passerin.pdf

Upload: rorro-proof

Post on 02-Jun-2018

217 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/10/2019 passerin.pdf

    1/17

    Legality and LegitimacyAuthor(s): Alexander P. d'EntrvesSource: The Review of Metaphysics, Vol. 16, No. 4 (Jun., 1963), pp. 687-702Published by: Philosophy Education Society Inc.Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/20123969.

    Accessed: 07/01/2015 13:14

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at.http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    .JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of

    content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms

    of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    .

    Philosophy Education Society Inc.is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The

    Review of Metaphysics.

    http://www.jstor.org

    This content downloaded from 200.75.10.74 on Wed, 7 Jan 2015 13:14:22 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=peshttp://www.jstor.org/stable/20123969?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/20123969?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=pes
  • 8/10/2019 passerin.pdf

    2/17

    LEGALITY

    AND

    LEGITIMACY

    *

    ALEXANDER P.

    D'ENTR?VES

    JLhe purpose of this

    paper

    is to examine the

    meaning

    of two

    key-words

    in

    political theory

    which,

    as

    their

    very

    roots

    indicate,

    are

    first

    and foremost

    legal

    words?words

    drawn

    from the vocab

    ulary

    of

    law,

    not

    of

    politics.

    The

    subject

    of

    legality

    and

    legitimacy

    presents

    the student

    of

    law

    and

    politics

    with

    a

    semantic

    puzzle

    to

    which

    it

    is

    not

    quite

    easy

    to

    find

    a

    clear and

    definite

    answer.1

    We all

    know

    of

    course

    more

    or

    less

    what

    the

    answer

    of

    the

    historian

    would

    be

    if

    we

    turned

    to

    him

    alone

    for

    enlightenment.

    He

    would,

    to

    be

    sure,

    begin

    by

    pointing

    out

    that

    throughout

    Western

    history

    the

    two

    notions

    of

    legality

    and

    legitimacy

    have

    played

    an

    important

    part

    in

    political

    thought,

    providing

    as

    it

    were

    two of

    its

    most

    solid

    pillars.

    Without

    reaching

    as

    far

    back

    as

    the

    Greeks,

    the

    historian

    would

    probably

    recall

    to

    our

    attention

    the

    distinction,

    current

    in Medieval and

    Renaissance

    thought,

    between

    the

    two

    criteria

    for

    establishing

    the

    rightfulness

    of

    political

    power.

    Power,

    in

    order

    to be

    "just,"

    must

    be

    both

    legitimate

    and

    law

    abiding.

    Accordingly,

    the

    unjust

    ruler

    or

    tyrant

    may

    be

    defined

    ex

    parte

    exercitii

    as

    well

    as

    ex

    defectu

    tituli. His rule

    can

    be

    unjust

    for the

    manner

    in

    which

    it

    is

    exercised,

    if

    he

    does

    not

    keep

    within the bounds of legality. But it can also be unjust, and is

    inevitably

    so,

    if it

    lacks

    that

    proper

    "title"

    which confers

    legi

    timacy

    upon

    it.

    The

    quest

    for

    that

    title,

    namely

    for

    the

    ultimate

    *

    A

    paper

    read

    to

    the

    Law

    School

    Faculty

    at

    Yale

    on

    December

    6,

    1962.

    1

    The

    only

    specific

    treatment

    of the

    subject

    I

    know

    of

    is

    C. Schmitt's

    little

    essay,

    Legalit?t

    und

    Legitimit?t

    (1932).

    Written

    by

    a

    Nazi

    supporter

    on

    the

    eve

    of

    the

    Nazi's

    seizure of

    power,

    it

    obviously

    presents

    a

    strongly

    biassed

    picture

    of

    the

    issues

    which the

    subject

    involves. I

    have

    attempted

    to

    clarify

    these issues in an article

    published

    in 1960

    ("Legalit?

    e

    legittimit?",

    in Studi

    in

    onore

    di

    E.

    Crosa,

    vol.

