review god, time and eternity wtj 63 no 2 fall 2001, p 439-445

Upload: berithrhadash

Post on 14-Apr-2018

216 views

Category:

Documents


1 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/29/2019 Review God, Time and Eternity WTJ 63 No 2 Fall 2001, p 439-445

    1/8

    REVIEWS OF BOOKS 439

    extent that one accepts or rejects Kuyper's views in these areas, to that extent one is mov

    ing beyond (legitimately or illegitimately) Calvin himself.

    Specifically, at least three legitimate questions can be posed with regard to Kuyper's

    neo-Calvinism as Bolt presents it: (1) Is Kuyper's view of God's kingdom a good and

    necessary consequence of Calvin's view? (2) Is Kuyper's view of liberty, and liberty of

    conscience, in line with Calvin's own emphasis? and (3) How would Kuyper reconcile

    Calvin's Geneva with his own public theology?

    These questions are not easily answered. Even if answered they still leave open the

    more important question of the relationship of Scripture and its teaching to public the

    ology. They do, however, it seems to me, reflect at least some of the major contours of

    neo-Calvinism and would be topics worthy of another volume (or two or three).Because Bolt gives us Kuyper the political poet, those looking specifically for propo

    sitions and principles of statecraft might be disappointed. On the other hand, it is

    refreshing to see the development of a Christian public theology that has at its core the

    necessity of persuasion over coercion. Thatmessage itself could be the most valuable of

    the book.

    Bolt's book is an informative, scholarly, insightful and provocative study. He has

    served the Reformed community, and the Christian church generally, well in offering

    such substantial and thorough suggestions for an evangelical public theology. Debatesand discussions of the relationship of church and state will now need to include Bolt's

    analysis and commendation of Kuyper to the American experiment.

    K. SCOTT OLIPHINT

    Westminster Theological Seminary

    Philadelphia, PA

    William Lane Craig: Time andEternity: Exploring God's Relationship to Time. WheatoIllinois: Crossway Books, 2001. 272 pp. $25.00.

    William Craig has attempted to set out a philosophically respectable position with

    respect to the concept of eternity and time. There are few more qualified than Craig to

    undertake such a task, and there is likely no other book available on this topic that isboth

    sparing in technical vocabulary and concepts, thus more widely available, and philo

    sophically sophisticated at the same time. The nonpareil accessibility of a book devoted

    to such a difficult subject will, therefore, likely broaden its circulation among philoso

    phers and non-specialists alike.

    As Craig attempts to work through the difficulties, not only of just what time is, but

  • 7/29/2019 Review God, Time and Eternity WTJ 63 No 2 Fall 2001, p 439-445

    2/8

    440 WESTMINSTER THEOLOGICAL JOURNAL

    only so, according to Craig, but simplicity and immutability are even less plausible than

    any notion of timelessness, so it is folly to attempt to ground the latter in the former. This

    dismissal or suspicion of the notions of simplicity and immutability in God is, as a mat

    ter of fact, exactly of the kind of problems that plague Christianity when philosophers

    attempt to do theology, the kind of problems that those who were required to study phi

    losophy brought to Christian theology. The impetus behind the notions of simplicity and

    immutability, theologically, is to safeguard the Scriptural truth that God is not essentially

    and independently affected by something other than Himself. That is to say, who God is,

    as eternal, independent, existing, etc., is determined only by God Himself. There are no

    properties or situations that serve to make God something that He would not otherwise

    essentially be. While it can be granted that certain notions of simplicity and immutabil

    ity obtained an abstractness not consistent with the biblical picture of God, thatproblemis not, first of all, due to misguided theology, but rather to the attempt of philosophy to

    define theology's parameters.

