sass et al 2011 copy

Upload: emiliano-diaz

Post on 04-Jun-2018

229 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/14/2019 Sass et al 2011 copy

    1/34

    Sass, Parnas,and Zahavi / Phenomenological Psychopathology and Schizophrenia 1

    Abstract: The present paper clarifies key issues in phenomenology and

    phenomenological psychopathol- ogy (especially of schizophrenia) through a

    critique of a recent article that addresses these topics. Topics include (1)

    Phenomenologys role in clarifying issues not amenable to purely empirical methods;

    (2) The relationship between a phenomenological approach (focusing on the

    subjective life of the patient) and em-pirical science, including neuroscience; (3) The

    nature of self-experience, especially in its pre-reflective form (ipseityinvolving

    operative intentiona lity), and its possible disturbance in schizophrenia (hyper-

    reflexivity and diminished self-affection);(4) The relationshipbetween self-

    disturbance in schizophrenia and disorders of both temporality and (what Husserltermed) passive syntheses;(5) The role of intentional or quasi-volitionalprocesses in

    the perceptual (and other) disorders in schizophrenia; (6) The nature and diversity of

    phenomenologys potential contribution to the enterprise of explanation;and (7)

    The meaning of several concepts: hermeneuticor existentialap-proach,

    phenomenological reflection,and negative symptoms.

    Keywords: self-disorder, pre-reflective self-awareness, ipseity, hyperreflexivity, self-

    affection, phenomenologi- cal reflection, phenomenological explanation

    in recent years. There has been aproliferation of works that focus on the nature of

    subjectivity in schizophrenia and related disorders, and that take inspiration from the

    work of such German and French philosophers as Husserl, Heidegger, and Merleau-

    Ponty, and such classical psychiatrists as Minkowski, Blankenburg, and Binswanger

    (Rulf 2003; Sass 2001a, 2001b). This trend in- cludes predominantly theoretical articles,

    which typically incorporate clinical material as well as reviews of empirical and

    experimental findings in psychopathology. Some very recent examples (since 2000) are

    studies of self-experience (Sass and Parnas 2003), temporal experience (Fuchs2005),delusions and delusional mood (Parnas and Sass 2001; Fuchs 2005), and psychiatric

    classification and diagnosis (Parnas & Zahavi2002), as well as of values and

    disturbances of common-sense (Stanghellini 2001, 2004; Stang- hellini and Ballerini 2007),

    affect or emotion (Ratcliffe 2008; Sass 2007a), negative sympt(Sass 2003a),perception

    (Nelson and Sass 2008; Sass 2004c; Schwartz et al. 2005), and personhood and autonomy

    (Sass 2007b, 2011). A major event of recent years is the appearance of a series of empirical

    studies that demonstrate the reality of clinical-phenomenal disorders of self-experience

    as a core factor in early schizophrenia and that differentiate diagnosis of schizophrenia-

    spectrum from other forms of psychosis or psychopathol- ogy (Mller and Husby 2000;

    Parnas et al. 1998; Parnas et al. 2003; Parnas, Handest, et al. 2005; Parnas, Mller, et al.

  • 8/14/2019 Sass et al 2011 copy

    2/34

    2 PPP / Vol.18, No. 1 / March 2011

    2005).

    This trend does not, of course, represent the first attempt to study subjectivity in

    schizophre- nia, nor is it the first time that the continentalphenomenological tradition has

    been introduced. Both Mayer-Grosss famous textbook ofpsychia- try (1954) and FishsSchizophrenia (Hamilton 1984, originally1962) attemptednobly but with limited

    successto bring phenomenological psychopathology into the mainstream of English-

    language psychiatry. The work of Karl Jaspers disciple, Kurt Schneider, on the First Rank

    Symp- toms of schizophrenia, was clearly Jaspersian on the methodological plane, but

    unfortunately was interpreted more in an operational than a truly phenomenological

    sense. Existence, an anthol- ogy edited by Rollo May, Ernst Angel, and Henri Ellenberger

    (1958), influenced humanistic trends in American clinical psychology. An important

    precursor to the above-mentioned empirical work is the research on schizophrenia-

    patients experience of the so-called basic symptoms of schizophrenia, carried out

    since the end of the 1960s by Huber, Klosterktter, and colleagues in Germany

    (Klosterktter 1988, 1992; Klosterktter et al. 1997, 2001).

    The most prominent Anglophone attempt to emphasize the importance of the subjective

    di- mension of schizophrenia was R. D. Laings first and finest book, The Divided Self

    (1959), a work admired by many who remain skeptical of Laings later contributions. The

    Divided Self, which uses ideas from Sartre, Heidegger, Minkowski, and Binswanger,

    was something of a bolt from theblue. Laings own interests and influence were soon

    diverted in an anti-psychiatric and sometimes ro- manticizing or otherwise anti-scientific

    direction.

    25 years between thepublication of Laingsbook and the appearance, starting in the

    mid 1980s, of articles by several authors. These include Sass (1985, 1987, 1988a, 1990a,

    1990b, 1992b)cul- minating in his books, Madness and Modernism:Insanity in the

    Light of Modern Art, Literature, and Thought (1992a), and The Paradoxes of Delusion

    (1994)Schwartz and Wiggins (1987; also Wiggins et al. 1990), Cutting and Dunne

    (1989), and Parnas and Bovet (1991; Bovet and Parnas 1993) . A superb anthology of

    classical European contributions on schizophrenia, editedby John Cutting and Michael

    Shepherd, appeared in 1987. Cuttings (1997) book on brain laterality had a strong

    phenomenological component.Now, however, we are seeing a reasonably broad-based

    attempt to bring phenomenological perspectives to bear on scientific psychiatry,particularly on schizophrenia, in the now-dominant world of Anglophone psychiatry and

    clinicalpsychology.

    These recent developments inphenomeno- logicalpsychopathology coincide with

    significant trends in both the mental health professions and the mind sciences. One such

    trend is a growing disillusionment, within mainstreampsychiatry, with the extreme

    emphasis on operationalizable concepts that began with the advent of DSM III in

    1982. A number of recent editorials by key figures inNorth American and European

    psychiatry (Andreasen 2007; Maj 2005; see also Mullen 2007; Parnas et al. 2008) have

    noted the relative lack of real scientific progress in the study of schizophrenia and many

  • 8/14/2019 Sass et al 2011 copy

    3/34

    Sass, Parnas,and Zahavi / Phenomenological Psychopathology and Schizophrenia 3

    other disorders, and have related this to the loss of validity that can occur when there is

    an over-focus on reliability (operational concepts). These editorials have re- lated this

    lack of progress to the loss, which they lament, of the rich, psychopathological tradition

    of European psychiatry, which is strongly (but not exclusively) rooted in

    phenomenology. This disillusionment coincides with a certain malaise, notable among

    younger psychiatrists and clinicalpsychologists, who are frustrated with the increas- ingly

    mechanical role they are expected to play in a clinical world defined bybureaucratic

    demands, and doubtful about a scientific world dominatedby empirical methodologies

    that can seem divorced from significant theoretical issues.

    Another, more broad-based trend is the disil- lusionment with purely neurocentristic,

    cognitiv- ist, and computationalist approaches that seems to be spreading among

    scholars and scientists in philosophy and the various sciences of mind,brain, and

    behavior. One can find a diverse group of thinkers including Dreyfus (1979), Varela et al.

    (1991), Clark (1997), Gallagher (2005), Zahavi (2005), Thompson (2007), and Gallagher

    and Zahavi (2008), who all in various ways have criticized the standardpicture by

    insisting on the need for a renewed focus on subjectivity and on the embodiment and

    embeddedness of the human subject. More recently, the concepts of self and of self-

    experience have also gained something of a renaissance in philosophy,psychology, and

    the cognitive sciences (cf. Gallagher and Shear 1999; Kircher and David 2003; Sass et al.

    2000).

    The revival of a phenomenological approach to psychiatry precedes the most recent of

    these trends, but fits in comfortably with current de- velopments. The phenomenological

    approach emphasizes the need to delve below superficial levels ofbehavioral description or

    common-sense, symptomatic descriptions (Parnas and Sass 2008; Zahavi and Parnas 1998).By offering a richer and more empirically grounded theoretical approach to the

    understanding of abnormal action and experience, it promises an escape from the opera-

    tionalist cul-de-sac that contemporary psychiatry is in danger of entering. The

    phenomenological study of schizophrenia in particular is of signal importance, not only

    because of schizophrenias preeminent place in the history of psychiatry, but also

    because of the profound, enigmatic, andpotentially revelatory nature of the alterations

    of subjectivity and selfhood that it involves. The increased focus, over the last 15 years, on

    early intervention for mental disorders, particularlypsy- chotic disorders, has particularly

    highlighted the importance of understanding subjective experience inpre-schizophrenic and

    schizophrenic conditions, which may be relevant for the prediction and identification

    of high risk, as well as treatmentefforts (Nelson, Sass, Skodlar et al. 2009; Nelson et al

    2008; Parnas 2005).

    A Source of

    Misunderstandings

    In this context, it is surprising that, very re- cently, an article should have appeared,

    addressed to a general psychiatric audience, in which recent trends in the

    phenomenological psychopathology of schizophrenia and key notions of phenomeno-

    logical philosophy are presented in a manner that is not only confusing, but highly

    inaccurate. Rath- er than clarifying matters, the article in questionblurs key theoretical

  • 8/14/2019 Sass et al 2011 copy

    4/34

    4 PPP / Vol.18, No. 1 / March 2011

    issues and leaves the reader with the impression that much of phenomeno- logical

    psychiatry must be, at its core, an obscure discipline, incomprehensible and somehow

    deeply anti-scientific in nature.

