scientific rationality, formal or informal

Upload: wjsteinle

Post on 02-Jun-2018

225 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/11/2019 Scientific Rationality, Formal or Informal

    1/16

    The British Society for the Philosophy of Science

    Scientific Rationality, Formal or Informal?Author(s): Jiang TianjiReviewed work(s):Source: The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, Vol. 36, No. 4 (Dec., 1985), pp. 409-

    423Published by: Oxford University Presson behalf of The British Society for the Philosophy of ScienceStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/687400.

    Accessed: 09/03/2012 11:55

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at.http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of

    content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms

    of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    Oxford University Pressand The British Society for the Philosophy of Scienceare collaborating with JSTOR to

    digitize, preserve and extend access to The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.

    http://www.jstor.org

    http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=ouphttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=bspshttp://www.jstor.org/stable/687400?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/687400?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=bspshttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=oup
  • 8/11/2019 Scientific Rationality, Formal or Informal

    2/16

  • 8/11/2019 Scientific Rationality, Formal or Informal

    3/16

    410

    Jiang

    Tianji

    ation

    of the

    standard

    conception

    of

    scientific

    rationality.

    Kuhn's

    heretical

    conception

    will

    be vindicated

    against

    charges

    of

    irrationalism in

    section

    3,

    and

    other

    models of

    informal

    rationality

    will be

    briefly

    discussed in

    section

    4.

    2

    STANDARD

    CONCEPTION OF

    SCIENTIFIC

    RATIONALITY

    Logical positivists

    and

    Popperians

    have believed that

    science

    proceeds

    by

    following

    a

    distinctive

    method,

    the scientific

    method,

    and

    rationality

    is

    nothing

    other than

    acting

    in

    conformity

    with the

    norms of this

    method.

    They

    have

    aspired

    after an

    explicit

    formalisation of

    rationality.

    In

    their

    opinion,

    rationality

    is identified with commitment to this formalisable

    method.

    From Mill

    to

    Carnap

    and

    Hempel,

    influential

    philosophers

    of science

    have

    continued to believe that

    some

    thing

    like a

    formal method

    ('inductive

    logic')

    underlies

    empirical

    science and that

    continued work

    might

    result

    in

    an

    explicit

    statement of this

    method,

    a formalisation of

    inductive

    logic

    comparable

    to the

    formalisation of

    deductive

    logic

    which was

    achieved

    by

    Frege

    and others. If

    such a method were

    discovered,

    then

    scientific

    rationality

    would be identified with

    the

    possession

    and

    employment

    of this

    method. This influential view was voiced

    by

    I. Scheffler as follows:

    Underlying

    historical

    changes

    of

    theory,

    there

    is

    ... a

    constancy

    of

    logic

    and

    method,

    which unifies each scientific

    age

    with that which

    preceded

    it

    and

    with

    that which

    is

    yet

    to follow.

    Such

    constancy comprises

    not

    merely

    the

    canons

    of

    formal

    deduction,

    but also those criteria

    by

    which

    hypotheses

    are confronted

    with

    the test

    of

    experience

    and

    subjected

    to

    comparative

    evaluation

    (Scheffler

    [19671, PP.

    9-1o).

    Proponents

    of this view admit that 'we do not .

    ..

    have

    explicit

    and

    general

    formulations

    of

    such

    criteria at the

    present

    time',

    but

    they

    insist

    that criteria

    'are embodied

    clearly

    enough

    in

    scientific

    practice

    to enable communication

    and

    agreement

    in a wide

    variety

    of

    specific

    cases

    (and such)

    communication

    and consensus

    indicate that there is a

    codifiable

    methodology underlying

    the

    scientific

    enterprise'

    (ibid.).

    It was

    assumed

    that there are

    universal

    principles

    of

    theory-acceptance

    implicit

    in

    scientific

    practice

    at least since the time modern science

    began;

    in

    other

    words,

    there

    is a

    rationality implicit

    in the work of natural scientists

    since about the time

    of

    Newton,

    this

    explains

    why

    this work is so successful.

    It is

    possible

    that these criteria of

    rationality

    are not well-understood

    at a

    given

    time and

    incorrectly applied

    on occasion. But it was further assumed

    that

    by

    i800

    or

    1850,

    this

    rationality

    was

    fully operative

    in the work of

    major

    natural

    scientists,

    so that we could

    speak

    of 'the'

    scientific

    method.

    Thus for

    logical positivists,

    it was assumed that scientific

    rationality

    takes

    the form of a

    logic.

    It

    is, therefore,

    formal. It is

    given

    once and

    for

    all;

    it

    never

    develops

    or

    changes.

    This was not to

    say

    that

    all

    scientists

    employ

    it

  • 8/11/2019 Scientific Rationality, Formal or Informal

    4/16

    Scientific Rationality,

    Formal or

    Informal?

    41I

    equally

    well. But

    the

    assumption

    was that there is a norm of

    rational

    procedure

    which

    all scientists

    should

    endeavour to

    comply

    with and

    all

    philosophers

    should

    endeavour to

    disclose.

    Logical positivists

    have at-

    tempted

    at an

    explicit general

    formulation

    of the

    principles

    of

    rational

    acceptance.

    Take

    Hempel's

    logic

    of

    confirmation,

    for instance. In his

    'Studies in

    the

    Logic

    of

    Confirmation',

    Hempel

    is

    engaged

    in a

    search

    for

    'general objective

    criteria

    determining

    whether

    .

    ..

    a

    hypothesis

    H

    may

    be

    said to be

    corroborated

    by

    a

    given

    body

    of evidence E'

    (Hempel

    [19651,

    p. 6).

    His aim

    in the

    essay

    is to

    provide

    definitions of

    the

    concepts

    of confirmation

    and disconfirmation which

    characterise those relations

    in a

    purely

    formal

    way:

    the criteria of confirmation 'should

    contain no reference to

    the

    specific

    subject

    matter of the

    hypothesis'

    (ibid.

    p.

    Io).

    For

    Hempel,

    one

    ought

    to

    be

    able to tell

    simply

    by

    looking

    at the

    logical

    forms of a

    hypothesis-sentence

    and an evidence-sentence whether the confirmation relation holds between

    them,

    just

    as

    one

    can tell

    simply

    by inspecting

    the

    logical

    forms of

    premise-

    sentences

    and the

    conclusion-sentence whether the

    implication

    relation

    holds between them.

    The

    search,

    then,

    is

    for formal

    syntactic

    criteria

    of

    confirmation

    analogous

    to the

    formal criteria for the

    validity

    of

    deductive

    arguments.

    What

    would count as evidence for an

    hypothesis

    is determined

    by

    the form of

    hypothesis-sentences

    and

    evidence-sentences,

    not

    by

    their

    content.

    The

    situation seems from

    an

    epistemological point

    of

    view ideal: the

    justification of hypotheses becomes a very straightforward matter. But, alas,

    reality

    has

    a

    way

    of

    eluding

    the

    ideal,

    for

    actual evidential

    relations

    in

    science

    are

    not

    captured by

    such

    analysis

    of

    confirmation.

