reflecting on callon with a case of fair trade coffee

37
REFLECTING ON CALLON WITH A CASE OF FAIR TRADE COFFEE Julie Whittaker University of Exeter University of Exeter Discussion Papers in Management Paper number 06/06 ISSN 1472-2939 Correspondence address: School of Business and Economics, University of Exeter, Streatham Court, Rennes Drive, Exeter EX4 4PU, United Kingdom Tel: +44 (0) 1392 263845, Fax: +44 (0) 1392 263242, Email: [email protected]

Upload: others

Post on 08-Jan-2022

4 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: REFLECTING ON CALLON WITH A CASE OF FAIR TRADE COFFEE

REFLECTING ON CALLON WITH A CASE

OF FAIR TRADE COFFEE

Julie Whittaker

University of Exeter

University of Exeter

Discussion Papers in Management

Paper number 06/06

ISSN 1472-2939

Correspondence address: School of Business and Economics, University of Exeter, Streatham Court,

Rennes Drive, Exeter EX4 4PU, United Kingdom Tel: +44 (0) 1392 263845, Fax: +44 (0) 1392 263242,

Email: [email protected]

Page 2: REFLECTING ON CALLON WITH A CASE OF FAIR TRADE COFFEE

2

Reflecting on Callon with a case of Fair Trade coffee

Julie Whittaker

Abstract

Michel Callon’s writings on markets offer a new approach for

studying market organisation. In the light of his understanding of

market dynamics Callon has suggested that issues of economic

justice can be re-examined. This paper explores the robustness

and relevance of some of his concepts by applying them to an

analysis of Fair Trade in coffee. Callon’s work gives weight to the

influence of material artefacts in networks, and while this has

relevance for understanding the processes leading to market

development, his explanation of the causes of market change are

limited by an overemphasis on the direct effect of material

factors. This highlights the lack of attention to price determination

in his framework, which proves to be problematic in trying to

analyse just markets, where the rate of exchange is crucial to the

discussion.

Page 3: REFLECTING ON CALLON WITH A CASE OF FAIR TRADE COFFEE

3

Reflecting on Callon with a case of Fair Trade coffee

Michel Callon, in his recent writings on markets, has argued anew that markets can take

many forms and that society has some choice in how they operate (Callon 1998a,b,

Callon 1999, Callon, Méadel and Rabeharisoa 2002, Callon and Muniesa 2005). Indeed,

the title of his initial book on the subject, The Laws of the Markets (Callon 1998), reflects

his belief that there is no natural market laws, and therefore society can create a diversity

of market processes. In Callon and Muniesa (2005) he suggests that with a new

understanding of the potential diversity of forms, it is relevant to reconsider the ability of

markets to address issues of justice and equity. This is timely in so far as one of the

causes of unease about global market liberalization has been that market values will

dominate moral principles leading to what Baumann (2001:25) has termed the

‘dissipation of responsibility for the distant stranger’. Recent years have witnessed

significant expression of concern about a lack of fairness within international markets,

reflected in the widespread emergence of campaigns for economic justice at the global

level.1 These focus on trading arrangements considered to be biased against the poor

either because of unfair world trade rules or because of the dominance of multinational

companies. Associated with the intensification of public interest in these campaigns, has

been a growth in Fair Trade sales, providing concrete demonstration of significant

interest in markets that appear just. Under Fair Trade arrangements, consumers, typically

in the northern hemisphere, voluntarily purchase products that guarantee a minimum

price for producers that are located mainly in the southern hemisphere. Goodman

(2004:893) has described Fair Trade as the ‘re-linking of production and consumption,

Page 4: REFLECTING ON CALLON WITH A CASE OF FAIR TRADE COFFEE

4

rising Polanyi-like from the ashes of globalization’. But Fair Trade has been criticised by

economists, for example Lindsey (2004), who has argued that those proclaiming

sympathy for the world’s poor lack understanding of how markets work, and suggests

that Fair Trade measures only exacerbate global poverty. It seems that Fair Trade

highlights some of the keen differences in focus between economic sociologists and

economists, the former being more preoccupied with distributional issues, and the latter

with efficiency criteria. Callon attempts to bridge the divide between sociologists and

economists, by embracing a network approach associated with new economic sociology,

whilst also emphasizing the relevance of economics within the network. Fair Trade

provides an opportunity to reflect upon Callon’s writings on markets, which while rich in

ideas, have some propensity for ambiguity. His view on the relevance of economics

already has been a subject of debate (see for example Miller 2002, 2005, Fine 2003).

Simultaneously, this paper uses Callon’s perspective on markets to try to understand how

Fair Trade initiatives emerged and exist, and to consider whether they are sustainable,

whether they can achieve their long term objectives.

The relevant issues are reflected upon by considering the market for the most widely Fair

Traded commodity, coffee. The paper begins by providing some background to Fair

Trade coffee, and then following, Callon’s approach to the study of markets is reviewed.

Callon argues that markets are inherently unstable as boundaries of markets are

perpetually contested. Reflecting on factors that have caused contestation in the case of

coffee, deliberation is given to what is included within Callon’s definition of overflowing

Page 5: REFLECTING ON CALLON WITH A CASE OF FAIR TRADE COFFEE

5

effects. At issue is Callon’s presumptions about price determination, and whether concern

for others can be expressed within his framework.

Fair Trade coffee

Fair Trade coffee developed from the impetus of two Dutchmen, who after working on

development projects in Central America for many years, reached the conclusion that

development efforts were wasted without reformation of the coffee market (Pendergrast

2001). Like many agricultural commodities, the world coffee market is characterized by

millions of producers, geographically separated. Under such conditions, prices have been

unstable, and in common with most agricultural commodities there has been long run

price decline. In 1988 the Max Havelaar coffee label2 was introduced in 1988 in the

Netherlands, as the first of many Fair Trade coffee brands launched into conventional

marketing channels with the purpose of improving market arrangements for small coffee

growers. Now there is an internationally agreed certification and labeling system, known

as the Fairtrade Mark that underpins fair trading arrangements for many coffee brands as

well as other products. The creation of this alternative supply chain was original in being

neither an initiative of the commercial sector, nor instigated by governments. Instead the

architecture of the Fair Trade chain was the result of the work of individuals operating in

non-profit organizations, collectively referred to as the Fair Trade movement. A result of

this is that although the designers chose to achieve development objectives via the

market, they appeared to be little influenced by economists’ conceptions of markets,

being primarily motivated to enhance the welfare of the coffee growers. Consequently,

the Fair Trade pricing structure gives emphasis to the needs of producers, providing

Page 6: REFLECTING ON CALLON WITH A CASE OF FAIR TRADE COFFEE

6

coffee growers with long-term contracts with minimum prices set to cover the costs of

production. Advance partial payments are made to avoid debt, with all transactions

conducted through producer co-operatives. In addition to the minimum price (or market

price if it is larger), a social premium is paid to the growers’ community to provide

opportunities to develop either their co-operative or a community project related to

educational, health or environmental goals.