    The article in question, published in Current Opinion in Psychiatry in 2007, was

    authored by Aaron Mishara and carries the title Missing links in phenomenologicalclinical neuroscience: Why we still are not there yet. Misharas critique primarily targets

    two articles by Sass and Parnas (2003, 2007), but also criticizes Sass (1992a), Parnas

    (2003), and Zahavi (2005). In his contribu- tion, Mishara strives to offer an ambitious

    review of the relationshipbetween phenomenology and neuroscience, and to construct a

    stark opposition between what he calls neo-phenomenology ver- sus existential or

    hermeneutic phenomenology. Mishara wishes to associate the first term with the work of

    Sass, Parnas, and Zahavi, and the second term with his own work and that of such

    figures as Binswanger, Blankenburg, Conrad, von Weiz- saecker, Matussek, and Wiggins

    and Schwartz. As we argue, however, the distinction in question is confused and

    misleading.1

    The publication of Misharas account is not entirely to be lamented, however: it articulates

    certain misunderstandings that may be widespread enough to be worth addressing in

    detail, thereby giving us the opportunity to correct potential mis- apprehensions and to

    explain some basic points about our own approach and the phenomeno- logical

    enterprise more generally. In thepresent article, we take hispublication as an occasion for

    clarifying a number of important issues (sometimes overlapping) concerning

    phenomenology and its role in the study of psychopathology in general and

    schizophrenia in particular; in this way, we offer a discussion that should be of generalinterest (see also Gallagher and Zahavi 2008). The issues treated below are the following:

    1. The role ofphenomenology in clarifying issues not amenable to purely empirical

    methods.

    2. The relationshipbetween a phenomenological ap-proach (focusing on the subjective

    life of thepatient) and that of empirical science, including neurosci- ence. (This

    relationship involves what is sometimes referred to as the naturalizingof

    phenomenology.)

    3. The nature of self-experience, especially in its pre-reflective form, and its possible

    disturbance in schizophrenia.4. The relationshipbetween self-disturbance in schizo-phrenia and disorders both of

    temporality and of (what Husserl termed) passive syntheses.

    5. The possible, contributing role of intentional or quasi-volitionalprocesses in the

    perceptual disorders in schizophrenia.

    6. The natureand especially the diversityof phe- nomenologyspotential contribution

    to the enterprise of explanation(broadly understood, in contrast with mere

    description).

    7. We also provide a number of necessary clarifications: of the meaning of a

    hermeneuticor an existen- tialapproach; of the nature and role of reflection in

    phenomenological accounts; and of the meaning of the concept of negative

  • 8/14/2019 Sass et al 2011 copy

    5/34

    Sass, Parnas,and Zahavi / Phenomenological Psychopathology and Schizophrenia 5

    symptoms.

    Misharas main justifications for distinguishing between what he calls neo-

    phenomenologyand existential/hermeneutic phenomenologyare two. The fact that

    his article vacillates between the two justifications, without distinguishing them clearly,

    adds to the confusion. One justification is largely methodological in nature, having to

    do with the status and role of phenomenology. Ac- cording to Mishara (2007a),

    whereas (so-called) neo-phenomenology claims to circumvent experi- mental

    procedures, the (so-called) existentialphenomenologywith which he associates himself

    is, by contrast, in an excellent position to supply hypotheses [and testableconstructs]

    for further experimental study (pp. 55960). The secondjustification is more substantive:

    it pertains to dis- cussions related to the structure of consciousness and the specific nature

    of the psychological abnor-mality in schizophrenia. Here Mishara rejects the claim that

    consciousness is as such characterizedby a pervasive but tacit dimension ofpre-reflective

    self-consciousness, and denies that self-disturbance is a central core feature ofschizophrenia. We con- sider Misharas claims and criticisms to beboth mistaken and

    misleading. We begin with general methodological and philosophical issues, namely, with

    Misharas views on the relevance ofphenom- enology, the notion of constraint (a term

    we use), and the nature ofphenomenological facts. Later we turn to selfhood and other

    topics.

    Nature and Role of Phenomenology

    In his article, Mishara states that Sass and Parnas (2007) and Zahavi (2005)

    proposedthatphenomenology is able to constrain neuroscience when applied to

    disorders such as schizophre- nia (Mishara 2007a, 559, emphasis added). Heexplains this point by stating that, according to Sass, Parnas, and Zahavi,

    phenomenologyprovides conclusive knowledge or limits, what Zahavi calls facts,

    about the patients subjective experience (Misharas words). We are said tobelieve

    that these facts could (in Misharas words once again) be directly incorporated into

    clini- cal neurosciencewithout requiring any kind of experimental procedure.

    Mishara continues: Rather than furnishing hypotheses or testable constructs to

    neuroscience, neo-phenomenology claims to circumvent experimental procedure by

    offering constraints about the nature of (human) subjectivity with a foundation in

    philosophical phenomenology.He contrasts this with what he calls the existential-

    phenomenological . . . view that phenomenologyprovides initial systematic means

    for studying subjectivity and seeks only to supplyhypotheses for further

    experimental study (p. 560). Misharas account isproblematic.Not only does he not

    grasp the standard meaning of constrainas this term is used in recent dis- cussions

    on the relation between phenomenology and cognitive science, he also fails to capture

    our own view of the matter, and ultimately provides a superficial picture of what the

    phenomenological tradition has to offer contemporarypsychiatry orthe project of the

    naturalizationof conscious- ness (the inclusion of consciousness within a

    general scientificperspective).

  • 8/14/2019 Sass et al 2011 copy

    6/34

    6 PPP / Vol.18, No. 1 / March 2011

    We agree, of course, that a major role forphenomenology is indeed to supply hypotheses

    for further empirical study. However, we reject the idea that phenomenologys relevance

    shouldbe restricted to this role. Psychiatry, after all, is faced with a host ofphilosophical

    questionsfor example, questions concerning the nature of rationality, the definition of

    delusion, and thepossibility of empathy with abnormal states of mind. To think that such

    questions can be settled by clinical trials or other purely empirical methods would amountto a kind of scientism that would certainly be rejected by all the major theorists of

    phenomenology. Phenomenology, together with other phi losophical approaches, has

    something to say on these issues.

    Mutual Constraints; Phenomenological Facts

    To cla rif y ph enomen o logy s rolew i t h i n the mind sciences, we must consider

    precisely what it means to say that phenomenology can constrain neuroscience.

    When using the term constrain (Sass and Parnas 2007, 73), we cited a well-known

    paper by Gallagher (1997): Mutualenlighten- ment: Recent phenomenology incognitive sci- ence. In the next paragraph, we cited another well-known article:

    Neurophenomenology, in which (the late) Francesco Varela (1996) speaks of

    mutualor reciprocalconstraintsbetween phenomenological accounts of

    the structure of experience and their counterparts in cogni- tive science (p.

    343). Thompson (2007), who collaborated extensively with Varela, clarifies:

    By reciprocal constraints[Varela] means thatphenomenological analyses can

    help guide and shape the scientific investigation of consciousness, and that scientific

    findings can in turn help guide and shape the phenomenological investigations (p.

    329).

    The term constrain does not, then, mean anything like inhibitor dictateto in a rigid

    or unilateral fashion. To say that the facts of subjec- tive life constrainneurobiological

    explanationis simply to say that these facts are among those that an adequate

    neurobiology must ultimately take into account. It would seem that anyperson with a

    remotely phenomenologicalbent would have to accept this latter point; indeed, it should

    even be accepted by reductionists who believe that consciousness is entirely dependent on

    thebiologi- cal substrate. After all, conscious experience is an explanandum in its own

    right (Chalmers, 1995, 209). And withoutsome idea . . . of what the subjective

    character of experience is, we cannot know what is required of physicalistic theory

    (Nagel 1979, 71).

    This does not, by the way, rule out the possibil- ity that cognitive or neurobiological findings

    might actually suggest new ways of thinking about and describing aspects ofphenomenal

    experience. On the contrary, we (like both Gallagher and Varela) are precisely arguing

    that the influence goesboth ways, that is, it would also be a question of letting

    phenomenology profit fromand be challengedbyempirical findings.2

    When it comes to cashing out this idea about mutuality or reciprocity in more concrete

    detail, various complementary proposals are currently on offer. One proposal, entitled

    neurophenomenol- ogy, was initially proposedby Varela (1996) and subsequently

  • 8/14/2019 Sass et al 2011 copy

    7/34

    Sass, Parnas,and Zahavi / Phenomenological Psychopathology and Schizophrenia 7

    developed by Lutz (2002), Lutz and Thompson (2003), and Thompson (2007). Here, the

    basic idea is to train experimental subjects to gain greater intimacy with their own

    experiences. Subsequently, the subjects are asked toprovide descriptions of these

    experiences using an open- question format, thus minimizing the imposition of

    predetermined theoretical categories. The ensuing descriptive categories are subsequently

    validated intersubjectively and then used to interpret corre- lated measurements of behavior

    and brain activity. At the same time, however, it is also suggested that, say, a consideration

    of insights from neurobiol- ogy and dynamical systems theory can help us to improve and

    refine the classicalphenomenological analyses (see Varela 1996; Thompson 2007). How is

    that supposed to happen?

    The basic idea is quite simple: let us assume, for instance, that our initial

    phenomenological descriptionpresents us with what seems to be a simple and unified

    phenomenon. When studyingthe neural correlates of this phenomenon (e.g., with

    magnetic resonance imaging), we discover that two quite distinct mechanisms are

    involved, mechanisms that are normally correlated with distinct experiential

    phenomena, say, perception and memory. This discovery might motivate us to return to

    our initialphenomenological description to see whether thephenomenon in question is truly

    as simple as we thought. Perhaps a more careful analysis will reveal that it harbors a

    concealed complexity. However, it is important to empha- size that the discovery of a

    significant complexity on the subpersonal levelto stick to this simple examplecannot

    by itself force us to refine or revise our phenomenological description. It can, however,

    serve as motivation for further inquiry.

