philosophy now - march 2016.pdf

Upload: ashley-tackoory

Post on 24-Feb-2018

226 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/25/2019 Philosophy Now - March 2016.pdf

    1/56

    ISSUE 112 FEBRUARY / MARCH 2016 UK 3.75 USA $7.99 CANADA $8.99

    PhilosophyNowa m a g a z i n e o f i d e a s

    Leibnizand hisastoundinginfinitemechanism!

    Altruism

    Is it evenpossible?

    WHAT NIETZSCHE DID TO DALI

  • 7/25/2019 Philosophy Now - March 2016.pdf

    2/56

    D a n c in g w it h A b su r d it y Y ou r M ost C he r ishe d B e lie f s

    a n d A ll Y ou r O t he r s ) A r e Pr ob a b ly W r on g

    P e t e r L a n g P u b lis h in g

    In t e r n a t ion a l A c a d e m ic P u b lis h e r s www p e t e r la n g c om

    Leavitt bulldozes various philosophicalconstructs, then merrily guides us through the

    wreckage without ever condescending to the reader. Glynn Washington, Host/Executive Producer of

    Snap Judgment (NPR)

    By Fred LeavittAmerican University Studies V:

    Philosophy; vol. 219

    Hardcover; 220 pages978-1-4331-2925-4 (print)978-1-4539-1490-8 (ebook)

    52.00 - 65.35 - SFR 79.00US$ 84.95

    ALSO AVAILABLE THROUGH AMAZON AND MOSTMAJOR LIBRARY WHOLESALERS

    NEW FROM STANFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS

    ho are the people behind the inventions, the discoveries, the

    did they come to play such a key role in making our modern

    THE MAKERS OF OUR

    MODERN WORLD

    is popularscience book iswidely available as a

    paperback and ebookon Amazon and otheronline retailers.

  • 7/25/2019 Philosophy Now - March 2016.pdf

    3/56

    February/March 2016 PhilosophyNow 3

    PhilosophyNow ISSUE 112 Feb/Mar 2016Philosophy Now ,

    43a Jerningham R oad,T elegraph H ill,

    L ondon SE14 5N QU nited K ingdom

    Tel. 020 7639 7314editors@ philosophynow.org

    philosophynow.org

    Editor-in-ChiefR ick L ewisEditors Anja S teinbauer,G rant B artleyDigital Editor B ora D oganGraphic Design G rant B artley,K atyB aker,Anja S teinbauerBook Reviews Editor T eresa B rittonFilm Editor T homas W artenbergMarketing Manager Sue R obertsAdministration E wa Stacey,K aty B akerAdvertising TeamJay Sanders,E llen S tevensjay.sanders@ philosophynow.orgUK Editorial BoardR ick L ewis,Anja Steinbauer,

    B ora D ogan,G rant B artleyUS Editorial BoardD r T imothy J. M adigan (St John F isherC ollege),P rof. C harles E chelbarger,P rof. R aymond Pfeiffer,P rof. M assimoP igliucci (C U N Y - C ity C ollege),P rof.T eresa Britton (E astern Illinois U niv.)Contributing EditorsAlexander R azin (M oscow State U niv.)L aura R oberts (U niv. ofQ ueensland)D avid B oersema (P acific U niversity)UK Editorial AdvisorsP iers B enn,C onstantine Sandis,G ordonG iles,P aul G regory,John H eawoodUS Editorial AdvisorsP rof. R aymond Angelo B elliotti,T oniV ogel C arey,P rof. W alter Sinnott-

    Armstrong,P rof. H arvey SiegelCover Image Steve L illie 2016P lease visitwww.stevelill ie.biz

    P rinted by G raspo C Z ,a.s.,P od Sternberkem 32 4,763 02 Z lin,C zech R epublic

    U K newstrade distribution through:C omag Specialist D ivision,T avistock W orks,T avistock R d,W est D rayton,M iddlesex U B 7 7Q XTel. 01895 433800

    U .S. & C anadian bookstores through:D isticor M agazine D istribution Services695 W estney R oad S.,U nit 14,

    Ajax,O ntario L 1S 6M 9Tel. (905)619 6565

    Australian newstrade distribution:G ordon & G otch ptyL evel 2,9 R odborough R oadF renchs F orest,N SW 2086Tel. 02 9972 8800

    T he opinions expressed in this magazinedo not necessarily reflect the views ofthe editor or editorial board of h i los op h y Now .

    Philosophy Now is published byAnja P ublications L td

    I S S N 0 9 6 1 - 5 9 0

    Back Issues p.52Subscriptions p.53

    FreeWillPages 6-17

    EDITORIAL, NEWS & INTERVIEWS4 F eel F ree to D isagree Grant Bartley

    5 N ews in Brief

    28 Interview:D .D . R aphael (1916-2015)

    Gideon Calder chatted with the ethicist shortly before his death

    38 E xistential C omics

    Corey M ohler records the batt les ofJeremy Bentham

    FREE WILL6 F ree W ill Is An Illusion,B ut Freedom Isnt

    Ching-Hung W oo explains the compatibilist account ofchoice

    8 T he N ew Argument About Freedom

    Natasha Gilbert says its not just about how determined we are

    10 T he B rains R isk/R eward System M akes O ur D ecisions

    Graham Boyd says i t i snt up to us

    13 Akrasia:W hy D o W e Act Against O ur B etter Judgement?

    George Singleton worries why we do what we know is wrong15 R eclaiming F reedom

    Steve Taylor defends a common-sense idea offree wi ll

    OTHER ARTICLES18 L eibniz and the Infinite M echanism

    Audrey Borowski tells us about Leibnizs biology

    20 H erder and H uman Identity

    Brian King says to understand the herd, you need a Herder!

    23 H ow N ietzsche Inspired D al

    M agdalena Scholle on ideas and moustaches

    26 Justifying O ur M oral Judgments

    Thomas Dabay derives a way ofdoing so from Hume & Kant30 W hy Self-Interest M akes R elationships V aluable

    Daniel Tippens tells you how to be good to yourselfthrough others

    REVIEWS44 B ook:The M ost Good You Can Do by P eter Singer

    reviewed by Joel M arks

    46 B ook:Does Altr uism Exist?by D avid Sloan W ilson

    reviewed by W illiam Irwin

    48 Film:Good W ill Hunting

    Tams Szabados existential ly analyses a moving encounter

    REGULARS

    34 P hilosophy T hen:Eastern PromisesPeter Adamson looks at the ideas ofancient India

    35 B riefL ives:Colin W ilson

    Vaughan Rapatahana on the life ofa unique mind

    40 L etters to the E ditor

    50 T allis in W onderland:W hat A Possessive!

    Raymond Tall is ponders a peculiarity ofpersonhood

    POETRY & FICTION F ree?

    Peter Duffskewers the problem offree will in a single stanza

    54 ... as it was determined to be so.

    Short story by Kevin Heinrich

    Altruism, or not?

    Self-interest, p.30Books, p.46

    Nietzsche & DalPage 23

    BRAINCOGSISTOCK.COM/WILDPIXEL

  • 7/25/2019 Philosophy Now - March 2016.pdf

    4/56

    4 Philosophy Now F e b r u a r y M a r c h 2 0 1 6

    FeelFree To Differsplendid example in some detail in his intriguing essay.

    T here is no doubt that many of these softer versions of

    determinism are correct, to various degrees: the interesting

    debate concerns to what degrees, and so to what extent we can

    escape, for example, the chains of our D N A. Even the most

    ardent libertarian agrees that there are constraints on our

    freedom. W hat makes them libertarians is their insistence that

    the limitations dont deny some space for true, not physically

    determined, conscious choice between options.

    I think there are two major problems for hard determinists

    (and so also for compatibilists) to address. Firstly, How do you

    justify your assum ption that causation isonly physical,n otalso m ental?

    T he idea that minds cant choose is so far only an assertion by

    determinists, and one thats not justified in experience (and so isnot empirically sound), since all our experience of willing

    informs us that we do make choices, and that we do so effec-

    tively. So what sound basis exists for saying we dont choose?

    T he second problem is: Why w ould consciousnessevolve ifit

    doesnt do anything? On a more rigid determinism, our

    conscious states and our actions are the results of automatic

    brain activity; so our actions would be the same with just the

    brain activity and without the consciousness. H owever,

    consciousness is an expensive luxury, being created through

    specially-evolved, dedicated and energy-hungry brain areas (eg

    V 4-V 6 for colour vision). C onsciousness is evidently not just a

    fortuitous free side-effect of other brain activity, as some deter-

    minists misrepresent it. So why evolve it?

    I m not convinced that determinists can answer either of

    these questions adequately. B ut there are major problems for

    the libertarian too. C hoice is primarily about the minds

    content: its primarily the choice to think one thought one

    set of mental contents rather than another (this is true even

    when choosing to act). W e now have irrefutable neurological

    reasons to believe that brains produce (or channel)

    consciousness. T herefore, if libertarianism is true (as I choose

    to believe), then any choicesm ade by a m ind m ust also be a choice

    ofthe brain state underpinning the m ind state chosen. In other

    words, in choosing our mental contents, we must also choose

    the brain state responsible for the generation of those mentalcontents! So if there is free will, then there must be some way

    for a mind to direct the state of its brain, like a sort of local

    mind-over-matter. Its difficult to see how this could happen.

    (I personally think that the power of wil l operates through our

    choices being indirect observations of our brain states in a

    quantum manner. B ut thats a story for another time.)

    Enjoy this investigation of this fundamental aspect of human

    existence. I think the question of choice boils down to the

    question, can we make decisions in our minds that influence the

    state of our brains? I suggest that we do not know precisely

    enough how consciousness is generated by brain activity to

    answer that question authoritatively, yet. G rant B artley

    Welcome to our issue on free will. D id you choose to read

    this? Im not asking out of mere politeness or aston-

    ishment; the question, Isconsciouschoice real? is right at

    the core of a tangle of philosophical problems around free will.