These pricing arrangements in effect redistribute income within the supply chain. This is

a clear aim of Fair Trade which operates on the presumption that mainstream coffee

companies receive too great a proportion of returns from the retail coffee market. Ponte

(2002) and Gilbert (1998) provide evidence that there has been a decline in the proportion

of income received by producers from the supply chain over time and this has led to the

opinion that liberalisation and deregulation of the coffee market in the early 1990s

encouraged a buyer-led commodity chain (Ponte 2002, Raynolds 2002, Ponte and Gibbon

2005). The sense of injustice to coffee growers, associated with this arrangement,

appeared greatest with the significant slump in coffee bean prices in 2001, when low

bean prices were not translated into lower retail coffee prices, leading to the conclusion

that company profits benefited whilst growers suffered (Oxfam 2002).

Fair Trade schemes3 not only provide price guarantees, they also develop trading

partnerships which are based on principles of dialogue, transparency and respect.

Producer co-operatives are encouraged in order to develop capacity, with coffee growers

becoming part of a business team rather than merely commodity suppliers. The assurance

Page 7: REFLECTING ON CALLON WITH A CASE OF FAIR TRADE COFFEE

7

of a long-term partnership provides security and the chance for growers to engage in long

term planning with others in the commodity chain as equal partners. Such an approach

not only addresses economic issues but also has a role in restoring dignity. In addition

Fair Trade products are considered to be a means of expressing concern about the current

unfairness of world trade rules. For example, the Fairtrade Foundation (2002) suggests

that buying Fair Trade coffee will ‘signal our support for much wider change in the

economic relationships between rich and poor countries’.4 In effect, Fair Trade coffee is a

product that embodies a set of principles, and it provides a means by which concerns

about economic justice can be materialized and demonstrated through purchases.

Callon on markets

Michel Callon considers that the organisation of markets increasingly is a subject of

public debate. To date, interest in Callon’s writings on markets (Callon 1998a,b,1999)

has focused principally on the performative role of economics in formatting the economy

(see Aspers 2004, MacKenzie and Milo 2003, MacKenzie 2004, Miller 2002, 2005). But

Smelser and Swedberg (2005) identify that Callon makes another contribution to new

economic sociology with his emphasis on the material, the non-human, in network

relations, a relevance derived from his work in actor-network theory (ANT).5 This

appears a constructive contribution given that markets are about humans exchanging

goods, which even when they are services typically have a material component and

furthermore, given anthropological research that suggests that objects have a social life

(Appadurai 1986). Even so, Callon (1999:183) initially considered markets to be a test

for ANT because the latter ‘was developed to analyse situations in which it is difficult to

Page 8: REFLECTING ON CALLON WITH A CASE OF FAIR TRADE COFFEE

8

separate humans and non-humans…whereas the market is diametrically opposed to this

situation; everything is delimited and roles are perfectly defined’. However, with

reflection he argues that ANT can contribute to an understanding of markets because it

can explain the emergence of rational calculative actants which enable the delineation

and alienation that is required for exchange.

Callon’s work has affinity with Granovetter (1985) in focusing on networks, and

disputing the duality imposed by analyses that assume the economy and society to be

distinct, with either society conditioning the economy, or the economy conditioning

society. Such positions are problematic because they imply the agent is homo clausus, in

the Eliasian sense (Elias 1994) being either an over-socialised homo sociologicus,

conditioned by conventions and culture, or an under-socialised homo economicus,

constrained by individualistic passions. Instead, Callon and Granovetter perceive the

agent to be homo apertus, part of a network of actors, each of whom is open to influence

and simultaneously influencing others. In effect the network configures ontologies

(Callon 1998, 1999). When asserting that the economy is embedded in social relations,

Granovetter not only accentuated the role of human agency in shaping markets, rather

than being dupes to social conventions, he also refuted the tenet of neo-institutional

economics that institutional arrangements are solely the result of efforts to maximise

efficiency, arguing that they can be designed also to meet social needs. Significantly,

Callon does not give emphasis to this latter point, but stresses the relevance of the

material, in shaping markets. Effectively he not only dismisses the dualism between

Page 9: REFLECTING ON CALLON WITH A CASE OF FAIR TRADE COFFEE

9

economy and society, but also discards the division between human and non-human

actors.

A key element of Callon’s thesis is that while individuals can be influenced by all kinds

of relations between human and non-human elements within the network, in choosing to

engage in a market, the buyer and seller at the point of transaction, become temporarily

alienated from the network entanglements; they make a rational calculation and

exchange, and in doing so are momentarily disentangled.6 Markets therefore are

distinctive in being calculating collective devices, with material artefacts and established

procedures necessary for constructing calculative agency (Callon and Muniesa 2005) in a

ANT like fashion. For goods to be exchanged they need to be qualified, made comparable

or differentiatable from other goods, and this requires material elements. Callon contends

that economics, rather than being dismissed by sociologists, should be recognised as a

technology which helps to create the tools that establish a market within a network.

Marketing and accountancy practices, for example, have been developed from

economics, and they enable the calculative process. He does not believe that individuals

are born psychologically endowed like homo economicus, but argues that for markets to

exist, homo economicus has to be created, ‘formatted, framed and equipped with

prostheses which help him in his calculations and which are, for the most part, produced

by economics’ (Callon 1998a:51). Provocatively he states that the ‘economy is embedded

not in society but in economics’ (1998a:30). However, in Barry and Slater (2002),

Callon argues that he is not trying to bolster economic arguments, but acknowledge that

economic discourse has a bearing on calculative market practices. He regards economists

Page 10: REFLECTING ON CALLON WITH A CASE OF FAIR TRADE COFFEE

10

and their texts as only one group of actors that influence markets, that other actors also

have a sway, determining what they want to include within a calculation, and how values

are computed (Callon, Méadel and Rabeharisoa 2002).

Callon’s starting position has appeal because it both recognises that agents operate within

an open system which configures their ontologies, so takes a broad view as to what

influences behaviour, yet also demarcates the market as a unique entity within a network.