    More recently, Gallagher (2003) has made a slightly different proposal that he has

    entitledfront-loaded phenomenology. Rather than focus- ing on training experimentalsubjects, the idea is to start with the experimental design, and to allow insights developed

    inphenomenological analyses to inform the way experiments are set up. To take a concrete

    example, let us consider the study of self-consciousness within developmental psychol-

    ogy, where the so-called mirror-recognition task has occasionally been heralded as the

    decisive test for self-consciousness (Lewis 2003). Aphenom- enological approach

    suggests moving beyond reliance on mirror-recognition alonewhichphe- nomenologists

    would typically consider evidence for the presence of a rather sophisticated form of self-

    consciousnessand attempting to detect thepresence of more primitive forms of

    propriocep- tive body awareness (Zahavi 2005). To front-loadphenomenology, however,

    does not imply that one simplypresupposes or accepts well-rehearsedphe- nomenological

    results. Rather, it involves testing those results and, more generally, incorporates a

    dialectical movement between previous insights gained in phenomenology and preliminary

    trials that will specify or extend these insights for pur- poses of the particular

    experiment or empirical investigation (Gallagher and Zahavi 2008).

    Once one grasps the actual (and, in this dis- course, standard) meaning of constrain,one

    immediately sees that the opposition Misharaposesbetween phenomenology serving

    as aconstraintversus as a generative source of hy-pothesesis entirely spurious.

    Indeed, it is only because experience is implicated in the overall causal/explanatory nexus

    (which is to say, that it serves as a constraintaccording to the standard

  • 8/14/2019 Sass et al 2011 copy

    8/34

    8 PPP / Vol.18, No. 1 / March 2011

    understanding of constrain)that it could possibly be relevant for hypothesizing. It

    is precisely this kind of mutualconstraint (between empirical data on

    neurodevelopmentalproblems, phenomenological data on initial stages of the illness, and

    neurobiological data concern- ing ontogenesis of cortico-cortical connectivity) that led

    one of the present authors to propose, in 1996, a binding problem associated with the

    phenomenological core features of schizophrenia, within a distributed mis-connectivity

    model of neurodevelopmental vulnerability to the illness (Parnas et al. 1996, 2001,

    2002).

    Before leaving the issue of methodological constraints, it is interesting to consider the

    peculiar way in which Mishara tries to establish our supposed commitment to the idea

    that phe- nomenology can provide conclusive and substan- tive knowledge about the

    nature of the mind that would determine theboundaries of neuroscientific research in a

    unidirectional manner. The textual evidence Mishara offers consists in only three

    quotations and references, all to works by Zahavi (2004, 343; 2005, 136; see Mishara

    2007a, 559). These Zahavi references are quotations taken out of context or tendentious

    attempts toparaphrase. Indeed, Mishara himself seems to recognize this last point, for he

    immediately goes on to admit (quite correctly) that Zahavi himself does not endorse this

    position.No quotations from Parnas or Sass are offered. But where, then, is the evidence

    that any of the three of us actually adopts the view Mishara attributes to us?

    A closely related misunderstanding concerns Misharas characterization of our

    understanding ofphenomenologicalfacts.Nowhere do we say that phenomenological

    methods generate abso- lutely precise and certain descriptions that cannotpossibly be

    criticized or improved uponthat is, that are not defeasible, in the sense of being inprin-

    ciple open to revision or valid objection. It is odd, then, to find Mishara claiming for himselfthe label of hermeneutic phenomenology.If hermeneuticphenomenology means a

    phenomenology that rejects aspiration to apodictic certainty in favor of a more humble

    understanding of the nature of thephenomenological enterprise (i.e., as an enterprise that

    requires interpretation rather than offering infallible description), then our worklike

    that of many otherscertainly falls under the rubric hermeneutic.3 Mishara (2007a)

    has no basis for claiming that we believe our phenomenological accounts to be immune

    to error(p. 561). Nor does Mishara offer any textual evidence to sustain his claim that

    neo-phenomenologyclaims to circumvent experimentalprocedures.Actually, a

    considerable amount of empirical work has been done and is underway to test the validity

    and rel- evance of our phenomenologically inspired model of schizophrenia (see further

    below).

    The Ipseity- or Self- Disturbance (IHM) View

    The second major way in which Mishara distin- guishes between what he calls neo-

    phenomenolo- gyand existential phenomenology is by saying that, whereas the former

    postulates disorders of selfhood (ipseity-hyperreflexivity model [IHM]) as the core of

    psychopathology of schizophrenia, the latter emphasizes, rather, disorders of passive

  • 8/14/2019 Sass et al 2011 copy

    9/34

    Sass, Parnas,and Zahavi / Phenomenological Psychopathology and Schizophrenia 9

    syntheses,binding, temporalization, and percep- tual organization. In his article, the IHM

    becomes an object of Misharas passionate attack.4 Here, however, Mishara

    misunderstands most of the key elements of our ipseity-, self-disturbance, or IHM view,

    which are clearly laid out in the two articles he targets (Sass and Parnas 2003, 2007).

    Briefly, this model claims that instability ofpre-reflective self-awareness is a core,generative feature of schizophrenia; the disorder affects what in cogni- tive literature is

    called minimal or core self. Here are some key passages from our account (Sass and Parnas,

    2007, 6870, unless otherwise noted).

    IPSEITY DISTURBANCE: [T]he core abnormality in schizophrenia is aparticular

    kind of disturbance of consciousness and, especially, of the sense of self or ipseity that

    is normally implicit in each act of aware- ness. (Ipseity derives from ipse, Latin for

    self or itself. Ipse-identity or ipseity refers to a crucial sense of self-sameness, of

    existing as a subject of experience that is at one with itself at any given moment

    [Henry1973; Ricoeur 1992; Zahavi 1999].) This self or ipseity disturbance has two

    main aspects or features that may at first sound mutually contradictory,but are in

    fact complementary. The first is hyper-reflexivitywhich re- fers to a kind of

    exaggerated self-consciousness, that is, a tendency to direct focal, objectifying attention

    towardprocesses and phenomena that would normally be in- habitedor experienced

    as part of oneself. The second is diminished self-affectionwhich refers to a decline

    in the (passively or automatically) experienced sense of existing as a living and

    unified subject of awareness.

    Ipseity disturbancealso involves a concomi- tant disturbance of the field of awareness

    that we label disturbed hold or grip(Sass 2004c; Sass and Parnas 2003, 436).

    HYPERREFLEXIVITY: The notion of hyperreflexivity includes some fairly volitional,

    quasi-volitional, or intel- lectual processes, which we term hyper-reflectivity.5 However:

    the hyperreflexivity in question is not, at its core, an intellectual, volitional, or

    reflective kind of self-consciousness; nor is it merely an intensi- fied awareness of

    something that would normally be taken as an object (e.g., in the case of an adolescents

    self-consciousness about his or her appearance). Mostbasic to schizophrenia is a kind of

    operativehyper- reflexivity that occurs in an automatic fashion. This has the effect

    of disrupting awareness and action by means of an automatic popping-up or popping-

    out ofphenomena and processes that would normally remain in the tacit background of

    awareness (where they serve as a medium of implicit self-affection), but that now cometo be experienced in an objectified and alienated manner (see Merleau-Ponty 1962, p. xviii

    re: operative intentionalityfungierendeIntentionalitt).

    Phenomenally speaking, hyperreflexivity can be manifest as an emergence or

    intensification of experience as such or a prominence of proximal over distal aspects of

    stimuli (see e.g. Sass 1994 re: phantom concreteness), or as focal awareness of

    kinesthetic bodily sensations, inner speech, or the processes or presuppositions of

    thinking.

  • 8/14/2019 Sass et al 2011 copy

    10/34

    10 PPP / Vol.18, No. 1 / March 2011

    DIMINISHED SELF-AFFECTION involves diminished sense of being a vital, first-person

    perspective on the world. It pertains to a fundamental sense of existing as an experiencing

    entity, . . . as a kind of implicit subject-pole that would normally serve as the vital center-

    point of subjective life. . . . [One] patient with schizophrenia described the condition of

    lacking this crucial if inef- fable self-affection that is essential to normal ipseity: I was

    simply there, only in that place, but without beingpresent.(Blankenburg 1971, 42;

    1991, 77)

    The hyperreflexivity and diminished self- affection central in schizophrenia involve

    distinc- tive disruptions of the tacit-focal structure of experience.[T]hese two features are

    best conceptualized not as separate processes but as mutually implicative aspects or facets

    of the intentional activity of awareness. Thus, whereas the notion of hyperreflexivity

    emphasizes the way in which something normally tacit becomes focal and explicit, the

    notion of diminished self-affection emphasizes a complementary aspect of this very same

    processthe fact that what once was tacit is no longerbeing inhabited as a medium of

    taken-for-granted self- hood. (Sass and Parnas 2003, 430)

    It makes little sense, incidentally, to character- ize our ipseity or IHM view by using a

    simple opposition between too much versus too littleself-experienceas do

    Lysaker and Lysaker (2008a, 32) in their interesting study of dialogical dimensions of

    schizophrenia. On our view, there is a sense in which the person with schizophrenia has

    both too little sense of self (diminished self- affection) and too much self-consciousness

    (hy-perreflexivity). Selfhood is too complex an issue to lend itself to unidimensional

    characterization and requires, among other things, sophisticated phenomenological analysis

    (Zahavi 2005). Before elaborating on theoretical issues, we outline recent empirical work

    that supports our self-disorderposition.

