richard rorty, "realism and the reasons of the heart", may 3, 1999

Upload: 1236howard

Post on 03-Apr-2018

214 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/28/2019 Richard Rorty, "Realism and the Reasons of the Heart", May 3, 1999

    1/30

    1

    REALISM AND THE REASONS OF THE HEART

    In a footnote to his seminal article The Natural Ontological

    Attitudean article which begins with the sentence Realism is dead

    Arthur Fine offers a pregnant analogy between realism and religion.

    In support of realism there seem to be only those reasons of the

    heart which, as Pascal says, reason does not know. Indeed, I have

    long felt that belief in realism involves a profound leap of faith, not

    at all dissimilar from the faith that animates deep religious

    convictions. I would welcome engagement with realists on this

    understanding, just as I enjoy conversation on a similar basis with my

    religious friends. The dialogue will proceed more fruitfully, I think,

    when the realists finally stop pretending to a rational support for

    their faith, which they do not have. Then we can all enjoy their

    intricate and sometimes beautiful philosophical constructions (of,

    e.g., knowledge, or reference, etc.) even though to us, the

    nonbelievers, they may seem only wonder-full castles in the air.

    In various recent articles, I have tried to expand on Fines analogy

    between realism and religion. I have been suggesting that we see realism

    as an etiolated version of the religious attempt to bow down before a

    non-human power to which human beings owe respect. I have also

    urged that we see the idea that natural science is privileged over other

    parts of culture as a version of the priestly project of c laiming respec t from

  • 7/28/2019 Richard Rorty, "Realism and the Reasons of the Heart", May 3, 1999

    2/30

    2

    other humans because of ones purported special relation to such a

    power. As I see it, the great divide in contemporary philosophical

    thinking is between representationalists who believe that there is an

    intrinsic nature of non-human reality to be held in human thought and

    antirepresentationalists who believe that scientific, like moral, progress is a

    matter of finding ever more effective ways for enriching human life.

    Representationalists are necessarily realists, since if they did not believe

    that there was a Way the World Is In Itself they would have no reason to

    insist that culture is divided between areas where there is a fact of the

    matter and areas in which there is not. Whereas realists find pathos in the

    thought of the gap which seperates human thought from its non-human

    object, we antirerpesenationalists find pathos in thinking of the distance

    which seperates us from a utopian human futurefrom the world in which

    our remote descendantsl have developed far better ways of dealing with

    the non-human environment, presently unimaginable artistic genres, and

    far kinder and more decent social institutions and customs.

    On my account of modern times, the pathos of mans seperation

    from God has been succeeded, among the intellectuals, by these two

    alaternative forms of pathos. If you do not like the term pathos, the

    word Romance will do as well. Or one could use Thomas Nagels term

    the ambition of transcendence. The important point is not the choice of

    terms but the recognition that both sides in contemporary philosophy are

  • 7/28/2019 Richard Rorty, "Realism and the Reasons of the Heart", May 3, 1999

    3/30

    3

    trying to find a suitable replacement for religion. Representationalism and

    realism are no more or less passtionately irrational than anti-

    representationalist humanism. Neither side is ever going to have a knock-

    down argument, any more than Enlightenment secularism had a knock-

    down argument against traditional theism. .

    The heartfelt conviction that there just must be a non-human

    authority to which we can resort has been, for a very long time, woven

    into the common sense of the West. It is a conviction common to Soc rates

    and to Luther, to scientists who say they love truth and fundamentalists

    who say they love C hrist. Reweaving the network of shared beliefs and

    desires which makes up Western culture so as to get rid of this conviction

    will take centuries, or perhaps millenia. This reweaving, if it ever occurs, will

    result in an inabilty to share the intuitions which, in our culture, are

    pumped up by the cosmological argument for the existence of God and

    by the argument that only correspondence to the intrinsic nature of reality

    can explain the success of natural science.

    I think that it is a bit misleading to say, as Fine does in the quotation

    with which I began, that such arguments as these cannot provide

    rational support for the view being defended. What counts as rational

    support, like what counts as valid inference, is a matter of what people

    are willing are accustomed to take as rational or as valid, and this in turn is

    what coheres with their intuitions. Those intuitions are determined by the

  • 7/28/2019 Richard Rorty, "Realism and the Reasons of the Heart", May 3, 1999

    4/30

    4

    culture in which they have been raised, and there is no way to short-

    circuit culture by appealing either to Reason or to Nature. The battle is

    always between an old culture and one striving to be born.

    As an example of what I mean, consider the theist who is told that

    the term God, as used in the conc lusion of the cosmological argument

    is merely a name for our ignorance. Consider the realist who is told that his

    explanation for the success of science is no better than Molieres doc tors

    explanation of why opium puts people to sleep. Both are, in most cases,

    equally unfazed. Even if they go so far as to admit that their opponents

    objection to their favorite argument admits of no refutation, they insist that

    it produces no conviction. For they feel the need for answers to questions

    like What came before the Big Bang? and Why does science

    succeed? So they typically fall back on rhetorical questions such as If

    not God, what? If not correspondence to reality, what? They think that

    anyone who does not share the need to answer these questions, anybody

    who just shrugs them off, is being irrational. Realists think that it is irrational

    for Fine to shirk the attempt to explain the success of science, just as

    theists think it irrational of Hume, Kant and Steven Weinberg to speculate

    about the nature of the First Cause.