    I f the answer is yes, you do choose, then your mind can decide

    what to think, and how you subsequently act, whether by

    speaking, or throwing a ball, or reading an editorial. T hat

    question is utterly different from the free will question that

    vexes theologians: Are we free if G od already knows everything

    well do? It is entirely consistent to say that we do choose, but

    G od knows what were going to choose. T hat would mean we

    have free will in one core way concerning choice but not in

    another way concerning, lets call it, our predictability. For

    this issues theme were interested specifically in issuessurrounding the power of choice.

    T here are three main positions concerning choice: libertari-

    anism ,determ inism ,and com patibilism . Take your pick!

    Libertarian ism is the belief that we make deliberated choices,

    which, through our brains, affect the material world, and that

    ultimately these choices are not absolutely determined by

    anything beyond the mind making them. Determ inism is the

    belief that all our choices are determined by factors beyond

    our conscious control. T he strong position says that through

    the brains processing of responses to environmental infor-

    mation, one brain state automatically causes a subsequent brain

    state, and conscious experience itself has no influence on the

    physical activities of the brain or the rest of the body.

    C om patibilism is an attempt to combine determinism with

    moral responsibility (it therefore presupposes determinism).

    V ersions vary, but the basic idea is that we simultaneously both

    are determined and somehow choose.

    D eterminism itself comes in different flavours. Hard deter-

    m inism of the most absolute sort is the theory that the entire

    history of the universe was already fixed from its very

    beginning by the setting of the laws of nature and the original

    states of the matter in it. T his is no longer tenable due to the

    intrinsic indeterm inacy the random behaviour at the heart

    of matter that is explored in quantum physics. B ut physics

    does apparently allow a somewhat less absolute determinism the idea that the behaviour of the world is determined by

    previous physical activities, but with some randomness as to

    what the particular outcomes will be. So a quantum deter-

    minist could defend an indeterministic determinism!

    T here are also softer determinisms. T hese say that we are

    very heavily influenced in our choices by factors beyond our

    control (and which we are often unaware of). O ne such soft

    determinism is genetic determinism, which says that who you

    become and what you do is inescapably influenced by your

    genetic make-up. I n his article in this issue, psychologist Steve

    Taylor lists several types of soft determinism before

    attempting to refute them; and Graham B oyd explores one

    E ditorial

  • 7/25/2019 Philosophy Now - March 2016.pdf

    5/56

    February/March 2016 PhilosophyNow 5

    Euthanasia for Children?Passive euthanasia, withdrawing or

    withholding treatment with the effect ofhastening a patients death, has long beenlegal in C anada. Active euthanasia, takingpositive measures to bring about a patientsdeath, will soon also be legal as per a deci-sion of the Supreme C ourt of C anada inFebruary 2 15 . A new public debate hasemerged in the wake of this step: Should

    the right to ask for ones own life to beterminated to be extended to children too?I t is not as strange a thought as it may

    seem: in the N etherlands euthanasia islawful for patients over the age of 12 , inB elgium for terminally i ll children of anyage if they are experiencing constant andunbearable suffering. T he consent ofparents and doctors is, of course, needed.D r E duard V erhagen is a lawyer and themedical director at the department ofpaediatrics at the U niversity M edicalC enter G roningen. H e argues that most

    children with a life-limiting illness, beforethey have even entered the terminal phase,have made decisions about their treat-ment, and about their lives 3 , 4 or 5times. A C anadian provincial-terri torialadvisory panel has now argued that accessto doctor-assisted dying should not behindered by the imposition of arbitraryage limits.

    Arthur C aplan, head of medical ethicsat N ew York U niversitys L angoneM edical C enter comments: Setting theprecedent that the state is going to tolerate

    killing children, even mature minors, isvery, very dangerous I ts the slipperyslope argument, and this is a slope I worryabout. Sometimes I dont, but this one Ido. T here is also serious opposition frommedical practitioners: M ost of our fight isabout kids that want to live ... not most ofour fight, all of our fight is about that, andhow to do it with as minimal suffering aspossible, says D r Stephen L iben, directorof the M ontreal C hildrens H ospital pedi-atric palliative care programme. T he lastthing I need as a pall iative care physician

    for children is a euthanasia law.

    Traditional Japanese Ethics ReturnsJapanese Prime M inister Shinzo Abe has

    taken steps to make traditional J apaneseethics a formal school subject from 2 18 .Japanese conservatives are on a quest torestore the values they say were rooted outduring the U S occupation after W orld W arI I . Part of an ongoing debate over nationalvalues and identity, the new teaching plansreflect their concern that Japanese people,

    especially the young, hold their owncountry and its history in low regard due toan over-emphasis in lessons on Japanswartime aggressions.

    T he foundations of the new ethicssyllabus will be the Imperial R escript onEducation signed by the Emperor M eiji in18 9 . T his document, once treated assacred by Japanese schools, stresses thedevelopment of a range of social virtuesincluding filial piety and loyalty to the state.T he guidelines are now being worked intotextbooks, ready to be used in new ethics

    classes taught in elementary and middleschools starting in 2 18 .

    Nadine and EdgarM eet N adine, an emotionally intelligent

    robot employed as a receptionist atN anyang T echnological U niversity inSingapore. She has her own personality,talks and behaves like a human, andexpresses emotions and change of moods asappropriate to topic and tone of the situa-tion. She can recognise people shes metbefore and remember what was said during

    previous conversations. T his is somewhatlike a real companion that is always withyou and conscious of what is happening,N adia T halmann, a robotics professorN T U s School of C omputer Engineering,argues in a press release. So in future,these socially intelligent robots could belike C -3 PO , the iconic golden droid fromStar Wars, with knowledge of language andetiquette.

    N ow meet Edgar, a tele-presence robotconstructed by the same team as N adine atN T U . H e can emulate the movements of

    his human user in real time. U sing a

    U niversity sc raps philosophy exam s

    Ethics teaching the M eiji way

    C anadians consider euthanasia for children

    N ew s reports by Anja Steinbauer.

    Newswebcam, he can be controlled fromanywhere in the world. H e can interactwith humans, sociably smiling and sayinghello and read a programmed script. T elepresence provides an additionaldimension to mobility, says engineeringprofessor G erald Seet. T he user mayproject his or her physical presence at oneor more locations simultaneously, meaningthat geography is no longer an obstacle.

    No More Exams!In a radical move, the U niversity of

    Essex is scrapping all philosophy exams: In the advanced study of a subject likephilosophy, we need to test students abilityto think in an original and creative way,rather than simply their power of recall ,argues Professor Fabian Freyenhagen,head of the universitys School of Philos-ophy in an article in The G uardian news-paper. Instead of cramming for exams,students will take extra modules in the

    summer term to pursue philosophical ques-tions in greater depth. T hey will demon-strate their learning through assessedcoursework; tests on unseen questions willstill be used in a few contexts, such asassessing logic skills.

    P h ilo s o phy No w FestivalW ed like to offer our deepes t thanks to all the

    speakers,volunteers and members ofthe public

    wh o took part in the 3rd Philosophy N ow F estival

    on 21 N ovember 201 5. Theres a picture gallery

    in the photos sec tion ofour Fac ebook page at:

    https://facebook.com/philosophynow and we areuploading videos to our YouTube channel.

  • 7/25/2019 Philosophy Now - March 2016.pdf

    6/56

    6 PhilosophyNow F e b r u a r y M a r c h 2 0 1 6

    from m any possible outcom es to o ne actualo utcom e takes place

    purely by chance.T he statisticald istribution for such chance

    events follow s strictrules,butthe o utcom e o fan individu al

    chan ce eventis unpredictable and cann ot be con trolled by w ill.

    Thus any decision is either the predictable resultofearlier causes

    (w hich m ay includ e quantum chance events)and is no tfree from

    determ inism ,or is itselfa qu antum chan ce event and is not

    w illed.E ither w ay,the free w illw e com m on ly take for granted is

    absent.Whatthen is the freedom to cho ose thatw e so cherish

    and w hich politicians like to invoke at every opportunity?

    Choice UnderDeterm inism

    In order to focus on the essen tialissues,let us put chance

    events aside,since,as w e have seen,qu antum rand om ness do esnot rescue free w ill.In this sim plified context,lets try to see

    w hether our subjective feeling of freedom can

    be reconciled w ith ph ysicald eterm inism .

    One thing w e cant avoid noticing is thatw e

    have the experience of m aking choices.In fact,

    each cho ice consists of tw o stages.In stage one

    w e conceive alternatives,an d in stage tw o w e are

    aw are that w e have picked on e ofthem .Often

    the option picked is the one w hose conse-

    quences w e prefer over the con sequences of its

    alternatives,b ut the com parison ofcon se-

    quences is notalw ays don e con sciously.Fu rther-

    m ore,bo th gen etic predispo sition s and past

    exp erien ces play a role in form ing an individuals

    preferences,so the cau sative factors leading to

    the m aking of a cho ice are com plex.Th e con -

    clusion is thatalthou gh w e do experience

    choice-m aking thattransition from stage one

    to stage tw o this doesntim ply the absence of

    determ ining causative factors.We also have the

    im pression that w e could h ave cho sen differ-

    ently.B ut on ce a choice has been m ade,w hat

    sense is there to this idea? T hatis,although a

    decision-m aker faced w ith the sam e setofalter-

    natives again m ay m ake a differentselection the

    second tim e,thatw ou ld b e because the overall

    situation,including the state of brain and m ind,

    has chang ed.B ut on ce again,this choice is the

    result ofprevious causes.Hence the existence of

    free w illin the sense ofan autonom ou s force at

    the very m om ent of decision un constrained by

    past causes,is notrequ ired to exp lain o ur actual

    experience ofchoo sing.Our experience of

    choice-m aking is perfectly com patible w ith

    determ inism ifw e accept thatthe transition

    from stage on e to stage tw o thatis,from m ul-

    tiple possible options to the one actually ch osen

    We com m on ly think it ob viou s that a person facing

    m ultiple alternatives can ch oo se any of them ,an d

    that the ou tcom e is decided by free w illat the

    m om ent of decision ,rather than b eing already determ ined b y

    earlier causes.Allthe even ts in the w orld,h ow ever,o bey the

    law of ph ysics,includ ing those that happ en inside a b rain.Ifall

    events in the brain unfold according to classicalphysics,then

    free w illin the ab ove sense d oes not exist.T his is becau se clas-

    sicalphysics is determ inistic:the state of the w orld at an y

    m om ent is the inevitable con sequen ce of its state atan earlier

    m om ent.H ence the alternatives are on ly apparently availab le to

    the d ecision-m aker,as in fact only a single alternative is des-

    tined to b e the on e cho sen.