    II)

    and

    in

    my

    recent

    book,

    La

    dottrina

    dello Stato

    (Torino,

    1962).

    This content downloaded from 200.75.10.74 on Wed, 7 Jan 2015 13:14:22 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 passerin.pdf

    3/17

    688

    ALEXANDER

    P.

    D'ENTR?VES

    foundation

    of

    authority,

    has

    long

    been

    the

    main

    concern

    of

    polit

    ical

    theory.

    Some

    among

    us are

    old

    enough

    to

    remember

    the

    time

    when

    dynastic

    legitimacy

    was

    still

    an

    accepted

    doctrine

    in

    Europe.

    In

    our

    day,

    legitimacy

    is

    rarely

    invoked,

    and does

    not

    seem

    to

    be

    any

    longer

    an

    intelligible

    political

    principle.

    Yet

    there

    is

    still

    one

    European

    statesman

    who

    does

    not hesitate

    to

    use

    it

    as

    a

    prop

    for his

    political

    doctrine,

    if

    he

    has

    any.

    Shortly

    after

    his

    accession

    to

    power,

    President

    de

    Gaulle

    made

    the

    startling

    claim

    that

    "for

    twenty

    years"

    he

    had been

    "the

    incarnation

    of national

    legitimacy."

    Some of

    his

    recent

    actions

    seem

    clearly

    to

    evince

    the view

    which

    he

    once

    candidly

    expounded

    to

    an

    American

    visitor:

    that

    "legitimacy

    does

    not

    depend

    on

    legality,

    and

    legality

    is

    not

    necessarily

    a

    proof

    of

    legitimacy."

    2

    So much

    for

    history

    and

    the historian's contribution to

    our

    problem.

    Let

    us

    now

    turn

    to

    the

    social

    and

    political

    scientists.

    They

    too

    have

    an

    answer

    to

    our

    quest;

    the

    notion

    of

    legitimacy

    is

    a

    fairly

    familiar

    one

    in

    their

    writings.

    They

    use

    it to

    illustrate

    the

    transition from the level of power to that

    authority. "Authority,"

    in

    Mr.

    Lasswell's

    words,

    "is the

    expected

    and

    legitimate

    possession

    of

    power."3

    Borrowing

    a

    phrase

    which

    was

    first

    coined

    by

    a

    fellow-countryman

    of

    mine

    at

    whose

    feet

    I sat

    as

    a

    student?Gae

    tano

    Mosca?modern

    political

    science indicates

    that "the

    source

    and

    basis

    of

    legitimacy"

    is the

    "political

    formula":

    the

    body,

    that

    is,

    of

    accepted

    beliefs

    and

    values

    (also

    called

    the

    ideology)

    which,

    in

    a

    given

    society,

    induce

    men

    to

    obedience

    and

    to

    the

    acceptance

    of

    the

    exercise of

    power

    as

    "just

    and

    proper."

    This

    at

    any

    rate?if

    I

    do

    not

    misinterpret

    his

    words?is

    the

    view which Mr.

    Lasswell

    puts

    forward

    in his classic book

    Power

    and

    Society.

    In

    a

    language

    more

    involved and

    obscure,

    Mr. Talcott

    Parsons defines

    "legitima

    tion"

    as

    "the

    appraisal

    of

    action

    in

    terms

    of shared

    or

    common

    values

    in the

    context

    of the

    involvement

    of

    the

    action in

    the

    social

    system."

    4

    One

    may

    wonder

    why

    this

    kind

    of

    appraisal

    should

    be

    referred

    to

    legitimacy

    rather

    than

    to

    legality.

    The

    answer

    may

    be,

    2

    Article

    by

    D.

    Sch?nbrun

    in New

    York Times

    Magazine,

    Feb.

    14,

    1960.

    3

    H.

    D.

    Lasswell

    and

    A.

    Kaplan,

    Power and

    Society

    (New

    Haven,

    1950),

    S 6.5.

    4

    T.