Slater (2002: 248) argues that Callon’s ideas help economic sociology to move on from

two ‘impossible alternatives’ that either ‘the market is absolutized as abstraction or it is

dissolved into culture’. Nevertheless, inevitably there are questions still begging. For

example, which aspects of economics are relevant for understanding and designing

calculative agency, and can they be separated easily from a market ideology based on

self-interest and price signals? Specific to this paper, is the question of whether markets

can be established and persist when distributional goals are prominent. The case of Fair

Trade also raises the issue of whether prices set to cover producer costs are sustainable

over time? With regard to Callon’s work, these questions highlight two areas for

examination. The first concerns the range of factors he considers can be included within a

market decision, and the second relates to his understanding of the role of prices.

Taking things into account

Callon recognises that for calculation to be achievable, there have to be limits on the

elements within the network which are actually taken into account. He gainfully

introduces Goffman’s concept of framing (Goffman 1971) to theorise that the arena for

Page 11: REFLECTING ON CALLON WITH A CASE OF FAIR TRADE COFFEE

11

market operations is but a framed portion of the network (Callon 1998a,b). Within the

social sciences, framing is primarily considered as a cognitive and linguistic device, a

schema which enables the processing of information to generate meaning. Callon,

consistent with the rest of his work, emphasises the material aspects of framing arguing

that investment is required to make relations visible and goods calculable, and ultimately

determine what is taken into account in a decision to exchange. Although not very

distinct within his writings, he identifies two dimensions of framing. First, in (Callon

1998a) he highlights the infrastructure that is required to define the goods as calculable

things, delineating their qualities, a process referred to as objectification. Associated with

the process of objectification is singularisation, which is the means by which consumers

become attached to the objective properties of a product, such that it acquires a calculable

value. However, in his discussion on framing in Callon (1998b) he gives greatest

emphasis to the material aspects of property rights, as factors that frame market

decisions. Certainly property rights are a vital aspect of a calculative market, determining

to whom the results of calculation can be attributed (Callon 1998a). They define legal

entitlements, and provide necessary bedrock for market exchange. Nonetheless, as argued

below, this does not preclude individuals from bringing other factors into the frame of

their transaction decisions. Callon tends to overstate the relevance property rights, insofar

as he neglects of other relevant factors that may be taken into account within a market

setting. Consequently he can appear to set limits on the new universe of potential forms

of market organisation that he claims his explanation of markets heralds.

Page 12: REFLECTING ON CALLON WITH A CASE OF FAIR TRADE COFFEE

12

Critical to a construal of Callon’s position is the interpretation of his idiom, overflows.

Callon argues that although framing is a requirement for market exchange, any frame is

permeable, it can never encompass all market impacts because of the complex

interconnectedness within a network. Life in the network beyond the frame ultimately has

an influence. The result is that market exchange inevitably leads to effects that overflow

beyond the boundaries into other parts of the network. Since overflows are typical,

market frames are always open to contestation. Therefore market instability is the norm,

as actors seek to reframe the market boundaries to accommodate the overflow effects.

However, Callon seems to constrain the factors that can cause reframing by aligning his

term of overflowing effects with the economists’ term of externalities (Callon 1998a,b).

This is limiting as externalities have a precise meaning within economic theory. They are

the impacts of economic activity on a third party which are not taken into account by the

economic decision maker, and are not reflected in their prices. Such impacts can be either

positive (in which case no impetus for change) or negative. As suggested by Callon,

pollution problems provide many illustrations of negative externalities. For example, if a

chemical company disposes of waste material into a river without regard for the impact

on the quality of river water extracted by a brewery downstream, it will affect brewery

costs and profits. Alternatively, an externality may affect the well-being of individuals,

e.g. nitrous oxides emitted from cars causing respiratory problems. The crucial aspect

about externalities is that there is a direct non-monetary effect on a third party’s welfare,

resulting from a lack of clearly defined property rights. In the examples given the

externalities occurred because it was not defined in law who had rights to use the river

and the atmosphere. Clearly, when there is public objection to the pollution, the

Page 13: REFLECTING ON CALLON WITH A CASE OF FAIR TRADE COFFEE

13

government can intervene, property rights can be redefined, and the market, in Callon’s

terms can be reframed. While externalities fit neatly with Callon’s standpoint because

they entail a material impact, a problem is that the factors that lead to market

reorganisation are not solely externalities; they frequently revolve around distributional

issues. These are not covered within the externality definition, which as Callon rightly

notes is centred on efficiency concerns (1998b:247). To elaborate the point, consider a

supermarket that achieves new economies of scale, so lowering its costs and leading to

lower shop shelf prices. The detrimental effect on the profitability of small high street

shops is not an externality, as the impact is pecuniary, it is reflected in the market and it is

not a material effect.7 Therefore, an implication of Callon’s association of overflows with

externalities is that distributional effects are never a reason for market reframing. If

Callon is aiming to be prescriptive here, then he seems to align himself with the

economists as this is clearly in line with much of their advice that improving efficiency

should be the only objective of policy. If instead, Callon’s intention is to be descriptive,

then he is factually wrong, as the historical reality is of frequent attempts to reorganise

market operations for distributional reasons, as the case of coffee illustrates.

Coffee market instability

Coffee is a valuable cash crop for around 25 million smallholders, who need to earn a

living from small patches of land. Furthermore, for the low-income countries where

coffee is grown, it is often a critical source of foreign exchange, sometimes accounting

for over 50% of total export earnings. There is long history of price variation and price

decline for coffee and because of the dependency of both poor farmers and whole

Page 14: REFLECTING ON CALLON WITH A CASE OF FAIR TRADE COFFEE

14

economies on this cash crop, the question of how the coffee market might be organised to

ameliorate the distributional effects of price instability and decline, has been a subject of

contestation for decades. A major attempt at market reframing to stabilize prices was an

inter-governmental effort in the early 1960s. This was because during the Cold War there

was a fear in western economies that price instability in coffee dependent economies

would lead them to Communism. As a result the International Coffee Organisation (ICO)

was founded and a market system heavily dependent on government intervention, in the

form of a quota system, introduced (Ponte 2002). However, after nearly four decades this

form of market organisation collapsed, because it proved costly, the political threat

removed, and market liberalization was the zeitgeist. Producer countries were advised by

international agencies such as the World Bank and the IMF, to dismantle marketing

boards and reduce government influence on commodity prices, leading to greater price

instability once again. It was the perceived negative impact of this on small vulnerable

coffee growers which gave impetus to the to development of the Fair Trade movement

(FTM), to bring into being a new type of supply chain, and campaign for more

widespread change.