    The

    analysis Hempel

    provides

    is

    of a

    formal,

    syntactic

    relation between

    sentences. This

    relation

    holds

    only

    between

    sentences

    containing

    the same

    predicates.

    But most

    interesting

    scientific

    theories

    are not

    evidentially supported

    by

    statements

    containing

    the

    same terms as

    occur in

    the

    theory,

    but

    by

    statements

    containing

    quite

    different

    kinds of

    terms.

    Therefore

    the

    Hempelian

    approach

    is

    applicable

    only

    to

    a

    restricted set of

    evidential

    relations,

    the

    relation between observation statements and theories which are merely

    generalisations

    of

    observation

    reports.

    Generally

    speaking,

    the

    logical

    positivist

    account of

    theory-acceptance

    is

    oversimplified.

    In

    his inductive

    logic

    Carnap

    treats all

    logical

    consequences

    as

    having

    the

    same

    evidential

    relationships

    to the

    hypothesis they

    support:

    no

    distinction

    is drawn

    between

    those known

    in

    advance

    and the

    'novel'

    ones.

    It

    would

    be

    very

    difficult for him to

    incorporate

    such a

    distinction

    into

    his

    scheme,

    because there

    is no

    way

    to know

    by

    a

    simple

    inspection

    of

    an

    observation

    statement whether

    it

    would

    count

    as

    'novel'

    or

    not.

    Only

    the

    history of the theory in question can tell one that. But the positivists have

    adopted

    a

    very

    abstract

    model of

    rationality

    in

    which

    only

    the

    formal

    structure of a

    theory

    and

    the

    empirical

    evidences

    drawn from it are

    relevant

    to

    theory

    evaluation.

    They paid

    no

    attention to the

    prior

    historical

    development

    of

    a

    theory

    and the

    different

    degrees

    of

    support

    conferred

    by

  • 8/11/2019 Scientific Rationality, Formal or Informal

    5/16

    412

    Jiang Tianji

    different

    sorts

    of

    evidence

    upon

    it.

    According

    to

    their intuitive

    principles

    based

    on

    an a

    priori

    notion

    of

    evidence,

    all

    accepted

    consequences

    lend the

    same

    degree

    of

    support

    to the

    theory

    or the same

    degree

    of disconfirmation

    if

    they

    are refuted. What

    they emphasised

    is

    the

    mere fact that

    theory

    and

    evidences

    are

    deductively

    related.

    They

    can

    easily

    set

    up

    a

    postulational

    system

    of

    plausible principles

    of

    evidence,

    the trouble

    is that this does

    not

    apply

    to what

    actually

    goes

    on

    in

    science.

    It is now

    generally

    agreed

    that,

    in

    actual

    scientific

    practice,

    what counts

    most of all in favour

    of a

    theory

    is not

    just

    its success

    in

    prediction

    but

    its

    'dynamical

    character' or its

    'fertility',

    its

    ability

    to meet

    anomaly

    in a creative and fruitful

    way.

    This is

    something

    which

    manifests

    itself

    only gradually

    over

    the course of

    time;

    one cannot

    attest

    to it

    until the

    theory

    has

    survived

    many

    tests and been extended

    in

    illuminatingly

    new

    ways.

    Time

    plays

    an

    essential role

    here. Whether such

    actual evidential

    relations

    can be

    formalised

    or

    not,

    we have

    yet

    to see.

    Popper

    and

    Popperians

    have

    attempted

    to

    formulate

    a more

    complex

    model of

    rationality

    than

    that of

    logical

    positivists.

    But with

    them

    they

    shared

    the

    assumption

    that

    there are norms

    of the scientific

    method,

    an

    unchanging

    set of intuitive

    principles

    underlying

    validation

    in science.

    According

    to

    Popper,

    a scientist

    ought

    to

    act in accordance

    with the dictates

    of

    the method

    of falsificationism:

    propose

    testable

    theories;

    not

    investigate

    ad hoc

    theories;

    accept

    that

    theory

    for further

    theoretical and

    practical

    purposes,

    which is best

    corroborated;

    select

    a

    simpler hypothesis

    because

    it

    is

    more testable

    than a less

    simple

    one;

    and so on.

    Popper

    has

    claimed that his

    method

    will

    give

    us

    a better chance

    to achieve the

    goal

    of

    epistemic progress.

    In this

    model of

    rationality,

    three

    criteria

    are offered

    for rational

    theory-

    choice:

    first,

    the

    criterion

    of

    prior

    appraisal;

    second,

    the criterion

    of

    posterior

    appraisal,

    and

    third,

    the criterion

    of

    appraisal

    for theories

    which

    are known

    to be

    false.

    The

    notions

    of

    empirical

    content

    and

    explanatory

    power,

    etc.,

    are defined

    in

    purely

    logical

    terms

    by

    Popper.

    In

    his

    explication

    of

    empirical

    content

    (or

    falsifiability),

    one

    important

    problem

    concerns

    the

    measurement

    or com-

    parison

    of contents.

    There

    are

    objections

    that content

    comparison

    is

    impossible

    because

    contents

    of

    theories

    are not subsets

    of each

    other.

    But

    Watkins

    still

    attempts

    to show

    that

    at least

    the idea

    of

    comparing

    empirical

    content-a

    pre-testing

    concept-can

    be

    rescued.

    As

    to

    theory

    testing,

    Popper

    thinks

    that

    only

    a novel

    fact

    can

    really

    support

    a

    theory.

    Thus

    he introduces

    the ideas of

    background

    knowledge

    and

    severity

    of a test

    to account

    for

    the distinction

    between

    'evidence'

    known

    in

    advance

    and

    verified

    prediction

    of a novel

    fact,

    a

    distinction

    which cannot

    be made in

    Carnap's

    theory

    of confirmation. The

    logical

    relation of

    deducibility

    cannot

    of

    itself

    convey

    this

    difference;

    a

    temporal

    analysis

    of

    some

    kind is needed.

    But

    success

    in

    novel

    prediction

    is not

    fertility.

    Fertility

    is not

    a matter of

    prediction

    at

    all.

    He concedes the

    importance

    of

    time

    order

    in

    theory appraisal

    but

    never

    quite

    comes

    to

    viewing

    fertility

    as a criterion

    of

    appraisal.

  • 8/11/2019 Scientific Rationality, Formal or Informal

    6/16

    Scientific

    Rationality,

    Formal or

    Informal?

    413

    Finally,

    Popper's

    formal

    concept

    of

    verisimilitude

    will

    allow

    two

    false

    theories

    to

    be

    compared

    with

    respect

    to their

    truthlikeness,

    the

    theory

    with

    more

    truth-content

    or

    less

    falsity-content

    is

    to

    be

    preferred.

    However this

    concept

    of verisimilitude

    has come under criticism from D. Miller

    and

    P.

    Tichy,

    and

    it

    seems

    that

    a

    precise

    definition of

    verisimilitude couched

    in a

    formalised

    language

    will

    never

    be

    possible,

    because truth-contents

    and

    false-contents

    are

    not

    comparable.