    Parsons,

    "Authority,

    Legitimation,

    and

    Political

    Action",

    in

    Authority,

    C. J.

    Friedrich,

    ed.

    (Cambridge,

    Mass.,

    1958),

    p.

    201.

    This content downloaded from 200.75.10.74 on Wed, 7 Jan 2015 13:14:22 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 passerin.pdf

    4/17

    LEGALITY

    ND

    LEGITIMACY 689

    perhaps,

    that

    political

    scientists

    are

    concerned

    with

    the

    actual

    behavior of

    men

    rather than with the

    formal

    framework of

    their

    actions.

    At

    any

    rate,

    they

    seem

    to

    leave the

    problem

    of

    legality

    to

    the

    lawyer,

    and for

    my

    part

    I

    would

    certainly

    not

    be

    inclined

    to

    blame

    them

    for

    doing

    so.

    But

    this

    places

    upon

    the

    lawyer

    a

    further

    duty

    to

    clarify

    the issue

    of

    legality

    versus

    legitimacy.

    It

    is

    precisely

    at

    this

    point

    that

    we are

    reminded of

    some

    famous remarks by a no less famous social scientist. Max Weber

    has left

    us a

    brief

    but

    fascinating

    treatment of the

    problem

    of

    legality

    and

    legitimacy.5

    Legitimacy,

    or,

    to

    use

    his

    own

    words,

    "the

    idea

    (Vorstellung)

    of the

    existence

    of

    a

    legitimate

    order,"

    is

    to

    him

    a

    basic

    tool

    of social

    research,

    for

    it

    is

    from

    this

    concept

    that

    the

    notion

    derives,

    of

    the

    "validity"

    of

    a

    given

    social

    order.

    According

    to

    Weber,

    history

    presents

    us

    with

    three

    basic

    types

    of

    validation

    or

    legitimation?though

    he

    warms

    us

    that

    these

    types

    are never

    "pure,"

    and lend

    themselves

    to

    manifold

    "combinations,

    mixtures,

    adaptations

    and

    modifications."

    These

    types

    are:

    ?

    "Charismatic"

    legitimacy,

    where

    the

    authority

    of

    a

    single

    individual is ascribed

    to

    the

    special

    gifts

    with

    which he is

    endowed,

    or

    believed

    to

    be

    endowed,

    as

    in the

    case

    of

    a

    prophet

    or a

    hero

    (or

    for

    that

    matter,

    though

    Weber

    wrote

    before

    Nazism,

    a

    F?hrer])

    ;

    ?

    "Traditional"

    legitimacy,

    where

    authority

    is

    derived

    from

    the sacredness

    of

    precedent

    or

    from

    dynastic

    succession;

    ?

    "Rational"

    legitimacy,

    where

    authority

    is

    based

    on

    "a

    system

    of

    consciously

    made rational rules

    (which

    may

    be

    agreed

    upon

    or

    imposed

    from

    above),

    which

    meet

    with

    obedience

    as

    generally

    binding

    norms

    whenever such

    obedience is claimed

    by

    him whom

    the

    rule

    designates."

    This

    type

    of

    legitimacy

    Weber

    identifies

    with

    legality.

    In

    it,

    "every

    single

    bearer

    of

    powers

    of

    command

    is

    legitimated

    by

    the

    system

    of

    rational

    norms,

    and

    his

    power

    is

    legitimate

    in

    so

    far

    as

    it

    corresponds

    with the

    norms.

    Obedience

    is

    thus

    given

    to

    the

    norms

    rather

    than to

    the

    person."

    5

    The

    relevant

    sections

    from

    Weber's

    Wirtschaft

    und

    Gesellschaft

    can

    be found

    in Max Weber

    on

    Law

    in

    Economy

    and

    Society,

    M.

    Rheinstein,

    ed. (Cambridge, Mass., 1954), pp. 3, 9, 336-337; but see also Weber's Wirt

    schaftsethik

    der

    Weltreligionen,

    in

    Gesammelte

    Aufs?tze

    zur

    Religions

    Soziologie,

    vol.