The story of the coffee market since the early 1960s demonstrates how the limitations of

one form of market organisation gave birth to another; from free market to ICO quotas,

back to free market, and then for some producers, to Fair Trade. Callon’s terminology of

overflowing effects leading to market reframing would seem to have relevance for

expressing such developments. However, since neither price instability nor political

change, nor concern for the less economically fortunate, can be defined as externality

Page 15: REFLECTING ON CALLON WITH A CASE OF FAIR TRADE COFFEE

15

effects, to apply the expression of overflowing, it is necessary to clarify that its definition

extends beyond externalities, to include any spillover effects from market activities that

are perceived to have a detrimental impact.8 This may be Callon’s intention, given his

claim that the notion of externality denotes ‘all the connections, relations and effects

which agents do not take into account in their calculations’ (Callon1998a:16). This

description is an incorrect economic definition of an externality, but is broad enough to

include distributional issues. Clarification of Callon’s position is required by seeking for

evidence elsewhere in his writings that might indicate that issues of justice can lead to

market change. A leading question is, whether Callon’s framework allows for interests

other than the self to be included in market decisions.

Calculating for whom?

Although Callon recognises that the relationship between two transacting partners can

have relevance in an exchange, but his focus is on the social connections that ease

economic transactions, rather than human relations that motivate duty or altruism. For

example, when there is market uncertainty he appreciates that it can make sense to take

account of whom you are trading with, and it can be an advantage to establish long-term

trusting trading relationships (Callon 1998a). However, what is at issue with regard to

Fair Trade, is whether Callon’s framework can encompass market arrangements that

privilege an individual or group on the grounds of compassion and altruism. There

appears to be some haziness within Callon’s writings on whether he assumes that human

actors always act out of self-interest, when operating in the market. The fact that Callon’s

agents live within an evolving network confers a broad view of what influences

Page 16: REFLECTING ON CALLON WITH A CASE OF FAIR TRADE COFFEE

16

behaviour, that an individual’s preferences are not static, and that unlike homo

economicus are not derived from an innate self, unswayed by the world around. They are

open to influences from all parts of the network. Nevertheless, by stating that the tools

derived from economics are an important influence on the network, indeed that homo

economicus can be created in the market, and that the economy is embedded in

economics, there is an implication in Callon’s work that within the market setting at least,

self interest is the expected pattern of behaviour. But then his position is tempered by

comments that other members of society can decide what to calculate and how. In a

certain respect, this can be viewed as no different from the neo-classical economic

position which does effectively allow for any preferences to be expressed (see

Hargreaves-Heap 2001 for an interesting discussion). Although the term calculating has

Machiavellian overtones, concern for others can be included within a calculation. A

consumer can be inclined towards ethical purchases, goods which are not bought solely

for the pleasure of individual consumption but also for the beneficial effects it brings to

other agents. For example, a consumer may be motivated to purchase solar panels for her

property because she wants to make a contribution to limiting carbon emissions, to

reduce climate change risks to future generations. Some economists consider this to result

in a warm glow effect that contributes to utility, and therefore there can be an element of

satisfaction from this action to the purchaser. Curiously though, Callon (2005) suggests

that an individual will buy environmentally friendly products only if the relevant aspects

of the environment are considered within the market frame. Given the emphasis he gives

to market reframing as involving the internalization of externalities, this is a precarious

statement because it insinuates that there are no voluntary purchases of environmentally

Page 17: REFLECTING ON CALLON WITH A CASE OF FAIR TRADE COFFEE

17

friendly products, and thereby that the only social obligation in market exchange is to act

within the law of property rights. However, before presuming that Callon’s framework

does not allow for such purchases, it is relevant to recall that his concept of market

framing, although stressing the delineation of property rights, does include also product

definition, and this could embrace the ethical credentials of a product. Therefore, in spite

of ambiguity caused by the overemphasis on reframings associated with externality type

ethical purchases, even though this is not entirely obvious from all his work.

Fair Trade goods are comparable to environmentally friendly products in so far as

consumers voluntarily purchase them, it is merely that concern for other humans rather

than concern for the environment is objectified and incorporated within calculations.

However, there is also difference. The raison d’être of Fair Trade is not directly related to

the physicality of the product (although as Fair Trade has evolved more attention has

been given to product quality). Instead, the main focus of Fair Trade is the rate of

exchange. Therefore, whereas the voluntary purchase of environmental goods is

compatible with a free market, within current Fair Trade schemes, there is an element of

price fixing. Although the final product on shop shelves can be sold at whatever price the

retailer chooses, a minimum price is guaranteed for the producers of the raw product, in

this case coffee beans. This is anathema to liberal minded economists, unsupportive of

pricing arrangements based on distributional criterion, but sociologists may view such

price agreements as merely a continuation of the history of market operations based on

social conventions. To consider whether Callon’s insights can help to bridge the gap

Page 18: REFLECTING ON CALLON WITH A CASE OF FAIR TRADE COFFEE

18

between understandings of economists and sociologists, requires reflecting on Callon’s

understanding on pricing arrangements.

Price determination

Callon views price agreement as being a peaceful means of resolving conflict between

opposing buyers and sellers (Callon 1998a:3). Price resolution is aided by a range of

collective calculative devices (see for a full discussion), amongst them accounting

practices and pricing tools, which help to attain a monetary expression of the value

(derived from entanglement) which enables the disentanglement required for exchange

(Callon 1998a, Callon and Muniesa 2005). For Callon, calculation does not solely

involve quantitative procedures, but also judgment areas of where there is uncertainty.

Therefore, his definition of calculation is a form of reckoning involving both quantitative

and qualitative data that might be paraphrased as ‘weighing things up’.

Another dimension of price determination is the process through which buyers place bids,

and sellers respond. Callon and Muniesa (2005) argue that various systems can be applied

in exchange encounters, and different ‘algorithmic configurations’ can lead to different

final prices. For example, the price achieved through a Dutch auction, may be differ from

one achieved through open bidding. Callon and Muniesa stress the role of material

devices in price determination, referring in particular to automated systems on stock

exchanges, but consistent with a network approach, they acknowledge that buyer/seller

relationships can have a bearing as well. An outcome of this is that at a given point in

time and space, a commodity can be sold at different prices to different buyers. Drawing

Page 19: REFLECTING ON CALLON WITH A CASE OF FAIR TRADE COFFEE

19

on research by Kirman (2001), they cite the Marseilles fish market as an example, where

the same species of fish are sold at different prices to loyal and disloyal customers.

Nonetheless, at the aggregate level, when quantities sold are reduced, then the average

price rises; the law of demand holds. The conclusion reached by Kirman (see also Härdle

and Kirman (1995)) is that observations made at the aggregate level should not be used to

make deductions of what happens at the micro level. At the aggregate level it might

appear that sales and purchases are totally price dependent, but analysis at the micro level

indicates that interactions are not solely price based. The reason given for this is that

individuals have imperfect information on overall levels of supply and demand.