    Therefore,

    both

    the

    problem

    of

    pre-

    testing

    measurement

    of content

    and the

    problem

    of

    post-testing compara-

    tive

    verisimilitude

    have met with severe technical

    difficulties,

    and the

    concept

    of

    degree

    of corroboration

    will

    not be

    very

    useful

    if all

    theories have

    been refuted

    or are

    bound

    to

    be

    refuted.

    The

    model of

    Popper's

    thus has its

    own unsolvable

    difficulties,

    not to

    speak

    of its

    inapplicability

    to

    theory-

    choice

    in

    actual

    scientific

    practice.

    Now we come

    to

    Lakatos's

    improvement

    of the

    Popperian methodology.

    Lakatos

    took

    one

    step

    further

    in

    insisting

    that

    the

    unit for

    appraisal

    is not the

    theory

    taken at a moment

    of

    time but the

    theory

    considered

    in

    terms of

    its

    entire historical

    career,

    what he

    called

    a

    'research

    programme'.

    He

    had two

    main criteria for

    the

    appraisal

    of

    scientific

    research

    programmes.

    One is

    increase

    in

    empirical

    content,

    at least some of which

    has been

    experimentally

    confirmed. The other is

    the

    idea that a research

    programme

    is better than

    a

    competitor

    if it has more

    heuristic

    power, potential

    for

    creating

    'evidential

    support',

    i.e.,

    if it

    makes

    possible

    the construction

    of

    a

    sequence

    of

    theories

    with

    increasing

    'evidential

    support'. Roughly,

    a

    research

    programme

    is

    fruitful

    if it

    can lead to a

    series

    of

    theories which

    produce

    novel

    knowledge.

    It

    appears

    that

    heuristic

    power

    is

    scarcely

    more than

    the

    capacity

    to

    generate

    increase in

    successful

    prediction.

    Urbach has

    attempted

    to

    show that the

    heuristic

    power

    of a

    research

    programme

    can

    be

    objectively

    determined. For

    Lakatos,

    a research

    programme

    is

    better

    than

    its rival if it has

    more

    'evidential

    support'

    and more heuristic

    power,

    i.e.,

    power

    to

    create theories

    with

    'evidential

    support'.

    Thus

    everything hinges,

    again,

    upon

    the

    idea of

    'evidential

    support'.

    But

    prediction

    failures

    are not

    relevant to the

    appraisal

    of

    research

    programmes.

    A

    major

    problem

    for

    Lakatosians is

    how

    to rule

    out ad

    hoc evidential

    support.

    Worrall

    suggests

    that

    those facts which

    have been

    used

    in

    the

    construction of the

    theory

    in

    question

    cannot

    'support'

    the

    theory.

    Worrall

    maintains

    that

    it can

    be

    objectively

    determined

    whether a fact was

    used

    in

    constructing

    a

    theory.

    If

    a

    fact has

    been used once in

    a

    theory,

    then

    the

    same

    fact

    can

    only

    be

    explained

    ad

    hoc

    by

    that

    theory-a

    fact cannot

    be used twice.

    Lakatos

    comes

    near

    to

    the

    criterion of

    fertility

    with his

    emphasis

    on the

    historical

    development

    of a

    programme,

    but

    not

    quite;

    it

    seems what is

    sought

    in a

    'good'

    development

    is mere

    increase

    in

    successful

    prediction.

    Of

    course Lakatos

    put emphasis

    on

    the

    importance

    of

    heuristics for the

    development

    of science. But

    this heuristic is said

    to set a

    'pre-conceived'

    plan

    for

    the research

    programme.

    And heuristic

    power

    is

    reduced

    to

    power

    to

    generate

    increase in successful

    prediction.

    Thus the

    principal

    criterion

  • 8/11/2019 Scientific Rationality, Formal or Informal

    7/16

    414

    Jiang

    Tianji

    for

    rational

    theory-choice

    is excess

    evidential

    support,

    not

    different from

    what

    is

    dictated

    by

    falsificationism:

    chose the

    best corroborated

    theory.

    Just

    like

    falsificationism,

    its

    formal

    approach

    to

    rationality

    cuts

    itself off

    from the

    particularity

    and

    peculiarity

    of the historical

    situations where

    scientific

    theory-choices

    take

    place. Necessarily,

    what

    appears

    to

    be

    development

    of a

    theory (a

    scientific

    research

    programme)

    is

    really

    a

    sequence

    of

    classes

    of

    propositions (theories)

    logically

    related to one another as

    specified

    by

    method.

    The

    fertility

    of a

    theory,

    on

    the other

    hand,

    refers to the

    theory's

    proven ability

    to

    take

    up

    new forms which are not

    deducible from the

    previous

    versions,

    but which are

    suggested by

    them,

    according

    to Ernan

    McMullin's account

    (see

    his

    [1976], pp. 398-402).

    The

    important

    relation-

    ship

    then becomes that of

    suggestion,

    holding

    between a

    previous

    and a

    later

    version of

    the same

    theory.

    It is a

    very significant

    fact

    that,

    as McMullin

    points

    out,

    this

    suggestion

    relation is not a

    purely logical

    one,

    but

    necessarily

    dependent

    on

    the historical record. The

    fertility

    of a

    theory

    would then be

    conceived in

    terms

    of

    the

    developmental

    transformations it has

    undergone

    to solve new

    problems,

    where later

    formulations are

    not

    inferable from

    previous

    ones,

    but

    suggestible by

    them in the

    light

    of the

    historically

    available evidence. We cannot

    hope

    to state

    precise

    rules

    for

    the relation of

    suggestion.

    But Lakatos did believe that the

    methodology

    of scientific

    research

    programme

    can

    be

    characterised

    by general

    rules

    that

    would be

    binding

    and

    consciously

    or

    instinctively

    observed

    by

    scientists.

    Lakatos

    and Lakatosians claimed with the

    help

    of case studies that the

    evaluative criteria

    which scientists

    actually

    use

    are those described

    by

    the

    methodology

    of scientific research

    programmes.

    It was claimed that when

    scientists

    fail to

    conform to

    Lakatos'

    methodology

    it

    is because of

    external

    pressures.

    That is to

    say,

    when

    they

    are

    acting rationally, they

    act

    in

    accordance

    with

    the

    dictates of this

    methodology;

    when

    they

    are

    acting

    irrationally,

    then

    they

    deviate

    from them. Therefore this

    methodology

    is an

    explicit

    formulation

    of the universal rational

    method

    underlying

    empirical

    science. Lakatosians

    expressed

    views about the

    constancy

    of scientific

    method

    just

    like those

    of

    logical positivists

    as

    voiced

    by

    I.

    Scheffler.

    Elie

    Zahar,

    for

    instance,

    has

    this to

    say:

    MSRP

    entails

    that

    the

    presystematic

    methodology

    instinctively

    used

    by

    scientists in

    judging

    individual achievements

    did not

    change

    very

    much

    over the

    centuries,

    say

    from the

    time of

    ancient

    Greece

    until

    the

    present day.