    Craig moves to an exposition of the special theory of relativity (STR), formulated by

    Einstein in 1905, and his general theory of relativity (GTR), completed in 1915. It is

    Craig's conviction that "any adequate theory of God's relationship to time must.. . take

    account of what these theories have to say about the nature of time" (p. 32). It turns out,

    however, that relativity theories are all founded on a false epistemological basis, i.e., that

    of empiricism, and thus provide no compelling reason for acceptance (p. 66).One promising argument for divine timelessness that Craig mentions, but eventually

    dismisses, is the argument from the incompleteness of temporal life. The argument

    depends primarily on the following premise for its cogency: Temporal existence is a less

    perfect mode of existence than timeless existence. Given that God, as the maximally

    perfect being, could not be maximally perfect if he experienced temporal loss, this argu

    ment rests, according to Craig, "on very powerful intuition" (p. 67). Those intuitions,

    however, are not sufficient to sustain the premise, says Craig, since "timeless life may not

    be the most perfect mode of existence of a perfect person" (p. 73). That is, it may be thecase that the experience of temporal succession adds to rather than subtracts from a per

    son such that to experience this succession may not be a defect.

    With respect to divine temporality (chapter three), Craig discusses the notion that

    God could not be timeless because he is personal. It is impossible for a person not to

    experience at least some kind of succession of moments. Is it possible for a personal God

    to stand in some kind of relationship to the world and remain timeless? Here we will

    quote Craig at length since the substance of his response to this question will form the

    foundation for some concerns below.

    It is very difficult to see how He can. Imagine once more God existing changelessly

    l i h i b i h h l d i i f i ill

  • 7/29/2019 Review God, Time and Eternity WTJ 63 No 2 Fall 2001, p 439-445

    3/8

    REVIEWS OF BOOKS 441

    This second alternative presents us with a new dilemma. Once time begins at the

    moment of creation, either God becomes temporal in virtue of His real relation to the

    temporal world or else He exists just as tunelessly with creation as He does without it.

    If we choose the first alternative, then, once again, God is temporal. But what about

    the second alternative? Can God remain untouched by the world's temporality? It

    seems not. For at the first moment of time, God stands in a new relation in which He

    did not stand before (since there was no "before"). Even if in creation the world God

    undergoes no intrinsic change, He at least undergoes an extnnsic change. For at the

    moment of creation, God comes into the relation of sustaining the universe or, at the

    very least, of co-existing with the universe, relations in which He did not stand before.

    Since He is free to refrain from creation, God could have never stood in those rela

    tions, had He so willed. But in virtue of His creating a temporal world, God comes

    into a relation with that world the moment it springs into being. Thus, even if it is not

    the case that God is temporal prior to His creation of the world, He nonetheless

    undergoes an extrinsic change at the moment of creation which draws Him into time

    in virtue of His real relation to the world. So even if God is timeless without creation,

    His free decision to create a temporal world also constitutes a free decision on His part

    to exist temporally, (pp. 86-87)

    One way to avoid a notion of divine temporality mentioned by Craig is the way of Tho

    mas Aquinas. Aquinas seeks to deny that God stands in any real relation to the world.

    While creatures are really related to God, God is not really related to creatures (p. 88).l

    This, however, argues Craig, is unintelligible. To say that the world is really related to God,

    but that God is not really related to the world "is to say that one can have real effects

    without a real cause" (p. 89).2

    The substance of his argument is found in chapter four, which is Craig's discussion of

    a dynamic conception of time. The best way to think about the difference between a

    dynamic and a static view of time is in terms of tense. A dynamic time theorist would

    hold (at least) that (1) it is impossible to eliminate tense from language and (2) tense is a

    feature of language just because it is a feature of the world itself. Thus, the world is

    objectively "tensed" and reality, therefore, flows whether we acknowledge it or not. Thestatic time theorist would likely hold that this "flow" of time is an unfortunate metaphor.

    While language may be tensed, the static time theorist would hold that this tense is rela

    tive, and that space-time itself is tenseless; it just is (p. 169). The discussion of a dynamic

    vs. a static view of time provides the foundation for Craig's conclusion with respect to

    time and eternity.

    The argument for a dynamic conception of time finds support in two positionsthe

    ineliminability of tense and the argument from our experience of time. The argument

    from the ineliminability of tense purports to show that tensed facts are not merely a con

    vention of language, they are constitutive of realityitself.