    It is often said that religion was refuted by showing the incoherence

    of the concept of God or by showing that there is no evidence for the

    existence of God. It is often said that realism can be refuted by showing

  • 7/28/2019 Richard Rorty, "Realism and the Reasons of the Heart", May 3, 1999

    5/30

    5

    the incoherence of the notions of World or correspondence as the

    realist uses them. Both claims seem to me almost entirely wrong. No one

    accustomed to throw around a term like the will of God or mind-

    independent World in complex and sometimes persuasive arguments is

    ever going to be persuaded that his concepts are incoherent. A concept

    is just the use of a word, and useful words cannot be denied coherence

    simply because their users can be forced into tight dialectical corners.

    Insofar as religion is dying, it is because of the attractions of a humanist

    culture, not because of flaws internal to the discourse of theists. Insofar as

    realism is dying, it is because of the attractions of a culture which is more

    deeply and unreservedly humanist than that offered by the arrogant

    scientism which is the philosophical position most frequently associated

    with the ideals of the Enlightenment.

    For all these reasons, it seems best to stop saying that either religion

    or realism is unsupported by rational argument, and instead to say that

    the notion of rational support is not apropros when it comes to proposals

    to retain, or to abandon, intuitions as deep-lying and long-lasting as those

    to which theists, realists, and we anti-representationalists appeal. Where

    argument always seems to fail, as J ames rightly says in The will to

    believe, the reasons of the heart should have their way. But this does not

    mean that the human heart always has the same reasons, asks the same

    questions, and hopes for the same answers. The gradual growth of

  • 7/28/2019 Richard Rorty, "Realism and the Reasons of the Heart", May 3, 1999

    6/30

    6

    secularismthe gradual increase in the number of people who do not

    find theism what J ames called a live, momentous and forced option, is

    testimony to the hearts malleability.

    Only when the sort of cultural change I envisage is complete will we

    be able to start doing what Fine suggests--enjoying such beautiful and

    intricate theistic or realistic constructions as SpinozasEth ic sand Kripkes

    Nam ing a nd Nec essityas aesthetic spec tac les. Only when realism is no

    longer a live, momentous and forced option for us, only when Dummett

    can no longer find an audience for his view of the history of philosophy,

    will we be able to hear questions about the mind-independence of the

    real as having the quaint charm of questions about the consubstantiality

    of the Persons of the Trinity. In the sort of culture which I hope our remote

    descendants may inhabit, the philosophical literature about realism and

    anti-realism will have been aestheticized in the same way as we have

    aestheticized the debate between Occamites and Scotists.

    Dummett capitalizes on a hope which has burned brightly since

    Platothe hope that we can divide up the culture into the bits where the

    non-human is encountered and acknowledged, the hard areas, and the

    softer areas in which we are on our own. This need to divide culture into

    harder and softer areas is, I think, the most familiar and pervasive

    contemporary form of the idea that there is something to which human

    beings are responsible save other human beingssomething like God or

  • 7/28/2019 Richard Rorty, "Realism and the Reasons of the Heart", May 3, 1999

    7/30

    7

    Truth or Reality. The idea of a hard area of culture is the idea of an area in

    which this responsibility is salient. Dummetts suggestion that a lot of

    philosophy is about the question of whether bivalence obtains for a

    certain range of sentences amounts to the c laim that philosophers have a

    spec ial responsibility for telling us where the hard ends and the soft begins.

    A great deal of Fines work is devoted to casting doubt on the need

    to draw that line. He is the philosopher of science who has done most to

    deflate the arrogance embodied in Quines quip that philosophy of

    science is philosophy enough. Much of what he has written gears in nicely

    with the writings of two other contemporary philosophersDonald

    Davidson and Robert Brandomwho are trying to put all true sentences

    on a referential par, and thereby to erase the line between the hard and

    the soft. Fine, Davidson and Brandom have helped us understand how to

    stop thinking of intellec tual progress as a matter of increasing tightness of

    fit with the non-human world and how to picture it instead as our being

    forced by that world to reweave our networks of belief and desire in ways

    that make us better able to cope. Humanism, in the sense I am using the

    term, will only triumph when we no longer discard the question Do I know

    the real object, or only one of its appearances? and replace it with the

    question Am I using the best possible description of the situation in which I

    find myself, or can I find a better one?

  • 7/28/2019 Richard Rorty, "Realism and the Reasons of the Heart", May 3, 1999

    8/30

    8

    I see Fines NOA papers as fitting in nicely with Davidsons claim

    that we can make no good use of the notion of mind-independent

    reality and with Brandoms Sellarsian attempt to interpret linguistic

    meanings as a matter of the rights and responsbilities of participants in a

    social practice. The writings of these three philosophers blend together, in

    my imagination, to form a sort of manifesto for the kind of anti-

    representationalist movement in philosophy whose aspirations I have just

    outlined.