Therefore buyers and sellers can gain from implicit contracts which guarantee sales and

purchases, even if price to one party might seem disadvantageous compared to the

average market price. In effect, the agents involved in the partnership have weighed up

the benefits of repeated exchange.9 The existence of implicit contracts leads Kirman (an

economist) to the conclusion that markets are much less predictive than might be

presumed in some economic forecasts. However Callon seems to view price uncertainty

as being adequately dealt with through the calculative relationships between buyers and

sellers and the result is no significant instability within the price system. For example,

Callon et.al., (2002: 194) state ‘One can find multiple socio-technical devices that are

designed by economic agents, which ensure the distribution of cognitive competencies,

and which constantly and finely tune supply and demand.’ In reality, price variation can

result from four related reasons. First, close links between buyers and sellers do not

always exist, secondly, aggregation from individual firm to industry level can lead to

unpredicted effects, thirdly, production cannot always be controlled so actual output

Page 20: REFLECTING ON CALLON WITH A CASE OF FAIR TRADE COFFEE

20

diverges from planned output, fourthly, (though not typically in the case of coffee)

demand can be capricious.

Uncontrollable environmental events such as disease and frost are at the root of price

instability in the coffee market, but their impact has been compounded by the thinness of

network ties, which contributes to aggregated effects that are detrimental. Because

production of coffee beans is by a large number of geographically dispersed small

growers, knowledge of consumer requirements and production strategies of competitors

is far from perfect, and there is heavy reliance on price signals. This lack of ties and non-

price information has meant that when disease or frost severely impacts on coffee

harvests as they regularly have done, they have had particularly destabilising effects. The

reduced supply leads to upward movements in price, and in an atomistic market, this

typically encourages new plantings. Two years on, when the bushes bear fruit, the

increased production results in significantly lower prices. Therefore prices fluctuate.

Because coffee consumption is fairly insensitive to price change, price reductions are not

fully offset by greater sales, and so income instability is closely associated with price

instability. Another consequence of limited network ties has been that price fluctuations

have occurred along a declining long run price trend. The tendency for the production of

coffee to increase and put downward pressure on prices over time is the result of

individual producers and producer countries calculating in isolation that expanding their

own supply will be profitable. Often governments have provided planting subsidies to

harvest foreign currency, with expansion plans based on an assumption that prices will

not change, or at least will not fall below a level which makes the expansion unprofitable.

Page 21: REFLECTING ON CALLON WITH A CASE OF FAIR TRADE COFFEE

21

However, if many countries independently raise output then the aggregate increase in

supply can reduce returns to all. A recent example of this was the severe slump in coffee

prices in 2001, which can be attributed largely to the promotion of low cost coffee

growing in Vietnam and expansion in Brazil (ICO 2004).

The materialisation of Fair Trade

Although Callon’s framework has limitations in explaining the factors that gave impetus

to Fair Trade initiatives, his interest in the linkages between actors (including the non-

human) gives his work an edge in understanding how new markets come into being. He

argues that the key to understanding new market forms is to appreciate what are the

entangling, framing and disentangling processes involved (Callon 2005). In the case of

Fair Trade, the Fair Trade movement (FTM) has sought to principally differentiate

products by the favourable trading arrangements with primary producers. To signal this

to consumers, every accredited Fair Trade product has the internationally agreed

Fairtrade mark on its packaging, which comprises of a logo and the maxim 'Guarantees a

better deal for Third World Producers'. Accordingly, the product is objectified and

distributional issues brought into the market frame. The FTM fosters a connection

between coffee producers and consumers with promotional literature focusing at least as

much on the producers as the product. Visual images and script contribute to the process

of singularisation by encouraging consumers to positively relate to growers.

In contrast to the proponents of unrestricted markets who engage the attention of a

network of policy makers with a discourse based in neo-liberal economics, the FTM has

Page 22: REFLECTING ON CALLON WITH A CASE OF FAIR TRADE COFFEE

22

used various literary inscriptions in the form of reports,10 web pages and campaigning

newsletters to persuade a network of coffee consumers of the case for alternative trading

arrangements (see Raynolds (2002) for further detail). When the movement was young

and resources scarce, the message was conveyed almost solely through NGO

campaigning networks, and through church based organisations where the appeal for

trade justice resonated with the message of the gospel. Thus it was possible to target a

group of consumers with established sensibilities towards helping those in difficult

economic circumstances. This group of consumers provided an initial base from which

the Fair Trade became established, with early sales of Fair Trade coffee made from NGO

outlets (charity shops and mail order) and from churches. In the UK case, in 1994, the

FTM established a company, Café Direct, to extend sales into supermarkets.

Consequently, through the increased availability of the product, and the use of more

conventional media channels, such as newspaper adverts and magazine articles the case

for Fair Trade was made to a wider audience. A few years later, Café Direct decided that

in order to significantly expand sales, it needed to reposition itself in the market as a

premium product since research conducted in 1998 revealed that although buying Fair

Trade goods made people feel slightly better about themselves, ultimately they wanted to

purchase a good tasting product.11 From a production perspective, promoting quality was

entirely complementary with Fair Trade arrangements, because providing a reasonable

bean price is a necessity for guaranteeing quality coffee. Bean quality is in part

determined by the maturity of the coffee cherry when it is picked and when growers

expect a low return for their crop they will harvest a coffee bush only once collecting

cherries of varying maturity. If the price is higher, growers can afford to pick just the

Page 23: REFLECTING ON CALLON WITH A CASE OF FAIR TRADE COFFEE

23

mature cherries, returning to the bush later in the season for the rest. Café Direct now

objectifies its product and promotes it on both its ethical and taste qualities with the

slogan ‘Excellent Café, Direct from the growers’.

Evolving outside the normal channels of commerce, using an unconventional business

model, Fair Trade coffee provides a clear example of a product emerging from a network,

co-produced by consumers and enabled by non-human objects. Callon names this process

of co-production, the economy of qualities (Callon, Méadel, and Rabeharisoa 2002). Fair

Trade products were able to gain a critical mass of support in early stages by operating in

networks where there were strong ties between actors holding sympathetic values, while

less ethical consumers provided the drive for higher quality. The FTM has used a variety

of media to communicate a different narrative on what is appropriate market conduct, and

to a degree has begun to change the dynamics of power, by altering social opinion of

expected company behaviour.12 The movement has achieved a degree of success in over-

riding the neo-liberal market argument that any exchange is freely entered into, outcomes

are the result of abstract market forces, so responsibility cannot be ascribed to any agent,

therefore companies are under no social obligation to consider the circumstances of their

suppliers. Instead the FTM have developed a message that challenges the indifference to

human consequences of liberalised markets. In particular it confronts the distributional

consequences of the free market by arguing that questions of power and responsibility

should not be ignored. Callon’ network approach which stresses the role of material

devices is appropriate for reflecting on how such novel market arrangements came into

Page 24: REFLECTING ON CALLON WITH A CASE OF FAIR TRADE COFFEE

24

being. However, it needs to be deliberated whether Fair Trade arrangements are

sustainable over time?