    Those who would hold to astatic view of time have attempted to show that tense can actually be eliminated from

    language without any loss of meaning Craig calls this view the "Old Tenseless Theory

  • 7/29/2019 Review God, Time and Eternity WTJ 63 No 2 Fall 2001, p 439-445

    4/8

    442 WESTMINSTER THEOLOGICAL JOURNAL

    of Language" as put forth, for example, by Bertrand Russell. The attempt here was to

    translate tensed sentences into a tenseless form without loss of meaning (p. 117). This,

    however, has itself been eliminated and the "New Tenseless Theory of Language" has

    arisen in its place. Here there would be agreement that tense cannot be eliminated fromlanguage, but the New Tenseless Theory would hold that this fact is irrelevant since all

    one needs are not tenseless statements, but tenseless facts. Without going into the details

    of the discussion, Craig's rebuttal of this notion, in its earlier and later stages, is simply to

    note that there seems to be no compelling argument for the notion that the truth condi

    tions of a sentence can be tenseless. D. H. Mellor, one of the main proponents of this

    view, fails to show, for example, what makes a fact true, not simply what makes it true at

    a particular time. Thus, Craig thinks there is no cogent arguments against the inelimina

    bility of tense.

    Craig goes on to critique "McTaggart's Paradox" which states, simply that time isessentially tensed, but that tense is self-contradictory. The conclusion of McTaggart,

    according to his own article, is "the unreality of time" (p. 144). That is, he denies that

    time has an objective reality. McTaggart's primary weakness, according to Craig, was

    that he was attempting to see reality sub specie aeternitatis and yet to include tense in his

    description of the world. He cannot have it both ways. Because there exists a different

    description of reality that holds at each given moment, to attempt to explain reality by

    assuming that there exists a single, comprehensive description of it is impossible (p. 154).

    It is impossible in a world of which tense is necessarily a part. So McTaggart's attempt

    sets up a paradox, one side of which is out of touch with the way the world really is.Thus, McTaggart's Paradox fails as a refutation of dynamic time. Craig goes on to cri

    tique the so-called "myth of passage" of time in support of his dynamic view of time.

    Craig then explains and critiques the notion of a static view of time in chapter five.

    His critique can be summarized in the following:

    The static time theorist cannot affirm that the world came into being at the first

    moment of its existence and therefore cannot affirm that God created the world in the

    full sense of the word "create." It seems to me, therefore, that a static conception of

    time is theologically unacceptable. A robust doctrine of creation requires a dynamic

    theory of time. (p. 214)

    Finally, and somewhat curiously, Craig devotes the last twenty pages to "God, Time, and

    Creation." Here Craig notes that tensed facts and temporal becoming are real. According

    to him, therefore, it follows from God's creative activity and omniscience that, given the

    existence of a temporal world, God is also temporal. God quite literally exists now (p. 217).

    Two brief points must be made with respect to this book. It should be noted that the

    points of concern have little to do with the substance of the discussion, but rather with

    the discussion's impetus, its method of approach, including its starting point. First, Craig

    is resolute that the solution to the problem of the relationship of time to eternity is foundin analytic philosophy (p. 11). (One aside: it is interesting that Craig sets time over

    i i l ib f G d' i h i i h " l "

  • 7/29/2019 Review God, Time and Eternity WTJ 63 No 2 Fall 2001, p 439-445

    5/8

    REVIEWS OF BOOKS 443

    notes that, contrary to the present situation, in the Middle Ages "students were not

    allowed to study theology until they had mastered all the other disciplines at the univer-

    Ay (p. 11).

    Craig's understanding of where or with whom to begin a discussion of this sort isunfortunate. For it is exactly in the discipline of theology that this kind of discussion

    needs first to be addressed. Craig's method of approach, it seems to me, taken to its logi

    cal conclusion, can serve and has served historically, to undermine the heart and soul of

    the Christian faith. Of course, Craig's view of this kind of Archimedean point has been

    asserted in the history of Christian thought. There have been schools of thought in the

    Christian tradition that have held views identical or similar to Craig's. Prior to our own

    country's founding it was thought that what theology needed was a heavy dose of rea

    son's influence in order to rid itself of notorious theological absurdities such as original

    sin, Trinity and divine incarnation. The way to rid ourselves of such pernicious doctrines is not by a review of God's revelation, but by looking to our own reasonable dis

    ciplines to solve the problem. Craig's argument isanother piece of natural theology with

    another now familiar conclusion such that aspects of the created world are assigned also

    to God.