    Occasionally, however, I come across passages, or lines of thought,

    in Fines work, which are obstacles to my syncretic efforts. There are two

    sets of passages in his 1984 paper (The Natural Ontologica l Attitude)

    which arouse doubts; passages about reference and passages about

    method. An example of the first reads as follows:

    When NOA counsels us to accept the results of science as true, I

    take it that we are to treat truth in the usual referential way, so that

    a sentence (or statement) is true just in case the entities referred to

    stand in the referred-to relations. Thus NOA sanctions ordinary

    referential semantics and commits us, via truth, to the existence of

    the individuals, properties, relations, processes, and so forth referred

    to by the scientific statements that we accept as true. (p. 130)

  • 7/28/2019 Richard Rorty, "Realism and the Reasons of the Heart", May 3, 1999

    9/30

    9

    Reading this passage leaves me uncertain of whether, like

    Davidson, Fine wants to read all the sentences we accept as truethe

    ones accepted after reading literary critics as well as after reading

    scientific textbooksas true just in case the entities referred to stand in

    the referred-to relations Davidson thinks that the sentence

    Perserverance makes honor bright is true in this way, just as much as

    F=MA. But Davidson thinks this because he does not think that reference

    has anything to do with ontological commitment, and indeed has no use

    for the latter.

    Fine does seem to have a use for this notions, and I suspec t he

    drags in ordinary referential semantics because he thinks that reference

    and ontological commitment have something to do with each other. I

    think it would be more harmonious with the overall drift of his thinking to

    mock that Quinean idea rather than to try to rehabilitate it. NOA, Fine

    says, tries to let science speak fo itself, and it trusts in our native ability to

    get the message without having to rely on metaphysical or

    epistemological hearing aids. (And not, p. 63) So why drag in a semiotic

    hearing aid such as ordinary referential semantics? If, as Fine

    recommends, we stop trying to conceive of truth as a substantial

    something, a something that will then act as limit for legitimate human

    aspirations (And not, p. 56) , as a goal of inquiry, should we still say that

    we are committed, via truth, to the existence of this or that? Whey

  • 7/28/2019 Richard Rorty, "Realism and the Reasons of the Heart", May 3, 1999

    10/30

    10

    should we conceive of existence as something which we sometimes

    commit to and sometimes refrain from committing to? If we give up the

    notion that we are trying to correspond to reality, as he suggests we do,

    will we still ask ourselves questions like Am I committed to the existence of

    X?

    As support for my suggestion that the notion of ontological

    commitment is one Fine could get along nicely without, let me cite

    another of his instructive remarks about the analogy between religion and

    realism. Fines answer to the question Do you believe in X?, for such Xs

    as electrons and dinosaurs and DNA, is I take the question of belief to be

    whether to accept the entities or instead to question the science that

    backs them up. (Afterword, p. 184) Then, in response to the objection

    But does not believe in mean that they really and truly exist out there in

    the world? Fine says that he is not sure it does. He points out that those

    who believe in the existence of God do not think that is the meaning, at

    least not in any ordinary sense of really and truly out there in the world.

    I take the point of the analogy to be that people who talk about

    God as the unquestioningly and unphilosphically religious do not need to

    distinguish between believing in God and talking the way they talk. To

    say that they believe in God and that they talk the talk are two ways of

    describing the same phenomenon. Similarly, Fine is saying, for a physicist

    to say that to say that she believes in electrons and to say that she does

  • 7/28/2019 Richard Rorty, "Realism and the Reasons of the Heart", May 3, 1999

    11/30

    11

    not question the science behind electron-talk are two ways of describing

    the same situation. When Kant or Tillich ask theists whether they are not

    really talking about a regulative ideal or a symbol of ultimate concern,

    rather than something that they think really exists, they are justifiably

    irritated. Physicists should be equally irritated when asked whether they

    think that statements about electrons are true or merely empirically

    adequate. The theist sees no reason to resort to demonstrations of

    existence, or analyses of the meaning of is when applied to God for he

    talks God-talk into his life as true in exac tly the manner, in her capacity as

    physicist, she talks electron-talk into her life as true.

    It accords with the overall humanist position I outlined in the first

    section of this paper to say there are no acts called assent or

    commitment which we can perform that will put us in a different relation

    to an object than simply talking about that object in sentences whose

    truth we have taken into our lives. To use a word in a certain way and to

    believe in the existence of the referent of that word is the same

    phenomenon. The idea that we might be in a better position to figure out

    what to believe by first finding out what there really and truly isby finding

    the right ontology--is an impossible attempt to separate thought and

    language from action.