Overflowing Fair Trade coffee

Fair Trade sales have risen significantly in recent years, but it remains a small market

niche. An ambition of the FTM is that this is changed by persuading large coffee

companies that dominate final coffee sales to adjust their mode of operation. By

producing a product with distinctive moral credentials and developing a customer base,

there has been a degree of pressure on large companies to change.13 However, some

predict that an expansion of Fair Trade would result in excess unsold coffee, what might

be termed an overflowing effect. Lindsey (2004:9) in a report for the Adam Smith

Institute argues that ‘Those who single out companies as scapegoats and advocate half-

baked schemes to prop up prices may have the best of intentions, but they are not really

helping.’ His reasoning is that if the principle of paying growers a minimum price to

cover costs of production was to be extended to the whole coffee market it would

exacerbate the problems of oversupply. Such a viewpoint, based in neoliberal economics

assumes that decisions are based solely on market price information, and does not take

into consideration that other ties within the network might reduce the disparity between

levels of production and consumption, for example, an arrangement whereby the price is

negotiated for a limited amount of beans. Nonetheless, even where some form of

contract is attractive, the extension of Fair Trade pricing conceivably would be too

formulaic to suit all players. Negotiating prices to encourage a long term trading

partnership is significantly different from having prices determined institutionally by the

Page 25: REFLECTING ON CALLON WITH A CASE OF FAIR TRADE COFFEE

25

Fair Trade formula. Furthermore, there is the conceptual problem that if all coffee was

bought under Fair Trade arrangements, there would be no world market price to base the

Fair Trade price upon. Therefore, the arithmetic of the Fair Trade payment system is not

effectively transferable to the whole world coffee market, such a market organization has

overflowing effects. However, this is not necessarily a serious concern, given that there is

evidence that the actual price is not the most important aspect of Fair Trade. Some Fair

Trade producers have indicated that the ability to engage in a long-term business

arrangement is more significant than prices.14 Fair Trade can be an opportunity to

demonstrate skills, witness the following comment from a coffee grower. ‘We don't want

the consumer to try our product because we are poor, because we have problems. The

image we want to present to you is that we offer a high quality product and we are a

sustainable organization.’ (Blanca Rosa Molina, CECOCAFEN, Nicaragua).15 The

building of partnerships is considered to be a less controversial aspect of the Fair Trade

supply chain than the Fair Trade pricing system, (Oxford Policy Management and

Sustainable Markets Group 2000, Lindsey 2004). Examples of good long term

partnerships already exist outside Fair Trade between roasters of speciality coffee and

growers. Nonetheless, the FTM has been instrumental in developing the capacity of some

growers to respond to consumer requirements for improved bean quality and develop

business acumen so they can play a strong role within a partnership. It would seem to be

this aspect of Fair Trade that is more likely to be sustained over time. Such an approach,

when there is an imbalance of power, is dependent on a respectful relationships and is

redolent of the argument made by Sayer (2004) that factors such as the interests,

Page 26: REFLECTING ON CALLON WITH A CASE OF FAIR TRADE COFFEE

26

commitments, moral dispositions and characters of participants should be included within

a market frame.

It follows that Fair Trade as it currently exists, perhaps should be viewed as having an

intermediate role, no longer being required once development objectives are met. Indeed

Fair Trade itself could be conceived as being a temporary socio-technical device,

something that is a means towards achieving fair trading relationships, rather than being

an end in itself.

Conclusion

Opinions have differed between economists and others on whether Fair Trade initiatives

can effectively address concerns about inequity within international commodity markets.

Callon’s writings on markets are interesting in this regard because he argues that both

economics and economic sociology have relevance for understanding how markets

operate. He recognises that people live in a constantly evolving network which shapes

their values and determines what is produced, and stresses the role of non-human

elements within those processes. In particular, he emphasises the significance of socio-

technical devices which translate economic ideas into actual market activity. Thereby

Callon emphasises the performative role of economics. However, while arguing that

economic concepts have significance in real markets, Callon also proposes that other

actors, with their ideas and values, can have a role in shaping markets, and that issues of

justice can be addressed. Essentially he perceives economics and its associated tools as

providing the necessary equipment for the calculations required for market exchange, but

Page 27: REFLECTING ON CALLON WITH A CASE OF FAIR TRADE COFFEE

27

other actors have an opportunity to determine what should be included within a

calculation and how values should be established. An object acquires value from network

entanglements that give it substance and meaning, but a calculation is required to

translate the value into a monetary equivalent for exchange.

Callon contributes to our understanding of the processes that establish use value and new

markets through his explanation of entanglements and framing, but study of the coffee

market identifies that his analysis does not go sufficiently far to develop an explanation

for exchange value. In effect, he does not adequately explicate price determination.

Though Callon and Muniesa (2005) provide a discussion on algorithmic configurations

which enable the process of reaching a price, no attention is given to a fundamental

determinant of price, the degree of scarcity. This seems to be the result of a presumption

in Callon’s work that typically there is close co-ordination between production and

consumption decisions such that supply and demand always match at a price that is

comfortable for both of the bargaining parties. Therefore price volatility is not an issue

for him.

This discussion on prices is important for understanding Fair Trade markets, for it is the

variability and overall decline in commodity prices that led to the establishment of Fair

Trade initiatives, and reasonably under such natal conditions, the price to be received by

producers became a central feature of the Fair Trade market design. Focusing on prices is

also central for reflecting on the differences between economists and sociologists, for

prices send important signals, but also have distributional consequences. Interestingly, for

Page 28: REFLECTING ON CALLON WITH A CASE OF FAIR TRADE COFFEE

28

economists, market instability is synonymous with price instability, but in Callon’s work

market instability is anything but price related.16 Neither does he give attention to

declining prices. This is somewhat curious particularly given that Polanyi discussed how

price instability and decline can be factors that prompt market reorganisation, in his book

The Great Transformation (Polanyi 1957), a text Callon refers to (1998a: 2). The cause of

Callon’s omission may be that his main aim is to stress the importance of the material

within networks. This intent leads him to disregard the conditions where there is actually

a deficiency of material conduits to communicate the information which facilitates price

stability. Intriguingly though, given his emphasis on non-human actors, there is also a

failure to appreciate that the material can be a direct player in determining price levels.