    I, pp.

    267-268.

    This content downloaded from 200.75.10.74 on Wed, 7 Jan 2015 13:14:22 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 passerin.pdf

    5/17

    690

    ALEXANDER

    P.

    D'ENTR?VES

    Now the

    interesting

    point

    about

    Weber's treatment of

    legality

    and

    legitimacy

    is

    that,

    in

    his

    view,

    legality

    is

    the

    prevailing

    type

    of

    legitimacy

    in

    modern

    society.

    "Today,"

    he

    writes,

    "the

    most

    common

    form

    of

    legitimacy

    is

    the

    belief

    in

    legality,

    i.e.,

    the

    acquiescence

    in

    enactments

    that

    are

    formally

    correct

    and

    which

    have been

    made

    according

    to

    established

    procedure."

    Most

    modern

    societies,

    Weber

    points

    out,

    and

    more

    particularly

    the

    modern State, are "legal" societies, societies where "commands

    are

    bestowed

    not in the

    name

    of

    a

    personal

    authority,

    but

    in the

    name

    of

    an

    impersonal

    norm;

    and

    [where]

    in

    turn

    the

    exercise

    of

    command

    is

    in

    itself obedience

    to

    a

    norm,

    and

    not

    an

    arbitrary

    decision,

    a

    dispensation

    or a

    privilege."

    In

    short,

    we

    live

    in

    a

    world

    where

    the

    rule

    of

    law

    is

    supreme

    or

    is

    expected

    to be

    so;

    where obedience is

    given

    to

    the

    laws,

    not

    to

    the

    persons.

    We

    have

    de-personalized

    power,

    thus

    tracing

    the

    roots

    of

    authority

    to

    law

    itself,

    not to

    some

    mystical

    principle

    that transcends

    it.

    Personally,

    I think

    that

    Weber's

    remarks contain

    a

    great

    amount

    of

    truth

    and

    that

    they

    shed

    a

    great

    amount

    of

    light

    on

    the

    question

    at

    issue.

    I

    am

    prompted

    to

    this conclusion

    not

    only

    by

    the fact

    that,

    every

    time

    I

    have

    asked

    the

    lawyers

    to

    tell

    me

    the

    difference

    between

    legality

    and

    legitimacy,

    I have

    noticed

    some

    embarrassment

    on

    their

    part,

    as

    if

    my

    question

    seemed

    to

    them

    meaningless

    or

    out

    of

    context.

    But

    I

    am

    also inclined

    to

    agree

    with

    Max Weber

    on

    historical

    grounds,

    since

    I believe

    that

    the

    greatest

    contribution

    which

    legal

    theory

    has

    made

    to Western

    political

    thought

    was

    to

    enable

    us

    to

    read

    politics

    in

    legal

    terms,

    and to conceive of power, and if you like of the "State," as the

    exercise

    not

    of

    arbitrary

    force

    but

    of lawful

    authority.

    In

    this

    sense

    the

    Anglo-American

    notion of

    the

    rule of

    law,

    as

    well

    as

    our

    Continental doctrine of the

    Rechtsstaat,

    are

    political

    as

    well

    as

    legal

    theories:

    theories in which

    the

    best

    tradition of

    Western

    thought

    have combined

    to

    produce

    that

    notion

    of

    a

    "legitimate

    order,"

    of

    a

    State based

    on

    law,

    which

    we

    consider

    one

    of the

    highest

    achievements

    of

    our

    civilization. The

    rule

    of

    law,

    not

    the

    old idea

    of

    dynastic

    allegiance

    nor

    the modern horrors

    of

    the

    F?hrerprinzip,

    is

    the

    bond that holds modern societies

    together.

