

namely, the seeing of ghosts; in this respect, this term is closer to the modern term

‘apparition’.

Second, the basic criterion these definitions employ is physical, not psycho-

logical. Specifically, a state is considered to be an instance of hallucination if

there is an actual physical mismatch, or lack of correspondence, between a per-

son’s perceptual experience and putatively corresponding physical objects.

The third characteristic is related to the second. The evaluation of hallucina-

tion is external in the sense that it is accomplished by an observer other than the

person experiencing the hallucination. It is this external observer who attests to

the lack of physical correspondence indicated above.

The foregoing three characteristics are, I think, criterial; that is, they define the

core of the standard conception of hallucination in the literature. In addition, I

would like to single out two characteristics which may be regarded as typical, but

not mandatory.

The first of these two is an epistemic criterion, which is implicit in the standard

definition. I refer to the hallucinating subject not appreciating that he or she is

hallucinating or is in a non-ordinary state of mind (cf. in contrast to specification

(iii) [ignorance] of the consensus). The significance of this aspect of the defini-

tion is underlined when the contrast to pseudo-hallucination is made.

Secondly, the characterization of a state as hallucinatory often involves a value

judgement. Specifically, it is assumed that this state is a perturbation of normal

cognitive functioning, that it is a symptom of a mind which is deranged, that it is a

condition that, in terms of good mental health, one should hope not to be in. This

value judgement is pervasive throughout the medical treatments of hallucination;

in the definitions cited above it is explicitly specified in that of Reber.

Phenomenological Analysis — A Second Round

In light of the five characteristics introduced in the previous section, let us

re-examine the examples presented earlier.

Content and ambiance

Consider first the assumption regarding the assumed content-free characteriza-

tion of hallucinations. Clearly, this assumption is not supported by the facts.

Often, the very content of the hallucinatory experience is the major factor indi-

cating to subjects that the experience at hand is distinct from ordinary perception.

HALLUCINATIONS 15

Cop

yrig

ht (

c) Im

prin

t Aca

dem

ic 2

013

For

per

sona

l use

onl

y --

not

for

repr

oduc

tion

Page 14: Shanon, B. 2003, Hallucinations

Hallucinations — especially those, like the ones specifically discussed here,

induced by psychotropic substances — often present contents that would not be

presented by ordinary perceptions. Typically, these contents are fantastic and

they usually exhibit unusual beauty and magnificence. Ayahuasca visions very

rarely depict scenes that the subject could have encountered in his or her

day-to-day life. Usually, the scenes seen pertain to what seem to be other places

and times, ancient and futuristic civilizations, mythological realms and, last and

definitely not least, the realm of the Divine. In a cross-population investigation

of the contents of Ayahuasca visions I have conducted (Shanon, 1998a) — the

only systematic such investigation in the literature — it was found that the most

frequent items that appear in these visions include serpents, felines, birds, pal-

aces and temples as well as objects of art and magic — all items that normally are

not part and parcel of subjects’ daily life experiences.

Coupled with the special contents seen in Ayahuasca visions is the special

ambiance associated with these visions. This ambiance is characterized by

otherworldliness, enchantment, beautification (that is, enhanced aesthetic qual-

ity) and sanctity. Typically, this ambiance induces feelings of, on the one hand,

fear and awe, and, on the other hand, euphoria and profound well-being, spiritual

uplifting and religious sentiments as well as powerful mystical experiences. Psy-

chological insights, intellectual ideas and philosophical reflections are also very

common. All these characteristics have also been observed with other psycho-

tropic substances, notably mescaline (see Huxley, 1971; Watts, 1962; Masters

and Houston, 1966).

The distinct contents seen in the visions and the very special ambiance associ-

ated with them often serve as sufficient indicators to the visioning person that

he/she is in a non-ordinary psychological state. This is especially true of halluci-

nations induced by psychotropic substances, notably DMT (as in Ayahuasca),

mescaline (as in San Pedro and peyote) and psilocybin (as in the various ‘magic

mushrooms’). As indicated by Example 7 (The hippy), this is not true of toé.

In this regard, it is interesting to mark the contrast between the contents of

Ayahuasca visions and those of dreams. The following observations are made on

the basis of a comparative analysis I have conducted of the contents of these

visions and those of three corpora of dreams — my own, those reported by Freud

in his Interpretation of Dreams (1900/1953) and those analyzed in Hall and Van

de Castle (1966). The distributions of contents in the visions and in the dreams

were very different. The contents of regular5 nocturnal dreams usually pertain to

the dreamers’ daily life and concerns — the majority of the items seen in dreams

depict personal acquaintances and ordinary objects. As noted, the contents seen

with Ayahuasca rarely pertain to the ordinary.

Above, I have employed the terms semantic and semiotic. This is because the

considerations entertained here are similar to those encountered in the study of

texts and works of art. The question as to whether there is anything in the

16 B. SHANON

[5] The epithet ‘regular’ comes by way of a differentiation vis-à-vis lucid dreams. The phenomenology ofthese may actually be much more similar to Ayahuasca visions than to that of ‘regular’ dreams (seeLaBerge, 1985).

Cop

yrig

ht (

c) Im

prin

t Aca

dem

ic 2

013

For

per

sona

l use

onl

y --

not

for

repr

oduc

tion

Page 15: Shanon, B. 2003, Hallucinations

hallucinatory experience that can tell one that this experience is indeed halluci-

natory is analogous to the question of whether looking at the contents of a text

one is able to determine its literary genre. Well, perhaps not fully and unequivo-

cally, but usually something can indeed be said. For instance, gnomes, fairies and

witches are usually found in fairy tales whereas murdered persons and detectives

are characteristic of detective stories. As indicated above, a major distinction of

Ayahuasca visions is the non-ordinariness of their content. Apparently (on the

basis of Example (7) as well as on subsequent queries with several informants),

with toé this is not the case.

Physicalistic vs Psychological Approaches

Overall, an experience of perception without a corresponding object in the real

world is, of course, a key feature of the phenomenon of hallucination. However,

the examples we have considered reveal that at times things are less clear-cut.

The contrast between Examples 1 (The golden city) and 2 (The enchanged forest)

indicates that there are cases where there being a physical correspondence or not

is not as criterial as one may surmise a priori. Experientially, the episodes

described in (1) and (2) were very similar, and both were very powerful. The fact

that in (2) there was partial overlap between items seen in the vision and objects

in the physical world by no means detracted from the feel and power of the hallu-

cination. Nor did the fact that the subject (me) was cognizant of the correspon-

dences and lack of correspondences in question. Example 8 (The starry night) is

more extreme: It presents a case in which a hallucinatory experience occurs even

though there is full correspondence from a physicalistic point of view. Would we

say that because of the existence of this correspondence there is no hallucinatory

experience? Or shall we base our judgement on the individual’s subjective expe-

rience and say that since he/she feels that he/she is in a non-ordinary state of con-

sciousness, phenomenologically the hallucinatory states does indeed obtain? I

strongly opt for the second assessment. To my mind, the subject matter at hand is

psychological phenomenology and the aim of the scientific enterprise pertaining

to it is the analysis of human experience and the understanding of its nature.