    MSRP

    does not

    of course

    presuppose

    absolute

    stability,

    but

    it nonetheless

    implies

    that deviations

    from

    its

    norms

    have

    been

    in

    the

    nature

    of

    local fluctuations

    very

    different

    in

    magnitude

    from

    large

    scale

    scientific revolutions.

    This

    stability thesis, namely

    that

    there have

    been

    no

    methodological

    upheavals

    on

    a

    par

    with scientific

    revolutions,

    may prove

    too

    strong.

    Still

    the

    stability

    thesis is

    to

    my

    mind

    a

    very interesting

    working

    hypothesis

    which

    ought

    to be

    investigated.

    .

    .

    .

    Many people

    have a

    strong feeling

    that intuitive

    methodology,

    like intuitive

    logic,

    has

    been

    largely

    stable

    (Zahar

    [1982]).

    He seemed to

    imply

    that Lakatos'

    methodology

    is this

    instinctive meth-

  • 8/11/2019 Scientific Rationality, Formal or Informal

    8/16

    Scientific

    Rationality,

    Formal or

    Informal?

    415

    odology

    made

    explicit,

    that is

    why

    scientists

    would

    tacitly

    subscribe

    to it

    if

    they

    are not

    under

    external

    pressures.

    From

    what

    is described

    above,

    it

    follows that

    Popper

    no less than

    Carnap,

    and Lakatos no less than earlier

    Hempel,

    would

    equate rationality

    with

    formal

    rationality.

    Formal

    rationality

    was

    regarded

    as actual

    rationality

    in

    science, i.e.,

    as

    explicit

    statement of the

    rationality implicit

    in

    scientific

    practice.

    Their models of

    rationality

    are based on the

    following

    assumptions:

    I.

    There is a

    unified

    scientific method or

    methodology

    which has

    been

    instinctively

    used

    by

    almost all scientists in all

    ages

    or at least from

    the

    time when real science

    began.

    This

    is

    the

    doctrine of

    unity,

    universality

    and

    stability

    of

    method.

    2.

    The instictive

    methodology

    or

    implicit rationality

    can

    be formulated and

    formalised,

    even

    if

    we do not

    yet

    have

    such

    a

    formulation at the

    present

    time. This is the

    theses of

    formalisability

    of method.

    3.

    The formal method or

    formalisable method can be used to achieve

    our

    objectives

    in

    science,

    be

    it

    the

    discovery

    of

    truth,

    epistemic

    progress,

    explanation

    and

    understanding, prediction

    and

    technological

    control,

    problem-solving,

    and

    what not. This is the thesis of

    rationality

    of

    method.

    4.

    The formal or

    formalisable

    method also serves as

    a

    demarcation

    criterion

    between

    science and

    other human

    pursuits,

    between science

    and non-

    science or

    pseudo-science.

    It is

    the

    defining

    characteristic of

    science.

    This

    is the

    thesis of

    essentiality

    of

    method. From

    this it is

    concluded

    that the

    formal method can

    serve as

    the

    very

    definition of

    rationality.

    3

    VINDICATION

    OF

    KUHN'S

    CONCEPTION OF

    INFORMAL

    RATIONALITY

    This standard conception of rationality is rejected by Thomas Kuhn, the

    leading proponent

    of a

    more

    complex

    view of

    scientific

    rationality.

    Kuhn has

    challenged

    all

    the above

    assumptions

    of the

    standard

    conception.

    According

    to

    the

    standard

    conception,

    the

    crux of

    rationality

    is

    the

    acceptance

    or

    rejection

    of

    beliefs on

    the basis of

    evidence.

    Whether

    the

    inductive

    support

    of

    logical

    positivists,

    the

    corroboration of

    Popper

    or

    the

    evidential

    support

    of

    Lakatos,

    all

    these

    are more or

    less

    formalised

    accounts of

    evidential

    relations

    holding

    between

    the

    theory

    being

    tested

    and

    observations.

    Rationality

    of

    the

    decisions of

    scientists

    consists in

    the formal

    relationships

    they bear to logic, on the one side, and to empirical facts on the other.

    Experience

    and

    logic

    can

    determine

    uniquely

    the

    acceptance

    or

    rejection

    of a

    theory.

    For

    Kuhn,

    this is

    possible

    only

    in

    normal

    science for

    determining

    the

    validity

    of an

    articulation or an

    application

    of

    an

    existing theory.

    Whole

    theories

    or

    paradigms

    cannot

    be

    judged by

    the same sort of

    criteria that

    are

    employed

    when

    judging

    a

    theory's

    individual research

    applications,

    he

    said:

    EE

  • 8/11/2019 Scientific Rationality, Formal or Informal

    9/16

    41

    6

    Jiang

    Tianji

    Observation and

    experiment

    can and

    must

    drastically

    restrict

    the

    range

    of

    admissible

    scientific

    beliefs,

    else there would be no

    science. But

    they

    cannot alone determine a

    particular body

    of

    scientific belief.

    An

    apparently arbitrary element,

    compounded

    of

    personal and historical accident, is always a formative ingredient of the beliefs

    espoused by

    a

    given

    scientific

    community

    in

    a

    given

    time

    (Kuhn

    [1972], p.

    4).

    Because of this

    arbitrary

    element,

    the outcome of

    theory

    choice cannot

    be

    dictated

    by

    logic

    and

    experiment

    alone. Therefore

    any

    formal

    account

    of

    evidential

    relations would not

    apply

    to actual scientific

    practice. Objecting

    to the

    positivist

    and

    Popperian

    models

    of

    rationality

    Kuhn

    said,

    both

    of

    them assume

    that 'the

    problem

    of

    theory-choice

    can be resolved

    by

    techniques

    which are

    semantically

    neutral.

    The

    observational

    consequences

    of both theories are

    first stated in a shared basic

    vocabulary

    (not necessarily

    complete

    or

    permanent).

    Some

    comparative

    measure

    of their

    truth/falsity

    count

    then

    provides

    the basis

    for a choice between them. For

    Sir Karl

    Popper

    and his

    school,

    no less than for

    Carnap

    and

    Reichenbach,

    canons of

    rationality

    thus

    derive

    exclusively

    from those of

    logical

    and

    linguistic

    syntax'

    (Kuhn

    [1970],

    p. 243).

    Their

    assumption

    of the

    rationality

    and

    essentiality

    of a formal

    method for

    theory

    evaluation is

    radically rejected by

    Kuhn.

    Now come to Kuhn's

    positive

    views

    on

    theory

    choice.

    First,

    he

    affirms

    that

    theory

    choice

    is

    definitely

    rational,

    there

    being good

    reasons

    of the sort

    usually

    described

    for

    choosing

    between

    competitive

    theories.

    Second,

    these

    reasons constitute

    values to be used

    in

    making

    choices rather

    than rules of

    choice.

    There cannot be

    any

    shared

    algorithm

    by

    the

    use

    of which

    all

    members

    of a scientific

    group

    will reach the same decision.