    As Dean Pound once

    put

    it in a

    humourous

    vein,

    the modern man's

    notion

    of the

    State

    may

    well

    be

    expressed

    with

    a

    paraphrase

    of the

    This content downloaded from 200.75.10.74 on Wed, 7 Jan 2015 13:14:22 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 passerin.pdf

    6/17

    LEGALITY

    AND

    LEGITIMACY

    691

    Psalm:

    "Propter

    legem

    tuam

    sustinui

    te,

    Domine "?"Because

    of

    thy

    law

    am

    I

    content

    with

    thee,

    o

    State."

    6

    Legality

    seems

    indeed

    to

    have

    become,

    as

    Weber

    said,

    the

    modern

    equivalent

    of

    legitimacy.

    Now

    the

    question

    which

    I

    would

    like

    to

    raise

    at

    this

    point

    is

    a

    very

    simple

    one,

    but

    one

    which

    seems

    to

    me

    to

    be of the

    utmost

    importance.

    The

    question,

    to

    put

    it

    in

    strictly

    analytical

    language,

    iswhether by subsuming the notion of legality under that of legit

    imacy

    we

    are

    not

    introducing

    a

    judgment

    of

    value

    into what

    is

    in

    essence

    a

    purely descriptive

    statement. In

    plain,

    ordinary

    speech,

    this doubt

    may

    be

    expressed

    even more

    forcibly

    by

    remarking:

    it

    is all

    very

    well

    to

    say,

    as

    Weber

    says,

    that in

    the

    modern

    State "commands

    are

    bestowed

    in

    the

    name

    of

    impersonal

    norms"

    and

    that

    legality

    has

    come

    to

    be

    considered

    as

    the best

    safeguard

    against

    arbitrary

    power.

    But this

    may

    well

    amount

    to

    nothing

    more

    than the

    account

    of

    an

    historical

    fact;

    it

    does

    not

    tell

    us

    much

    about

    the kind

    of

    legality

    which

    alone

    can

    constitute

    that

    safeguard,

    nor

    about the

    values

    which

    we

    consider worth

    safeguarding.

    Are

    we

    disposed

    to

    approve,

    and

    consider

    legit

    imate,

    any

    legal

    order

    as

    such,

    or

    shall

    we

    reserve

    our

    applause

    for

    that

    particular

    kind

    of

    order

    alone

    that

    is

    established

    in

    view

    of

    the

    attainment of certain

    goals,

    of

    the insurance

    of

    certain

    deter

    minate

    values?

    Are

    we

    prepared

    to

    make of

    legality

    a

    fetish,

    thereby

    reducing

    legitimacy

    to

    the

    mere

    respect

    of

    the rules of

    the

    game,

    without

    any

    concern

    for the

    game itself,

    whatever its

    stake

    and whatever its

    consequences?

    This,

    I

    believe,

    is

    the crucial

    question which the modern identification of legality and legit

    imacy

    raises.

    I

    submit

    that

    we

    must

    take

    into

    account

    the

    fact

    that

    the notion

    of

    legality

    is

    at

    variance

    in

    the modern

    world,

    and

    that

    in

    this

    variance

    we

    can

    find the

    key

    of

    many

    disturbing

    diversities

    in

    legal

    as

    well

    as

    in

    political

    thinking.

    Let

    me

    enlarge

    briefly

    on

    this

    point

    which

    has been

    very

    much

    in

    my

    mind

    ever

    since

    I have

    made

    it

    a

    habit of

    crossing

    the

    Atlantic

    every year

    and

    of

    dividing

    my

    time between

    strikingly

    different

    surroundings.

    That such

    expressions

    as

    the

    "rule

    of

    law,"

    "government

    6

    Inaugural

    address

    by

    Roscoe

    Pound,

    The

    Future

    of

    the

    Common

    Law,,

    Harvard

    Trecentenary

    Publications,

    1937

    This content downloaded from 200.75.10.74 on Wed, 7 Jan 2015 13:14:22 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 passerin.pdf

    7/17

    692

    ALEXANDER

    P.