Specifically, if there is an increase in supply of a material product, for example coffee

beans, the price is likely to fall and the converse when supply is lower than expected,

because price acts as a rationing device. Callon does not discuss this. Instead, he

accentuates the connections that exist between buyers and sellers which can result in

differing prices between differing pairs of actors, for the same commodity at a given

point in time (Callon and Muniesa 2005). While this may be so, it is likely that such

relationships are sometimes mediated by overall conditions of supply relative to

requirements. Adopting a network perspective, we can consider A and B who trade with

each other frequently, trying to agree on a price. To some extent they may be bound by a

combination of loyalty and self interest to maintain an established trading partnership.

However, alternative options are likely to have some influence on the exchange decision

to. Although neither actor may have exact information on overall supply conditions,

nonetheless they are likely to be aware when other agents in the network, C and D, are

Page 29: REFLECTING ON CALLON WITH A CASE OF FAIR TRADE COFFEE

29

having problems selling all their goods. Therefore, B knows that if he disagrees with A’s

terms, another seller (C or D) can easily be found, while simultaneously A appreciates

that it will be difficult to find alternative buyers. Therefore external conditions are likely

to have at least some effect on the price negotiations between A and B, with prices

having a tendency to fall when supply increases. The greater the change in supply

conditions, the greater will be the strain on implicit contracts. In the longer, through

network entanglements, tastes might change but in the shorter run if supply increases,

normally the only way that all beans (in the case of coffee) can be sold is for them to be

offered at a lesser price so sales are extended to lower income groups and to existing

coffee drinkers with declining marginal utility.

Sayer (2002:52) in a critique of embeddedness has highlighted insufficient recognition in

new economic sociology that ultimately for some there is an economic actuality that ‘the

bottom line remains the bottom line’. Human agents do not always have control of prices,

and some markets have become ‘systems’, in the sense of operating ‘behind actors’

backs’ (Habermas 1987) and thereby making actors subject to ‘blind’ market forces

(Sayer 2002). Economic history provides countless examples of social conventions and

long term arrangements that have been altered as a result of changes in relative scarcities.

Meanwhile, Callon argues that economics has relevance, but only as a mental construct

that actors collectively materialise. Market regularities have merely ‘the obduracy of the

real’ (Callon 1998a:47). His position has utopian undertones, in that members of society

are considered to have a significant degree of choice and influence in determining how

markets operate.

Page 30: REFLECTING ON CALLON WITH A CASE OF FAIR TRADE COFFEE

30

The emergence of Fair Trade, appears to support his case, in so far that it was designed

by actors who dispensed with typical economic thinking to create a new form of supply

chain with an explicit social goal. Callon’s tools also help in gaining an understanding of

how the Fair Trade concept was enabled. However, the impetus for the new market

arrangements (variable and declining prices) cannot be sufficiently explained by his

framework. This is because his theory on price is deficient, and his emphasis on the

causes of market change being related to externality effects is historically imprecise.

Callon chooses to focus on direct material effects on markets but fails to give attention to

material effects that impact indirectly via price changes. Whilst economic discussion that

blithely refers to the laws of supply and demand can accredit actors with too little

influence over their destiny, there is a danger of naivety in assuming that humanly

controlled co-ordination is sufficient to manage prices within acceptable levels.

Nonetheless, even though Callon’s work is not illuminating in considering the

sustainability of the Fair Trade pricing scheme, there is a confluence between Callon’s

view of market arrangements involving close relations between producers and

consumers, and the most likely durable aspect of Fair Trade which is enduring

partnerships. Callon’s application of the concept of framing is useful for considering

how markets might be organized. However, for issues of justice to be addressed

effectively, there needs to be a more complete explanation of what is included within the

frame, and of the determinants of the rate of exchange.

Page 31: REFLECTING ON CALLON WITH A CASE OF FAIR TRADE COFFEE

31

Notes

1 These campaigns are internationally co-ordinated by the Global Call to Action against Poverty. This is a

worldwide alliance of a variety of actors including existing coalitions, community groups, trade unions,

individuals, religious and faith groups committed to the cause of ending poverty. They focus on several

issues of which trade justice is one, and others are debt cancellation Details on http://www.whiteband.org/

2 Named after a character in a Dutch novel who protested against the poor treatment of coffee plantation

workers in Java in the nineteenth century.

3 There is an international accreditation scheme for products that meet the Fair Trade standards. When the

standards are met, permission is granted to label the product and describe it as fairtrade (one word).

4 There is a link between low coffee prices and world trade arrangements, in so far as existing trade barriers

exacerbate the problems in the coffee and other commodity markets, by reducing diversification options for

agricultural producers in the southern hemisphere, there is a link between low coffee prices and world trade

arrangements.

5 Actor-network theory now also is referred to as Science and Technology Studies (STS).

6 Callon adopts the expression of disentanglement and its antonym, entanglement from Thomas (1991).

7 In the UK there is currently a debate about the impact of supermarkets on local shops and communities.

Competition policy, based on economic principles does not provide any basis for intervention.

8 There can be positive knock-on effects as well, but these are likely to reinforce the current system of

market organisation and therefore do not prompt reframing.

9 Repeated exchange is a behaviour pattern that is a familiar assumption within economic game-theoretic

models.

10 See for example Oxfam(2002) Mugged: Poverty in your coffee cup and Fairtrade Foundation (2002)

Spilling the beans on the coffee trade.

Page 32: REFLECTING ON CALLON WITH A CASE OF FAIR TRADE COFFEE

32

11 CaféDirect's Share Prospectus, 2004.

12 Ponte and Gibbon (2005) also draw attention to how the ‘diffusion of dominant normative paradigms’

(p3) can influence the way supply chains are managed.

13 In October 2005 one of the largest coffee companies, Nestle, introduced a Fair Trade coffee into their

brand range. They said that their decision had been driven by the consumer.

(http://news.bbc.co.uk/1/hi/business/4318882.stm)

14 Quarterly Return, 51, Spring 2004, Newsletter of Shared Interest Society Limited.

15 CaféDirect's Share Prospectus, 2004.

16 Unlike like the literature on embeddeddness, Callon’s vocabulary on markets currently does not seem to

differentiate between levels of reliance on price information and on network relations.