    Looked at another way, this idea epitomizes a confusion between

    existential commitment and a profession of satisfaction with a way of

  • 7/28/2019 Richard Rorty, "Realism and the Reasons of the Heart", May 3, 1999

    12/30

    12

    speaking or a social practice. An existential commitment, as Brandom

    nicely says in MAKING IT EXPLICIT, is a claim to be able to provide an

    address for a certain singular term within the structured space provide

    mapped out by certain canonical designators. (See MIE, pp. 444ff.) To

    deny the existence of Pegasus, for example, is to deny that a continuous

    spatiotemporal trejectory can be traced out connecting the region of

    space-time occupied by the speaker to one occupied by Pegasus. To

    deny that Sherlock Holmes fairy godmother exists is to deny that she can

    be related to Conan Doyles text in the way that Moriarity and Mycroft

    can. And so on for other structured spaces, such as those of

    mathematics. The point of putting the matter Brandoms way is to make

    clear that metaphysical discourse, the discourse of ontological

    commitment, does not provide us with a such a structured space. It is,

    instead, a discourse in which we express our like or dislike, our patience or

    impatience with, various linguistic practices. We do so by pretending that

    our decision about whether to engage in those practices can be based

    upon reflection on the desirability of certain ontological commitments. But

    this is fantasy. We talk first, and commitment falls out of the talk. Similarly,

    as Davidson points out, we talk first, and reference falls out of the attempt

    to interpret what we are saying.

    Fine and Davidson seem to me entirely right in saying that we need

    to stop the pendulum swinging back and forth between an analysis of trut

  • 7/28/2019 Richard Rorty, "Realism and the Reasons of the Heart", May 3, 1999

    13/30

    13

    of correspondence and an analysis of it as acceptance. I entirely agree

    with Fines claim that we should be neither realists nor antirealists, and

    should acknowledge that the concept of truth cannot be explained

    or given an account of without circularity (And not, p. 62). But there

    seems to me at least the potential for a division between Find and

    Davidson when it comes to reference. If one takes Davidsons line on

    reference, one will not find it natural to hook it up with the notion of

    ontological commitments or attitudes. One will lots of sentential attitudes,

    but no ontological ones.

    Davidson urges that we not treat reference as a concept to be

    given an independent analysis or interpretation in terms of non-linguistic

    concepts. (Inquiries, p. 219) Rather, reference is, he says, a posit we

    need to implement a theory of truth (bid., p. 222) For Davidson, a theory

    of truth for a natural language does not explain reference, at least in this

    sense: it assigns no empirica l content direc tly to relations between names

    or predicates and objects. These relations are given a content indirectly

    when the T-sentences are. (ibid, p. 223) If one assumes that a theory

    which permits the deduction of all the T-sentences is all we need in the

    way of what Fine calls ordinary referential semantics, then the notion of

    reference becomes hard to tie up with that of ontological commitment. It

    seems equally unnatural to ask whether I am committed either to the

    existence of jejuneness or of magnetic monopoles. The notion of

  • 7/28/2019 Richard Rorty, "Realism and the Reasons of the Heart", May 3, 1999

    14/30

    14

    ontological attitude, or ontological commitment, seems to have no

    function in the life of someone who takes the results of both physics and

    literary criticism in the same way as we accept the evidence of our

    senses (to use Fines phrase).

    Perhaps, however, Fine would agree both with Davidson about the

    nature of the notion of reference and with me about the need to treat

    literary criticism and physics as producing truth, and reference, of exactly

    the same sort. That he would is suggested by his saying that those who

    accept NOA are being asked not to distinguish between kinds of truth or

    modes of existence or the like, but only among truths themselves in terms

    of centrality, degrees of belief, and the like. (NOA, 127)

    This last quotation chimes with Fines remark that NOA is basically

    at odds with the temperament that looks for definite boundaries

    demarcating science from pseudo-science, or that is inclined to award

    the title scientific like a blue ribbon on a prize goat. (And not, p. 62) It

    chimes also with the last paragraph of his recent Presidential Address to

    the APA, in which he says that the first false step in this whole area is the

    notion that science is spec ial and that scientific thinking is unlike any

    other. (Viewpoint, p. 19) If Fine would carry through on these remarks by

    saying that there is no more point in using notions like reference and

    ontological attitude in connection with physics than in connection with

    literary criticism, then he and I might agree that nobody should ever

  • 7/28/2019 Richard Rorty, "Realism and the Reasons of the Heart", May 3, 1999

    15/30

    15

    bother to have an ontology. Nobody should have the sort of worries

    Quine had, about having more things in his ontology than there are in

    heaven and earth. To give up on the project of dividing culture into the

    hard and the soft areas would lead one to give up on the project of listing

    the things that there are in heaven and earth, a list presumed to be

    shorter than the list of expressions in our language which can be

    nominalized and thereby reified.