There is no question about it: experientially — hence, I propose, as far as any

psychological inquiry is concerned — the case at hand is not one of ordinary per-

ception. This is so even though, from a physicalistic point of view, there is a cor-

respondence between what is seen in the hallucination and states of affairs in the

real world.

The external perspective

The consideration of the external perspective is directly linked to that of the con-

trast between the physicalistic and the psychological approaches. Manifestly,

some aspects of mental life simply cannot be captured by an externalistic analy-

sis. The paradigmatic case is that of subjective experience. As pointed out by

Nagel (1947), what distinguishes subjective experience is its being defined by a

point of view. States of affairs in the physical world are not defined in this manner:

HALLUCINATIONS 17

Cop

yrig

ht (

c) Im

prin

t Aca

dem

ic 2

013

For

per

sona

l use

onl

y --

not

for

repr

oduc

tion

Page 16: Shanon, B. 2003, Hallucinations

they can be investigated from any point of view, or rather — in effect, from ‘no-

where’ (see Nagel, 1986). Not so states of mind — these are grounded in a point of

view. Even when two persons entertain the same thought, even when two persons

see the same image (same in content and in structure), the very fact that each per-

son’s experience is his or hers renders these mental states distinct and different.

Thus, psychological phenomena are by their very nature subjective and internal.

Confronted with this, the psychologist can take one of two positions. The first

is to dispense with the subjective. This stance reflects psychologists’ great con-

cern with being ‘scientific’ and ‘objective’ and is grounded in a meta-scientific

perspective that regards the methods of the natural sciences as paradigmatic. By

this approach, then, if psychology is to be scientific it has to dispense with any-

thing that is intrinsically subjective. This, in turn, implies that psychological the-

ories have to be formulated in terms which are not genuinely psychological —

patterns of overt behavioor (as in behaviourism), brain activity (as in biological

reductionism) or underlying computational processes (as in the dominating para-

digms in contemporary cognitive science). Alternatively, it may be argued that in

psychology, subjective experience is the very topic of investigation (see James,

1890; Nagel, 1974; Searle, 1992). It is an objective fact that human beings have

subjective experiences. Such experiences are part and parcel of the fabric of the

world (see the essay ‘Does consciousness exist?’ in James, 1912). The job of the

psychologist is precisely this — to chart these experiences, to define lawful pat-

terns in them, to establish orders and interdependencies between them, and to

ground all these in a suitable theoretical framework.

Epistemic Considerations

Throughout the literature, not knowing that one is hallucinating is taken to be a

mandatory criterion for the experience to be characterized as a hallucination. As

indicated above, when this criterion is not met the label pseudo-hallucination is

usually employed. To my mind, this practice is misguided and it does not do jus-

tice to the psychological phenomenology at hand.

As revealed by the examples presented above (notably, Examples 1 (The

golden city), 2 (The enchanted forest) and 4 (The rock lions)), with Ayahuasca,

people do know that what they see are not ordinary perceptions. In other words,

the persons under the intoxication do know that they perceive without there

being a physical object, at least a physical object in the standard sense, in front of

them. Furthermore, it is very rare that drinkers of Ayahuasca confuse the visions

that they have with real-world objects or scenes. As indicated in Examples 1 (The

golden city) and 2 (The enchanted forest), drinkers usually differentiate between

the two correctly and the hallucinatory state does not lead them to relate to per-

sons and objects in the real world in a inappropriate fashion. This is the case even

when the hallucinatory experience may be very powerful.6

18 B. SHANON

[6] Leudar and Thomas (2000) present analogous data in the auditory modality. They point out that indi-viduals who experience auditory hallucinations may at the same time appreciate that the voices theyhear are not real.

Cop

yrig

ht (

c) Im

prin

t Aca

dem

ic 2

013

For

per

sona

l use

onl

y --

not

for

repr

oduc

tion

Khristos
Highlight
Page 17: Shanon, B. 2003, Hallucinations

At the same time, what is seen in the visions is not simply dismissed as

‘unreal’. Rather, the common assessment subjects make is that this material per-

tains to another kind of reality. The assessment is based on the coupling of two

features of the visions: On the one hand, they appear so vivid, so stupendous,

and, indeed, so very real; on the other hand, the states of affairs presented in them

are so different from anything one has encountered in one’s regular life and they

seem to surpass the scope of one’s personal imagination. I shall note that this

stance towards the visionary material is adopted even by individuals with no

prior familiarity with Ayahuasca and that in general it perseveres long after the

intoxication is over.

From an epistemic point of view, also pertinent are subjects’ attitudes towards

the insights and ideations associated with the visions. These insights and ide-

ations may be either psychological (concerning either the subject or other per-

sons he/she knows) or intellectual (concerning various subject matters, not

necessarily ones with which the subject is concerned with in his/her ordinary

life). Ideations of metaphysical and theological nature are especially common

with Ayahuasca (see Shanon, 1998b). As indicated above, subjects highly value

these insights and ideations and very often these become permanently held

beliefs and opinions. Furthermore, as in Example 5 (The dilapidated house), the

psychological insights often have concrete ramifications resulting in profound

personal transformations and actual changes in people’s conduct of their lives. I

shall also note that similar effects are encountered with mystical experiences

which are not substance induced, be they associated with visions or not. Indeed,

noetic feelings (that is, the subjective experience that one is gaining knowledge)

have been singled out as a key characteristic feature of mystical experience in

general (see James, 1929, and Stace, 1961).

Value judgements

Of all the specifications of the consensus, that pertaining to value judgements is

the only one that has been seriously contested in the literature. It has been noted

that there are social and cultural contexts in which hallucinatory experiences are

highly valued and are believed to afford psychological and spiritual growth (see,

for instance, Sarbin, 1967; La Barre, 1975; Sarbin and Juhasz, 1975; Slade and

Bentall, 1988; Bentall, 2000; Leudar and Thomas, 2000). As indicated above,

this is true of the traditional Amerindian cultures. Psychotropic substances were

central to both the religious and the social life of these cultures and were promi-

nent in their various aspects of the artistic expressions, notably myths, music and

drawing (see, for instance, Reichel-Dolmatoff, 1975). Universally, these sub-

stances were considered as sacred and regarded as masters and teachers leading

human beings to knowledge (see, for instance, Luna, 1984). In fact, in pre-

Colombian America they were all considered to be ‘Plants of the Gods’ and even

divinities in their own right. It goes without saying that these substances were

always used in the context of sacred ritualized ceremonies and never in an indi-

vidualistic, recreational manner.