    On the

    contrary,

    accuracy, simplicity,

    scope,

    fruitfulness,

    and so

    on,

    constitute a shared

    ideology

    for the

    group.

    Scientists who share

    the same

    ideology

    may

    nevertheless

    make different

    choices in the same

    concrete situation.

    Group

    behaviour

    will

    be

    affected

    decisively by

    the shared

    commitments,

    but

    individual

    choice

    will be a function

    also of

    personality,

    education,

    and

    prior

    pattern

    of

    professional

    research.

    Therefore individual scientists

    will not all

    apply

    the same values

    in the same

    way.

    Even

    if

    they agree

    about

    the

    importance

    of the various

    values,

    there

    would

    remain

    the

    problem

    of

    combining

    them all

    into one

    precise

    overall criterion

    which would

    de-

    termine

    which of

    two

    competing

    theories

    to

    accept.

    But

    there

    is no

    unanimity

    at all as

    to the relative

    weights

    that

    are to be

    assigned

    to different

    values

    in the overall

    comparison

    of theories.

    Third,

    the choice

    between

    competing

    theories

    lies

    in the hands

    of the

    group

    of

    specialists.

    These

    specialists

    share the

    same commitments.

    Even

    though they

    don't share

    precise

    criteria for

    theory

    choice,

    and even

    though

    their

    preference

    is

    determined

    in

    part

    also

    by idiosyncratic

    factors,

    there does

    in

    fact,

    in the

    process

    of

    a

    controversy

    over

    the relative

    merits of

    two

    competing

    theories,

    eventually emerge

    a consensus

    leading

    to

    the

    acceptance

    of one of

    the

    rivals.

    Though

    there are

    no

    explicit

    rules

    of

    acceptance

    for

    Kuhn,

    he neverthe-

    less

    offers what amounts

    to a

    justification

    for the

    group

    behaviour

    in

    theory

  • 8/11/2019 Scientific Rationality, Formal or Informal

    10/16

    Scientific Rationality,

    Formal or

    Informal?

    417

    choice. Here

    Kuhn

    argues

    that scientists'

    modes of behaviour as

    exemplified

    in

    theory

    choice

    have certain

    essential

    functions:

    'In the absence

    of alternate

    mode

    that would

    serve

    similar

    functions,

    scientists

    should behave

    essen-

    tially

    as

    they

    do

    if their concern

    is to

    improve

    scientific

    knowledge'

    (Kuhn

    [1970],

    p. 237).

    Kuhn

    regards

    all behaviour essential to scientific

    develop-

    ment as

    rational;

    since

    scientific behaviour

    in

    theory

    choice

    conduces to the

    improvement

    of scientific

    knowledge,

    this

    is also an

    argument

    in favour

    of

    the

    claim that scientific

    activity

    is

    rational.

    Now

    the

    crucial

    question

    is: is

    theory

    choice

    as characterised

    by

    Kuhn

    really

    rational? There

    are at least

    several

    objections.

    First, many

    philosophers

    insist that

    an action

    ordecision

    in science

    cannot

    be

    considered

    rational unless

    it is based

    on

    logical

    or

    methodological

    rules

    which are

    objective

    in the sense that

    different scientists

    following

    the same

    rules

    and

    provided

    with

    the same

    information

    will

    arrive

    at

    the

    same

    decision.

    The basic

    assumption

    is that

    all

    rationality

    should be

    equated

    with

    formal

    rationality.

    Since

    Kuhn would not have

    anything

    to do with such

    rules,

    decision

    as to which of the

    competing theory

    is

    to be

    chosen cannot be

    based

    on

    logic

    or

    methodology,

    but rather based

    on a value

    system

    or

    ideology,

    the

    application

    of which

    in

    a concrete

    situation

    will

    not lead

    to

    unanimous decisions

    by

    different

    scientists.

    Personal

    factors

    have to

    be

    taken

    into

    account,

    and

    what

    actually

    determines

    a

    decision

    is individual

    judgement

    rather

    than

    general

    rules. But

    according

    to the

    objection,

    such

    personal

    factors

    dependent

    on

    historical

    contingencies

    are

    irrelevant

    to

    rational

    theory

    choice. Since for

    Kuhn,

    scientists

    actually rely

    on

    sub-

    jectivistic

    and

    psychologistic

    criteria

    for

    choosing

    between

    competing

    theories,

    such choice

    is not

    rational,

    it is irrational. Kuhn is accused

    of

    irrationalism.

    This

    objection

    is

    untenable.

    On

    Kuhn's

    view,

    both the shared values and

    personal

    factors are relevant

    to

    individual

    decisions.

    Because

    perception

    and

    judgement

    are

    involved

    in

    applying

    values in a concrete

    situation,

    each value

    can be

    judged

    quite differently,

    individual

    variability

    in decisions is

    naturally

    to be

    expected.

    But individual decisions are

    not

    final,

    they

    generally

    take risks

    and

    might

    be

    wrong.

    Still

    they

    are not

    irrational,

    because

    they

    are not

    made

    arbitrarily

    without reasons.

    And

    they

    do

    not violate

    any

    accepted

    rules

    because

    there

    are

    no

    such

    binding

    rules in

    scientific

    practice.

    What is

    important

    is

    the unanimous decision

    belatedly

    reached

    in

    a

    group.

    Neither

    individual choice

    nor

    group

    choice is based

    on what is

    called sub-

    jectivistic

    and

    psychologistic

    criteria,

    though psychology

    is not irrelevant

    because

    theory

    choice is a human

    activity,

    and occurs

    not

    in the 'world

    3'

    of

    Popper,

    but in this real world of our scientists.

    Second,

    from

    the

    standpoint

    of the

    objectors,

    consensus

    eventually

    emerging

    within the

    group

    of

    scientists,

    leading

    to

    the

    acceptance

    of a

    paradigm,

    is not a

    rational decision

    either,

    for

    according

    to their

    conception

    of formal

    rationality,

    the

    consensus criterion

    is not

    objective,

    but sub-

    jectivistic. Only

    the

    logical positivists' degree

    of

    confirmation

    or

    inductive

  • 8/11/2019 Scientific Rationality, Formal or Informal

    11/16

    418

    Jiang

    Tianji

    support

    and the

    Popperian comparative degree

    of

    corroboration are

    objective

    criteria

    for

    theory

    choice.

    They

    seem

    to think

    that

    for

    Kuhn

    a

    group

    of scientists

    may

    choose

    any theory they

    like so

    long

    as

    they agree

    in

    their

    choice

    and therefore enforce it.

    This,

    of

    course,

    would

    be sub-

    jectivistic.

    But

    nothing

    of the

    sort is

    implied

    in

    Kuhn's

    concept

    of

    consensus. On Kuhn's

    view,

    when a

    group

    of

    specialists

    reach a

    unanimous

    decision,

    it

    is

    never

    arbitrary,

    but must be based on

    good

    reasons.

    It

    may

    be

    a

    conclusion reached

    at the end of a

    process

    of

    deliberation

    or

    argumentation,

    or

    it

    may

    be

    more or less

    easily

    arrived at as a

    result

    of the

    relative

    unanimity

    of the

    professional judgements

    of

    these

    specialists.