    To take this line would mean that Einstein would not have been

    worrying about a serious question when he, as Fine puts it, wanted to

    claim genuine reality for the cnetral theoretical entities of the general

    theory, the four-dimensional space-time manifold and assoc iated tensor

    fields. Fine goes on to say that had Eintsteins claim been right then

    space and time cease to be real. But if Fines ultimate view is what I

    think it ought to be, he should hesitate to say that the war between

    Einstein, the realist, and Bohr, the nonrea list, was not just a sideshow in

    physics, nor an idle intellectual exercise. He should say rather that an idle

    intellec tual exercise was the outward and visible form of a serious

    discussion about what young physicists should and should not spend their

    time looking for. Nor, if Fines view were what I would like it to be, would

    he himself express the hope that quantum theory is at least consistent

    with some kind of underlying reality. He would translate this ontological-

    sounding remark into some sort of suggestion about what lines of research

  • 7/28/2019 Richard Rorty, "Realism and the Reasons of the Heart", May 3, 1999

    16/30

    16

    physicists will find profitable and which not. He would, in short, translate

    remarks about what non-human things there really are into remarks about

    what human beings should do to improve the human future.

    One more example of a passage which makes me wonder whether

    Fines view coincides with my own can be be found in the Afterword to

    THE SHAKY GAME. There Fine says that

    It is no possible to have a globa l characterization of scientific

    productsneither as constructions, nor as externally real things, nor

    as generally reliable models. If science is genuinely open, we need

    to go local and particularist. We need to look at each case and see

    what there is to say about the character of scientific products and

    representations and whether any general characterization is

    needed at all. (p. 188)

    On the view I am suggesting, there is no need for a local characterization

    either. For once we have decided that a scientific product (a set of

    statements, a new device, a new hormone, a new vocabulary) is useful

    for this and useless for that, and once we know how to get, or avoid

    getting, similar products by steering students into this disciplinary matrix

    rather than that, it is not clear what else we need to do. It is not clear why

    we should want any further characterization, for the only

    characterizations which might come to mind are likely to be variations on

    the worn-out themes of hardness and softness: characterizations such as

  • 7/28/2019 Richard Rorty, "Realism and the Reasons of the Heart", May 3, 1999

    17/30

    17

    made found, instrumental and real. So although I applaud the

    spirit of Fines remark that the realists determinate, external world is just

    one more social construction, I balk at the letter. The realists conception

    of inquiry, like the theists conception of mans position in the universe, is

    no more or less constructed than is the human self-image which will, I

    hope, dominate the culture of our remote descendantsa self-image in

    which non-human authority plays no role, and in which the notion of love

    of truth has become interchangeable with that of love of conversation.

    I would rather say that we shall only escape the need for a hard-

    soft distinction when we have abjured the made-found distinction, and

    that therefore never start asking, about some given scientific product,

    what our share and what natures share in its production has been. This is

    why I am dubious about the Fines claim that Constructivism is a useful

    antidote to realism; its attention to science in action deepens our

    understanding of the soc ial in science and the myriad ways in which

    science is open (p. 188). It seems to me that one can follow Latour

    around on his tours of laboratory life without adopting anything remotely

    like constructivism. I take the moral of Davidsons doctrine of

    triangulation to be that everything we can ever speak of is a much

    constructed, and as much real, as anything else. If that doctrine is right,

    we do not need Latours notion of quasi-object, because there are no

    objects which are not quasi..

  • 7/28/2019 Richard Rorty, "Realism and the Reasons of the Heart", May 3, 1999

    18/30

    18

    Before leaving the topics of reference and ontological

    commimtment, let me remark that the passage I quoted about ordinary

    referential semantics has been seized upon by Alan Musgrave tp ridicule

    Fines claim to have a position distinct from that of the realist. Musgrave

    would have had less ammunition, I think, if Fine had not only omitted this

    passage but had been more explicit in admitting that NOA, as J ared

    Leplin has lately said, is not an alternative to realism and antirealism, but

    a preemption of philosophy altogether, at least at the metalevel. (Leplin,

    p. 174) Leplin is right, in my opinion, to say that Fines idea that scientific

    theories speak for themselves, that one can read off of them the

    answers to a ll legitimate philosophical questions abouit science, cannot

    be squared with the rich tradition of philosophical debate among

    scientists over the proper interpretation of theories. So I think that the

    Fine should not attempt to take the Einstein-Bohr debate at face value,

    nor to rehabilitate notions like ontological commitment. He should grant

    to Leplin that Philosophy of science in the role of interpreter and

    evaluator of the scientific enterprise, and realism in particular, as such a

    philosophy of science, are superfluous. (Leplin, p. 139) He should say that

    we felt the need for such an interpreter, evaluator, and public-relations

    man only so long as we thought of natural science as privileged by a

    spec ial relation to non-human reality, and of scientists as the priests of the

    modern age. .