    In quantum physics the so-called p robability am plitudeevolves according to determ inistic law s butthe transform ation

    Free W illIs An Illusion,

    But Freedom IsntChing-Hung W oo sa ys free dom is c ompa tible w ith choices be ing de termined.

    No t W ha t Th e y Se e m

    by Danelle Hellen Gallo

    GRAPHIC

    DANELLEHELLEN

    GALLO

    2016

    PLEASEVISIT

    W

    W

    W

    .ARTBYDANELLE.WEEBLY.COM

    r e e W ill

  • 7/25/2019 Philosophy Now - March 2016.pdf

    7/56

    February/March 2016 PhilosophyNow

    is, like any other kind of event in the world, the result of previ-

    ous causes.

    Once choice is properly understood in this way as being

    causally, physically determined we can proceed to consider

    the notion of free choice in wider ways. I f a man holds a gun to

    my head and demands my wallet, and I choose to obey him

    rather than to try and fight, thats a coerced choice. I n con-

    trast with this, we can say that a free choice is one that is not

    coerced. U ltimately, freedom in this sense depends on theabsence of conflict between the choice-makers nature, charac-

    ter, or core desires and the intended consequences of their

    actions. Since we are not averse to admitting that our nature is

    the result of our genetic predispositions and our past circum-

    stances, this notion of freedom can readily coexist with the

    hidden operation of physical determinism, and also with the

    fuller scientific worldview where physical determinism is sup-

    plemented by quantum randomness.

    Compatibilism & Moral ResponsibilityStill, how can I be respon siblefor the consequences of such

    free choices, when the chains of events that cause them weredetermined outside myself, beginning long ago? T he answer is

    hinted at in the word responsible. T he president of a nation

    may take responsibility for his administrations bad handling of

    relief work after a natural disaster, for example, even though he

    was not personally involved in any of the snafus occurring at the

    operational level. Analogously, although many aspects of my

    being pull me in different directions and argue with one another

    during the making of a difficult decision, there is a relatively

    stable center that I identify as my self, and this recognition means

    that I can take or own the responsibility for each decision thats

    made by me, even through or after the competition of all these

    factors. T his is an appropriate expediency, since the detailed

    tracing of all the responsible factors is practically impossible.

    T he nature of the self is obviously complex. Some people

    have a narrow sense, and some an expansive sense, of the

    responsible self, and even the same persons self-perception may

    change over time. Or for example, a drug addict caught in a

    crime may claim M y habit made me do it! In so saying hes

    treating his habit as if its not a part of him. H owever, in ponder-

    ing his responsibility, the jury ought to take into consideration

    whether his habit was formed with his knowledge or without it

    (it might sometimes be a result of taking medicine his doctor

    prescribed). In other words, the jury should assign responsibility

    for the crime not just on the basis of whether the recent crimi-

    nal act was itself a completely uncoerced choice, but also on

    whether some past free acts of the accused contributed to him

    being in a state where he committed the present crime.

    In contrast to this addict, some people discover room for

    freedom that is, for choices compatible with their nature

    even when theyre under strong coercion. W hen H enry D avid

    T horeau was jailed for refusing to pay the poll tax, he felt hewas still free because his mind could go anywhere, and, as he

    observed dryly, his mind constituted all that was dangerous.

    And J ean-Paul Sartre claimed that Frenchmen were never

    freer than when France was under the N azi occupation. H ow

    so? W ell, the occupation created opportunities for defiance,

    and whether to risk defiance or not is a significant choice;

    hence Frenchmen were freer in the sense of possessing a

    richer menu of significant choices. T he wiggle room allowed

    under coercion, however, is not always large enough for a

    choice to be meaningfully called free. Sophies choice, in

    W illiam Styrons novel of that title, was to sacrifice one of her

    children or the other to the gas chamber. R easonable people

    would regard the alternatives offered to her by the N azi doctoras not much of a choice at all, and absolve Sophie of any

    responsibility for the death of the non-chosen child.

    Adopting the absence of coercion instead of the absence of

    determinism as the essence of freedom gets us out of a conflict

    with the prevalent scientific worldview. N onetheless, this

    notion still captures the importance of freedom as a condi-

    tion that enables a person to be true to himself, and also as a

    criterion for judging whether it is fair to hold a person respon-

    sible for their actions.

    PROF. CHING-HUNG WOO 2016

    The late C hing-Hung Woo w as for m any yearsP rofessor ofP hysics

    at the Un iversity ofMaryland.

    In X anadu did Kubla Khan a stately pleasure dome decree...

    Samuel Taylor Coleridge became addicted to laudanum (opium dissolved

    in alcohol) as a result of being prescribed it by his doctor for toothache.

    So was he entirely responsible for this poem written under its influence?

    Free?

    Are c hoice s free ly ma de jus t a s it s ee ms

    Or do the atom s c hoose for us inste ad?

    Do pe ople jus t re sp ond or inte rvene ?

    By choice illusions are w e e ac h misled?

    Ifnow Ichoos e to w ork ins te ad ofplay

    Is tha t bec aus e tha t impulse is m ore s trong?Else w hat de cides w hich impulse will hold swa y?

    Are w e the move rs or jus t move d a long?

    And w hen d ec idedly Iam resolved

    To take s ome course ofac tion come wha t may

    Wa s Iobs e rving or w as Iinvolved

    In tha t de cision in the prope r wa y?

    Despite the doubts , Imus t be lieve I'm fre e

    Acce pting that Iam too nea r to se e.

    PETER DUFF 2016

    Peter Du ffisa solicitor w ith a sm allpractice in B lackrock,

    C oun ty Du blin.For m ore,visit hisdaily poem site at

    dailypoem.net/index.php/about-daily-poem/.

    Fre e Will

  • 7/25/2019 Philosophy Now - March 2016.pdf

    8/56

    8 Philosophy Now F e b r u a r y M a r c h 2 0 1 6

    scious fashion. B ut for this to be the case, one would have to

    exist prior to that choice, with a certain set of preferences

    about how to choose ones preferences in a reasoned and con-

    scious fashion. And so it goes on. I t seems then that being the

    sort of person one is, having the desires and beliefs one does, is

    something over which we cannot have ultimate control its

    only the result of our upbringing, etc. And ones life and all one

    does is an unfolding of non-self-chosen preferences. So ulti-

    mately speaking, one is not free in any meaningful sense.

    D eterminism is not the problem with responsibil ity, then;

    rather, its the incoherence of the libertarian quest. As Strawsonsays, True self-determination is impossible because it requires

    the actual completion of an infinite regress of choices and prin-

    ciples of choice (Freedom and B elief, 19 8 6 , p.2 9 ) .

    W hat is striking about this is that since the argument didnt

    appeal to determinism, it seems that the problem that has been

    the bane of the free wil l debate can be dispensed with. T his

    realisation opens up a whole new avenue of investigation.

    D eterminism is moot, but this does not mean that the issue of

    moral responsibility is also dispensed with. R ather the question

    becomes something like I s moral responsibility compatible

    with the ultimate absence of libertarian free wil l?

    Strawsons approach to this question is to take the same line

    as the hard determinist: he concludes that moral responsibility

    is impossible, and hence that it would be wrong to praise or

    blame anyone on account of his or her actions. In response,

    Professor Saul Smilansky, author of Free Willand Illusion

    (2 0 0 0 ), claims that Strawson demonstrates the impossibility of

    libertarian free wil l, but not of moral responsibil ity; even

    though libertarianism is incoherent so that ultimate responsi-

    bility eludes us, there still remains the real and important com-

    patibilist sense in which we are free to act and so can take

    responsibility for our actions. For the compatibilist, distin-

    guishing between an action that was coerced and one that was

    conducted with autonomy is relevant to the way we should

    treat the agent. C onsider Adam, B eryl and C heryl. Adam stealssomething whilst B eryl does not. C heryl also steals, but is a

    kleptomaniac. T he hard determinist perspective hold all

    There has been a recent surge of interest in the old

    problem of free will. B ut away from time-worn

    debates over the questions Are we free? and Are

    we morally responsible? some fresh waters are at

    last in reach. As I will show, some progress can be made here

    by putting the age-old problem of determinism aside and by

    giving up the libertarian ghost. T his will leave us open to

    asking new, clear and sensible questions in a debate that is

    surely close to everyones heart.

    Traditionally, conflicting positions on free will have

    diverged and defined themselves according to the question:Are free will and moral responsibility compatible with deter-

    minism? I t does seem that we are free to act, if our choice is

    not the result of external coercion and reflects our own desires,

    beliefs and deliberations. T his is enough for compatibilists to

    grant us moral responsibility for these actions and declare that

    free will is compatible with determinism.

    H owever libertarians are steadfast in their plea for persons

    to be truly deserving of praise and blame. If determinism is

    true then the situations in which we make our choices, and the

    desires and beliefs upon which we base them, are the inevitable

    result of chains of cause and effect starting long before our

    births. So in what sense can we be truly responsible for them?