    D'ENTR?VES

    under

    law,"

    l?galit?,

    Rechtsstaat

    are

    not

    exactly

    equivalent

    but

    carry

    with

    them

    many

    subtle shades

    of

    different

    implications,

    is

    a

    fact

    that

    weighed

    heavily

    on

    the

    minds of

    the

    lawyers

    who

    met

    in

    Chicago

    in

    1957

    to

    discuss the

    problem

    of

    "The

    Rule

    of

    Law

    as

    Understood

    in

    the West."

    This

    should be

    no cause

    of

    surprise

    to

    anyone

    who

    is

    aware

    of

    the

    deep

    differences

    between

    the countries

    of

    Common

    Law

    and

    those

    of

    the

    Roman

    tradition.

    To

    the

    Conti

    nental mind, law is primarily the expression of a deliberate act of

    lawgiving:

    "Lex

    est

    quod

    populus

    iubet

    atque

    constituit"

    ;

    "La Loi

    est

    l'expression

    de la

    volont?

    g?n?rale."

    There

    is

    a

    close

    affinity,

    though

    not

    necessarily

    an

    unbroken

    continuity

    of

    thought,

    between

    the views

    of

    the

    Roman

    lawyers

    and those

    of

    the

    French

    Revolutionaries,

    both

    with

    regard

    to the nature

    of

    law

    and

    to

    the

    position

    of

    the

    legislator

    as

    sovereign.

    This

    is the historical

    back

    ground

    which

    we

    must

    bear

    in mind in order

    to

    understand

    the

    Continental

    democracies'

    interpretation

    of

    legality

    and

    legitimacy.

    No

    doubt,

    in

    modern

    Continental

    democracies

    the

    notion

    of

    popular

    sovereignty

    provides

    the overall

    principle

    of

    legitimation

    of

    the

    whole

    legal

    system.

    But

    the

    test

    of

    legitimacy

    of

    each

    and

    every

    norm

    that

    composes

    that

    system

    is

    a

    merely

    formal

    one,

    namely,

    the

    ultimate

    derivation

    from,

    and

    conformity

    to,

    the

    will

    of

    the

    sovereign.

    Legality

    is

    thus

    of

    itself

    a

    token

    of

    legitimacy.

    Such views

    have

    not

    only deeply

    affected

    our

    political

    thought,

    they

    are

    reflected

    in

    many

    of

    our

    institutions.

    I need

    hardly

    remind

    you

    that,

    in Continental

    countries,

    the

    guarantee

    of

    legality

    has

    always

    been

    conceived

    as

    the

    protection

    of

    the

    people

    against

    the

    encroachment

    of

    executive

    and administrative

    action.

    Strange

    as

    it

    may

    seem,

    Continental

    constitutions

    have

    long

    failed

    to

    provide

    adequate protection

    against

    the

    omnipotence

    of the

    legislature.7

    But

    I

    am

    not

    here

    concerned

    with

    Constitutional

    Law.

    It

    is

    to

    the

    particular

    reflection

    of

    such views

    on

    legal

    thinking

    that

    I

    would

    like

    to

    call

    your

    attention.

    I have

    found

    in

    a

    passage

    of

    Tocqueville

    a

    particularly

    apt

    description

    of

    the

    attitude

    of

    the

    legal

    profession

    on

    the Continent.

    Lawyers,

    according

    to

    Tocque

    7

    This point is brilliantly illustrated in Professor A. Tune's contribution

    to

    the Harvard

    Conference

    on

    Government

    under

    Law

    (Cambridge,

    Mass.,

    1956).

    This content downloaded from 200.75.10.74 on Wed, 7 Jan 2015 13:14:22 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 passerin.pdf

    8/17

    LEGALITY

    ND

    LEGITIMACY

    693

    ville,

    "are attached

    to

    public

    order

    beyond

    every

    other consid

    eration;

    and

    the

    best

    security

    of

    public

    order

    is

    authority.