HALLUCINATIONS 19

Cop

yrig

ht (

c) Im

prin

t Aca

dem

ic 2

013

For

per

sona

l use

onl

y --

not

for

repr

oduc

tion

Page 18: Shanon, B. 2003, Hallucinations

The negative value judgements noted are, of course, reflections of a general

bias of the contemporary secular Western civilization (for general discussion, see

Ott, 1995). However, important as it is from a socio-cultural point of view, this

aspect of the definition of hallucination is not of much psychological and philo-

sophical interest to us here. It reflects important social biases and prejudices, but

not cognitive assumptions of any theoretical import. Thus, the judgements at

hand may be very important in sociological and anthropological studies of

altered states of consciousness, but not to us here. For general anthropological

and cross-cultural discussions, the reader is referred to Bourguignon (1970),

Furst (1976) and Dobkin de Rios (1984).

More than anything, the negative value judgements reflect the psychological

literature on hallucination being based on clinical observations of psychiatric

and neurological patients. For these individuals, hallucinations are the symptom

of an unhappy condition which is neither wanted nor desired. This, however,

need not be universally the case. Opening the study of hallucinations to non-

patient populations and to contexts that value the hallucinatory state positively,

may, I suspect, have substantive effect on the conceptualization of the phenome-

non of hallucination and its cognitive understanding.

Having said the above, let me clearly acknowledge that psychopathology is an

unhappy fact of the human condition, and that hallucination can indeed be a

symptom of neurological and psychological dysfunction. There is no question

about it: The psychological states of psychotic patients and of persons willingly

partaking of psychoactive substances (especially in controlled ritualised con-

texts that are embedded in an established socio-cultural framework!) are categor-

ically different. Thus, Walsh (1990) points out that whereas the shamanic

experience is structured, the psychotic one is not, and while the shaman finds joy

and fulfilment in his experience the psychiatric patient does not. The discussion

presented here aims at marking the limitations and failures of the standard theo-

retical conceptualization of hallucination; by no means am I claiming that stan-

dard distinctions and analyses are inappropriate in the clinical context of their

application.

Phenomenological Analysis — A Third Round

Before I proceed to more general theoretical considerations, I would like to high-

light another phenomenological aspect revealed by the examples discussed here.

I refer to variations with respect to the experiences of reality. In this respect, I

would like to distinguish three main types of hallucinatory experiences.

First are experiences in which non-real scenes are perceived as if they were

real without the experiencer appreciating this to be the case. Essentially, this is

the state indicated by the standard definitions of hallucination in the literature.

With psychotropic substances, however, experiences of this kind are rare. Per-

sonally, I have experienced this type of hallucinatory state only with toé, as in

Example 7 (The hippy).

Experiences of the second kind constitute the paradigmatic case discussed

here. In it, non-real scenes are perceived as real while the experiencer does

20 B. SHANON

Cop

yrig

ht (

c) Im

prin

t Aca

dem

ic 2

013

For

per

sona

l use

onl

y --

not

for

repr

oduc

tion

Page 19: Shanon, B. 2003, Hallucinations

appreciate this to be the case. Two subsidiary distinctions will be made between

major and minor types of such experiences, the difference having to do with the

impact of the hallucination and the significance attached to it. In the cases char-

acterized as minor, all sorts of non-standard perceptions are experienced but not

much significance is associated with them and the psychological and/or spiritual

impact they have on the experiencer is not remarkable. In contrast, in the major

hallucinatory experiences, the subject encounters entire scenes that he/she appre-

ciates as non-real in the standard sense of the term but comes to appreciate as real

in another sense. Universally, the experience is regarded as presenting one with

another, ‘separate’, reality. I shall emphasize that I am not making any ontologi-

cal statement here; my concern is only with human psychology. What is signifi-

cant to us here is that, regardless of the status the visions might have in any

absolute ontological sense, cognitively they are experienced as real. Furthermore

(and as will be further discussed below) a distinction is usually made between

this reality and the ordinary one. The conferral of reality has various repercus-

sions which extend beyond the hallucinatory phase itself (hence, beyond the

physiological state of intoxication). In particular, the visions may radically mod-

ify one’s worldview, lead to new beliefs that one will regard as veridical long

after the hallucinatory experience itself. As a result, people often undergo major

personal transformations which may very well have concrete manifestations in

the future conduct of their lives.

The third type of hallucinatory experience noted here is one in which the real

is perceived as not-real. Again, in the context of psychotropic substances this is a

rare case and I myself have experienced it only once, in conjunction with San

Pedro as recounted in Example 8 (The starry night).

The distinctions just noted bring us to a more general, theoretical analysis of

the experience of reality.

Further Theoretical Considerations

I now turn to more general theoretical considerations. Central in the following

discussion is the topic of reality and the assessment that, as far as the psychology

of hallucination is concerned, the dichotomous distinction between reality and

non-reality is not sufficient. Thus, a third status, that of non-ordinary reality, will

be introduced. The discussion will be related to the topic of fiction and special

emphasis will be made on pragmatic considerations.

Before I proceed, I shall emphasize once again that what I am discussing here

is the phenomenology of experience, not ontology. All distinctions made here are

introduced by way of attempting a systematic charting of this phenomenology

and defining significant lawful patterns in it. No metaphysical or paranormal

conclusions whatsoever are implied.

Reality, non-reality and other-reality

The data we have surveyed suggest that in addition to reality and non-reality, the

phenomenology of hallucination calls for a third category, one of other-reality.

HALLUCINATIONS 21

Cop

yrig

ht (

c) Im

prin

t Aca

dem

ic 2

013

For

per

sona

l use

onl

y --

not

for

repr

oduc

tion

Page 20: Shanon, B. 2003, Hallucinations

From an external, physicalistic point of view the hallucinatory perceptions are,

of course, not real. In this sense, the standard definitions of hallucination are

valid. But, again, the question is how insightful and enriching these definitions

are, and what their import on the further study of hallucination is. A main point of

my critique is that labelling the hallucinatory perceptions as non-real will not do

justice to the psychological phenomenology at hand. Phenomenologically, these

perceptions are characterized by several features that distinguish them from

mere illusions or phantasms and, by contrast, mark a commonality between them

and ordinary perception of what is normally deemed to be real. Essentially, all

these features are the various facets or symptoms of one underlying common

denominator, namely, the feeling that what is seen is not dependent on the indi-

vidual at hand. This quality is to be denoted by the term otherworldliness; the fol-

lowing are several aspects that characterize this quality.