  • 7/28/2019 Richard Rorty, "Realism and the Reasons of the Heart", May 3, 1999

    19/30

    19

    I said earlier that there is a sec ond set of passages in Fines writings

    which made me wonder if I am really entitled to include him in my

    syncretic projects. These are the passages in which he uses the term

    method. Sometimes Fine seems to take this notion more seriously than I

    think it deserves. At the beginning of The Natural Ontological Attitude

    Fine says that Boyd and Putnam have focused on on the methods

    embodied in scientific practice, methods teased out in ways that seem to

    me accurate and preceptive about ongoing science, methods that

    lead to scientific success. (NOA, p. 113) Here Fine speaks in the same

    idiom as Philip Kitcher who, in his book THE ADVANCEMENT OF SCIENCE,

    undertakes to to defend realism on the basis of an examination of what

    he calls processes that are well-designed for promoting cognitive

    progress (Kitcher, p. 192)

    Kitchers argument for the residual truth of rationalism in the philosophy

    of science is based on the claim that we can isolate such proc esses and

    attribute the achievement of cognitive progress to their use. To make his

    case, he would have to find a middle ground between the substantive

    explanations of events put forward by scientists, and the disciplinary

    matrices which shape themselves around acceptance of those

    explanations, on the one hand, and uttterly general and completely

    uncontroversial methodological platittudes on the other. I do not think

  • 7/28/2019 Richard Rorty, "Realism and the Reasons of the Heart", May 3, 1999

    20/30

    20

    that he, or any other writer on scientific method I have read, succeeds in

    this task. When Kitcher commends, for example, elimination of

    alternatives through the production of inconsistency, forced retreats that

    open problems, and employment of background constraints (Kitcher, p.

    288), he is not recommending anything that deserves to be called a

    method or a cognitive process. He is describing an activity which all

    human beings perform every day. When, on the other hand, Kitchers

    examples of superior cognitive strategies are more spec ific, theya re

    simply summaries of the arguments by means of which some victorious

    scientific theory triumphed. Kitcher fails to give us an interesting difference

    the difference between a process of reasoning and and an explanatory

    schema, between a method a good idea.

    I suspect that Fine became more dubious about the notion of

    method, and less sympathetic to such efforts as Kitchers, in the years that

    separate his 1984 article from his Presidential Address to the APA. For in the

    latter we find him making fun of the idea that There are universal

    principles governing the procedures that make for objectivity, principles

    whose absence would lead to something that involves relativisim and

    irrationalism. (Viewpoint, p. 13) His attitude in this paper chimes with

    that in the Afterword, where he says that NOA is an attitude of trust in

    two senses, the first of which he describes as follows:

  • 7/28/2019 Richard Rorty, "Realism and the Reasons of the Heart", May 3, 1999

    21/30

    21

    NOA trusts that scientists are serious people trying to do good work

    and that scientific procedures are reliable ways of conducting that

    serious enterprise. (the contrast here is with antiscience attitudes,

    ranging from general skepticism to the derisive contempt toward

    science that one sometimes encounters in the humanities.)

    If one trusts that scientists are serious and reliable, then one will not

    be inclined to ask what methods they employ. One will not try to find

    something intermediate between their practices and their successes

    something which can be called a cognitive strategy or a process of

    reasoning, and evaluated for reliability in a general, methodological,

    way. So one will not distinguish between epistemic and non-

    epistemic or rational and irrational factors in scientific research, any

    more than between artistic and non-artistic or creative and non-

    creative factors in artistic production. One will settle for saying that we

    call a scientists results true, and instances of cognitive progress, when we

    think they compare well with those of her competitors, just as we praise an

    artists productions when they compare well with his.

    The same goes when one regards various other groups of people as

    serious and reliable: for example, those politicians, literary critics, lawyers,

    theologians, philosophers, hairdressers, carpenters, bird-watchers,

    astrologers or engineers whom one has gotten in the habit of trusting.

    One may have no use for, and therefore neither trust nor distrust

  • 7/28/2019 Richard Rorty, "Realism and the Reasons of the Heart", May 3, 1999

    22/30

    22

    concerning, one or another of these groups of experts. One may feel

    derisive contempt for such a group if, having once been tempted to rely

    on their results, one was severely disappointed. But ones attitude toward

    any such group will not be determined by any methodological critique of

    their procedures of justification. If I attribute a blissfully happy marriage, as

    well as spectacular financial and professional success, to faithfully

    following my favorite astrologers advice, I will not ask for an account of

    how his procedures fit in with the nature of things, any more than I ask

    how the expert bird-watcher can tell the Great Yellowlegs from the Lesser

    from a hundred yards away. I shall trust them both, and no mere

    philosopherand certainly no specialist in comparative methodologist--is

    going to make me dubious. My trust is determined by their past utility, not

    by ones grasp of the procedures of justification which are employed

    within the group.

    As I see it, the notion of method is a residue of the idea that

    natural scientists, unlike literary critics, politicians and chicken-sexers, have

    found a way to cut through appearance to reality. Viewed

    etymologically, a method is a road that takes one from subject to object.

    If one stops thinking of knowledge as a relation between mind or

    language and an object, and instead thinks of it as the grasp of more true

    sentences, then the notion of such a road becomes less plausible. Instead

    of thinking of how we can get access to a kind of object, we view the

  • 7/28/2019 Richard Rorty, "Realism and the Reasons of the Heart", May 3, 1999

    23/30

    23

    object as whatever it is we are trying to talk about. If we talk about it, we

    are never without access to it, and our attempt to say more useful things

    about it is not a matter of getting closer to it or getting a clearer view of it

    or fitting it better.