References

Appadurai, A. (1986) The Social Life of Things: Commodities in Cultural Perspective,

Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Aspers, P. (2005) Performativity, Neoclassical theory and Economic Sociology.

Economic Sociology: European Electronic Newsletter, 6/2 (February): 3-20.

Barry, A. and Slater, D. (2002) ‘Technology, politics and the market: an interview with

Michel Callon’ Economy and Society, 31, 2,285-306.

Bauman, Z. (2001) ‘The Telos Interview’ in Beilharz, P. (ed.) The Bauman Reader.

Oxford: Blackwells.

Page 33: REFLECTING ON CALLON WITH A CASE OF FAIR TRADE COFFEE

33

Callon, M. (1998a) 'Introduction: The embeddedness of economic markets in economics'

in Callon, M. (ed.) The Laws of the Markets, Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.

Callon, M. (1998b) 'An essay on framing and overflowing: economic externalities

revisited by sociology' in Callon, M. (ed.) The Laws of the Markets, Oxford: Blackwell

Publishers.

Callon, M. (1999) ‘Actor-network theory – the market test’ in Law, J. and Hassard, J.

(eds.) Actor Network Theory and after, Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.

Callon, M. (2005) ‘Why Virtualism paves the way to Political Impotence: A reply to

Daniel Miller’s critique of the Laws of the Markets’. Economic Sociology: European

Electronic Newsletter, 6/2 (February): 3-20.

Callon, M., Méadel, C. and Rabeharisoa, V. (2002) ‘The economy of qualities’ Economy

and Society, 31, 2, 194-217.

Callon, M. and Muniesa, F. (2005) ‘Economic Markets as Collective Calculative

Devices’ Organisation Studies, 26, 8, 1229-1250.

Elias, Norbert (1994) The Civilizing Process, Vols. 1 and 2. Oxford: Blackwell.

Page 34: REFLECTING ON CALLON WITH A CASE OF FAIR TRADE COFFEE

34

Fairtrade Foundation (2002) Spilling the beans on the coffee trade. (Available from

website: www.fairtradefoundation.co.uk).

Fine, B. (2003) ‘Callonistics: a disentanglement’ Economy and Society, 32, 3, 478-484.

Gilbert, C. (1987) 'International Commodity Agreements: Design and Performance'

World Development, 15, 5, 591-616.

Goffman, E. (1971) Frame Analysis: an essay on the organization of experience.

Chicago: Northeastern University Press.

Goodman, M.K. (2004) ‘Reading fair-trade: Political ecological imaginary and the moral

economy of Fair Trade foods’ Political Geography, 23, 891-915.

Granovetter, M. (1985) ‘Economic action and social structure: The problem of

embeddedness’ American Journal of Sociology, 91, 3, 481-510.

Habermas, J. (1987) The Theory of Communicative Action, Vol. 2, translated by

T.McCarthy, Cambridge, Polity

Hargreaves Heap, S. (2001)‘Postmodernity, rationality and justice’. in Cullenberg, S.,

Amariglio, J. and Ruccio, D.F. (eds.) Postmodernism, economics and knowledge.

London: Routledge

Page 35: REFLECTING ON CALLON WITH A CASE OF FAIR TRADE COFFEE

35

ICO (2004) Website of the International Coffee Organisation: www.ico.org

Kirman, A. (2001) ‘Market organization and individual behaviour: Evidence from fish

markets’ in. J.E.Raunch and A.Casella (eds.) Networks and Markets 155-195. New York:

Russell Sage Foundation.

Härdle, W., Kirman, A. (1995) ‘Non-classical demand: A model-free examination of

price-quantity relations in the Marseilles fish market’. Journal of Econometrics, 67,227-

257.

Lindsey, B. (2004) Grounds for Complaint? 'Fair Trade' and the coffee crisis. London:

Adam Smith Institute.

MacKenzie, D. and Millo, Y. (2003) ‘Constructing a market, performing theory: The

historical sociology of a financial derivatives exchange’. American Journal of Sociology,

109,1,107-145.

MacKenzie, D. (2004) ‘The big, bad wolf and the rational market: portfolio insurance,

the 1987 crash and the performativity of economics’ Economy and Society, 33, 3,303-

334.

Miller, D. (2002) ‘Turning Callon the right way up’ Economy and Society, 31,2,218-233.

Page 36: REFLECTING ON CALLON WITH A CASE OF FAIR TRADE COFFEE

36

Miller, D. (2005) ‘Reply to Michel Callon’. Economic Sociology: European Electronic

Newsletter, 6/3 (July): 3-13.

Oxfam (2002) Mugged: Poverty in your coffee cup (Available from website:

www.oxfam.co.uk).

Oxfam Policy Management and Sustainable Markets Group (2000) Fair Trade:

Overview, Impact, Challenges. Study to inform DFID’s support to Fair Trade. Source:

Pendergrast, M. (2001) Uncommon Grounds - The history of coffee and how it

transformed our world, London: Texere.

Polanyi, K. (1957) The Great Transformation. Boston: Beacon Press

Ponte, S. (2002) 'The "Latte Revolution"? Regulation, markets, and consumption in the

Global coffee chain' World Development, 30, 7, 1099-1122.

Ponte, S. and Gibbon, P.(2005) ‘Quality standards, conventions and the governance of

global value chains’ Economy and Society, 34,1, 1-31.

Raynolds, L.T. (2002) 'Consumer/Producer Links in Fair Trade Coffee Networks'

Sociologia Ruralis, 42, 4, 405- 423.

Page 37: REFLECTING ON CALLON WITH A CASE OF FAIR TRADE COFFEE

37

Sayer, A. (2002) ‘Markets, Embeddedness and Trust: Problems of Polysemy and

Idealism’ Chapter 2 in Metcalfe, S. and Warde, A. (eds.) Market relations and the

competitive process, Manchester: Manchester University Press.

Sayer (2004) ‘Moral Economy’ published by the Dept of Sociology, Lancaster

University, Lancaster, LA1 4YL, UK at

http://www.comp.lancs.ac.uk/sociology/papers/sayer-moral-economy.pdf

Slater, D. (2002) ‘From calculation to alienation: disentangling economic abstractions’

Economy and Society, 31, 2,285-306

Smelser,N.J. and Swedberg, R. (2005) The Handbook of Economic Sociology. Princeton:

Princeton University Press.

Thomas, N. (1991) Entangled objects: Exchange, Material Culture and Colonialism in

the Pacific. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Uzzi, B. (1996) The Sources and Consequences of Embeddedness for the Economic

Performance of Organizations: The Network Effect American Sociological Review, Vol.

61, No. 4 pp. 674-698