The first aspect pertains to content. Typically, the contents of the visions are

unfamiliar — they need not be related to one’s life history nor to one’s socio-cul-

tural background and they present states of affairs that strike one as foreign and

which one had not known of beforehand. The second aspect or symptom has to

do with the general ambiance of the visionary experience. Often what one sees is

so magnificent, awesome and/or wondrous that one feels that it is not possible

that these are merely the fancies of human imagination. Third to be noted is the

ideational aspect. As noted in Example 5 (The dilapidated house) above, the

visionary experience often imparts upon people insights and ideas that they

regard as true, meaningful and important. Not infrequently, these effects have

concrete, long-lasting ramifications.

The characterization of what is presented by the visions as pertaining to

another reality is also grounded in direct experience in a manner not attributable

to specific details of content or meaning. I am referring to a non-mediated experi-

ence of evidentiality: One sees and one believes. Directly related to evidentiality

is what may be referred to as the gripping quality of the hallucinatory experience.

When this experience is powerful, one feels that without having any say or

choice in the matter, one is sucked into it. Come to think of it, the same holds for

ordinary perception (see Llinás and Ribary, 1994).

Not only what is seen in hallucination may be deemed as ‘real’, it may be

regarded as ‘more real than real’. Many have argued that what distinguishes true

perception, on the one hand, and memories, imagination and dreams, on the

other, is that the former is clearer, more distinct, and more coherent than the latter

(for a classical analysis, see Hume, 1739/1978; for a modern treatment, see

Casey, 1976). In contrast, the Ayahuasca experience presents cases of an enhanced

sense of reality. Typically coupled with it are an enhanced sense of meaning-

fulness and noesis (feeling of knowledge).

Fictionality

The introduction of a state of affairs which is neither real (in the ordinary sense)

nor unreal is, in fact, familiar to us all. Some of the experiences considered in the

22 B. SHANON

Cop

yrig

ht (

c) Im

prin

t Aca

dem

ic 2

013

For

per

sona

l use

onl

y --

not

for

repr

oduc

tion

Page 21: Shanon, B. 2003, Hallucinations

foregoing discussion are reminiscent of those encountered in a theatre hall or in

the cinema. In plays we are presented with, and even carried into, a world of fic-

tion. The curtain is lifted and one sees scenes depicting other people, other

places, other times. These scenes may strike one as very real and they may

strongly take hold of one both cognitively and emotionally. In the case of the

theatre, it is further the case that the people on the stage over there are indeed real

people. Yet, in no way does one confuse whatever one sees either on the screen or

on the stage with what is there in the hall around one. Furthermore, one fully

knows that what one sees is not reality in the ordinary sense of the term. And still,

the psychological effect of what one observes may be both powerful and mean-

ingful. On the one hand, a film or a play may cause one to laugh or cry; on the

other hand, films and plays may have significant, and even long-lasting, effects

on viewers’ beliefs and attitudes. Thus, while not real in the ordinary sense of the

term, the fictional has a reality of its own, one which is distinct from both the

(ordinary) real and the (ordinary) unreal. I propose that hallucinations be treated

in the same fashion: rather than dismissing them as unreal, it would be more

proper to characterize them as fictional.

By way of further driving my point, let me present the following hypothetical

scenario. In the midst of a performance of Hamlet, a person in the audience raises

up and shouts: ‘I know this man, he is not the Prince of Denmark, he is my neigh-

bour John Smith!’. The ridiculousness of this act calls for no further comment.

But note: It is grounded in exactly the very externalistic, semantically naïve, per-

spective which is the basis for the standard definition and treatment of hallucina-

tion in the literature.

Fiction is not only an epistemic status, it is a domain of artistic creation and

genius. The achievements of the author of fiction are not confined to the creation

of another reality — this is a mere, very elementary, outcome of his/her toil.

What differentiates works of fiction and what makes them great is their semiotic

richness, the structural complexity they exhibit, the formal compositions they

present. The same is true with hallucinations. Complex visionary experiences

may be composed of several visions that are linked in various manners. These

include semantic variations on a common theme, the intercalation of two the-

matic series, visions within visions, and higher order visions. Focusing on this

phenomenological richness opens the door for, to my mind, is the really interest-

ing, psychologically genuine, study of hallucination.

The pragmatic dimension

On several occasions throughout the foregoing discussion allusions to actual,

manifest behaviour were made. These indicate that the hallucinatory experience

is not merely a perceptual one, it also pertains to action. Following is a review of

the different actional facets of this experience; on the basis of it, I shall argue that

the study of hallucination cannot be confined to the semantic (or semiotic) level

and that it should also involve a pragmatic dimension.

HALLUCINATIONS 23

Cop

yrig

ht (

c) Im

prin

t Aca

dem

ic 2

013

For

per

sona

l use

onl

y --

not

for

repr

oduc

tion

Page 22: Shanon, B. 2003, Hallucinations

The first pragmatic aspect to be noted is enactment: the hallucinatory experi-

ence is not confined to perception, it may also involve action. Indeed, when

visions are powerful, the person under the intoxication stops being a mere specta-

tor and he/she may assume the role of an actor. As described in detail in Shanon

(2002b), enactments of this kind have a different form, differing in degree of

involvement and level of initiative. One may step into the scene of one’s visions

but remain passive and not move about, one may move about in the scene but not

interact with the beings and objects in it, and one may totally immerse oneself

within the scene and act within it as if in reality. At times, immersion may be cou-

pled with an experience of identity change and metamorphosis — in these one

feels that one is transformed into another person or creature.

The second pragmatic aspect to be noted is one that is also encountered in con-

junction with films and plays. As indicated above, attending these involves a dif-

ferential pattern of behaviour whereby some manifest behaviours normally

associated with the real world are allowed, but others not. Normally, laughing or

weeping in the lack of any real cause is considered inappropriate, but doing so

when watching a film or a play is totally acceptable. In contrast, attempting to

converse with the people seen in a film or a play is ludicrous; this is the case even

though the people on stage are actually flesh and blood. Likewise in the case of

visionary experience. It is simply not true to say that since the hallucinations are

not real, any behaviour relating to them which is manifest is, by dint of this very

fact, inappropriate. As in the case of fiction, some manifest behaviours executed

in conjunction with hallucinations are definitely appropriate. As shown in Exam-

ple 3 (The cosmic lottery), the most salient such behaviour is singing, Often, the

activities in question exhibit remarkable levels of performance and are appreci-

ated as special also by external observers not under the influence. Thus, just as

with respect to reality, where the dichotomous distinction between real and

non-real is not sufficient, so on the pragmatic level: distinct profiles of appropri-

ateness have to be invoked. Systematically charting the various profiles of prag-

matic appropriateness can serve, I propose, as a new and constructive basis for

the psychological study of hallucination.