    I think that the idea of scientific method and the idea that such

    disciplines as philosophy or political science or law should become more

    scientific are symptoms of our having been held capture by the picture

    of an abyss which seperates human minds from non-human reality If we

    instead get our pathos, romance, and ambition of transcendence by

    contemplating the gap between ourselves and a utopian human future,

    we should stop lamenting our lack of method and scientificity, and also

    stop trying to reveal the natural scientists secrets of success.

    If it were not for the public relations role of philosophy of science--a

    role which was necessary in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries,

    but which should have doffed in the course of the nineteenthI doubt

    that we should ever have been told that geologists, astrophysicists,

    evolutionary biologists, and botanists all used the same method. We

    should not have thought that there was a natural kind called natural

    science which had a subject and method of its own. We should have

    assumed that one became a good scientist by going into somebodys lab

    or seminar room and getting the hang of it. We should have found it

    natural that no scientist would want his apprentices taking time off to

  • 7/28/2019 Richard Rorty, "Realism and the Reasons of the Heart", May 3, 1999

    24/30

    24

    study Cohen and Nagels INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC AND SCIENTIFIC

    METHOD, or any other work which advised them about what cognitive

    processes to use.

    In arguing, as I have in the past, that natural science is not a

    natural kind, I am of course speaking out of dense ignorance. All I am

    entitled to say is that I have not yet encountered a work of philosophy of

    science which gave me reason to think that geology, astrophysics and

    the rest are any more closely linked to one another than to medicine, law

    and engineering. It is always possible that Paul Gross is right when he says

    that people who have not practiced science cannot understand the

    nature of science. Perhaps Daniel Dennett is right that what he calls

    flatfooted ignorance of the proven methods of scientific truth-seeking

    and their power is responsible for my holding the philosophical views that

    I do, and for my lack of what he calls the intellectual leverage provided

    by scientists fa ith in truth. Dennett claims that on the view I espouse it is

    all just conversations, and [that] there are only politica l or historical or

    aesthetic grounds for taking one role or another in an ongoing

    conversation

    I do indeed want to substitute the notion of conversation for that of

    method. Agreeing as I do with Brandom that conversation is the highest

    good for discursive creatures, I think that to take conversation seriously

    to trust, at least initially, that ones interlocutors are serious and reliable

  • 7/28/2019 Richard Rorty, "Realism and the Reasons of the Heart", May 3, 1999

    25/30

    25

    inquirersis the best way to display the virtue Dennett calls love of truth.

    Dennett thinks my writings discourage people from acquiring this virtue.

    But he is wrong to suggest that, on my view, only such traditionally soft

    grounds as might be labeled politica l or historical or aesthetic are

    available. I think that the obvious grounds for being on one side or

    another of a conversation about choosing between scientific theoires are

    specifically scientific grounds. But I do not think that one can explicate

    specifically scientific in any way that accords with the traditional project

    of philosophy of science. One can identify a scientific ground for taking

    a conversational side only by immersing oneself in the disciplinary matrix

    within which a particular conversation is going on, and by making the

    current state of that conversation part of your life.

    To love truth in a given area of culture is, ninety-nine times out of a

    hundred, simply to immerse oneself in one or another conversation

    among people one trusts as serious and reliable, and then do ones best

    to meet the expectations of ones interlocutors. In the hundreth case, of

    course, the love of truth may lead one to break out of the disciplinary

    matrix within which that conversation has been going on, and to try to set

    up a new one. But I cannot see that either fidelity to disciplinary

    expectations or the courage to effect a break-out can be correlated with

    ones view on the philosophical questions over which Dennett and I, or

    Fine and Leplin, disagree.

  • 7/28/2019 Richard Rorty, "Realism and the Reasons of the Heart", May 3, 1999

    26/30

    26

    Dennett, and many other critics of my work, seem to think that

    scientists and desirably hard-minded philosophersargue, whereas literary

    critics, bird-watchers, astrologers, and politicians simply c h a t . But

    astrologers, like the the Oxbridge and Sorbonne Aristotelians of the

    seventeenth century. do argue. One should grant them all the clarity and

    rigor they claim, even if one agrees with Bacon and Descartes that the

    topics they argue about are not worth discussing. The argument-chat

    distinction is perfectly real, and most of us can tell which we are doing

    when. But it does not map onto the traditional hard-soft distinction.

    Argument between Heidegger and Sartre, or between T. S. Eliot and

    Harold Bloom, are just as unchatty and just as serious as arguments about

    Tyler Burge and Donald Davidson, or between Einstein and Bohr.

    Dennett says that we have created a technology of truth and

    that its name is science, I would respond that its name is high culture.