    To secure the libertarian quest for moral responsibility it is

    required that a person is self-determined, rather than merely

    not physically determined by something else or the result of

    chance. B ut as Galen Strawson has demonstrated, any

    attempts at establishing this will lead to a self-defeating infi-

    nite regress.

    C onsider that a choice or free action must be done for a

    reason to be non-arbitrary. T he reason can be in the form of

    principles, preferences or values. B ut if someone is responsible

    for their actions, they must act in accordance with principles,

    preferences or values they themselves have freely chosen: that

    is, one must be responsible for the preferences upon which

    one acts. T he question must then arise, where do these prefer-ences come from? In order to be responsible for our prefer-

    ences, etc, they too must be chosen in a reasoned and con-

    The New Argum ent

    AboutFreedomNatasha Gilbertsays out with the old arguments,and in with the new.

    True self-determ ination is im possible because itrequires

    the actualcom pletion ofan infinite regress ofchoices

    and principles ofchoice.

    Galen Straw son,Free dom a nd Bel ief

    Free Will

  • 7/25/2019 Philosophy Now - March 2016.pdf

    9/56

    February/March 2016 PhilosophyNow 9

    morally equal as morally unresponsible. From the compati-

    bilist perspective, however, since both Adam and B eryl were

    able to resist, yet only B eryl did, there are grounds for holding

    Adam responsible. However, since C heryl is a born kleptoma-

    niac, we have reason to distinguish her from Adam. D espite

    some potential ultimate injustice in holding Adam responsible

    and punishing him, to hold C heryl responsible and punish her

    would be much more unjust. I n fact, the failure of hard deter-

    minism in distinguishing between such cases shows its inade-

    quacy.I t has been shown that determinism need no longer be our

    main concern in considering moral responsibility, since the

    problem over it arises whether determinism is true or false.

    T he futile search for l ibertarian free wil l can also at last be laid

    to rest. I have tentatively suggested what seems the most fruit-

    ful avenue of investigation from this point: this is also Smilan-

    skys suggestion, to start from the collapse that results from

    the realization of the absence of libertarian free will and its

    implications, and then reconstruct the free will related concep-

    tual world on the basis of the shallower compatibilist

    resources (from a personal correspondence).

    A revolution is occurring in the debate on free will that

    requires the renouncement of instinctively-held ideals and

    beliefs. T he first step is to renounce the idea that the central

    problem concerns determinism. T his will in turn pave the way

    for the truth about libertarianism to be seen. G iving up liber-

    tarianism, however, isnt a step to be taken lightly, since it

    encapsulates the kind of freedom we normatively think we

    have and need. T he greatest obstacle therefore, is going to be

    whether people can live with the truth concerning free will.

    NATASHA GILBERT 2016

    Natasha G ilbertisa freelance journ alist.She has an MSc in the

    P hilosophy ofScience from the London SchoolofEconom ics.

    G alen Strawson, (19 8 6 ) Freedom and B elief, Oxford U niversity Press.

    I SB N -13 : 9 78 - 0 19 9 2 475 0 9

    Saul Smilansky, (2 0 0 0 ) Free Willan d Illusion, O xford U niversity Press,

    I SB N -13 : 9 78 - 0 19 8 2 5 0 18 0

    Finding out more

    Free W ill

  • 7/25/2019 Philosophy Now - March 2016.pdf

    10/56

    rational,slow,and controlled system ofthought,where we

    reason through ouroptions. (Form ore aboutthese systemsof

    thought,seeT hin k in g F a s a n d S lo ,DanielKahnem an,2011.)

    Tucked away in the centre ofthe brain,System 1 m onitors

    the environm entone way oranotherto m inim ize risk to sur-

    vivaland m axim ize reward. Feedback continually updatesthe

    system aboutthe environm ent. The em otionalresponse system

    evaluatesallthe incom ing sensory inform ation,and then scores

    itfora winner-takes-allcom petition to decide on the best

    response. My contention in thisarticle isthatSystem 1 inter-

    acting with incom ing sensory inform ation runseverything.

    There isno room forany hom unculushere.

    The detailsofthe processare intriguing. Allincom ing sense

    data are converted into a com m on cerebralcurrency,placedinto context,assessed fortheirpredicted risk orreward value in

    the em otionalbrain,and the likely errorofthatassessm ent. T he

    resultsare then ranked in whatI have dubbed em otion scores,to

    allow disparate information to be com pared untila successful

    com petitorforstim ulating a response em ergeswithin the

    system . Thisdecision and choice mechanism isquantitatively

    quite precise (see m y O n S t r e ssD is a s a n d E v olu t io : A U n ifyin g

    T h o y ,2012,to see justhow precise:e p in tsu t a s ed u .a u / 1 2 6 7 1 / ).

    Nota bad start?Then welcom e to the world ofSystem 1.

    Butofcourse you willnow go and spoilthingsby asking:

    W hataboutthe capacity forrationalthought?Can thatbe

    accom m odated within thisway ofthinking?

    W ell,actually,yesitcan,butin a rathercom plex way.

    T h e R a t ion a l B r a i n

    Itisnow clearthatthe two system sfordecision-m aking in

    m an operate so-called dualprocessm onitoring(see for

    instance De Neysand G lum icic in C o n it io Vol. 106,2008). I

    see the m echanism forthisdualprocessing being asfollows. If

    atany tim e a certain threshold foralerting System 1 isnot

    exceeded,judgem entiswithheld,and the m ore deliberative,

    rationalSystem 2 m ay com e into play. Nonetheless,the intu-

    itive,em otionalsystem stilltendsto strongly dom inate. De

    Neysand G lum icic have found thatsubjectsstruggle to over-

    ride the instinctive em otionalrisk/reward brain responses,since

    rationalthoughtoptionsoften do notreceive enough cerebral

    weightto prevailoverthe choicesofthe em otionalbrain.

    My suggestion forhow to understand thatisasfollows. The

    em otionalbrain alwaysharveststhe bestoption forresponse as

    the one having the highestrisk/reward em otion score,w he t h r

    t his s o e is d e r iv e d p im a r ily f r o t h e m o io a l b r a in o in d ir e c t ly

    v ia t h r a t io a l b r a in . Ifnothing above a certain threshold ispro-

    duced from the prim ary analysisofthe incom ing sensory infor-

    m ation by the em otionalsystem ,then analysisisswitched to the

    slowerdeliberationsofthe rationalsystem . But and heresthe

    rub the eventualrisk/reward score calculated isnotestim ated

    prim arily through a rationalranking,butrather,isbased on the

    Recently I wastrying to explain to an intelligentwom an the problem of

    trying to understand how itiswe perceive anything atall,and I wasnot

    having any success. She could notsee why there wasa problem . Finally in

    despairI asked herhow she herselfthoughtshe saw the world. She replied

    thatshe probably had som ewhere in herhead som ething like a little televi-

    sion set. So who,I asked islooking atit?She now saw the problem

    im m ediately. F.H . Crick,in S c ie n t if ic A m e r ic a n ,1979

    The firstquestion to be answered is:W ho orwhatisrun-

    ning the show?In Part1 I willattemptto explain

    hum an decision-m aking withoutthe need fora hidden

    hom unculus. Part2 willthen go on to look athow the brain can

    operate within thisenvironm entto generate the im pression of

    an individualbeing driven by a highly consciousself.The argum entsoverwhathasbecom e known asthe m ind-

    body problem go back atleastto Ren DescartesSeventeenth

    Century dualistview thattheresm ind stuffand body stuff

    and the two are quite separate,the m ind stuffbeing ethereal.

    In the face ofallthe neuroscience data accum ulated since

    Descartestim e,I view thisasa truly em barrassing stance to

    take in the Twenty-FirstCentury,so the firstpartofthisarti-

    cle willbe concerned with seeing ifwe can getaround it. I

    think we can. My approach isa tad autocratic and the conclu-

    sion equally radical,so be warned.

    Letslook firstlook athow the brain m akesitsdecisions.

    P a r t 1 : D E C I S I O NS

    There are two m ajorwaysofprocessing inform ation facili-

    tated by the hum an brain. I hold thatalldecisionsare m ade by a

    risk/reward com parison ofthe incom ing sensory inform ation

    within the em otionalbrain (System 1 thinking)ratherthan

    within the rationalbrain (System 2 thinking). System 1,the

    em otionalsystem forprocessing sensory inform ation and gen-

    erating responsesto itaccording to a risk orreward weighting,

    isautom atic,intuitive,and fast,even im pulsive. System 2 isthe

    1 0 Philosophy ow February/March 2016

    T h e B r a i n s R i s k / R e w a r d S y s t e m M a k e s O u r C h oic e s

    Not U sG r a h a m W B oy d argues

    that choice is an illusion.

    B A S E ju m p i n g :

    T h e e m ot ion a l b r a i n i n a c t ion

    SAM

    LAMING

    BASEJUMPING

    BEACHYHEAD

    S

    AM

    LAMING.SEE

    FACEBOOK.COM/LAYINGONTHESKY

    Fre e Will

  • 7/25/2019 Philosophy Now - March 2016.pdf

    11/56

    risk/reward value ofthatresponse to thee m oio a l brain. More-

    over,because ofthe way the brain works,the emotionalscore of

    rationaldeliberationsislikely to often be lessthan rating from

    any analysisprim arily through the em otionalsystem . In effect

    then:R a t io a l op io s a r e c hos n if a n d o ly if t h e m o io s o e s t h y

    e v o e in t h e v a lu a t io o t h e m o io a l b r a in a r e hig h e n o g h tob e a t

    t h s o e s o a n y m o e in t u it iv e c o p t it o r e spo s s.