    It

    must

    not

    be

    forgotten

    also"?continues

    Tocqueville?"that

    if

    they

    prize

    freedom

    much,

    they

    generally

    value

    legality

    still

    more:

    they

    are

    less

    afraid of

    tyranny

    than of

    arbitrary

    power;

    and,

    provided

    the

    legislature

    undertakes

    of itself

    to

    deprive

    men

    of

    their

    independ

    ence,

    they

    are

    not

    dissatisfied."8

    At first

    sight,

    one

    would

    be

    inclined to describe such

    an

    attitude

    as

    conservative, perhaps

    even

    reactionary.

    But

    I

    think

    that

    it

    might

    better

    be described

    as

    fundamentally

    agnostic.

    It

    implies

    the

    deliberate

    renunciation

    on

    the

    part

    of

    the

    lawyer

    to

    pass

    any

    judgment

    on

    the

    content

    of

    the

    law,

    a

    conception

    of

    legality

    as

    a

    matter

    of

    form,

    not

    of

    substance.

    It is

    as

    if the

    lawyer

    would

    say

    :

    let the

    legislator

    take

    upon

    himself

    to

    decide

    upon

    all

    major

    issues;

    let

    him

    make

    the

    basic choices

    in

    matters

    of

    policy

    ;

    all

    I

    am

    concerned

    with is to

    ascertain whether

    this

    particular

    rule,

    this

    particular

    decision

    is

    correct,

    whether it

    is

    law,

    no

    matter if

    I

    like

    or

    dislike it.

    "Formalism"

    is

    an

    essential

    characteristic of the Continental

    approach

    to law.9 Modern

    legal

    positivism

    has done

    nothing

    more

    than

    to

    bring

    this

    assumption

    to

    its

    extreme

    logical

    consequences.

    I

    know

    only

    too

    well

    that

    the

    hold

    of

    positivism

    on

    Conti

    nental

    legal thought

    is

    a

    stumbling

    block

    to

    American

    lawyers.

    I

    feel that

    I

    must

    say

    a

    few

    words

    to

    explain

    that

    hold,

    and

    even,

    within

    certain

    limits,

    to

    justify

    it. To

    begin

    with,

    I

    would

    like

    to

    point

    out

    that

    the

    blame,

    if

    blame

    it

    be,

    should not

    be levelled

    exclusively

    against

    us

    Continentals.

    It

    was

    John

    Austin after

    all

    who

    first

    drafted what

    may

    be

    called

    the

    positivist

    manifesto.

    "The

    existence

    of law

    is

    one

    thing;

    its

    merit

    or

    demerit

    another.

    Whether

    it be

    or

    be

    not

    is

    one

    inquiry,

    whether it

    be

    or

    be

    not

    conformable

    to

    an

    assumed standard

    is

    another

    inquiry.

    A

    law,

    8

    A. de

    Tocqueville, Democracy

    in

    America, I,

    xvi,

    2.

    9

    Needless

    to

    say,

    "formalism" is

    a

    very

    general

    term

    which would

    need further definition. In the

    sense

    in

    which

    it

    is used

    by

    Continental

    lawyers,

    it

    indicates

    not

    only

    a

    justification

    of

    "conceptualism"

    in

    law,

    but

    the

    tendency

    which

    I have

    described,

    to

    abstain

    from

    any

    consideration

    of

    substance

    and

    to

    focus attention

    on

    the

    logical

    coherence

    of

    a

    given legal

    system. For an excellent analysis of this type of "formalism" I would like

    to

    refer

    to

    an

    article

    by

    N.

    Bobbio,

    "Sul

    formalismo

    giuridico",

    in

    Rivista

    italiana

    di diritto

    e

    procedure p?nale,

    I,

    1958.

    This content downloaded from 200.75.10.74 on Wed, 7 Jan 2015 13:14:22 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 passerin.pdf

    9/17

    694

    ALEXANDER

    P.