The assessment that hallucinations are associated with differential, non-stan-

dard profiles of appropriateness may be linked to the following ethnographic

observation. When in the Amazon, I collected indigenous myths related to

Ayahuasca. In one such myth mention was made of creatures that disappear once

they are touched. It seems to me that this distinction reflects the fact that tactile

hallucinations are especially rare: The modality of vision is far more likely to

produce hallucinations than the modality of touch. Thus, if under the Ayahuasca

intoxication a person were to test his or her visions with the touch of the hand,

this person would be likely to lose the hallucinatory experience. If, indeed, one

wishes to maintain this experience, one had better not attempt to touch what one

sees in the hallucination. Thus, as far as the hallucinatory state is concerned, not

all behaviours are on the same par. With experience, people learn the constraints

on the spectrum of behaviours that may be invoked in conjunction with this state.

24 B. SHANON

Cop

yrig

ht (

c) Im

prin

t Aca

dem

ic 2

013

For

per

sona

l use

onl

y --

not

for

repr

oduc

tion

Page 23: Shanon, B. 2003, Hallucinations

Lastly, let me mention overt patterns of behaviour that are part and parcel of

the special state of mind induced by psychotropic substances. Being manifest,

these are actually observable from an external point of view. In the context of

Ayahuasca especially noted are activities associated with music: singing, the

playing of instruments, dancing. Under the intoxication, some people achieve

remarkable accomplishments in these activities. Again, the achievements are

observable and can be appreciated and enjoyed also by external observers.

Back to the definition of hallucination

Earlier in this article I criticized the standard definitions of hallucination, and

argued that qua psychological phenomenon hallucination has to be investigated

from the internal point of view of subjective experience. The consideration of the

pragmatic dimension brings forth additional features of these definitions and

marks further limitations thereof.

As we have seen, the external, physicalistic perspective assumed by the stan-

dard definitions involves a criterion of correspondence (and the marking of

non-correspondence between experienced percepts and states of affairs in the

external world). This criterion is also central in the domain of semantics. Spe-

cifically, in classical theories the meaning of expressions is established by refer-

ence to a correspondence to states of affairs that these expressions represent or

refer to (see Frege, 1892/1952 ; Wittgenstein, 1922; Tarsky, 1944). Following the

later work of Wittgenstein (1953; 1958), correspondence accounts of meaning

have been criticized and alternatives based on the notion of verbal behaviour and

language use were put forward (see, for instance, Austin, 1962; Searle, 1969).

Such accounts carry the study of meaning from the strict domain of semantics

and bring it to the more general realm of pragmatics (see also Shanon, 1988;

1993). The ideas presented here define an analogous move — from the semantic

to the pragmatic — in a new domain, hitherto not analyzed from this perspective.

I might note that the pragmatic approach may be especially useful in the clini-

cal context. The semantic approach puts an emphasis on whether the hallucinat-

ing person knows or does not that he/she is hallucinating (hence the notion of

pseudo-hallucination which, as pointed out, does not seem to be phenomenolo-

gically apt). Alternatively, a pragmatic characterization of the hallucinatory state

will highlight the appropriateness and inappropriateness of a person’s behaviour

vis-à-vis his/her hallucinations. An individual may declare not knowing that

he/she is hallucinating, yet his/her actual behaviour may manifest patterns that

are distinct from those associated with ordinary behaviour he/she exhibits in

relations to objects and states of affairs in the real world. Such patterns of a mis-

match between declared knowledge and actual behaviour are, in fact, encoun-

tered in conjunction with other cases — notably, confabulations and blindsight

(for reviews, see Moscovitch, 1995; Weiskrantz, 1986, respectively).

HALLUCINATIONS 25

Cop

yrig

ht (

c) Im

prin

t Aca

dem

ic 2

013

For

per

sona

l use

onl

y --

not

for

repr

oduc

tion

Page 24: Shanon, B. 2003, Hallucinations

Brief Allusion to Topics Not Discussed Here

In closing, I would like to mention three topics which are directly related to the

issues examined here, but whose discussion would carry us outside the scope of

this paper. The first concerns the nature of perception, the second is that of reality

judgement and reality monitoring, and the third pertains to the mechanisms by

which hallucinations are generated. I also mark limitations of the present discus-

sion with respect to the phenomenological study of the hallucinatory experience.

The nature of perception

Much of what has been said above concerns not only hallucination, but also ordi-

nary perception. Often, perception is conceptualized as the reception of exter-

nally produced sensory impressions that the perceiver receives in a manner

analogous to a camera (admittedly, an intelligent one). Against this prevailing

view, Gibson (1979) and his followers in the school of ecological psychology

proposed that perception is an active process which cannot be divorced from the

cognitive agent’s acting and being in the world (for a review, see Michaels and

Carello, 1981). The present analysis of the phenomenology of hallucination sup-

ports this view. If perception is the recording of external sensory stimuli then

there is not much room for variation: either perception is veridical or not. In con-

trast, the alternative ecological view — along with the view advocated here —

affords variation: just as there are various ways by which cognitive agents may

act in the world, there are numerous ways by which they may perceive it. One

way is ordinary perception, another is that associated with films and plays (inci-

dentally, a case with which Gibson himself was concerned), dreaming is yet

another way and so is hallucination.

Reality judgement and reality monitoring

As we have repeatedly noted, judgements pertaining to reality (and non-reality)

are central to the hallucinatory experience. Such judgements are important in the

various contexts of the more ordinary states of people’s existence. In particular,

the extensive research program of Johnson and her associates (see, for instance,

Johnson and Raye, 1981 and Johnson et al., 1993) on reality monitoring should

be mentioned. These investigators especially focus on people’s differentiation of

memories of real events and recollections which are internally produced (e.g.,

dreams and fantasies). I have not referred to these studies here for, while they

relate to kindred topics, in their specifics they do not bear on the particular issues

examined here.

Above, I have mentioned that hallucinations may be experienced to me ‘more

real than real’. This indicates that reality judgement is actually a parameter that

can take different values. Dreams and imagination usually decrease the value

assigned to this parameter; the Ayahuasca experience may increase it (for a

related discussion in the context of mysticism, see Deikman, 1969). This notion

of an enhanced sense of the real as it manifests itself in sensation, perception,

26 B. SHANON

Cop

yrig

ht (

c) Im

prin

t Aca

dem

ic 2

013

For

per

sona

l use

onl

y --

not

for

repr

oduc

tion

Khristos
Highlight
Page 25: Shanon, B. 2003, Hallucinations

ideation and noesis is, I find, potentially fruitful, and can serve as the basis for

cognitive research not necessarily confined to hallucination.