    Therefore

    the consensus

    among

    scientists is

    objectively

    arrived

    at,

    and is at least

    partly

    a

    product

    of

    objective

    social conditions

    and

    institutions.

    As

    Kuhn

    well said:

    Recognition

    of the

    existence

    of

    a

    uniquely

    competent professional group

    and

    acceptance

    of

    its

    role

    as the exclusive arbitor

    of

    professional

    achievement has further

    implications.

    The

    group's members,

    as individuals and

    by

    virtue

    of their

    shared

    training

    and

    experience,

    must be seen as

    the

    sole

    possessors

    of the

    rules

    of

    the

    game

    or

    of

    some

    equivalent

    basis

    for

    unequivocal judgements

    (Kuhn

    [1972], p. 168).

    Why

    should scientific

    communities be able to reach

    a

    firm

    consensus

    unattainable

    in other fields like

    art and

    philosophy?

    According

    to

    Kuhn,

    science

    is

    the

    only

    field that

    shows

    progress

    in

    increasing

    the

    number

    and

    precision

    of the solved

    problems.

    The nature of scientific communities

    'provides

    a virtual

    guarantee

    that

    both

    the

    list of

    problems

    solved

    by

    science

    and

    the

    precision

    of individual

    problem-solutions

    will

    grow

    and

    grow'.

    At

    least,

    the nature

    of

    the

    community

    provides

    such a

    guarantee

    if

    there

    is

    any

    way

    at

    all

    in

    which

    it can

    be

    provided.

    What

    better

    criterion

    than the decision

    of

    the

    scientific

    group

    could

    there be?

    (Kuhn

    [1972],

    p. 170).

    If

    for

    Popper,

    'there is

    nothing

    more rational than .

    . .

    the method of science'

    (Popper

    [1972],

    p. 27),

    then,

    Kuhn

    should have

    said,

    'there

    is

    nothing

    more

    rational than the decision of a

    scientific

    group'.

    But

    unlike

    logical

    positivists

    and

    Popperians

    for whom

    inductive

    support

    or evidential

    support

    would

    be the

    sole

    or at least the

    principal

    criterion

    for

    theory

    acceptance,

    the

    ability

    to solve

    empirical problems

    is for Kuhn neither

    the

    unique

    nor an

    unequivocal

    basis

    for

    paradigm

    choice

    by

    a scientific

    group.

    There can be

    no criterion of that

    sort,

    and no

    criterion is needed.

    The

    group's

    decision is based

    on

    examples

    of

    what

    a scientific

    theory

    achieves

    and

    on

    judgements

    of value.

    That is

    why

    there is no formal

    rationality,

    informal

    rationality

    is

    all we have.

    Third,

    there

    are still some other

    philosophers

    who would

    neither

    denounce Kuhn's

    model of

    theory

    choice as

    irrational,

    nor concede

    that it is

    rational.

    According

    to

    them,

    'any

    kind of

    action,

    including

    scientific

    choice,

    can

    be called

    rational

    only

    if it

    can be

    causally

    linked

    to

    deliberation

    or

    reasoning

    aimed at

    achieving

    specific

    ends.

    Scientific

    theory

    choice

    as

    characterized

    by

    Kuhn would not be rational

    in this sense but would

    rather

    be akin to...

    latently

    functional behaviour

    patterns,

    which

    serve a

    function

  • 8/11/2019 Scientific Rationality, Formal or Informal

    12/16

    Scientific

    Rationality,

    Formal or

    Informal? 419

    they

    were

    never

    chosen to

    fulfill'

    (Hempel

    [I981]).

    I think what

    Hempel

    emphasises

    here is

    correct,

    the

    question

    whether

    an action is rational or

    non-

    rational

    hinges

    on this

    point:

    whether

    or not it involves a

    process

    of

    deliberation.

    A

    spontaneous,

    unconscious

    action is

    non-rational. But

    a

    deliberate

    and considered

    judgement,

    even

    when it is

    not the conclusion of

    a

    cogent

    reasoning,

    can

    be

    rational. We should not

    suppose

    that the

    judgements

    of a

    scientific

    group

    on

    the

    comparative

    merits of

    competing

    theories cannot be

    causally

    linked to

    any

    deliberation at

    all.

    The

    drux

    of the

    matter is:

    how

    extensive

    and detailed a

    process

    of

    deliberation

    is

    required

    before it can confer

    rationality upon

    the

    action

    that

    will

    ensue from

    it.

    If

    it

    were demanded that

    a

    scientist

    knows

    what his alternatives

    are,

    and he

    knows what

    the

    possible

    outcomes

    of

    these alternatives

    are,

    and he also

    knows what his

    preferences

    are

    among

    the

    possible

    outcomes

    (that

    is,

    if it

    were demanded that he must know

    what

    alternatives will

    maximise his

    expected utility,

    before

    his

    choice

    can

    be

    rational),

    then choices of an

    individual scientist are seldom rational.

    By

    the

    same

    token,

    group

    choices

    are

    very

    seldom

    rational,

    because we cannot

    expect any

    scientist to know

    all

    this.

    But

    why

    should

    we

    demand

    of

    a

    scientist or a

    group

    of scientists this

    knowledge

    of all

    alternatives

    and

    especially

    of

    all

    the

    possible

    outcomes

    of

    them?

    Actions

    of

    scientists,

    including

    theory

    choice,

    can

    be rational

    if a

    less

    extensive

    and less

    careful deliberation is

    required.

    The

    theory

    choice as

    characterised

    by

    Kuhn is not rational in

    the

    utility-maximisation

    sense of

    rationality.

    What is

    at

    issue is

    the

    problem

    of formal versus

    informal

    rationality.

    The

    standard

    conception

    of

    scientific

    rationality

    identifies

    rationality

    with

    formal

    rationality,

    commitment to a

    formal

    method

    of

    science.

    Logical

    positivists

    and

    Popperians

    have

    attempted

    to

    'explicate'

    scientific

    pro-

    cedures

    as

    governed

    by

    explicit

    and

    precise

    rules. The

    acceptance

    or

    rejection

    of

    a

    theory

    is

    rational

    if it can

    be

    justified by

    some of

    these

    rules,

    otherwise

    it

    would be

    irrational or

    non-rational. This

    overly

    narrow and

    abstract

    conception

    of

    rationality

    would

    relegate

    most scientific

    decisions

    and

    beliefs

    to

    irrationality.

    The

    contributions of

    Thomas Kuhn

    consist in

    the

    liberalisation of

    rationality.

    Formal

    rationality

    becomes

    only

    a

    part,

    and

    may

    be an

    unimportant

    part,

    of

    rationality,

    because scientific

    method

    in

    an

    especially comprehensive

    and

    momentous

    context,

    namely

    in

    regard

    to

    scientific

    revolutions

    and

    theory

    change,

    cannot be

    characterised

    by

    explicit

    general

    rules

    to

    be

    observed

    by

    practising

    scientists. It is

    obvious that

    where

    formalisation

    of scientific

    procedures

    is

    impracticable

    or

    unsuccessful,

    there

    people

    have to

    rely

    on

    informal

    rationality.