    This is the area of culture which contains those disciplinary matrices in

    which power and money matter less than achieving free agreement on

    the answers to questions unintelligible to the vulgar. Philosophy is one

    prominent part of high culture, so defined. One of the differences

    between Dennett and myself is about whether Kant, Husserl, Russell on

    others who wanted to put philosophy on the secure path of a science

    improved or damaged the quality of philosophical conversation. I think

    that these effects were harmful, and in my utopian human future they

  • 7/28/2019 Richard Rorty, "Realism and the Reasons of the Heart", May 3, 1999

    27/30

    27

    would c ease to be made. More specifically, I think that the question

    What should the method of philosophy be? should cease to be asked.

    J ust as the way to become a good scientist is to go into

    somebodys laboratory and try to get in the swing of things, so the way to

    become a good philosopher is to throw oneself into the works of some

    well-reputed philosopher and try to talk his or her talk. This will work no

    matter whether the good philosopher in question is Kant or Hegel,

    Heidegger or Davidson, Nietzsche or Mill. You get into the philospohical

    conversation by discussing what such people discussed, and in particular

    by answering or being persuaded by their critics How good a philosopher

    you get to be as a result of throwing yourself into one philosophical

    conversation rather than another is not determined by your initial choice,

    but of how conversable you are in later life: how well you can fuse your

    own c onversational horizons with those of lots of other philosophers,

    philosophers trained in different matrices and different countries.

    In particular, there is no point in adivising young people, looking for

    a philosopher whom they can heroize and imitate, that they should

    attend to the methods being used. If I were told that Davidson uses a

    good method, and Heidegger a bad one, or the converse, I would be

    baffled. They seem to me to be distinguished not by methods but by

    contexts of discussion, and further distinguished by the fact that they, but

    not most of the other membesr of their respec tive cohorts, happened to

  • 7/28/2019 Richard Rorty, "Realism and the Reasons of the Heart", May 3, 1999

    28/30

    28

    come up with some brilliantly original ideasideas which wer no more the

    result of applying a method than were Einsteins or Bohrs. .The terms

    analytic method and phenomenological method strike me as of no

    use. I would not know how to teach either method to a student. Neither

    notion helps explains what differentiates Davidson from all the second-

    rate hacks who also call themselves analytic philosophers, or Heidegger

    from all those slavish disciples of Husserl who never had the guts to break

    out on their own. Davidson entered philosophy by getting in on a

    conversation between Quine and Carnap. Heidegger entered the field

    by imagining a conversation between the Marburg neo-Kantians and

    such figures as Kierkegaard and Nietzsche. Both men turned out to have

    some original ideas. The search for a criterion which would make one of

    them a good clear, rigorous philosopher and the other a bad, unclear,

    unrigorous philosopher seems to me pointless,. Such a search, once

    undertaken will always become a public relations exercise on behalf of

    ones favored candidate. The notions of clarity and rigor, like that of

    rationa l support, are determined by cultural expec tations. Differing

    expectations about what to get out of physics accounted for the fac t

    that, as Kuhn recounts, it took a hundred years to domestic a non-

    Aristotelian mechanics. Differing expectations about what to get out of

    philosophy typically take even longer to be resolved.

  • 7/28/2019 Richard Rorty, "Realism and the Reasons of the Heart", May 3, 1999

    29/30

    29

    . Leplin has one set of expectations about what counts as

    philosophy of science, Fine another. Fine is, as Leplin suggests, staging a

    break-out from a familiar disciplinary matrix. So, in less obvious ways, are

    Brandom and Davidson; if there work were taken to heart, huge piles of

    books and articles in the philosophy of language would be thought to

    contain nothing but clever answers to pointless questions. The dec isions

    participants in the relevant conversations come to about whether to

    follow these three men into a non-representationalist philosophical utopia,

    will not be made on what Dennett calls political or aesthetic or historical

    grounds. They will be made on philosohical grounds, in the sense that

    they will be the outcome of conversations in which only people who have

    read quite a lot of philosophy will be able to take part.

    But they will not be made by following a good or a bad

    philosophical method, any more than you and I dec ide whom to vote for,

    whom to propose marriage to, or where to go to school by following a

    good or a bad method. They will be made in the way human beings have

    always made such decisions when faced with a choice between two sets

    of people, both made up serious, reliable, trustworthy interlocutors. When

    the trustworthy disagree, we are on our own. But this is not to say that are

    choices become irrational or aesthetic or political. They remain

    conversational.

  • 7/28/2019 Richard Rorty, "Realism and the Reasons of the Heart", May 3, 1999

    30/30

    30

    In the areas of culture traditionally called hard, most of the

    participants in the conversation eventually agree about what decision

    was best. In other areas they do not. But this is not to be explained by the

    existence of contact with the non-human in the former areas and lack of

    such contacts in the latter. It is to be expalined by the fact that in the

    former there is more agreement about what kind of product a given

    disciplinary matrix is expected to produce. The sources of such

    agreement are to the province of historians and sociologists, not of

    epistemologists or ontologists.

    Richard Rorty

    May 3, 1999