    The point, however, is that, while Craig notes the Middle Ages as an exemplary time

    for doing theology, he neglects to mention the monumentally crucial point that the

    Middle Ages demanded a Reformation, and the theology coming from that Reforma

    tion was designed to subvert the very methodology that Craig wants to praise. This

    method of philosophy's right to dictate theology's conclusions, contra the Reformed tra

    dition, is a reassertion of the usus magistenalis rationis that has, in certain key times and

    places, driven orthodox Christianity eventually to a point where it becomes utterly

    opposed to its initial tenets.

    To his credit, Craig does consult Scripture in various places through the book. It is

    most unfortunate, however, that in this approach (and like discussions concerning God)

    the tradition of theology, and more importantly its source (i.e., Scripture), seems to be, at

    best, tangential to the discussion and the supposedly newer and more adequate method

    (philosophy) is set forth as coming to the rescue of both reason andtheology. For all of its

    erudition, the method employed in this discussion, if adopted consistendy, will lead readers beyond open theism (which Craig wants, for now, to reject) to something much

    worse.3

    Secondly, there is a small hint, though inadvertent, toward a better way to think of

    God's relationship (in all of His attributes) to His creation. In the lengthy quote above,

    Craig is wrestling with the notion of God's relationship to creation. He concludes,

    remember, with the following: "So even if God is timeless without creation, His free

    decision to create a temporal world also constitutes a free decision on His part to exist

    temporally." That is, God's free decision to create entailed a further free decision on His

    part to abandon timeless existence altogether and to become temporal. This conclusion,however, does not follow, particularly given the historic creeds of the Christian faith.

  • 7/29/2019 Review God, Time and Eternity WTJ 63 No 2 Fall 2001, p 439-445

    6/8

    444 WESTMINSTERTHEOLOGICAL JOURNAL

    world with a beginning is a decision on God's part to abandon timelessness and to take

    on a temporal mode of existence" (p. 241). Perhaps at this point Craig would have been

    betterserved by letting the theologians speak.

    The Scriptures are replete with examples of God relating to His creation, and more

    specifically to His creatures made in His image. How do we go about understanding

    these examples? The best way to understand these examples is guided by the way in

    which we understand revelation generally, i.e., as God's infallible redemptive-historical

    record of His covenant with His creation. In this way, the examples of God relating to

    His creatures and to His creation are to be interpreted in the light of God's climactic

    example of relating to His creation in the Incarnation of the Son of God. Or to use

    philosophical jargon, examples of God relating to His creation in Scripture, including

    God's relationship to time, must be seen as different "tokens" of God's condescension,

    of which the incarnation of the Son of God is the (only) "type." That is to say, in God's

    redemptive-historical economy, all revelations preceding and proceeding from the Incar-

    nation of the Son of God are meant to be seen in the light of God's covenanting with

    His creatures in and through that Incarnate Word, His Son. We understand who God is,

    primarily and preeminendy, in His Son. Everything else we understand about God flows

    from that primary, climactic revelation.

    With respect to the relationship of God, as eternal (and infinite, and holy, and

    unchangeable, and etc., etc.) to His creation, including time, we lookfirst to the Incar

    nation of the Son of God. The incarnation has never been seen as God's abandoning of

    any of His essential attributes at all. As a matter of fact, it is in the incarnation that we

    begin to see how it is that God can relate to His creation, including time, without becom

    ing less than God. Theology has traditionally affirmed that the Son of God, as God, is to

    be "acknowledged in two natures inconfusedly (), unchangeably (),

    indivisibly (), and inseparably ()" (Chalcedonian Creed). On this

    the great creeds of the church have agreed. Craig's "solution" to the relationship of

    (only?) one of God's essential attributes to His creation is a kind of theistic Eutychianism

    in which the nature of God, at the point of creation, becomes changed and conse-

    quendy confused with the nature of His creation.

    However, since it is the case that we can know God only as He has revealed Himself,

    and since the climax of God's revelation and relationship to us is in His Incarnate Son,

    ourknowledge of God's relationship to His creation must be mediated through that cli

    mactic revelation of God in Christ. God, the Triune God, can indeed, then, given the

    incarnation of God Himself (in the second Person of the Trinity) exist temporally, while

    atthe same time, existing eternally as God. The incarnation teaches us that such things are

    not onlypossible with God, but are a substantial part of our reason to worship Him. In

    the words of Exod 3, the God of Abraham, Isaac and Jacob is and remains as well the "I

    Am."