The generation of hallucination

In this article, I confined myself to a phenomenological analysis and considered

only issues which are directly related to the way hallucination is defined. I have

not discussed the psychological processes involved with hallucinations and the

mechanisms by which these are generated (for a recent review, see Bentall, 2000).

These topics deserve an independent discussion; some reflections in this regard

are presented in Shanon (2002b). There, I favour an approach that analyses the

visionary experience in terms of enhanced creativity. Apparently, when under the

influence of psychotropic substances at least some people can achieve virtual artis-

tic-like creations that by far surpass those they could produce normally. The gener-

ative approach is to be contrasted with that characterizing the effect of these

substances (and hence, hallucinations) in terms of the uncovering of covert inter-

nal representations and unconscious mental material. Most psychological analyses

of hallucination — both cognitive and psychoanalytical — are in terms of this lat-

ter approach (see, for instance, Horowitz, 1975 and Reed, 1972, respectively). I

shall note that my own generative approach is grounded in views not specific to

hallucination at all, notably my view of metaphor (Shanon, 1992; 1993).

Other limitations

Finally, I would like to make it clear that the present discussion does not present a

comprehensive phenomenological study of hallucinations. All I have attempted

here is to examine the standard definition of hallucination and mark its problems.

My critique was based on the consideration of some empirical data, but let me be

clear: There is so much about the phenomenon of hallucination that I have not

even mentioned here. A systematic analysis of the hallucinatory experiences

encountered with Ayahuasca is presented in my forthcoming book.

A Final Caveat

Before closing, let me add some words of further clarification. In reaction to the

foregoing discussion it may be argued that what I have been talking about are not

hallucinations but rather visions (see, for instance, Slade and Bentall, 1988). By

this stance, the symptoms manifested by neurological and psychiatric patients

pertain to the first category, whereas my experiences and those of the traditional

users of psychotropic substances pertain to the second. I am ready to accept this

distinction. Indeed, because of the pejorative connotations of the term hallucina-

tion, both the modern users of Ayahuasca (notably, the members of the Brazilian

religious groups employing this substance) and myself (in my writings about this

brew) prefer to employ the term vision instead. This, however, is not the practice

scientists and clinicians usually employ. In general, these professionals refer to

substances such as those discussed here as hallucinogens and to the non-ordinary

HALLUCINATIONS 27

Cop

yrig

ht (

c) Im

prin

t Aca

dem

ic 2

013

For

per

sona

l use

onl

y --

not

for

repr

oduc

tion

Page 26: Shanon, B. 2003, Hallucinations

perceptions induced by them as hallucinations. I acknowledge the possible dis-

tinction, but would like to underline what is of primary import in this discussion

and what is not. The aim of my critique was not to show that the standard defini-

tion of hallucination has no sense whatsoever. Obviously, in some basic, and

simple, straightforward sense hallucinations are — as the standard definition

stipulates — perceptions experienced without there being corresponding physi-

cal objects or states of affairs in the real world to trigger them. The onus of the

present critique was not to show that non-ordinary perceptions — be they called

hallucinations or visions — are something totally different. Rather, as stated

throughout this paper, the upshot of my critique was threefold. First, to identify

the underlying premises — psychological, epistemological, methodological and

sociocultural — in which the standard definition is grounded and to argue against

them. Second, to show that there are cases in which the conditions postulated by

the standard definition are not met and that the actual phenomenology of non-

ordinary perceptions is much more varied and complex than what the standard

definition suggests. Third, to argue that the perspective on which the standard

definition is based directs the cognitive–psychological study of non-ordinary

perceptions into a certain direction and fixes it in a certain mould. As such, it

misses what to my mind are the interesting phenomena and issues at hand. In

contrast, the alternative perspective I advocate opens the door for new directions

of investigation and lays the foundations for a genuine cognitive–psychological

study of non-ordinary perceptions, be they called hallucinations or visions.

Whatever the terms used, the question remains as to what are the similarities and

differences between the experiences encountered with neurological and psychi-

atric patients and those reported by mentally healthy individuals who, on their

own initiative, partake of psychotropic substances. This last question is an

empirical one that lies outside the scope of the conceptual, programmatic discus-

sion which is the topic of this paper.

Conclusion: Towards an Experientially Oriented Study of Hallucination

The moral of the present discussion is clear: the externalistic approach is not fit-

ting for the cognitive psychological study of hallucination. The phenomenology

of hallucination is rich and it defies seemingly straightforward definitions based

on an externalistic, physicalistic point of view. Inspection of this phenomenol-

ogy reveals that the criteria postulated by the standard definitions of hallucina-

tion are neither necessary nor sufficient. By and large, these definitions do not do

justice to the complexity of the psychological facts. Furthermore, they seem to

divert the study of hallucination from what, to my mind, are the cognitive issues

of primary significance.

In light of this, a twofold conclusion follows. On the one hand, a serious

rethinking of our conceptualization of hallucination is required. On the other

hand, systematic empirical data of the phenomenology are needed. If they are to

be of general cognitive–psychological import, such data should not be confined

to the clinical, psychiatric context. I shall also dare say that the phenomenology

28 B. SHANON

Cop

yrig

ht (

c) Im

prin

t Aca

dem

ic 2

013

For

per

sona

l use

onl

y --

not

for

repr

oduc

tion

Page 27: Shanon, B. 2003, Hallucinations

of hallucination cannot be appreciated without investigators having personal

first-hand acquaintance of it. As I have said at the outset of this paper, would any-

one theorize about dreams or music without ever having experienced these one-

self? In the case of hallucination, very few of the investigators can attest that they

had such a personal acquaintance. For a general presentation of this methodolog-

ical stance the reader is referred to Shanon (2002b); for other phenomenological

investigations of hallucination — albeit not based on first-hand experiences —

the reader is referred to Casey, (1976) as well as to the older essay by Sartre

(1940/1995). Recently, phenomenological studies of verbal hallucinations appeared

— Leudar and Thomas (2000), and Stephens and Graham (2000); for earlier psy-

chiatric investigations of this phenomenon, see Hoffman (1986) and the various

responses to it.

Stated positively, the approach I am advocating is a genuine psychological

one. As such, it is an internalistic one involving the consideration of experience,

meaning and action. I shall point out that while the ideas made here are directly

based on empirical observations of the phenomenology of hallucination, from a

theoretical point of view, they are in line with more general ones I have devel-

oped independently. In Shanon (1993), I defend the view whereby theories in

psychology should be genuinely psychological. This contrasts with the more pre-

vailing approaches that attempt to found psychological phenomena on either

neurological or computational ones. This change in theoretical perspective entails

a radical change in the goals of the cognitive enterprise. To my mind, rather than

attempting the modelling of underlying structures and mechanisms, students of

mind should focus on the systematic study of experience: They should chart the

geography of mental life, define lawful regularities in it, and attempt a theoretical

formalization thereof. In this endeavour, the notion of meaning is pivotal. The

present study of hallucination, along with other concurrent investigations of con-

sciousness — both ordinary and non-ordinary — are to be viewed as specific, con-

crete implementations of this general theoretical approach.