    Empirical Supportfor the Ipseity-Disturbance (IHM) View

    Like virtually all scientific work, the IHM is partly rooted in theoretical work, including

    such psychopathological studies as Sass (1987, 1992a, Chapter 7) and Spitzer (1988), as

    well as philo- sophical work including Henry (1973, 1975) and Zahavi (1999), among many

    others. It is important to point out, however, that our phenomenological claims concerning

    anomalous self-experience as a core feature of schizophrenia-spectrum disor- ders, is not

    aproduct of arm-chair theorizing or anecdotal discussion, as Mishara portrays it,but

    derives, in large measure, from years of clinical experience and considerable empirical

    research.This includes descriptive and follow-up studies of different diagnosticcategories (Vollmer-Larsen

    2008), predictive work on early psychosis (see below), and also some experimental work

    correlat- ing anomalies of experience with neurocognitive measures (Parnas et al. 2001).

    Thus, in contemporary psychiatry the notion of self-disorders as the initial, core

    features of schizophrenia was almost simultaneously first reported from a Danish study

    of 19 first-onset schizophrenia-spectrum patients (Parnas et al.

    1998) and a Norwegian study of 20 first admitted schizophrenia patients (Mller and

    Husby 2000). These findings were subsequently supported in a longitudinal study of

    155 first admitted patients, of whom about 60% suffered from schizophrenia or

  • 8/14/2019 Sass et al 2011 copy

    11/34

    Sass, Parnas,and Zahavi / Phenomenological Psychopathology and Schizophrenia 11

    schizotypal disorders (Handest and Parnas 2005; Parnas, Handest, et al. 2005).

    These pa- tients have been reassessed at a 5-year follow-up, showing that self-disorders

    are predictive of new incident cases of schizophrenia spectrum disorders (Vollmer-Larsen

    2008). A separate study compar- ing residual schizophrenia patients with remitted

    psychotic bipolar illness patients demonstrated that self-disorders were characteristic

    of schizo-phrenia (Parnas et al. 2003), suggesting a certain specificity to schizophreniaspectrum disorders. Currently, several other samples are being studied (Skodlar et al.

    2008), and data analyses are being conducted on opportunistic samples of high-risk and

    genetic research performed in Copenhagen. Similar research projects and studies on early

    identification of schizophrenia are being under- taken in several European countries,

    Israel, and Australia. A phenomenologically oriented, semi- structured psychiatric

    interviewthe EASE scale (Parnas, Mller, et al. 2005)hasbeen developed and shown

    to achieve good inter-rater reliability (Vollmer-Larsen et al. 2007). The EASE scales

    description of self-disorders seems to have satisfied a clinical void as testified by the fact

    that the scale has so far been translated into seven languages. In summary, there is now

    considerable empirical evidence available that shows trait-likepresence of self-disordersin the schizophrenia spectrum disorders. The measures of self-disorder are now being

    included in studies targeting early recogni- tion and treatment of schizophrenia.

    In his article, Mishara omits all the (then available) empirical studies mentioned.

    Oddly, however, he does mention one vignette from a conceptual publicationby Parnas

    and Handest (2003), only to warn his readers that we must be careful not to draw

    conclusions from anecdotalself-reports(Mishara 2007a, 565, italics added).

    The Notion of Ipseity or Pre- Reflective Self-Awareness

    Mishara (2007a) also gets the central theoreti- cal features of our view on self-disorder(ipseity disturbance) wrong in various ways. Consider his statement that we view the

    core deficit inschizophrenia to be on the level of intentionality of fully constituted objects

    and self(p. 560, italics added). This is incorrect.The IHM model claims that a central

    phenom- enon of the schizophrenia spectrum disorders is a disturbance in pre-reflective

    self-awareness (or ipseity, from Latin: ipse = self, itself), that is, a disturbance of the very

    mineness or first-personperspective that characterizes any experience.

    What do we mean by first-person perspective,by pre-reflective self-awareness, and what

    does the mineness of experience refer to?

    When we refer to the mineness of experience, we are not referring to a specific content ofexperi- ence, like yellow, or being salty or spongy. We are referring to the first-personal

    presence, givenness- to-me, or perspectival ownership of experience, to the fact that

    experience feels like something for somebody. For a subject to own something in a

    perspectival sense, is for the experience in question to present itself in a distinctive

    manner to the subject whose experience it is. Ipseity couldbe defined as the self-presence

    (the presence to itself) of the self-as-subject. Thesepre-reflective aspects of experience

    contribute to what we (and others) call the minimal self (cf. Zahavi 1999,2005).6 We

    admit, however, that an analysis of the minimal self is something of an abstraction as

    long as it fails to include the temporal dimen- sion (more about this in a moment). The

    basic or minimal self-experience to which we refer is not something willed or explicitly

  • 8/14/2019 Sass et al 2011 copy

    12/34

    12 PPP / Vol.18, No. 1 / March 2011

    assumed, nor does it involve reference to a full-fledged self, as Mishara seems to think. It

    is a passive and automaticprocess that must be regarded as the diachronic and

    synchronic prerequisite or precondition for any more substantial or elaborate sense of

    self.

    Having or embodying a first-person perspec- tive does not, incidentally, require beingable to articulate it linguistically. Indeed, it provides an experiential grounding of the

    latter possibility All the major figures inphenomenologyinclud- ing Husserl, Merleau-

    Ponty, Sartre, and Michel Henryconsidered a minimal form of self-con- sciousness to

    be an integral part of experience. This, for instance, is what Sartre meant when he

    declared that self-consciousness constitutes the mode of being of intentional

    consciousness (Sartre 1956, liv).

    The Issue of Phenomenological

    Reflection

    Mishara (2007a) claims that Zahavis (2005) argument for the existence of a pervasive

    pre- reflective self-awareness (ipseity) is tenuous because of numerous conceptual

    problems. He then mentions the following difficulty: there is no way of knowing

    whether what I describe in reflection was truly there before reflection,because the reflecting

    itself may have somehow added or inserted precisely those aspects I was looking for

    (Mishara 2007a, 561). As is widely acknowl- edged, recognition of this methodological

    or epistemologicalproblem is an utter commonplace inphenomenological discussion. It

    wasbroachedby Husserl himself (see, e.g., his discussion with H.J. Watt in 79 of Ideas

    I [Husserl 1982]) and was later discussed by numerous authors within the

    phenomenological tradition (cf. Chapter 4 in Zahavi 2005).

    All the phenomenologists recognized that, rather than merely copying or repeating the

    origi- nal experience, reflection actually transforms it, or as Husserl explicitly admitted, it

    alters it (Husserl1950, 72; 1987, 89). Husserl spoke of reflection as a process that

    discloses, disentangles, explicates, articulates, and accentuates (herausgehoben) all those

    components and structures that were implic- itly contained in the pre-reflective experience

    (Hus- serl 1984, 244; 1966a, 129; 1966b, 205, 236).

    One might see the phenomenologicalposition as being situated between two extremes.

    On one hand, we have the view that reflection merely cop- ies or mirrors pre-reflective

    experience faithfully; on the other, the view that reflection distorts lived experienceirredeemably. The middle course is to recognize that reflection involves both a gain and a

    loss. For Husserl, Sartre, and Merleau-Ponty, reflection is constrainedby what ispre-

    reflectively lived through; it is answerable to experiential facts and is not

    constitutively self-fulfilling. But at the same time, they recognized that reflection qua

    thematic self-experiences does not simply re-produce the lived experiences unaltered, and

    that this may be precisely what makes reflection cogni- tively valuable. As Husserl put it, in

    thebeginning we are confronted with a dumb experience that through reflection must

    then be made to articulate its own sense (Husserl 1950, 77; Merleau-Ponty

    1945, 207).

  • 8/14/2019 Sass et al 2011 copy

    13/34

    Sass, Parnas,and Zahavi / Phenomenological Psychopathology and Schizophrenia 13

    A widely held view, to which we adhere, then, is that phenomenological reflection does

    contain the potential for a kind of iatrogenic error, and that this is one reason why its

    results cannot be considered to have the status of apodictic certi- tude. This does not,

    however, preclude the value ofphenomenological reflection so long as this reflection is

    imbued with a self-critical awareness of precisely such dangers. Moreover, as Husserl

    argued, any skeptical claim to the effect that reflec- tion necessarily falsifies the lived

    experiences and that they consequently elude it completely is self- refuting: after all, this

    very claim mustpresuppose knowledge of those very same lived experiences, and how

    should one obtain that except through some kind of reflection (Husserl 1982, 79)?

    Thus, rather than adding new, distorting components and structures to the experience

    reflected upon, a reflection might, at best, simplybe accentuating structures already

    inherent in the lived experience. But how does this apply to the specific issue of the first-

    personal givenness of ex-perience that we were just discussing? To claim, as Mishara does,

    that it is reflection that creates the distinctive first-personal quality of experience, that

    experience lacked such qualities before becoming the object of a first-person thought, is to

    attribute quite exceptional powers to reflection. Such a view is not, however,

    unprecedented. Indeed, on one reading, this is precisely the position adoptedby many

    higher-order thought theorists in contemporary analytic philosophy of mind. Some of

    them have bitten the bullet and accepted the consequences of their position regarding the

    as- cription ofphenomenal consciousness to creatures that lack the capacity for higher-

    order first-person thoughts. Carruthers, for instance, holds the view that animals (and

    children under the age of three) are simply blind to the very existence of their own mental

    states; and that there is, in fact, nothing at all that it is like for them to feel pain or

    pleasure (Carruthers 1998, 216). Such a position certainly seems counterintuitive. And asCarruthers himself notes, it might have profound implications for our moral attitudes

    toward animals and animal suffering (Carruthers 1996, 221). Is this the kind of position

    that Mishara is endorsing?