    The situation here iscom plex. Ittakestim e and trouble to

    allocate em otionalrisk/reward scoresto rationalsystem

    response optionsso thatthey can com pete in the em otional

    brain. Actually,given the m agnitude and com plexity ofthe task

    involved,the wonderisthatrationaloptionseverm anage to get

    converted into having com petitive em otionalrisk/reward scores

    atall. Allthatthe rationalsystem would have to go on would be

    pastexperience;and atbest,thatwould m erely be analogousto

    any presentsituation ratherthan precisely the sam e m eaning

    thatthe processofconverting rationaloptionsto em otional

    risk/reward optionswilloften lead to an underestim ation of

    theirpersuasiveness. By contrast,the em otionalbrain hasan

    innate strength and createscorrespondingly strong options

    because ofitslong evolutionary history ofdevelopm entto aidsurvival. Thissystem isnoteasily overcom e. Thiswould

    explain why deliberationsaboutr a t io a l optionsoften carry less

    weight. In effect,System 2 isgenerally lessassertive. Itisalso

    circum spect,and lazy (see Kahnem an,p.44).

    The upshotofallthisisthatifany assessm entofany situation

    by the em otionalbrain scoresabove threshold atfirstpass,it

    decidesthe response withoutdeliberation being required. Butif

    not,an option on the sam e inform ation through the r a t io a l

    m ode ofthoughtcan stilloccasionally win on being converted

    back to a em otionalbrain score. Itsem otionalscore can im prove

    with experience and training to eventually prevailin specific

    cases. Thisiswhatlearning logic isallabout. Forexam ple,once

    ithaslearned the value ofVenn diagram sin solving som e logic

    problem s,the rationalbrain can use Venn diagram thinking in

    others. So the rationalbrain m ay be lessassertive,butaspectsof

    itm ay be m ore trainable than em otionalbrain processes,caus-

    ing them to eventually dom inate and be preferred in particular

    cases. HoweverI hold that,in the end,they willbe usefulin

    reaching decisionsonly ifthey have enough appealin the em o-

    tionalbrain to outbid theirm ore intuitive rivals. Putanother

    way whetherwe like itornot,we choose rationaloptionsonly

    insofarasthey are judged to be potentially m ore em otionally

    rewarding than theirintuitive rivals in essence,only ifour

    rationaldeliberationsfeelbetter. (O fcourse,rationaloptions

    can be ofvalue in m aking decisionseven when they m erelyin f o m the intuitive decision-making process.)

    Letstake a breath,because thispointaboutthe em otion

    scoring ofrationaloptionsisnoteasy,and I wantto m ake sure

    itisgrasped. The whole em otion scoring system Ive described

    I see asbeing eventually based entirely on the long-established

    evolutionarily-derived intuitive,risk-reward em otionalinfor-

    m ation-processing system 1. Everything would be a lotsim pler

    ifoptionscould be ranked fortheirrationality,and then

    allowed to com pete directly with intuitive optionsfrom the

    em otionalsystem . Butthatisnothow itworks:the only scor-

    ing system available isthatbased on the em otionalresponses

    evoked within the risk/reward system ,so optionsarising from

    the rationalsystem need to have theirrationalscoresconverted

    to em otionalscoresbefore they can com pete. In the situations

    described,they occasionally do;butoverall,the em otionaltail

    wagsthe rationaldog (Kahnem an,p.140). Incidentally,there

    isno reason to think thatany ofthisevaluation need be carried

    outata consciouslevel.

    A u t on om y of D e c i s ion - M a k i n g

    Allthisbearsdirectly on the question:Can the whole

    system run autonom ously thatis,with ourresponses,even

    ourthoughts,being determ ined e n t ir e ly by the sensory input

    interacting with the em otionalbrain?

    Indeed itcan. The brain hasno need ofany hom unculusor

    remote-controltelevision viewerto drive it. And thatisby far

    and away the m ostim portantconclusion I have to offerhere.So how com e italllooksso m uch otherwise so m uch asif

    we are in controlofourreactionsasconsciousselves?Letm e

    now try to convince you thatthe selfisan artificialconstruct

    thatself-consciousnessisthe productofthe brain interacting

    with incom ing inform ation in the way Ive justdiscussed,and

    thatallthistogethergivesthe false im pression ofprim ary con-

    sciousnesswith an active selfin charge.

    P a r t 2 : C O NS C I O U S NE S S A ND T H E S E L F

    Following Benjam in Libetssem inalstudies(originally pub-

    lished in B e ha v io a l B r a in S c ie n c esVol.8,1985),itisclearthat

    February/March 2016 PhilosophyNow 1 1

    DETERMINISM

    RULES

    JACK

    HODGES

    2016

    PLEASE

    VISIT

    WWW.JACKHODGES.TUMB

    LR.COM

    Fre e Will

  • 7/25/2019 Philosophy Now - March 2016.pdf

    12/56

    consciousnessislate on the scene ofany brain activity. This

    m eansthatconsciousnessisan epiphenom enon:itisproducedby brain activity,butdoesnotitselfinfluence brain activity.

    G iven this,I suggestthatfinaldecisionsfrom the brain are

    sim ply f e d in t oa constructwe callthe self.

    Allgetsa bitcom plicated here,so letslook atthe selffirst.

    T h e S e l f

    There are generally held to be two sortsofselves:the

    bodily self,orself-as-object;and the first-person self,the

    innerI,the 'self-as-subject supposedly the selfin active

    charge ofeverything m eaning thatthe individualexperiences

    thatthe highestlinguistic deliberationsofthe brain are

    referred foroutputto thisinnerself-constructasifto an

    active self-as-subject. However,I suggestthatthisfirstperson

    self-as-subjectconstructisnotatallactively in charge ofvoli-

    tion,attention and decision-making in the way we experience

    and so profoundly believe itto be. Instead,culture,especially

    language,play a large partboth in thisselfsdevelopm entand

    in ourillusion thatithascontrol.

    The way I see everything developing isasfollows.

    Asthe child m aturesand getsa grasp oflanguage,society

    expectsherto be accountable forheractions a controlling

    self-as-subject.Butthere isno such active selfcontrolling

    everything:the brainsconsciousoutputisdetermined entirely

    by the com petitive risk/reward em otion-scoring system (s)I

    described. Above this,there rem ainsonly the individualwithherpassive innerself-construct thatisherexperience of

    being a selfthathasbeen created through otherbrain activity.

    Nonetheless,given socialpressure,the child m ustrespond

    appropriately. She doesso in the only way she can by

    unwittingly allowing herpassive innerself-constructbe

    form ed a sif itwere the active selfin charge. Again though,the

    apparently active nature ofthisnewly deem ed self-as-subject

    isillusory. There isno inneractive selfdriving thoughtand

    behaviour justa passive innerself-constructto which allof

    the higherbrainslanguage-based output(including rational

    choice)isreferred forownershipto m ake itseem thatthere

    is,and in the processsatisfy socialexpectations.

    S e l f - C on s c iou s n e s s

    From thisI also suggestthatthe acquisition oflanguage

    skillsisvitalforestablishing yetanotherlayerofhigherhum an

    brain functioning self-consciousness.

    Fora hum an being to achieve herm axim um potential

    awarenessofthe outside world,she m ustlearn the language

    skillsofherculturalgroup. T hisgiveshera highly sophisti-

    cated m eansofprocessing inform ation to understand and

    describe the world including nam esforvariousentitiesand a

    grasp ofthe value ofm odelsand m etaphorsin com ing to term s

    with difficultnew concepts.

    O nce the sense ofself-as-subjecthasbeen constructed,the

    individualisin possession ofa robust(iffalse)sense ofan

    active innerI. Itthen becom esnaturalforthisconstructto

    appearto own the language-based higherbrain outputtoo. I

    suggestthatwhen thishappens,thatbrainsoutputbecom es

    whatwe callself-consciousand the illusion iscom plete:it

    then appearscertain to usthatwe are a true active innerselfin

    charge ofthe stream ofconsciousness the very hom unculus

    watching and controlling the television screen. Self-conscious-

    nessisthusseen here asbeing essentially an em ergentfeatureofthe grounding ofalllanguage-based higher-brain outputin

    the self-as-subject. Itisa state ofawarenessofthe world so

    heightened overthatofnon-linguistic creaturesthatitis

    deem ed to warrantthe distinctterm self-consciousness. The

    m ore thatsociety and the world are experienced and learned

    overtim e via such com m unication,the m ore self-conscious-

    nesseach individualattains. Yetfrom thisperspective,neither

    self-consciousnessnorthe self-as-subjectplaysany role in the

    creation ofthought. They are entirely secondary,non-causal

    phenom ena resulting from higherbrain activity the effect

    and notthe cause ofthe way the world becomesknown,of

    how the individualcom esto be with knowledge(con-scious).

    Allthisisnotto say thatthose withoutlanguage are notcon-

    sciousin som e way. ItsjustthatI see self-consciousnessasa state

    ofawarenessso heightened by language thatitdeservesto be

    distinguished from it. By thisreckoning,anim alawarenesscould

    include a lowerlevelofconsciousness. Also,the m ore com m uni-

    cation an individualm asters,the m ore awareness-and eventu-

    ally self-consciousness isattained. Itsalla m atterofdegree.

    These,then,are m y views.

    Challenging?W ell,thatsthe whole point.

    C on c l u s i on

    The brain m akesitsdecisionsvia itsem otion-scoring

    risk/reward system interacting with sensory inputfrom theenvironm ent,with itsoutputsbeing m uch lessrationalthan we

    think. Inputsfrom the rationalsystem occasionally receive suf-

    ficiently high em otion scoresto successfully com pete. This

    system hasno need ofany m ysteriousCartesian m ind to drive

    it. The selfand self-consciousnessare both passive constructs,

    although societysinteraction with the individualdeterm ines

    thatthey com e to be viewed otherwise. So thatsit allwith

    apologiesto Descartes,ofcourse.