Acknowledgements

Most of this paper was written while the author was a Golestan fellow at the

Netherlands Institute for Advanced Study (NIAS). The assistance of the NIAS

library in the finding of bibliographical material was essential. In the Hebrew

University, my assistants Nurit Shacham, Yoel Strimling and Yossi Schellas

helped in the preparation of the manuscript. Thanks are also due to the partici-

pants in my graduate seminar on the phenomenology of human consciousness in

which some of the ideas presented here were discussed, as well as to Zvi Carmelli

for his comments on an earlier version of the manuscript.

References

American Psychiatric Association. (1994), Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (4thed.). (Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Association).

Austin, J. (1962), How to Do Things with Words (Oxford: Clarendon Press).Bentall, R.P. (2000), ‘Hallucinatory experiences’, in Varieties of Anomalous Experience: Examining the

Scientific Evidence, eds. E. Cardeña, S. J. Lynn, S. Kripner (Washington, DC: APA).

HALLUCINATIONS 29

Cop

yrig

ht (

c) Im

prin

t Aca

dem

ic 2

013

For

per

sona

l use

onl

y --

not

for

repr

oduc

tion

Page 28: Shanon, B. 2003, Hallucinations

Bourguignon, E. (1970), ‘Hallucinations and trance: An anthropologist’s perspective’, in Origins andMechanisms of Hallucinations, ed. W. Keup (New York: Plenum Press).

Burkhardt, F., Bowers, F. (Eds.) (1986), Essays in Psychical Research (Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP).Campbell, R.J. (ed. 1981), Psychiatric Dictionary (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Casey, E. (1976), ‘Comparative phenomenology of mental activity: Memory, hallucination, and fantasy

contrasted with imagination’, Research in Phenomenology, 6, pp. 1–25.Chango, A. (1984), Yachaj Sami Yachachinu (Quito: Abya Yala).Deikman, A.J. (1969), ‘Deautomatization and the mystic experience’, in Altered States of Conscious-

ness, ed. C.T. Tart (Garden City, NJ: Anchor Books).Dobkin de Rios, M. (1972), Visionary Vine: Hallucinogenic Healing in the Peruvian Amazon (San Fran-

cisco, CA: Chandler).Dobkin de Rios, M. (1984), Hallucinogens: Cross-cultural Perspectives (Albuquerque, NM: University

of New Mexico Press).Encyclopaedia Britannica. (1971) (Chicago, IL: William Benton).Esquirol, J.E.D. (1845/1965), Mental Maladies — A Treatise on Insanity (New York: Hafner).Frege, G. (1892/1952), ‘On sense and reference’, in Translations from the Philosophical Writings of

Gottlob Frege, eds. & trans. P. Geach & M. Black (Oxford: Blackwell).Freud, S. (1900/1953), The Interpretation of Dreams, Standard Edition Vols. 4 & 5. (London: Hogarth Press).Furst, P.T. (1976), Hallucinogens and Culture (San Francisco: Chandler & Sharp).Gibson, J.J. (1979), The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception (Boston: Houghton-Mifflin).Hall, C., Van de Castle, R. (1966), The Content Analysis of Dreams (New York: Appleton-Century- Crofts).Harner, M.J. (ed. 1973), Hallucinogens and Shamanism (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Hoffman, R. (1986), ‘Verbal hallucinations and language production processes in schizophrenia’,

Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 9, pp. 503–17.Horowitz, M. (1975), ‘Hallucinations: An information-processing approach’, in Hallucinations: Behav-

ior, Experience, and Theory, eds. R. Siegel & L. West (New York: J. Wiley & Sons).Hume, D. (1739/1978), A Treatise of Human Nature (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Huxley, A. (1971), The Doors of Perception and Heaven and Hell (Harmondsworth: Penguin Books).James, W. (1890/1950), The Principles of Psychology (New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston).James, W. (1890/1986), ‘The name hallucination’, in The Works of William James: Essays in Psychical

Research, eds. F. Burkhardt & F. Bowers (Cambridge, MA.: Harvard University Press).James, W. (1912), Essays in Radical Empiricism (New York: Longmans, Green & Co).James, W. (1929), The Varieties of Religious Experience (New York: Modern Library).Johnson, M., Hashtroudi, S., Lindsay, D. (1993), ‘Source monitoring’, Psychological Bulletin, 114, pp. 3–28.Johnson, M., Raye, C. (1981), ‘Reality monitoring’, Psychological Review, 88, pp. 67–85.Klüver, H. (1928), Mescal: The ‘Divine’ Plant and its Psychological Effects (London: Kegan, Paul,

Trench, Trubner and Co).Klüver, H. (1966), Mescal and Mechanisms of Hallucinations (Chicago: University of Chicago Press).La Barre, W. (1972), The Ghost Dance: Origins of Religion (New York: Delta Books).La Barre, W. (1975), ‘Anthropological perspectives on hallucination and hallucinogens’, in Hallucina-

tions: Behavior, Experience, and Theory, eds. R. Siegel & L. West (New York: J. Wiley & Sons).LaBerge, S. (1985), Lucid Dreaming (Los Angeles: J.P. Tarcher).Langdon, E.J. (1979), ‘Yagé among the Siona: Cultural patterns in visions’, in Spirits, Shamans and

Stars, eds. D. Browman & R. Schwarz (The Hague: Mouton Publishers).Langdon, E. J. (1992), ‘Dau: Shamanic power in Siona religion and medicine’, in Portals of Power: Shamanism

in South America, eds. E. J. Langdon & G. Baer (Albuquerque, NM: University of New Mexico Press).Leudar, I., Thomas, P. (2000) Voices of Reason, Voices of Insanity: Studies of Verbal Hallucinations

(London: Routledge).Llinás, R.R., Ribary, U. (1994), ‘Perception as an oneiric-like state modulated by the senses’, in

Large-scale Neuronal Theories of the Brain, ed. C. Koch & J. L. Davis (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press).Luna, L.E. (1984), ‘The concept of plants as teachers among four mestizo shamans of Iquitos, northeast-

ern Peru’, Journal of Ethnopharmacology, 11, pp. 135–56.Luna, L.E. (1986a), Vegetalismo Shamanism Among the Mestizo Population of the Peruvian Amazon