    Self-Awareness and

    Absorption in the World

    Throughout his writings, Husserl, the founder of phenomenology, is very explicit in

    arguing that self-consciousnessrather than being something that only occurs during

    exceptional circumstances, namely, whenever we direct explicit attention to our

    conscious lifeis a feature characterizing normal human subjectivity as such, nomatter what worldly entities the subject might otherwisebe conscious of and occupied

    with. As Husserl for instance puts it in Zur Phnomenologie der Intersubjektivitt II,

    To be a subject is to be in the mode of being aware of oneself (Husserl

    1973, 151). It is clearly erroneous, then, for Mis- hara to take Husserl as supporting his

    claim that world-absorption and self-awareness are mutually exclusive (Mishara 2007a,

    5601). When Husserl talks about Selbstverlorenheit in connection with our intentional

    absorption in the world, he does not refer to a complete loss of self, as Mishara (2007a)

    seems to think (p. 561), but to the ab- sence of a thematic or reflective self-experience

    (see Zahavi 1999).

  • 8/14/2019 Sass et al 2011 copy

    14/34

    14 PPP / Vol.18, No. 1 / March 2011

    Heideggera key figure for hermeneuticand existential trends in phenomenology

    is also referring to pre-reflective self-experience when he argues that the self is present

    and implicated in all of its intentional (world- or object-directed) comportments; that the

    co-disclosure of the self belongs to intentionality as such (Heidegger 1989, 225).

    Heidegger also wrote that every worldly experiencing involves a certain component of

    self-familiarity, and that every experiencing is characterizedby the fact that Iam always

    some- how acquainted with myself (Heidegger 1993,251; 1989, 225).

    Misharas draws a supposed contrast between, on one hand, Sass and Parnass (2003)

    claim that we are self-aware through our practical absorp- tion in the world of objects

    (p. 430), and, on the other hand, what he calls the existentialphenomenological notion

    that what he terms self-awareness and absorption in experience are mutually

    exclusive (Mishara 2007a, 560). There is, in fact, no contrast here at all: it is just that

    two different notions of self, both clearly distinguished in much of the phenomenological

    tradition, are being conflated by Mishara. As Sass and Parnas emphasize, the self-

    awareness (ipseity) to which they primarily refer is not self- as-intentional-object-of-experience, but rather the implicit or pre-reflective self-awareness of the self-as-subject

    which most phenomenologists see as a concomitant of object awareness and a pre-

    requisite of reflective self-awareness (for details see Zahavi 1999; 2005). Thus, Paul

    Ricoeur (1966, 601), the most prominent synthesizer of phe- nomenology and

    hermeneutics, criticizes the view that consciousness turned toward the other [is]

    unconscious of itself and that self-consciousness [he is referring to pre-reflective self-

    consciousness or ipseity] corrod[es] the consciousness which is directed toward something

    other than itself.

    It is noteworthy that, here again, there seems tobe slippage in Misharas treatment of theissues: at one point, he seems to acknowledge the nonobject-like and (in a sense) non-

    representational nature of ipseity: citing Sass and Parnas (2007), he notes that the IHM

    model speaks of a disruption of a tacitly functioning operative intentionality which

    forms the background of consciousness (Mishara 2007a, 560). But then, when he

    at- tempts to argue against ipseitys fundamental role in experience, he clearly conflates

    ipseity with an object-like or representational modewhat he now calls self-

    awareness (in terms of self- reference) or an image-representation of self, that is,

    having a self, a me, rather than being a self, an I (p. 560). Yet the distinction

    betweenpre-reflective self-experience and the experience of self-as-object is at the very

    heart of the articlesby Sass and Parnas (2003; 2007) that Mishara criticizes and a book by

    Zahavi that Mishara also cites (Zahavi 2005; also 1999).

    In summary: the IHM does not focus on distur- bance of a fully constituted self or self-

    as-object nor of fully constituted object, nor does it speak of a focal, thematic

    intentionality. Rather, we speak of disturbed or unstable preconditions for the normal,

    concordant, and smooth articulation of the self-object correlation. Once one grasps this

    key point, one sees that the dynamic, ever-shifting qualities of self-experience that

    Mishara (2007a) rightly emphasizes (p. 563) are, in fact, perfectly consistent with what

    we mean by ipseity. It is obvious that the pre-reflective self would not be a static entity, but

    something more like an ongoingprocess that must exist and constantly reconstitute itself

  • 8/14/2019 Sass et al 2011 copy

    15/34

    Sass, Parnas,and Zahavi / Phenomenological Psychopathology and Schizophrenia 15

    in time.7

    Passive Synthesesand

    Operative Intentionality

    As a supposedly existential-phenomenological response or alternative view, Mishara

    (2007a) proposes that the primary disorder of schizophre- nia resides in passive

    syntheses of pre-attentive binding between subcomponents of the self (e.g., I, me, and

    mine. . .) (p. 562). (He does not, how- ever, say much about how this would cash out in

    fundamental clinical features of schizophrenia.) Mishara wants to offer the reader a

    polarized choice between ipseity, on one hand, andpassive synthesis or temporality, on the

    other, as potential candidates of a generative disorder in schizophre- nia. In this way, he

    falsely reifies phenomenological concepts into mutually exclusive natural-kindlike

    categories, while failing to grasp key distinctions between levels of discourse and of

    psychological reality.

    Mishara thus fails to grasp that, when we speak of such phenomena as schizophrenic

    autism, lackof self-affection, operative hyperreflexivity, lack of common sense, loss of

    natural self-evidence, diminished feelings of immersion, perplexity, and other aspects of

    the ipseity disturbance, we are also referring to the phenomenal manifestations of

    disturbed passive synthetic processes. Our use of the term operative intentionality,

    coined by Husserl and elaborated by Merleau-Ponty, refers precisely to the tacit, pre-

    objectival, largely pas- sive processes that found the coherence of the experiential field

    of the embedded subject (Sass2003a , 157; Sass and Parnas 2007, 69, 8285). Mishara

    (2007a) does in one passage (p. 560) note our use of the phrase operative

    intentionality,but then ignores this key point when he goes on to criticize our position.

    In a recent article by Uhlhaas and Mishara (2007) our IHM or ipseity-disturbance

    approach is described as being essentially a top-down model that emphasizes deficits in

    higher cognitive func- tions or an excess of rationality and reflective- ness (pp. 1423,

    150). Uhlhaas and Mishara describe Sass (1992a) and Sass and Parnas (2003) as claim[ing]

    that fragmentation and destruction of the self come from above by means of an excess of

    rationality or hyper self-consciousness (p.

    146). As summaries of the IHM or Sasss current or earlier writings, these are clearly

    misreadings.

    Hyperreflexivity certainly can involve intel- lectual or volitional processes, which can indeedhave pathogenetic importance. (The parallel with modernism makes these processes

    especially salient in Sasss Madness and Modernism.) But contrary to what Uhlhaas and

    Mishara imply,both Sass and Sass and Parnas have stated explicitly that hyperreflexivity

    should not be equated with intellectual or volitional processes of a higher nature

    which might better be termed hyper- reflectivitybut also involves the popping out, in

    a kind of automatic fashion, of phenomena that would not normally be in the focus of

    awareness. Sass (2003b, 249) and Sass and Parnas (2007, 69,

    8285) term this latter process operative hyper- reflexivity. They state that the operative

    type is likely in fact to be more primary in apathogenetic sense than is the reflective type of

    hyperreflexivity (p. 83),8 affecting what Blankenburg (following Husserl) calls the

  • 8/14/2019 Sass et al 2011 copy

    16/34

    16 PPP / Vol.18, No. 1 / March 2011

    fundamental receptivity of the automatic or passive syntheses that structure the

    basic act of consciousness and constitute a persons most immediate and fundamental

    rela- tionship to self and to world(Sass 2003a, 167,

    157). Earlier Sass (1992a) noted the possibility of neurophysiological disturbance of

    those lower and more automatic processes that normally al- low for spontaneity while

    providing a sense of natural embeddedness in the practical and social world (p. 396).

    Misharas characterization of our position as one that views schizophrenia as

    essentially deter- mined by higheror volitional processes is thus a misrepresentation

    of what is, in fact, an attempt to demonstrate the complexity of the interaction of

    intentional/reflective and non-intentional or operativefactors.

    In a recent article, Lysaker and Lysaker (2008b) adopt this mistaken view, portraying

    Sass as plac- ing exclusive emphasis on the withering effect of an inward gaze of

    radical intensity(p. 335). As their citations and phrasings indicate, their discussion of

    Sasss views derives largely from a single, second-hand source: a paper by Mishara(2004). They cite only one paper by Sass (2000), while ignoring passages from that paper

    that contradict theirs and Misharas portrayal. The Lysakers uncritical acceptance of

    Misharas inter-pretation mars the treatment ofphenomenology in their otherwise useful

    review article, and seems to have lead them into absurdities of which they are perhaps

    unaware. Thus, they portray Parnas and Sass as having incompatible views when, in

    reality, Parnas and Sass have been close collaborators for ten years, with congruent

    views as co-authors of papers on self-disorder and the phenomenology of

    schizophrenia.