    P R O F . G R A H A M W . B O Y D 2 0 1 6

    T he la t e G r a ha m B oyd w a s E m e r it u s Pr o e sso o M e d ic in e a t the

    U n iv e r sit y o T a s a n ia , a n d a n H o o a r y R e s a r ch F e llo in t he

    D e p r t m e n t o M e d ic in e a t the U n iv e r sity o W e s e r n A u s r a lia .

    1 2 Philosophy ow February/March 2016

    MIND

    CONFERENCE

    P

    ETER

    PULLEN

    2016PLEASE

    VISIT

    WWW.PETERPULLEN.COM

    T h e e m ot ion a l a n d t h e

    r a t ion a l m i n d i n d e b a t e

    Fre e Will

  • 7/25/2019 Philosophy Now - March 2016.pdf

    13/56

    February/March 2016 PhilosophyNow 13

    I t is natural, Aristotle argues, for humans to acknowledge

    akrasia. I ndeed, he argues for two different kinds of akrasia.

    T he first is motivated by impetuosity, or more specifically, pas-

    sion, which can cause a lapse in reason allowing a person to be

    led away from what they (still) believe to be good actions.

    T his analysis seems more reasonable than Platos approach,

    as it explains many scenarios, such as the heroin example: the

    intense pleasure brought about by such substances can cause a

    lapse in reason. H owever, examples of suchakrasia

    are by nomeans limited to addiction, or even pleasure. O ther types of

    passion, such as anger, can also hinder our judgement.

    C onsider a heated argument. T hings are often said in the

    heat of the moment that are clearly not fully thought through:

    those involved might digress into petty insults, and go too far.

    In this case, the person is so blinded by anger that they act

    without a reasonable consideration of the consequences of what

    theyre doing the insult is swiftly pushed out of ones mouth

    by ones ego, rather than being properly assessed by ones super-

    ego, we might say. In his Nichom achean Ethics(3 5 0 B C E ), Aris-

    totle compares these instances to hasty servants who run out

    before they have heard the whole of what one says, and then

    muddle the order. T he servants do not properly evaluate theiraction they simply do it without stopping to think.

    In her Essayson AristotlesEthics(19 9 2 ), Am lie R orty exam-

    ines the extent to which these ideas are similar or dissimilar to

    the Platonic/Socratic perspective. I n R ortys view, Aristotle

    stands the Socratic diagnosis of akratic ignorance on its head.

    She says that rather than a person being misled by pleasure

    into ignorance of whats good, Aristotle contends that a

    persons ignorance causes them to be misled by pleasure. Per-

    haps it is no surprise that Aristotle therefore reaches the oppo-

    site conclusion that akrasia does, in fact, exist.

    T he second type of akrasia Aristotle details is caused by

    w eakness. I n contrast to the passionate person, the weak person

    Almost all heavy smokers are well aware of the likely

    consequences of their tobacco tendencies. M any even

    concede that it would be best to give up the habit. Still,

    a large proportion of these people cannot help but continue to

    smoke, in spite of their better judgement. B etween puffs of

    nicotine and regret, they may ask themselves, W hy do I con-

    tinue to smoke when I know it would be better not to? One

    response to this question although not one in everyday terms

    is that smoking is an akraticaction. Akrasia comes from the

    G reek for lacking control of oneself, and it means to act

    against ones better judgement.

    The Platonic/Socratic ResponsePlatos dialogue P rotagorasaddresses a more general incarna-

    tion of the smokers question. T here Platos spokesman Socrates

    asks, if one judges a certain behaviour to be the best course of

    action, why would one do anything else? T he conclusion that

    Socrates draws is that people will only ever choose the perceived

    best course of action, since no-one goes wil lingly towards the

    bad. T hat is to say, for Socrates, akrasia does not exist. R ather

    wrongdoing stems from ignorance of what exactly is good, not

    someone consciously doing what they know to be wrong. So his

    view is that if someone actually believed that they should stop

    smoking, they would do so with ease. Socrates does allow that

    the person who apparently acts against their better judgement

    will say that its because theyre overcome by the pleasure their

    action provides. Yet to him this is a self-contradiction, since

    their argument actually translates into: I knew that act was bad,

    but I was overcome by my perceiving the good of it.

    Socrates argument here fatally relies upon the acceptance

    of a fairly large false assumption: that goodness and pleasure

    are the same. H is argument cannot work if one rejects the

    notion that goodness and pleasure are interchangeable.

    L et us spare smokers the limelight briefly, and turn to the

    example of the heroin addict. H eroin provides the user with

    enormous amounts of pleasure; but this is not the same asheroin addiction being good. R egardless of the pleasure

    induced, can abuse of a substance that results in such a high

    likelihood of death by overdosing, or choking on ones vomit,

    or through severe damage to ones veins, ever be considered

    good? W hilst there may be no definitive philosophical answer

    to this, it makes Socrates/Platos viewpoint questionable, at

    the very least.

    Aristotles ResponseAristotle disagrees with Plato about akrasia. H e takes an

    approach more in line with actual experience than his teachers

    purely theoretical angle.

    AkrasiaWhy Do We Act Against Our Better Judgement?

    George Singleton a sks w hy w e splash out on luxurie s w orth a months incom e,

    s truggle to g ive up smoking, and resort to below-the-be lt insults in hea ted a rgume nts.

    Fre e Will

  • 7/25/2019 Philosophy Now - March 2016.pdf

    14/56

  • 7/25/2019 Philosophy Now - March 2016.pdf

    15/56

    February/March 2016 PhilosophyNow 15

    fore unchosen desire to increase our reproductive success, or

    else is the instinctive result of traits selected and developed in

    our ancestors because they provided some survival advantage.

    So the reason why some of us feel driven to gain success in

    fields like politics and creativity, is because success makes us

    more attractive to the opposite sex, and so increases our repro-

    ductive possibilities; or, for example, according to Steven

    Pinker, the reason we find lush countryside landscapes beautiful

    is because for our ancestors such vistas represented a plentiful

    supply of resources to foster their survival, so nature selected

    those who were drawn to such landscapes.

    In much neuroscience, brain activity that is, the behaviour

    of neuronal networks and brain chemicals play a similar

    causal role to genes. Your moods, your desires, and yourbehaviour, are determined by the levels of various brain chemi-

    cals such as serotonin or dopamine, or by the automatic activa-

    tion of neuronal networks which predispose you to certain

    traits or impulses. If you feel depressed, its because of a low

    level of serotonin. I f you are psychopathic, its because areas of

    your ventromedial prefrontal cortex are less active than

    normal. I f you are a B orn Again C hristian, its because you

    have a smaller than normal hippocampus. (T he latter two are

    actual neuroscientific hypotheses.)

    T hese versions of both contemporary gene theory and neu-

    roscience are what might be called cant help approaches: we

    cant help being depressive, psychopathic, religious, racist,

    polygamous (if you are a male), and so forth, because our genes

    have programmed us to be so, or because we have been biolog-

    ically burdened with the brain chemistry or neural networks

    associated with that behaviour.

    Harnessing Free WillW hat is the root of these assaults on our autonomy? W hy

    do intellectuals and scientists feel such a strong impulse to

    show us that we are powerless, controlled by forces beyond our

    own control?

    Perhaps its an unconscious desire to abdicate responsibility.

    Perhaps the modern world has become so complex and stress-

    ful that scientists and philosophers feel an impulse to retreatfrom responsibility, to pretend that we have no control over

    the chaos. I wouldnt go so far myself, but a conspiracy theorist

    might argue (and some already have) that this autonomy-denial

    is a form of oppression an attempt by the intellectual elite to

    keep us down, convincing us that we are powerless so that we

    wont challenge their authority. M ore rationally, the rash of

    free will denial may be related to the desire to prove that there

    is no self. Free will is, of course, one of the strongest features

    of the self. I f you believe that inside our mental space there is

    no one there that our sense of self is just an illusion, which

    itself is a mere side-effect of neurological processes then you

    have to believe that the selfs free will is an illusion, too.

    One of the main trends of recent academic culture has

    been to take freedom and autonomy away from human

    beings. I dont mean that professors armed with guns

    have been locking up their intellectual opponents; I mean that

    from sociology to philosophy, from psychology to neuro-

    science, a common theme has been to try to show that our free

    will is either severely limited or non-existent, and that we have

    much less control over our own lives than wed like to believe.

    I t was one of the central beliefs of behaviourist psychology.

    You might feelas if you are free, making your own decisions

    and choices, but in reality everything you do, or think, or feel,

    is the result of environmental influences. Your behaviour is just

    the output or response to the input or stimuli which your

    brain has absorbed and processed. Freudian psychology alsoemphasized the lack of free wil l. I t suggested that your con-

    scious self is just one small facet of your whole psyche the tip

    of the iceberg and that its activity is determined by your

    unconscious mind, which includes instinctive and other auto-

    matic biological drives beyond your conscious control

    B y contrast, existentialist philosophy and humanistic psy-

    chology emphasised human autonomy, asserting that choice is

    one of the defining characteristics of human life, even if it isnt

    necessarily a positive faculty. According to S ren K ierkegaard,

    the sheer extent of our freedom may induce a state of disorien-

    tation and dread, and we make our choices in fear and trem-

    bling. Similarly, Jean-Paul Sartre believed that the freedom to

    choose courses of action without fully controlling or even

    knowing their consequences contributed to human anxiety. I n

    his famous phrase, we are condemned to be free. And in reac-

    tion to behaviourism and Freudian psychology, humanistic psy-

    chologists such as Abraham M aslow and C arl R ogers asserted

    that human behaviour is not necessarily determined by our past

    and present experiences, since we always have the capacity to

    make choices based on our assessments of current situations.

    H owever, in sociology, there was a movement towards the

    denial of autonomy. T heorists argued that your sense of self is a

    social construction and that people are necessarily formed and

    exist inside a nexus of social influences which determine their

    lives. L inguistic theorists also argued that our view of reality iscreated through and limited by our language. W e cannot see

    beyond the assumptions in the framework of the semantic and

    grammatical structures we have absorbed from our parents and

    our cultures.