(Stockholm: Almqvist & Wiksell International).Luna, L.E. (1986b), ‘Bibliografía sobre el Ayahuasca’, America Indígena, 46, pp. 235–45.Luna, L.E., Amaringo, P. (1993), Ayahuasca Visions (Berkeley, CA: North Atlantic Books).Luna, L.E., White, S. (Eds.) (2000), Ayahuasca Reader: Encounters with the Amazon’s Sacred Vine

(Santa Fe, NM: Synergetic Press).Mabit, J. (1996), ‘Ayahuasca and shamanism in addiction therapy: A report from the Peruvian Amazon’,

Bulletin of the Multidisciplinary Association for Psychedelic Studies, 6, pp. 24–31.Masters, R., Houston, J. (1966), The Varieties of Psychedelic Experience (New York: Holt, Rinehart & Winston).Michaels, C., Carello, C. (1981) Direct Perception (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall).Michaux, H. (1972) Misérable Miracle: Le Mescaline (Paris: Gallimard).Moscovitch, M. (1995) ‘Confabulation’, in Memory Distortion, eds. D. Schachter, J. Coyle, G. Fischbach,

M. Mesulum, L. Sullivan (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press).

30 B. SHANON

Cop

yrig

ht (

c) Im

prin

t Aca

dem

ic 2

013

For

per

sona

l use

onl

y --

not

for

repr

oduc

tion

Page 29: Shanon, B. 2003, Hallucinations

Nagel, T. (1974) ‘What is it like to be a bat?’, Philosophical Review, 83, pp. 435–50.Nagel, T. (1986) The View from Nowhere (Oxford: Oxfrod University Press).Noll, R. (2000), The Encyclopedia of Schizophrenia and Other Psychotic Disorders (New York: Facts on File).Ott, J. (1993), Pharmacotheon: Entheogenic Drugs, their Plant Sources and History (Kennewick, WA:

Natural Products Co).Ott, J. (1994), Ayahuasca Analogues —Pangean Entheogens (Kennewick, WA: Natural Products Co).Ott, J. (1995), The Age of Entheogenes & the Angels’ Dictionary (Kennewick, WA: Natural Products Co).Reber, A. (1984), The Penguin Dictionary of Psychology (Harmondsworth, UK: Penguin Books).Reed, G. (1972), The Psychology of Anomalous Experience: A Cognitive Approach (London: Hutchin-

son University Library).Reichel-Dolmatoff, G. (1975), The Shaman and the Jaguar: A Study of Narcotic Drugs among the Indi-

ans in Colombia (Philadelphia, PA: Temple University Press).Reichel-Dolmatoff, G. (1978), Beyond the Milky Way: Hallucinatory Imagery of the Tukano Indians

(Los Angeles: UCLA Latin America Center).Reichel-Dolmatoff, G. (1996) The Forest Within: The World-view of the Tukano Amazonian Indians

(Foxhole, UK: Themis Books).Sarbin, T.R. (1967) ‘The concept of hallucination’, Journal of Personality, 35, pp. 359–80.Sarbin, T.R., Juhasz, J.B. (1967), ‘The historical background of the concept of hallucination’, Journal of

the History of the Behavioral Sciences, 5, pp. 339–58.Sarbin, T.R., Juhasz, J.B. (1975) ‘The social context of hallucinations’, in Hallucinations: Behavior,

Experience, and Theory, eds. R. Siegel, L. West (New York: J. Wiley & Sons).Sartre, J.P. (1940/1995), The Psychology of the Imagination (London: Routledge).Schultes, R.E. (1972), ‘An overview of hallucinogens in the Western hemisphere’, in Flesh of the Gods:

The Ritual Use of Hallucinogens, ed. P.T. Furst (Prospect Heights, IL: Waveland Press).Searle, J.R. (1969) Speech Acts: An Essay in the Philosophy of Language (Cambridge: CUP).Searle, J.R. (1992) The Rediscovery of the Mind (Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press).Shanon, B. (1988), ‘Semantic representations of meaning — a critique’, Psychological Bulletin, 104, pp. 70–83.Shanon, B. (1992) ‘Metaphor: From fixedness and selection to differentiation and creation’, Poetics

Today, 13, pp. 659–85.Shanon, B. (1993), The Representational and the Presentational: An Essay on Cognition and the Study of

Mind (London: Harvester-Wheatsheaf).Shanon, B. (1997a), ‘A cognitive–psychological study of Ayahuasca’, Newsletter of the Multidisciplinary

Association for Psychedelic Studies, 7, pp. 13–15.Shanon, B. (1997b) ‘Cognitive psychology and the study of Ayahuasca’, Yearbook of Ethnomedicine and

the Study of Consciousness, 6, pp. 77–94.Shanon, B. (1998a), ‘Ayahuasca visions: A comparative cognitive investigation’, Yearbook of Ethno-

medicine and the Study of Consciousness, 7, pp. 227–50.Shanon, B. (1998b), ‘Ideas and reflections associated with Ayahuasca visions’, Newsletter of the

Multidisciplinary Association for Psychedelic Studies, 8, pp. 18–21.Shanon, B. (2001) ‘Altered temporality’, Journal of Consciousness Studies, 8 (1), pp. 35–58.Shanon, B. (2002a) ‘Ayahuasca visualizations’, Journal of Consciousness Studies, 9 (2), pp. 3–30.Shanon, B. (2002b) The Antipodes of the Mind: Charting the Phenomenology of the Ayahuasca Experi-

ence (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Slade, P., Bentall, R. (1988), Sensory Deception: A Scientific Analysis of Hallucination (Baltimore, MD:

The Johns Hopkins University Press).Stace, W. (1961), Mysticism and Philosophy (London: MacMillan Press).Stephens, G.L., Graham, G. (2000), When Self-Consciousness Breaks: Alien Voices and Inserted

Thoughts (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press).Tarsky, A. (1944) ‘The semantic conception of truth and the foundation of semantics’, Philosophy and

Phenomenological Research, 4, pp. 341–76.Walsh, R. (1990), The Spirit of Shamanism (Los Angeles: Jeremy P. Tarcher).Watts, A. (1962), The Joyous Cosmology: Adventures in the Chemistry of Consciousness (New York:

Pantheon Books).Webster’s Third New International Dictionary (1975), (Springfield, MA: G. & C. Merriam Co).Weiskrantz, L. (1986), Blindsight: A Case Study and Implications (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Wittgenstein, L. (1922), Tractatus Logico Philosophicus (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul).Wittgenstein, L. (1953), Philosophical Investigations (Oxford: Blackwell).Wittgenstein, L. (1958), The Blue and Brown Books (Oxford: Blackwell).

Paper received November 2001

HALLUCINATIONS 31

Cop

yrig

ht (

c) Im

prin

t Aca

dem

ic 2

013

For

per

sona

l use

onl

y --

not

for

repr

oduc

tion