    Also misleading is the Lysakers (2008b, 335) reference to what they call Misharas

    suggestion (emphasis added) regarding the core pathogenetic role of disruption of

    bodily systems that allowpersons, without self-conscious effort, to suddenly attend to

    novel information.In fact, the pathoge- netic significance (for schizophrenic cognition)

    of disruption of automatic processes that normally orient attention toward the novel, is

    perfectly explicit in work by Hemsley and Gray, who em- phasize disorders of the

    hippocampus-based comparator system (Hemsley 1987, 2005). Also mistaken is the

    Lysakerspresentation of this view as somehow antithetical to Sasss position (also

    implied by Uhlhaas and Mishara 2007, 150, who cite Hemsley). Indeed, this view is

    perhaps the main neurocognitive hypothesis Sass singles out for its compatibility with

    his own position (see references in Sass 1992a; 2007a, 83, and other ar- ticles).9

    InMadness andModernism, Sass (1992a, 228) discusses the role such factors might play

    in self-fragmentation and bodily alienationthe very point the Lysakers ascribe to a

    2005 publica- tion by Mishara. The compatibility of Hemsleys comparator approach

    with Sass is acknowledged in Hemsley (1998).10

    Temporality and Self- Experience

    Here we will not attempt to discuss, in any detail, the relationshipbetween temporality

    and self-experience. Clearly, however, there is some- thing absurd, from a

  • 8/14/2019 Sass et al 2011 copy

    17/34

    Sass, Parnas,and Zahavi / Phenomenological Psychopathology and Schizophrenia 17

    phenomenological stand-point, about treating self-experience and temporal experience as

    if these were distinct faculties of the mindas Mishara (2007a, 565) seems to do when

    arguing that temporality is more basic than self in the schizophrenia disturbance. Indeed

    the central point of Zahavis influential interpretation of Husserls writings on time was

    precisely that the latters notion of inner time-consciousness amounts to a form of pre-

    reflective self-awareness (Zahavi 1999, 2003a, 2003b).The temporal distortions of

    schizophrenia have long been recognized, in both the experimental and

    phenomenological literature on schizophrenia (e.g., Bovet and Parnas 1993; Minkowski

    1927;1933/2005). Before being convinced that tempo- rality in particular is playing a

    foundational role in thepathogenesis of schizophrenia, it would be necessary to show (at

    least) that (A) the disorder is reasonablyspecific to schizophrenia inparticular and (B) the

    temporal abnormality is more striking than other abnormalities in schizophrenia (thereby

    addressing some of the concerns raised long agoby Chapman and Chapman 1973).

    Mishara has not addressed either of these concerns.

    By now it should be clear that in his article, Missing links in phenomenological

    clinical neuroscience, Mishara tends to oversimplify, misrepresent, and offer

    misleading polarization of alternatives. So far we have focused primar- ily on his

    polemical treatment of our own work. Oversimplification and polarization are also

    characteristic of his conceptualizations of the possible underlying psychopathology of

    schizo-phrenia. Both tendencies emerge with clarity if we compare Misharas with

    Sasss discussion of the German Gestalt psychiatrist Matusseks ideas about prodromal

    features (including the so-called Wahrnehmungstarre) and of the relevance of Wolfgang

    Blankenburgs work for understanding negative symptoms, and also Misharas attack on

    Sass and Parnass (2007) exploration of the pos- sible explanatory relevance ofphenomenology.

    Die Wahrnehmungstarre and the Existential Complexity of Schizophrenic

    Symptoms

  • 8/14/2019 Sass et al 2011 copy

    18/34

    18 PPP / Vol.18, No. 1 / March 2011

    In Madness and Modernism (1992a, Chapter 2),

    Sass uses the phrase Truth-taking stare to capture thephenomenon described in

    Germanpsychiatry by the term Wahrnehmungstarre. Wah- rnehmungstarre refers to the

    fixed gaze that canbe especially common in early phases of schizophre- nia; it wouldtypically be translated as rigidity ofperception(as both Sass 1992a, 423, n4 and

    Mishara 2007a, 564n note). In his article, Mishara claims that Sasss use of the phrase

    truth-taking is a fanciful but apocryphal(p. 564) mistransla- tion, which suggests that

    Sass misunderstands the meaning of the German term Wahrnehmungstarre, which means

    perceptual rigidity; and that this is one indication of what Mishara calls a gross lapse of

    textual/philological accuracy that should call Sasss scholarly reliability and

    hermeneutic competence into question. Mishara goes so far as to accuse Sass of

    overlook[ing]the fundamental hermeneutic principlesby granting [himself] the

    license to slip at these basic levels of textual-philological accuracy (e.g., translation,

    historical context, or careful and correct citing of sources) (p. 564f).

    It is not difficult to show that the misunder- standings and textual/philological

    lapses are entirely Misharas. This should be apparent from

    Misharas apparent failure to take into account the following endnote, which is appended to

    Sasss first mention of the term Wahrnehmungstarre: War- hrnehmung means

    perception or observation in German. I have chosen to translate this in an unusually

    literal wayas truth-takingbecause this seems better to capture the schizophrenic

    experience in question(Sass 1992a, 44, 423).

    Wahr in German means true, as in the term Wahrheit,meaning truth.Nehmung is derived from nehmenas in to take.(Starre means stiffnessor

    rigidity.) The above-quoted note makes it perfectly obvious that Sass was de- liberately

    and overtly using a kind of poetic license (in accordance with the etymology of the parts of

    the word, and with full knowledge of thestandard meaning of Wahrnehmung) to convey a

    sense of thepatients experience of a kind of revelation that can accompany the fixed or

    rigid stare common inprodromal schizophrenia. There is, incidentally, something of a

    tradition of this kind of creative etymology within phenomenology, especially in the

    later Heidegger.

    Mishara commits other textual/philological lapses against both Sass and Matussek. Atonepoint, Mishara (2007a, 564) criticizes Sass for not following Matusseks lead more

    closely, and thereby failing to appreciate the role of rigidity or attentional capture

    while overemphasizing instead what Sass calls a mode of deliberateness and

    hyperawareness. In fact, Sass (1992a, 72,

    427f, notes 43, 44) criticizes Matusseks (Gestalt) theoretical account for downplaying

    the role of intentionality, while noting that, in his clinical de-scriptions, Matussek

    emphasizes both intentional and non-intentional aspects. Matussek (1987) does say

    that the schizophrenic isheld captiveby the object; but he also writes, The schizophrenic

    . . . is capable, to a much greater degree, of fixing his attention on an isolated object,

  • 8/14/2019 Sass et al 2011 copy

    19/34

    Sass, Parnas,and Zahavi / Phenomenological Psychopathology and Schizophrenia 19

    noting thepatients abilityand pleasurein doing so (p.

    934, emphasis added).

    Misharas characterization of Sass displays a lack of familiarity with the argumentsput

    forward in the works he criticizes. In writing on schizo-phrenia, Sass never denies the

    role of deficien- cies, dysfunctions, or other forms of affliction. Indeed, Sass (1992a,

    73) states that it would be

    absurd to claim that schizophrenic states are entirely under the patients control, and

    foolish to view schizophrenia as purely volitional and entirely self-aware(p. 114).

    Misharas attempt to appropriate for himself the label existential phenomenology

    ispeculiar. The approach Mishara offers in his article fails, in fact, to go beyond a rather

    mechanical or passive vision of the nature of schizophrenia, in which the patients

    role is simply to be afflicted with disturbances of passive synthesis; little if anything is

    said about broader human or existential consequences or about thepatients

    conscious and self-conscious project of being-in-the-world.By contrast, much of thework that Mishara criticizes does explore these aspects in considerable depth (see

    especially Sass 1992a, 2003a, 2004a; Sass and Parnas 2007). Recently, Sass has focused

    on the nature of both personhood (2007b) and autonomy (2011) in schizophrenia, noting,

    for example, that schizophrenia, a heterogeneous condition, can sometimes involve

    not simple diminishment of autonomy, but more complex disruptions of the normal

    balance between independence and de-pendence or between autonomy and

    heteronomy Misharas overly mechanical portrayal of passive syntheses seems

    particularly unsuited to accounting for the remarkable variability of schizophrenic

    symptoms and cognitive/affective abnormalities, which as often noted (e.g., Bleuler

    1950, 72) may vary with context, motivation, and attitude. It is noteworthy, forexample, that cognitive and perceptual disorganization is by no means constant, and

    often disappears in the presence of a strong motivation toward practical activity (for

    references see Sass 1992a, Chapter

    1, p. 24 and notes 47, 48, 49; Chapter 2, p. 71 and notes 105, 112). In this sense it

    seems to be linked up with particular orientations of the self (including forms of

    reflexivity and self-affection). An understanding of ipseity disturbances is also relevant

    for conceptualizingpsychotherapeutic interventions. It suggests the potential danger in

    overemphasizing certain forms of confrontation and self-reflection in the therapeutic

    process. It may also help to illuminate the potentially agen- tive role of the patient, and

    thereby suggest more subtle ways of helping patients both to identify

    with their experiences and to engage in the thera-peutic encounter (Nelson, Sass, and

    Skodlar 2009).

    Negative Symptoms

    In the sameparagraph in which Mishara ques- tions Sasss translation of

    Wahrnehmungstarre, he accuses Sass of another scholarly error; but once again, it is

    Mishara who commits errors of both fact and logic. Mishara (2007a, 565) says that

  • 8/14/2019 Sass et al 2011 copy

    20/34

    20 PPP / Vol.18, No. 1 / March 2011

    thephrase negative symptomshad not been applied to schizophrenia at the time that

    thephenomeno- logicalpsychiatrist Blankenburgpublished his book, The loss of

    natural self-evidence, in 1971, and that for this reason it is inappropriate for Sass to

    consider the book to be relevant to what we now call negative symptoms.