    Gene Theory & NeuroscienceM odern genetics and neuroscience often deny our autonomy

    in a much more direct way. According to geneticists such as

    R ichard D awkins, we our bodies and minds exist as carriers

    for our genes, to enable them to survive and replicate. Every-

    thing we do is determined by and is on behalf of our genes. Our

    behaviour is either the result of our own instinctive and there-

    Reclaiming FreedomSteve Taylorsays of determinism:Irefute it thus!

    Free Will

  • 7/25/2019 Philosophy Now - March 2016.pdf

    16/56

    16 PhilosophyNow F e b r u a r y M a r c h 2 0 1 6

    Yet no matter what the motivation, one is tempted to reply

    to these assaults on free will in the same way that the eigh-

    teenth century author D octor Johnson responded to George

    B erkeleys arguments that matter was a mental phenomenon:

    he shouted I refute it thus! as he kicked a stone. Johnson

    could have used the same method to illustrate the denial of

    determinism and his capacity for free will . I ts difficult for

    anyone to persuasively argue that we dont have free will when

    our everyday experience is that there are always a variety ofchoices of thoughts and actions in front of us, like a pack of

    cards spread for us to pick from, and we feel we have the free-

    dom to choose any of them, and to change our minds at any

    point. After all, whenever you read a book or listen to a lecture

    claiming that there is no such thing as free will, youre free to

    close the book, or to throw a rotten tomato at the lecturer.

    One of the problems is that scientists, and philosophers,

    often tend towards absolutism. Geneticists may argue that

    behaviour is com pletely determined by our genes; neuroscien-

    tists that behaviour is com pletely determined by brain activity;

    social constructionists and behaviourists may argue that social

    and environmental forcescom pletely determine our behaviour,and so forth. B ut in my view, its more sensible to be democra-

    tic than absolutist: its likely that all of these factors have som e

    influence on our behaviour. T hey all affect us to some degree.

    B ut none of them individually, nor all of them together, are

    completely dominant.

    I believe the same is true of free wil l. T he conscious self is

    not an authoritarian dictator; but it isnt a slave either. R ather,

    our free will is another factor or force amongst this chaotic

    coalition of influences. T he upshot of that is that no matter

    what social and environmental forces influence me, no matter

    what genes or brain structure I ve inherited from my parents,

    I m in here too, and I can decide whether to kick the stone or

    not, and, generally speaking, how I react to the world.

    Freedom Strikes Back

    Interestingly, some popular neuroscientific ideas about the

    limitations of free wil l are being contradicted by neuroscience

    itself. For instance, recent research has shown that rather than

    being fixed, our brain structure is very flexible, and continuallychanging: the brain is not hard-wired but soft-wired. T he rela-

    tively new field of neuroplasticity shows that practicing habits

    or behaviours brings real physical changes to the parts of the

    brain associated with those activities. For example, if you begin

    to learn to play the piano, you will develop more neural con-

    nections, and perhaps, through the process of neurogenesis,

    even more brain cells themselves, in the parts of the brain asso-

    ciated with motor activity the motor cortex and cerebellum

    and musical perception in the temporal lobes. O r if you medi-

    tate regularly for years, you will develop more gray matter in

    the areas associated with attention, concentration and compas-

    sion in the frontal lobes. So in this sense, rather than beingcompletely controlled by our brains, we have control over them .

    R igid determinism in gene theory is similarly contradicted

    by recent findings in genetics. T he field of epigeneticsshows

    that the genetic structures we inherit from our parents dont

    remain fixed throughout our lives either, but are altered by our

    life experiences, so that the biology we pass on to our children

    will be different from that we inherited. For example, experi-

    ments training mice to develop an aversion to a particular

    smell have shown that this aversion was genetically passed

    down to their offspring, who became two hundred times more

    sensitive to the smell than other mice. T his new behaviour is

    reflected in changes to both the genes and brain structure of

    the mice. Similarly, in human beings, studies show that twins

    exposed to very different environments and experiences show

    striking differences in their D N A in later life. Or, in a Swedish

    study of the descendants of a population which endured

    famine in the N ineteenth C entury, it was found that the men

    had inherited a much stronger than normal resistance to car-

    diovascular disease, whilst those women descended from

    women who had been exposed to the famine while in the

    womb had a shorter than average life span.

    One application of these findings would be to actively take

    responsibility for our genes, knowing that the health and well-

    being of our descendants depends on them. W e could make a

    conscious effort to live positively, to be free of trauma andstress, and undergo as many positive and rich experiences as

    possible, to ensure that the genetic inheritance we pass on is as

    ideal as possible. I t could be said that we have the capacity to

    control our genes rather than them just controlling us.

    Increasing Free W ill

    I would argue that one of the most important tasks of our

    lives is to develop more free wil l and autonomy. I n fact, a pri-

    mary way to develop positively and begin to live more mean-

    ingfully is to transcend the influences of our environment to

    become more oriented towards who we authentically are.

    As humanistic psychology suggests, we have innate poten-

    Free W ill

  • 7/25/2019 Philosophy Now - March 2016.pdf

    17/56

    February/March 2016 PhilosophyNow 1

    tials and characteristics that are independent of external factors,

    even if this aspect of us may be so obscured from us that we can

    barely see it. To humanistic psychology, our task is to allow that

    part of us to express itself more fully which often means over-riding adverse cultural and social influences. T he same thinking

    applies to genes and brain chemistry too. T hey may predispose

    us to certain types of behaviour, but we can resist those influ-

    ences, to control and even re-mould our behaviour. I ts by no

    means easy, but we can overcome our programming. W e dont

    have to blindly follow the environmental, genetic and neuro-

    logical instructions we were born with. W e can with resolve

    increase the quotient of autonomy with which we were born, to

    the extent that it becomes more powerful than our genetics,

    neurology, or the environment. (Strangely, despite his other-

    wise apparently rigid genetic determinism, D awkins agrees with

    this assessment of our potential, stating that humans are the only

    beings who have the power to ignore the dictates of their genes.)

    Paths To AutonomyPerhaps many people do seem to be largely the products of

    their environments and biological inheritance. B ut I would

    argue that whatever the term greatness means, it is usually

    manifested by those who have exercised their autonomy to a

    considerable degree, to significantly free themselves from exter-

    nal influences. T hese are usually people who have used their

    strong wil l-power to harness their autonomy and self-discipline

    to expand themselves and develop a high level of skill and

    expertise, to actualise their innate potential, and so become

    more than the sum of their influences.

    In a sense, this is only an extension of what every human

    being ideally does as they move from childhood to adulthood: to

    develop more self-control and autonomy. As we move through

    childhood, with the help of our parents, we hopefully begin to

    control our impulses and desires. For example, we learn that we

    cant have everything exactly when we want it, and so learn to

    delay gratification, developing self-control. As we need less care

    and attention from our parents, we exercise more autonomy,

    learn to make more decisions for ourselves and to follow ourown interests and goals. In this sense, human development is a

    process of becoming less bound by biological and environmental

    influences and gain more free will and autonomy. And ideally,

    this process should continue throughout our lives.

    Spiritual development can also be seen as a process of gaining

    increased autonomy. For example, many Eastern spiritual tradi-

    tions, such as B uddhism or yoga, place great emphasis on self-

    discipline and self-control: control of our own behaviour, so that

    we no longer cause harm to others; control of our desires, so

    that we no longer lust after physical pleasures; control of our

    thoughts, so that we can quieten the mind through meditation,

    and so on. I n some traditions, spiritual development is seen asa process of taming the body and mind, and this is, of course,

    only possible through intense self-discipline, requiring self-

    control. Although it can sometimes occur suddenly and spon-

    taneously, the deep serenity and intensified awareness of spiri-

    tual awakening is usually the culmination of a long process of

    increasing our innate quotient of personal freedom to the

    point where our minds become the dominant influence. W hen

    spiritually awakened people are referred to as masters, this

    could easily refer to them as being masters of themselves.

    In W estern philosophy, Friedrich N ietzsche meant some-

    thing similar with his concept of self-overcoming. N ietszche

    spoke disparagingly of the U ltimate M an, who is completely

    satisfied with himself as he is and strives only to make his life

    as comfortable and pleasurable as possible. B ut in reality, says

    N ietzsche, human nature is not fixed or finished. H uman

    beings are part of an evolutionary process not a goal, but a

    bridge a rope fastened between animal and Superman

    (Thu sSpake Z arathustra, 18 9 1). T he potential Superman is the

    human being who is not self-satisfied, who has the urge to

    overcome himself. For him, life is an attempt at bridging the

    gulf between animal and superman.

    Liberating FreedomW e all possess a degree of freedom, and we all have the

    capacity to extend the degree of freedom were bequeathed to become less dominated by our genes, our brain chemistry,

    and the society and wider environment into which were born.

    W e are all potentially much more powerful than we have been

    led to believe, even to the extent of being able to alter or even

    control the forces that have been supposed to completely con-

    trol us. And to a large extent our well-being, our achievements

    and our sense of meaning in life depend on this. T he more you

    exercise and increase your freedom, the more meaningful and

    fulfill ing your life will be.

    DR STEVE TAY LOR 2016

    Steve Taylor isa Senior Lecturer in P sychology at LeedsB eckett

    University,U K.

    Find freedom in and

    through your mind

    Fre e Will

  • 7/25/2019 Philosophy Now - March 2016.pdf

    18/56

    verse and are preserved foralleternity. I n a passage which m ay

    provide uswith som e solace,Leibniz elaborated thatA natural

    m achine can neverbe absolutely destroyed justasitcan never

    absolutely begin,butitonly decreasesorincreases,enfoldsor

    unfolds,alwayspreserving in itselfsom e degree oflife [ it a lit a s]

    or,ifyou prefer,som e degree ofprim itive activity [ ct u osita s]

    ( n B o y a n d F o c e , A g a in s the C a r t e sia n s,1702).