    But is it

    true that

    where

    a

    formal

    method

    exists,

    no recourse to informal

    rationality

    is

    needed?

    Kuhn

    seemed

    to

    imply

    this in

    what

    he said:

    That

    part

    of his

    (Karl

    Popper's) writing

    which

    seek

    an

    algorithm

    for

    verisimilitude,

    if

    successful,

    would

    eliminate all need for

    recourse to

    group

    values,

    to

    judgements

    made

    by

    minds

    prepared

    in a

    particular

    way (Kuhn

    [1970],

    p.

    238).

  • 8/11/2019 Scientific Rationality, Formal or Informal

    13/16

    420

    Jiang

    Tianji

    I

    think that

    this is incorrect.

    It is

    highly unlikely

    that

    a

    complete

    formalisation of all scientific

    procedures

    would be

    forthcoming,

    and even if

    we

    got

    such

    a

    formal

    method,

    in

    applying

    it

    we cannot

    dispense

    with human

    intelligence

    and

    judgement.

    4

    OTHER MODELS OF

    INFORMAL RATIONALITY

    While Thomas

    Kuhn

    has

    established,

    in

    a more

    or

    less

    descriptive

    way,

    that

    theory

    choice is under the

    sway

    of

    informal

    rationality, Hilary

    Putnam

    provides

    a

    powerful argument against

    the

    formalisability

    of scientific

    rationality.

    His

    central idea

    is

    that

    the

    need for an

    informal element

    is

    indispensable for any formal method. The formalised scientific method

    depends

    on

    inputs

    which are not formalisable. Take

    the

    Bayesian

    Approach

    for instance.

    In

    computing

    the

    degree

    of

    support

    of

    various

    hypotheses

    using

    the

    Bayesian

    theorem,

    as

    'inputs'

    we need not

    only

    the

    computable

    likehoods,

    but also the

    prior probabilities

    of

    the various

    hypotheses,

    i.e.,

    the

    'subjective degrees

    of belief'

    assigned

    by

    scientists to those alternative

    hypotheses

    prior

    to

    examining

    the

    observational evidence.

    It

    turns out that

    difference

    in

    the

    prior probability

    function can lead to violent difference

    in

    the

    actual

    degrees

    of

    support assigned

    to

    theories.

    Putnam

    draws

    the

    conclusion that formal rationality does

    not

    guarantee

    real and actual

    rationality.

    If

    one starts out

    with a 'reasonable'

    prior probability

    function,

    then one will

    only assign degrees

    of

    support

    to 'reasonable'

    hypotheses,

    but

    if one's

    prior probability

    function is

    'unreasonable',

    then

    one's

    assignment

    of

    degrees

    of

    support

    to various

    hypotheses

    will be 'irrational'. This

    prior

    probability

    metric

    represents

    the scientists'

    antecedent beliefs about

    the

    world.

    It

    seems

    that one

    of the

    inputs

    to the method itself is a set

    of

    substantive

    factual beliefs

    (or

    degrees

    of of

    belief).

    The

    need

    for an informal

    element is similar

    in

    other

    approaches.

    Therefore

    it

    is

    not

    possible

    to

    draw

    a

    sharp

    line between

    the content

    of

    science

    and the method

    of science. Both

    Putnam and

    Shapere

    lay

    stress

    on the

    dependence

    of scientific

    method

    upon

    scientific

    beliefs,

    and

    maintain that scientific

    method

    changes

    constantly

    as

    the content

    of science

    changes.

    If

    the

    method of science

    changes

    constantly,

    then the traditional

    belief

    in a

    universal

    stable method

    is untenable

    and the

    attempts

    to

    formalise

    it

    would

    be doomed

    to failure.

    Putnam has this

    to

    say,

    The

    hope

    for

    a

    formalisable

    method,

    capable

    of

    being

    isolated

    from actual human

    judgements

    about

    the contents

    of

    science

    (about

    the

    world),

    and

    capable

    of

    actually

    being

    stated

    seems

    to have

    evaporated

    (Putnam

    [1981]).

    If from

    the

    constancy

    of

    scientific

    method

    the ideal

    of formalisation

    is

    derived,

    and as a result

    the

    praises

    of formal

    rationality

    are

    sung,

    and formal

    rationality

    is identified

    with

    the

    very rationality

    itself,

    then

    from

    the

    changeability

    of scientific

    method

    we should

    be convinced

    that

    complete

    formalisation

    is

    hopeless

    and

    informal

    rationality

    must

    be restored to

    its

  • 8/11/2019 Scientific Rationality, Formal or Informal

    14/16

    Scientific Rationality,

    Formal or

    Informal?

    421

    legitimate

    status.

    During

    the

    period

    from fifteenth to seventeenth

    century,

    when new science was

    originated

    and

    developed, general methodological

    maxims instead of precise formal rules were put forward by scientists and

    philosophers

    for the

    guidance

    of scientific

    inquiry.

    In

    the

    application

    of

    general

    maxims to

    particular

    cases

    intelligence

    and

    judgement

    are

    required,

    thus

    it

    was informal rather than formal

    rationality

    that

    prevailed

    in

    scientific

    practice

    of

    that

    period.

    After a

    long

    tradition of

    attempts

    at formalisation

    from

    Mill

    to

    Carnap

    and

    Popper,

    it was

    Polany

    and

    Kuhn,

    in

    the

    years

    around

    i960,

    who

    first threw off the

    tyrannical yoke

    of formal

    rationality

    imposed by logical positivists

    and

    Popperians. Polanyi

    is

    sceptical

    of the

    degree

    to

    which the skill of

    theory-assessment

    which

    develops historically

    in

    the scientific

    community

    can be made

    explicit

    either

    by

    scientists

    or, post

    factum,

    by philosophers.

    In

    his

    view,

    scientific

    rationality

    can

    never be made

    fully

    explicit

    or even rendered

    unambiguous

    in

    outcome. Kuhn

    claimed

    that

    decision

    in

    theory-choice

    is

    based on

    ideology

    rather than on

    logic.

    There

    cannot be

    any algorithm

    for

    theory-choice

    which will

    dictate the same

    decision for all

    members of the

    group.

    The

    upshot

    of all this is to

    replace

    formal

    rationality by

    informal

    rationality.

    Other models of informal

    rationality

    include both

    the inferential and the

    noninferential ones.

    Shapere's

    discussion of

    principles

    of

    reasoning

    as

    having

    a central

    role

    in

    many

    scientific decisions between

    competing

    theories

    or lines of research is a

    clarification of the

    functioning

    of informal

    reasoning

    in

    scientific

    practice.

    These

    principles

    of

    reasonable scientific

    research are

    not formal

    rules,

    the

    reasons

    they

    provide

    for

    seeking

    a certain

    type

    of

    theory

    are of course

    not

    conclusive.