    As it happens, Mishara is wrong on the histori- cal point: several French psychiatrists,including De Clerambault,Nayrac, and Ey, spoke of negative symptoms in schizophrenia

    quite early in the twen- tieth century (Berrios 1985, 1991). This historical error is

    almost beside the point, however. Even if Mishara had been factually correct, his

    point would amount to a non sequitur that, if taken seriously, would preclude our

    finding much of contemporary relevance in older works ofpsycho-pathology, which

    often apply somewhat different terminology to recognizable conditions that now have

    different labels. (Often, of course, the over- lapping of categories is only partial, and

    this com- plicates the comparisons.) Mishara (2007a) also states that what

    Blankenburg calls schizophrenia simplexis a verydifferent diagnostic category

    from that of negative-symptom schizophrenia (p.

    565). The concept negative symptom is not, however, a diagnostic category at all,

    but part of a currently popular way of subtyping symptoms of schizophrenia (and some

    other conditions); nega- tive symptoms are typically distinguished frompositive and

    disorganization symptoms.

    It is obvious, in any case, that schizophrenia simplex,which lacks both positive and

    dis- organized symptoms, exemplifies at least one, particularly clear type of the

    negative syndrome. Indeed Misharas own description of schizophrenia simplex, in the

    article of his own that he cites here (his only relevant citation on the issue; Mishara

    2001, 31920), actually describes schizophrenia simplex (following ICD-10) in clear

    negative- symptom terms, namely, as exhibit[ing] thebasic but not the accessory symptoms

    of schizophrenia, as being fairly undramatic and inconspicuous in its own right, as

    manifesting decline in totalperformance,and as having the characteristic

    negativefeatures of residual schizophrenia (e.g.,blunting of affect, loss of volition)

    [which] develop withoutbeing preceded by any overt psychotic symptoms. If this is not a

    negative-symptom syndrome, what is?

    Phenomenological

    Explanation

    We end by considering the important but complex topic of phenomenologys relevance

    for explanation. We approach this issue by discussing the inaccuracies in Misharas

    characterization of Sass and Parnas (2007), Explainingschizophre- nia: The relevance

    of phenomenology.Mishara describes Sass and Parnas as offering a proposal to

    conflate explanation and understanding in their 2007 article, and as somehow

    suggesting that phenomenological explanation need not rely on experimental

    procedure. He also states that Sass andParnas opt to associate theirphe- nomenology

    with everyday explanation(p. 563). Each of these three statements is flatly mistaken. It

    is not surprising, then, that in the paragraphs containing these statements, Mishara

  • 8/14/2019 Sass et al 2011 copy

    21/34

    Sass, Parnas,and Zahavi / Phenomenological Psychopathology and Schizophrenia 21

    offers virtu- ally no quotations from Sass and Parnas (2007) (except a single phrase, and

    even that turns out to be inaccurate; on page 87, the phrase used is not explanatory

    powerbut explanatorysig- nificance; see Mishara 2007a, 563).

    The first point to be realized is that the Sass and Parnas article from 2007 does not in

    any way deny the crucial role of neurobiological factors in the explanation ofschizophrenia (nor does Sass

    1992a, which in fact contains a lengthy appendix discussing Neurobiological

    Considerations). The article focuses, rather, on the distinct yet of- ten complementary

    role that an understanding of subjectivity can play. The second point is that the article does

    not focus primarily on the distinctionbetween understanding and explanation,but on

    that between description and explanation. Sass and Parnas (2007) attempt to show that

    a com- monly held viewnamely, that phenomenology is relevant only to description

    and not to expla- nationis inaccurate. It then proceeds to differ- entiate a variety of

    senses of the word explana- tion. The paper explicitly offers a preliminary taxonomy

    of six forms ofphenomenological explanation (p. 67) divided into two groups, the

    first involving a kind of phenomenological implication,the second a kind of at least

    quasi- causal significance. The diversity of these modes of explanation is central to the

    argument.

    The point, then, in Sass and Parnas (2007), is to show that phenomenological

    accounts are not merely descriptive. But this in no way implies that all that is

    nondescriptive, or explanatory in some sense of the latter term, is somehow the

    sameas Misharas accusation regarding con- flatingwould seem to imply. (If A = not-xand B

    = not-x, this does not imply that A = B.) On the contrary, the whole point of the article is

    to make it very clear that not only the general term explana- tion. but also the forms of

    explanation to which phenomenology is relevant. are extremely various, ranging from the

    demonstration of meaningful unities to the clarification of causal sequences and

    interactions.

    In the article, Sass and Parnas (2007) note thatphenomenology (namely, the description of

    forms of experience or of subjective life) can help to explain,in one sense of that term,

    by showing, for example, how seemingly distinct features of conscious experience mayactually be mutually interdependent in the sense of being different as-pects of the same

    experiential whole (this is called a kind of implicative relationship). In another sense of

    the term explanation,phenomenology can help one to understand (and also to

    explain) how one form of experience might lead into an- other, as when unusual features

    of the subjectively experienced perceptual field (e.g.,perceptual frag- mentation) can

    inspire or motivate certain forms of (over-focused) attention, which can in turn lead to

    further transformations of the perceptual field (eventually involving, say, delusional

    per- ceptas discussed by Matussek, 1987, and also Sass 1992a, Chapter 2). The

    understanding of

  • 8/14/2019 Sass et al 2011 copy

    22/34

    22 PPP / Vol.18, No. 1 / March 2011

    such sequences has explanatorysignificance in the sense that it clarifies forms of causal

    or quasi- causal relationship that link one phase to another (viz., it is because the visual

    world has a certain kind of peculiar looka feature of subjectivitythat the patient is

    motivated to scrutinize what is before him, and this in turn leads to certain

    consequences). Sass and Parnas take the view that mental patients are conscious human

    beings; and that, in addition to manifesting the relatively direct consequences of

    neurobiological abnormali- ties, they will also react to their abnormalities in all kinds of

    ways that may sometimes require the categories of meaning and experience in order tobe

    understood or explained.

    There is something surprisingly mechanistic about the proposal Mishara (2007a) makes.

    Al- though he does not say this in so many words, he discusses the patient as if he or she

    were exclusively the victim of brain eventsas if intentional activ- ity were irrelevant and

    subjective experience no more than epiphenomenal. Misharas characteriza- tion of natural

    science as generally seeking out explanatory relationshipsbetween ever-smallerparts

    (p. 563) represents a highly reductionistic vision of science that runs counter to

    mainstream views in both modern and contemporary philoso-phy of science (re the latter,

    see articles in Kendler and Parnas, 2008)

    Sass and Parnas do not dispute that neural abnormalitiesplay a crucial role, nor indeed

    that they may often play the most fundamental role in terms of kicking off the

    sequence of events. In its most primary form, then, this irritation may well occur in a

    largely passive manner, and therefore represents an operative rather than

    reflectivekind of hyper-reflexivity, write Sass and Parnas (2007, 83; also Sass 1992a,

    6873,

    37497). This irritationmay, in fact, be a rather direct consequence of a neurally based

    cognitive dysfunction.As examples of the latter dysfunc- tion, Sass and Parnas

    mention disturbances of the hippocampus-based comparator system or of

    cognitivecoordination(citing Gray et al. 1991; Phillips and Silverstein, 2003).

    This does not mean, however, that experi- ential phenomena, together with

    responses to these phenomena, involving different degrees of

    volition, may not also play a key role. After all, even in the case of major physical

    illnesses, we are nearly always confronted with a complex combination of factors,

    which include both the organisms and the persons defensive and com-pensatory

    responses to the originating cause. In the case of psychiatric disorders, these

    responses are particularly likely to involve reactions (both consequentialand

    compensatory;Sass and Parnas 2007) to lived experiences of various kinds. Bleuler

    (1950), who firmly believed in thephysical nature of schizophrenia, nevertheless

    recognized the crucial importance of these factors, as can be seen in his subtle

    discussion of the precise nature of the affective disturbance in schizophrenia (see pp.

    4053, 36373). Even if something like a neurologicallybased disorder of attention

    (see, for example, Hemsley 2005 for an especiallyplausible account) is primary in a

  • 8/14/2019 Sass et al 2011 copy

    23/34

    Sass, Parnas,and Zahavi / Phenomenological Psychopathology and Schizophrenia 23

    chronological sense, we are nevertheless presented with a person who, over time,

    develops aparticular cognitive/perceptual style, way of living, and world

    perspectivenone of which can be entirely reduced to the attentional dysfunction itself

    (Sass 2007b). Understanding such styles or perspectives is of obvious relevance for

    understanding pathogenetic pathways and also in the therapeutic encounter and for

    devising new forms of psychological intervention.

    Consideration of possible psychological, meaning-driven sequences is not,

    incidentally, something that can be separated from the search for neurobiological

    causes. Just onepossible contribution of the former type of analysis, for instance, is

    that it may help the neuroscientist topare away features that may not be directly

    related to a malfunctioning or abnormal neural substrate (because these features are

    psychologically ex-plicable) to have a purified understanding of the more direct

    cognitive or behavioral consequences of the substrate condition. But it is also true that

    a predilection for particular modes of attention or experience may have its effect on

    the neuro-biological plane (sometimes termed downward causation).In his

    discussion, Mishara shows no sensitivity to these possibilities.

    It is also simply false to say that Sass and Par- nas opt to associate their

    phenomenology with everyday explanation (Mishara 2007a, 563).