    Crucially,Leibnizstheory oforganism providesuswith an

    insightinto the kind ofparadoxicalinfinity which drove

    m uch ofhisthoughtprocess,and which he deployed

    throughouthissystem . From hislinguistic investi-

    gationsto hishistory ofthe Earth,infinity for

    Leibniz isneverabstractorquantitative,butthor-

    oughly em bodied,continuous,and infinitely

    nested (exceptin hism athem aticalinvestigations,

    where he intentionally adoptsa fictitiousreadingofinfinity forpracticalpurposes). In itsincarnation

    in thisway,infinity cannotbe disassociated from

    som e kind ofunity. AsLeibniz him selfoften conceded,

    My m editationsturn on two things,nam ely unity and

    infinity. Indeed,within divinely-inspired reality,the connec-

    tion between infinity and unity wasnotone ofsim ple

    dichotom y,butofinterdependence and variety. Indeed,even so-

    called finitehum an creatureswere infinite in theirown way.

    Leibnizstheory oforganism isalso em blem atic ofhis

    broaderm o u sop r a n d i,which involved shunning radicaldistinc-

    tionsin favourofsubtle variations. Farfrom rejecting m echa-

    nism outofhand,Leibniz co-opted it,reworking itto suithis

    own purposes. Forhim ,organism referred to an organizational

    principle ratherthan a particularily biologicalsortofstuff:

    O rganism ,thatisto say orderand artifice,issom ething essen-

    tialto m atter,produced and arranged by the sovereign wisdom .

    (Leibniz,Philosophica l L e t t e r s,volIII,ed C.I . G erhardt,p.340).

    Living beingswere thussubjected to a particularvariety of

    m echanism ,which unfolded infinitely and dynam ically. Ulti-

    m ately,in the infinite subtlety oftheirartifice, natural

    m achineswere borne outofdivine wisdom ,which itselfwassep-

    arated from usby an im m ense distance ( e w S ys e m o N a t u r e ).

    Leibnizsunderstanding oforganism would be echoed m any

    yearslaterby the physicistErwin Schrdingerin the finalsec-

    tion ofhisfamous1944 essay,W ha t is L if e ? ,which addressedThe Relation between Clockwork and O rganism :

    Itneedsno poetic im agination butonly clearand soberscientific reflec-

    tion to recognize thatwe are here obviously faced with eventswhose regu-

    larand lawfulunfolding isguided by a m echanism producing events

    which are a paragon oforderliness. W hetherwe find itastonishing or

    whetherwe find itquite plausible thata sm allbuthighly organized group

    ofatom sbe capable ofacting in thism anner,the situation isunprece-

    dented;itisunknown anywhere else exceptin living m atter.

    A U D R E Y B O R O W S K I 2 0 1 6

    A u d r e y B o o s i g r a d u a t e d f r o O x f o d a n d is d oin g a PhD in the

    H is o y o I d e a s S he s in t e r e s e d in t he his o y o lin g u is ic t ho g ht .

    Farfrom shunning the infinite ashisphilosophicalprede-

    cessorsPascaland Descarteshad done,G ottfried W il-

    helm Leibniz (1646-1716)em braced and celebrated it,

    seeing itasa m ark ofthe divine. According to him ,the infinite

    permeated reality,in the m icroscopic aswellasin the infinitely

    large,in such a m annerthatevery particle ofthe universe

    containsa world ofan infinity ofcreatures (Leibniz,C olle c t e d

    P p r sa n d L e tt e r s,Series6,Volum e 4,1647-8).

    Leibniz waswriting ata tim e ofintellectual

    upheaval. The early Seventeenth Century had

    ushered in an era ofscientific discoveriesand

    innovations an era in which m e cha n is ,as

    exem plified by c lo k w o k ,had emerged asthe

    privileged conceptualtoolthrough which to

    elucidate and grasp the cosm os,the state,

    and even the hum an body. T he applicationofthism echanized world picture to life was

    pioneered by Ren D escartes,who in hisT r e a -

    t is o M a n of1637 effectively equated living

    bodiesto com plex autom ata. D escartescould see

    no difference between the m achinesbuiltby artisans

    and the variousbodiescom posed by nature alone. (p.50).

    Leibniz feltthatthe m odernshad erred in ascribing this

    godlessm odelto life itself. He setoutto restore the unique-

    nessoflife by positing thatin f in ity wasitsdefining feature. For

    Leibniz,even in theirsm allestpartsorganism swere m achines

    and therefore were m achinesa d in f in it u m ,akin to onions

    thatcould neverbe com pletely peeled. O rganism spreserved

    theirinfinitely nested m echanicalstructure,and always

    rem ained the same m achine throughoutthe variouschanges

    they underwent,being m erely transform ed through different

    enfoldings. (Leibniz,N e w S ys e m o N a t u r e ,1695). Moreover,

    only the particularkind ofinfinity displayed by naturalorgan-

    ism syielded true unity which unity in turn endowed them

    with sensation,perception and consciousness(Letterto Sophie

    and Elizabeth Charlotte,November1696). Each wasanim ated

    by an alwayssubsisting unity (ib id a prim itive com m unica-

    tionsnetwork which also expressed the activity ofallthe

    m achinesnested in it,unfolding in concertwith them . W ithin

    thism echanism ,both m aterialand spiritualrealm sdeveloped

    in perfectcorrespondence whilstneverdirectly interacting,in

    pre-established harmony. By contrast,even the m ostartfully

    assem bled artificialm achine could neverhope to overcom e its

    essentialstate ofbeing aggregated from parts. So m ore than

    three centuriesbefore debatessurrounding artificialintelli-

    gence,Leibniz had already warned ofthe inherently noncon-

    sciousnature ofartificialm achines:although they m ight

    behave asifanim ated by a unifying spiritualforce,they would

    stillbe essentially soulless.

    The infinitely entangled structure ofnaturalm achinesalso

    foundstheirindestructibility. Birth and death em erge asm ere

    developm entsand envelopm entsofa vastliving m achinery

    which,while im perceptible to us,radiate throughoutthe uni-

    1 8 Philosophy ow February/March 2016

    L e i b n i z t h e In f in it e M e c h a n is m of L i f e

    A u d r e y B or ows k i peers into the infinity inside all organisms,including us.

    L e i b n iz

  • 7/25/2019 Philosophy Now - March 2016.pdf

    19/56

    February/March 2016 PhilosophyNow 19

  • 7/25/2019 Philosophy Now - March 2016.pdf

    20/56

    valuesto us. Becom ing som eone isprincipally (butnotonly)a

    collectivistthing;asKwam e Appiah says,the individualiden-

    tity islikely to have whatH erderwould have seen asa national

    identity asa com ponentofitscollective dim ension ( h E thicso

    I d e n t it y ,2005). So although Herderdoessee thateach person

    hasan originalway ofbeing hum an and thathe oughtto be true

    to him self(a basic existentialistidea),he also seesthatan essen-

    tialpartofa personsidentity ishanded down to him through his

    culture,and istherefore nota m atterofchoice.

    ForHerder,each nation isseparate,distinguished by cli-

    m ate,education,custom ,tradition,and heredity. He claim s

    thatProvidence wonderfully separated nationalitiesnotonly

    by woodsand m ountains,seasand deserts,riversand clim ates,

    butm ore particularly by languages,inclinationsand charac-

    ters. He emphasized the im portance ofnationalculture in theform ation ofonesidentity and nature by saying,he thathas

    losthispatriotic spirithaslosthim selfand the whole world

    abouthim self whilstteaching thatin a certain sense every

    hum an perfection isnational.

    So forH erder,becom ing som eone involvesa person grow-

    ing and learning to fully identify with hisorherculture and

    values. Thatisa large partofa personstruenature. He

    attachesgreatim portance to culture and also nationalidentity,

    astransm itted through language thatm ostbasic and essential

    ofallhum an capacities.

    The processofpassing on valuesoccursin fam iliesatfirst.

    By teaching children language,a fam ilysm annerofthinking

    and setofvaluesare developed and preserved in them . Then

    valuesare passed on through largerunitssuch asschools,and

    eventually through societiesornations,the largestunitsthat

    identify with the language. Each com m unity ornation hasits

    own language,unique tradition and history,which shapesthe

    livesand values,the artand ideas,the activitiesand leisure pur-

    suitsofitsinhabitants itsculture and m akesthem the

    people they are givesthem theiridentity.

    To a certain extentH erderisanticipating the Sapir-W horf

    hypothesisthatlanguage determ inesthoughtand behaviour. In

    1929 Edward Sapirsaid,T he factofthe matteristhatthe

    realworldisto a large extentunconsciously builtupon the

    language habitsofthe group. N o two languagesare eversuffi-ciently sim ilarto be considered asrepresenting the sam e social

    reality. The worldsin which differentsocietieslive are distinct

    worlds,notm erely the sam e world with differentlabels

    attached... W e see and hearand otherwise experience very

    largely aswe do because the language habitsofourcom m unity

    predispose certain choicesofinterpretation. (From a 1929

    article entitled The StatusofLinguisticsasa Sciencein L a n -

    g u a g e Vol5,No 4). Thism ould theoryoflanguage doesnot

    justsay thatourthoughtsare determ ined by ourlanguage,but

    thatourvery culture,valuesand waysofperceiving the world

    are m oulded by the language in which we learn them ,and that

    ourability to think outside the culture istherefore lim ited,if

    O

    ne question abouthum an nature iswhetheritisthe

    sam e forallpeople atalltim es,orwhetheritisfunda-

    m entally differentin differentculturesorhistorical

    periods. The argum entthatitiseverywhere the same is

    im plicitin the evolutionary view,since we allshare com m on

    ancestors;butithasa longerpedigree than that. Platos

    accountofthe soulassum esthatitappliesto allm en;H um e

    believed thatmankind isso