    4

    I fear that these kinds of discussions, left unchecked by Scriptural/Reformed theol

    ill t d d i l f th bibli l i f th I ti itself Th

  • 7/29/2019 Review God, Time and Eternity WTJ 63 No 2 Fall 2001, p 439-445

    7/8

    REVIEWS OF BOOKS 445

    well. Only as Christian philosophers begin more carefully to listen to Christian theolo

    gians will their conclusions move toward real help, intellectually and otherwise, for the

    communities they wish to serve.

    I shall only say, that those who are inconversant with these objects of faithwhose

    minds are not delighted in the admiration of, and acquiescency in, things incompre

    hensible, such as is this constitution of the person of Christwho would reduce all

    things to the measure of their own understandings, or else wilfully live in the neglect

    of what they cannot comprehenddo not much prepare themselves for that vision of

    these things in glory, wherein our blessedness doth consist.5

    K. SCOTT OLIPHINT

    Westminster Theological Seminary

    Herman Hanko: For Thy Truth's Sake: A Doctrinal History of the Protestant Refor

    Churches. Grandville: Reformed Free Publishing Association, 2000. Xxvi + 541 pp.

    $39.95, cloth.

    For all those who have an interest in the tradition of Dutch Reformed theology in

    North America, this book provides interesting, if on occasion somewhat sad, reading.

    Written as a history of the PRC which focuses particularly on its doctrinal distinctives, it

    offers valuable insights not only into what the PRC believes but why it believes throughfocusing on the two defining controversies of the church's first seventy-five years: the

    common grace crisis of the 1924 synod of the Christian Reformed Church and the con

    flict of the late forties and earlyfiftieswith the Schilderites of the Liberated Churches.

    For those in the Westminster constituency, there is also some treatment of the Clark-Van

    Til controversy, upon which Herman Hoeksema commented at some length and in

    which he decidedly favored Clark.

    Written by a second-generation PR minister who knew many of the personalities

    involved in the events he describes, Hanko has a sensitivity and an understanding of theissues and events which only an insider can possess. On the whole, history has not been

    kind to Hoeksema and his followers, and many of their legitimate concerns have disap

    peared from debate not because they are not legitimate but because they have been

    made to look ridiculous through the unfair caricaturing of exacdy what was at stake,

    particularly in 1924. The world can cope with a more sympathetic reading of the PRC,

    and this book provides just that.

    Nevertheless, the book's strength is also its weakness: Hanko's very closeness to these

    things limits his ability to sympathize with those who "lost"and this is most definitely

    a history of "winners" (the PRC) and "losers" (the CRC; those who were influenced by

    the covenant teaching of Klaas Schilder). Clearly, part of the purpose of the work is to

  • 7/29/2019 Review God, Time and Eternity WTJ 63 No 2 Fall 2001, p 439-445

    8/8

    ^ s

    Copyright and Use:

    As an ATLAS user, you may print, download, or send articles for individual useaccording to fair use as defined by U.S. and international copyright law and as

    otherwise authorized under your respective ATLAS subscriber agreement.

    No content may be copied or emailed to multiple sites or publicly posted without the

    copyright holder(s)' express written permission. Any use, decompiling,

    reproduction, or distribution of this journal in excess of fair use provisions may be a

    violation of copyright law.

    This journal is made available to you through the ATLAS collection with permissionfrom the copyright holder(s). The copyright holder for an entire issue of a journaltypically is the journal owner, who also may own the copyright in each article. However,for certain articles, the author of the article may maintain the copyright in the article.Please contact the copyright holder(s) to request permission to use an article or specificwork for any use not covered by the fair use provisions of the copyright laws or coveredby your respective ATLAS subscriber agreement. For information regarding thecopyright holder(s), please refer to the copyright information in the journal, if available,or contact ATLA to request contact information for the copyright holder(s).

    About ATLAS:

    The ATLA Serials (ATLAS) collection contains electronic versions of previouslypublished religion and theology journals reproduced with permission. The ATLAScollection is owned and managed by the American Theological Library Association(ATLA) and received initial funding from Lilly Endowment Inc.

    The design and final form of this electronic document is the property of the AmericanTheological Library Association.