    Indeed, in the article Mishara criticizes, Sass and Parnas (2007, 746) explicitly contrast

    the distinc- tive explanatory contribution ofphenomenology with the practical syllogism

    and thebelief-desireparadigm of mental causation that is commonlyproposed in analytic

    philosophy and that is gener- ally associated with everyday forms of explana- tion. Sass and

    Parnas do not deny the relevance of the beliefdesire paradigm for explaining certain

    things. However, they note the problems inherent in applying this unadulterated form of

    everyday explanation to many apparently irrational actions and beliefs (such as found in

    schizophrenia); and they argue that phenomenological explanation typically directs

    ones attention in a different direction, namely, towardformal or structural features

    that involve more pervasive aspects or in- frastructures of human experience (e.g., modes

    of temporal or spatial experience, general qualities of the object world, forms of self-

    experience) (Sass and Parnas 2007, 76). As Sass and Parnas say, the latter features are

    typically not part of everyday ex-planationwhich is one reason whypsychiatrists and

    psychologists would do well to be familiar with the phenomenological tradition

    precisely to be able to go beyond the resources of everyday or common-sensicalexplanation (Gallagher and Zahavi 2008; Parnas and Sass 2008; Parnas and Zahavi

    2002; Zahavi and Parnas 1998).

    In several publications, Bovet, Parnas, and Sass

    (Bovet and Parnas 1993; Parnas and Sass 2001,

    2008; Sass 1990b, 1992a Chapter 9, 1992b,

    1994, 2004b) have emphasized, for example, the relevance of such non-everyday,

    phenomenological distinctions as Heideggers between the ontologi- cal and the ontic

    for the understanding and explanation of delusions. They have noted, for example, that

    whereas many paranoid delusions do imply fairly straightforward forms of poor re-

  • 8/14/2019 Sass et al 2011 copy

    24/34

    24 PPP / Vol.18, No. 1 / March 2011

    ality-testing(the patient believes something false about a world whose structure is largely

    analogous to the normal worldonticor empiricaldelu- sions), this is not so clearly

    the case with some of the more bizarre or metaphysical (ontological) delusions in

    schizophrenia. Recently Sass (2004b,

    2007a) has argued that phenomenological notions about ipseity and the horizonsofexperience can help to explain some of the anomalies of

    emotion and affect in schizophrenia (including certain neurophysiological findings),

    notably the curious possibility that such patients can experi- ence a heightening of certain

    forms of affectivity (awe, ontological anxiety) simultaneous with a diminishment of the

    more passionate or standard forms of emotionality.

    Conclusion

    Overall, Misharas arguments in Missing linkbetray misunderstanding of the relevant

    phenom- enological and psychiatric literature as well as failure to grasp the key points of

    thepublications he criticizes. In this article, we have addressed most of Misharas errors,

    attempting to do so in a way that serves the larger purpose of clarifying gen- eral issues

    pertainingboth to phenomenological psychopathology and to our own perspective on

    schizophrenia. We have concentrated especially on several broad points: these include the

    mutuality of the relationshipbetween thephenomenological en- terprise and cognitive

    (neuro)science; the nature of self-experienceparticularly ipseity or pre-reflec- tive self-

    consciousness together with the notions of hyperreflexivity and diminished self-affection

    and their possible disturbance in schizophrenia; thepotentially complex interactions of

    intentional or quasi-volitional with non-volitional processes in the formation ofsymptomatology; and thepos- sible (and diverse) contribution ofphenomenology to

    psychological explanation.

    Notes1. An additional reason for rejecting Misharas use of the term neophenomenology: it

    has already been used extensively by Herman Schmitz (2003).

    2. Mishara himself quotes the phrases reciprocal constraintand mutual

    enlightenment,even including them in the abstract, in Mishara et al. (1998).

    3. Sasss Madness and Modernism (1992a, see pp.

    9, 10, 27) is perhaps the most extended recent attempt (together with his The Paradoxes of

    Delusion [1994]) to offer an explicitly hermeneutic-phenomenological approach to

    schizophrenia. For introductions to her- meneutic phenomenologys relevance, see Sass 1988b,

    1998. (In retrospect, Sass would revise his discussion of Husserl in these latter articlesalong

    lines inspired by Zahavi [2003a] and explained in Thompson [2007, appendix A].)

    4. A more accurate (but impossibly unwieldy) label for the overall model would perhaps be

    the IHRDSAM, standing for the Ipseity/HyperReflexivity/Dimished-Self- Affection Model.

    5. Hyper-reflective processes are not always active; they can, for example, be quasi-

    automatized. There are many nuances to the activity/passivity issue.

    6. More could be said about this topic (self-aware- ness vs self), but detailed analysis is

  • 8/14/2019 Sass et al 2011 copy

    25/34

    Sass, Parnas,and Zahavi / Phenomenological Psychopathology and Schizophrenia 25

    beyond the scope of this paper. See Zahavi (2005, 2009).

    7. For discussion of how seeking a static, object-like entity precludes finding the self-as-subject,

    see discussion of William James in chapter 7 of Sass (1992a).

    8. Mishara (2007a) misses the relevant point when he acknowledges that, for the IHM,

    hyperreflexiv- ity (or exaggerated self-reflection) may itselfbecome automatic in

    schizophrenia leading to the pop outof irrelevant background stimuli and disruptive

    bottom up processes (560; also in Mishara 2007b, p. 716n). Sass and Parnas do indeed

    mention this latter kind of development (which involves an automatizing of reflec- tion).

    It would have been more relevant, however, to recognize that, according to our IHM view,

    operative hyperreflexivity is more fundamental, temporally and causally, than is hyper-

    reflection (Sass and Parnas 2007,

    69, 825)the latter point directly refutes Misharas critique.

    9. Sass (1992a, 228) writes:

    [The] mode of exigent introspection . . . could also reflect some more specific cognitive factor

    rooted in neurobiological abnormalities, such as an incapacity (or a disinclination) to synthesize

    larger Gestalts or, perhaps, an inability to desist from paying attention to stimuli that are

    habitually experienced and that would not normally be focused on (kinesthetic and other in-

    ner sensations would be one important subset of such sensations). In these latter cases,

    fragmentation of the self would be not just a consequence but, in a sense, also a cause of a certain

    kind of hyperfocused introspection.

    An attached note cites Hemsley as well as Matussek and Conrad.

    10. The top down-versus-bottom up or from above-versus-from below distinction

    misconstrues the difference between Misharas and our view, as explained. Also

    erroneous is using Nietzsches notion of the Dionysianto describe the view that

    common sense fails because perceptual and automatic meaning processing are [sic]

    disrupted from below (Lysaker and Lysaker 2008a, 32; 2008b, 335, citing Mishara). In

    Nietzsches Birth of Tragedy, Dionysianism refers to self-dissolution from excess of passion

    or instinct. This has nothing in common with the disrupted perceptual/ automatic-

    processing view and seems antithetical to the nature of schizophrenia (Sass 1992a,

    Prologue; 2007a).

    ReferencesAndreasen, N. C. 2007. DSM and the death of phe- nomenology in America: An example of

    unintended consequences. Schizophrenia Bulletin 33:108112. Berrios, G. E. 1985. Positive and

    negative symptoms and Jackson. A conceptual history. Archives of General

    Psychiatry 42:958.

    . 1991. French views on positive and negative symptoms: A conceptual history.

    Comprehensive Psychiatry 32:395403.

    Blankenburg, W. 1971. Der Verlust der naturlichen Selb- stverstandlichkeit:Ein Beitrag zur

  • 8/14/2019 Sass et al 2011 copy

    26/34

    26 PPP / Vol.18, No. 1 / March 2011

    Psychopathologie symptomarmer Schizophrenien. Stuttgart: Ferdinand Enke Verlag. (The

    loss of natural self-evidence.)

    . 1991. La Perte de LEvidence Naturelle: Une Contribution a la Psychopathologie des

    Schizophr- nies Pauci-Symptomatiques, trans. J.-M. Azorin, and Y. Totoyan. Paris: Presses

    Universitaires de France (The loss of natural self-evidence.)

    Bleuler, E. 1950. Dementiapraecox or the group of schizophrenias. New York: International

    Universi- ties Press.

    Bovet, P., and J. Parnas. 1993. Schizophrenic delusions: A phenomenological approach.

    Schizophrenia Bul- letin 19:57997.

    Carruthers, P. 1996. Language, thoughts and con- sciousness. An essay in philosophical

    psychology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    . 1998. Natural theories of consciousness. Euro- pean Journal of Philosophy 6, no.

    2:20322.

    Chalmers, D. 1995. Facing up to the problem of consciousness. Journal of Consciousness

    Studies

    2:20019.

    Chapman, L. J., and J. P. Chapman. 1973. Disordered thought in schizophrenia. New York:

    Appleton- Century-Crofts.

    Clark, A. 1997. Being there: Putting brain, body, and world together again. Cambridge: MIT

    Press.

    Cutting, J. 1997. Principles of psychopathology: Two worldstwo mindstwo hemispheres.

    Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

    Cutting, J., and F. Dunne. 1989. Subjective experience of schizophrenia. Schizophrenia Bulletin

    15:21731. Cutting, J., and M. Shepherd, eds. 1987. Clinical roots of the schizophrenia concept.

    Cambridge UK: Cam-

    bridge University Press.

    Dreyfus, H. 1979. What computers cant do, revised edition. New York: Harper and Row.

    Fuchs, T. 2005. Delusional mood and delusional per- ceptionA phenomenological analysis.

    Psychopa- thology 38:1339.

    . 2007. The temporal structure of intentionality and its disturbance in schizophrenia.

    Psychopathol- ogy 40:22935.

    Gallagher, S. 1997. Mutual enlightenment: Recent phenomenology in cognitive science.Journal

    of Consciousness Studies 4:195214.

    . 2003. Phenomenology and experimental de