    Shapere

    said,

    'that

    the

    reasons were not

    logically

    conclusive did

    not

    make them

    any

    the

    less reasons-and

    good

    ones,

    relative to the state of

    science

    at

    that time-nor

    did

    it

    make action in

    accordance with

    them

    any

    the

    less rational'

    (Shapere

    [19741,

    p.

    409).

    Therefore

    in

    accounting

    for the

    rationality

    of scientific

    discovery

    as well as of

    justification

    our one

    recourse is

    to

    informal

    rationality.

    The

    non-inferential

    models of informal

    rationality

    are

    emphasised,

    besides

    Kuhn

    and

    Putnam,

    by Polanyi,

    Grene,

    Toulmin and

    Wartofsky.

    It

    is a form of rational

    judgement

    modelled on

    judgement

    in

    the

    law,

    in

    medical

    diagnosis

    and

    in

    aesthetic

    appraisal;

    this form

    of

    informed,

    skilled

    judge-

    ment involves

    the

    application

    of

    general

    maxims or

    directive to

    particular

    cases,

    but it is not

    rigorously

    rule-determined. It is

    rational

    in

    the

    sense that

    judgements may

    be

    defended

    by citing

    particular

    cases,

    previous

    appli-

    cations of the

    maxims and the

    like.

    Wartofsky

    wants to

    resurrect a

    historical

    alternative

    conception

    long

    overshadowed

    by

    the

    standard

    conception

    of

    rationality.

    This

    is the

    'heuristic tradition'

    involving

    'craftsmanlike skill

    in

    judgement'

    and

    'tinkering'.

    The scientific

    theorists

    tinker with

    ideas

    (see

    his

    [1980]).

    This

    kind

    of

    down-to-earth

    tinkering

    found

    in

    crafts

    allows for

    creative

    innovation

    in

    science.

    Thus

    this

    model of informal

    rationality

    would make

    scientific

    behaviour both

    creative and rational.

  • 8/11/2019 Scientific Rationality, Formal or Informal

    15/16

    422

    Jiang

    Tianji

    5

    CONCLUSION

    We

    have seen that the standard

    onception

    f scientific

    ationality,

    he

    model of formal and abstract rationality, is divorced from scientific practice.

    This normative

    conception

    is

    in conflict with the historical

    fact that

    standards

    of

    rationality

    change

    over time.

    It is the

    assumption

    of fact-value

    dichotomy

    that renders the standard

    conception

    seemingly

    invulnerable.

    But

    starting

    from

    Kuhn and

    others,

    philosophers

    are

    increasingly coming

    to

    agree

    that scientific

    rationality

    includes an informal

    part

    whose

    importance

    is estimated

    differently by

    different

    philosophers.

    Both

    extreme

    positions-

    the identification

    of

    rationality

    with a formal

    method or the

    complete

    neglect

    of formal

    rationality-seem

    to be

    incorrect. Thomas

    Kuhn

    gives

    formal

    rationality its due in normal science. Hilary Putnam would think that each

    functioning

    of scientific

    rationality

    includes a formal

    part

    and an informal

    part.

    This 'liberation'

    of

    rationality

    from

    formal

    logic

    or normative

    methodology

    is a

    good thing.

    Let

    us

    quote

    Kuhn

    again:

    The

    man who

    embraces

    a new

    paradigm

    at an

    early stage

    must often do so

    in

    defiance

    of the

    evidence

    provided by problem-solving.

    ... There

    must also be

    a

    basis,

    though

    it need be

    neither rational nor

    ultimately

    correct,

    for

    faith in

    the

    particular

    candidate

    chosen.

    Something

    must make

    at

    least a few scientists

    feel that the new

    proposal

    is on

    the

    right

    track

    ...

    (Kuhn

    [1972],

    p. 158).

    For

    Kuhn,

    belief or faith

    in a

    theory's

    promise

    is a most

    important

    factor

    relevant

    to

    theory-choice,

    but

    the faith need

    not be based on a rational

    inference

    (and

    thus

    would be

    rejected by

    the standard

    conception

    of

    rationality

    as

    irrational),

    but based

    on a rational

    judgement

    or an

    insight:

    the

    scientists

    feel that

    the new

    proposal

    is

    on the

    right

    track.

    Only specialists

    can

    make

    such a

    judgement.

    Even

    if the

    judgement

    is sometimes

    inarticulate

    or

    turns out to be

    wrong,

    might

    we

    say

    that

    it

    is

    irrational?

    I think not. The

    liberalisation

    of

    rationality

    must

    be extended

    to

    the

    point

    of

    including

    such a

    judgement among the rational ones.

    Wuhan

    University

    People's

    Republic

    of

    China

    REFERENCES

    HEMPEL,

    C.

    G.

    [1965]:

    Aspects

    of

    Scientific

    Explanation

    and

    Other

    Essays

    in

    the

    Philosophy

    of

    Science.

    HEMPEL,

    C. G.

    [1981]:

    'Turns

    in the Evolution of Problem

    of

    Induction',

    Synthese, 46,

    p.

    402.

    KUHN,

    T.

    [I970o]:

    Reflections

    on

    My

    Critics',

    in I. Lakatos

    and

    A.

    Musgrave

    (eds.),

    Criticism

    and the Growthof Knowledge.

    KUHN,

    T.

    [1972]:

    The Structure

    of

    Scientific

    Revolutions,

    2nd ed.

    LAKATOS,

    I. and

    MUSGRAVE,

    A.

    (eds.)

    [I970o]:

    Criticism

    and the

    Growth

    of

    Knowledge.

    MCMULLIN,

    E.

    [1976]:

    'The

    Fertility

    of

    Theory

    and

    the Unit

    of

    Appraisal

    in

    Science',

    in R.

    S.

    Cohen et

    al.

    (eds.),

    Essay

    in

    Memory of

    Imre

    Lakatos.

    POPPER,

    K.

    [1972]:

    Objective

    Knowledge.

    PUTNAM,

    H.

    [198

    1]:

    'The

    Impact

    of Science

    on

    Modern

    Conceptions

    of

    Rationality',

    Synthese,

    46, p.

    375.

  • 8/11/2019 Scientific Rationality, Formal or Informal

    16/16

    Scientific Rationality,

    Formal or

    Informal?

    423

    SCHEFFLER,

    I.

    [1976]:

    Science

    and

    Subjectivity.

    SHAPERE,

    D.

    [1974]:

    'Discovery, Rationality

    and

    Progress

    in

    Science:

    A

    Perspective

    in the

    Philosophy

    of

    Science',

    in

    K.

    Schaffer and

    R.

    Cohen

    (eds.),

    PSA

    1972.

    WARTOFSKY,

    ARX

    W. [I980]: 'Scientific Judgement: Creativity and Discovery in Scientific

    Thought',

    in

    T. Nickles

    (ed.),

    Scientific

    Discovery:

    Case Studies.

    ZAHAR,

    E.

    [1982]:

    'Feyerabend

    on

    Observation and

    Empirical

    Content',

    British

    Journalfor

    the

    Philosophy

    of

    Science,

    33,

    P. 407.