    D'ENTR?VES

    which

    actually

    exists,

    is

    a

    law,

    though

    we

    happen

    to

    dislike

    it,

    or

    though

    it

    may

    vary

    from

    the

    text,

    by

    which

    we

    regulate

    our

    appro

    bation

    or

    disapprobation."10

    It

    appears

    from

    these words

    that

    the

    first and

    basic

    requirement

    for

    the

    positivist

    is

    an

    attitude

    of

    "ethical

    neutrality."

    If this

    be

    so,

    surely

    the Continental

    lawyer

    is

    predestined,

    as

    it

    were,

    to

    be

    a

    positivist.

    In countries

    where

    judge-made

    law

    is ruled

    out,

    where

    judicial

    review is

    a

    com

    paratively recent innovation, the only "existing," the only "valid"

    law is

    the

    one

    which is

    laid down

    by

    the

    sovereign.

    If

    this

    is

    the

    background

    of

    fact,

    I

    can

    think of

    two

    valid

    justifications

    of

    legal

    positivism.

    The

    first

    is

    the remarkable

    advance which

    legal

    science?our

    proud

    Continental

    Rechtswissenschaft?has

    made

    by

    adopting

    the

    positivist

    method.

    It

    seems

    to

    me

    (though

    I

    am

    not

    sure

    that

    many

    lawyers

    in

    this

    country

    would

    agree

    with

    me

    on

    this

    point)

    that

    legal

    science,

    if

    it

    be

    a

    science

    at

    all,

    must

    necessar

    ily

    be

    "formal" and

    "neutral,"

    at

    any

    rate

    in

    its

    method.

    The

    task

    of

    the scientist

    is

    not

    to

    approve

    or

    to

    disapprove,

    nor

    to

    propose

    an

    ideal,

    but

    to

    explain,

    and

    to

    provide

    an

    intelligible

    recon

    struction

    of

    a

    given

    slice

    of

    human

    experience.

    In

    Herbert

    Hart's

    words,

    "the

    analysis

    or

    study

    of

    meanings

    of

    legal

    concepts

    is

    an

    important study

    to

    be

    distinguished

    from

    (though

    in

    no

    way

    hostile

    to)

    historical

    inquiries,

    sociological

    inquiries,

    and

    the

    crit

    ical

    appraisal

    of law

    in

    terms

    of

    morals,

    social

    aims,

    func

    tions,

    etc."

    X1

    This

    is the

    aim

    that Continental

    Rechtswissenschaft

    set

    out to

    pursue,

    and

    you

    must

    admit

    that

    it has

    proved

    remark

    ably

    successful.

    Actually,

    in

    its

    most

    recent and

    most

    up-to-date

    form?that of Kelsen's "Pure Theory

    of

    Law"?Continental

    legal

    science

    has

    succeeded

    in

    achieving

    that

    supreme

    tour

    de

    force

    which,

    to

    quote

    Hart

    again,

    is

    the

    crown

    of

    the

    positivist

    method:

    to

    construe

    the

    legal

    order

    as

    a

    coherent

    whole,

    and

    to

    show

    "that

    a

    legal

    system

    is

    a

    'closed

    logical system'

    in

    which

    correct

    decisions

    can

    be

    deduced

    from

    predetermined

    legal

    rules

    by

    logical

    means

    alone."12

    Incidentally,

    I

    would

    like to

    point

    out

    that,

    thus

    con

    ceived,

    positivist

    legal

    science

    seems

    to

    provide

    an

    ideal

    ground

    10

    J.

    Austin,

    The

    Province

    of

    Jurisprudence

    Determined

    (London

    1954 ed.), p. 184.

    11

    H. L.

    A.

    Hart,

    The

    Concept

    of

    Law

    (Oxford,

    1961),

    p.

    253.

    12

    Ibid.,

    p.

    253.

    This content downloaded from 200.75.10.74 on Wed, 7 Jan 2015 13:14:22 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 passerin.pdf

    10/17

    LEGALITY AND LEGITIMACY

    695

    for

    one

    of the

    more

    interesting

    recent ventures

    in

    legal

    theory

    :

    the

    exploration

    of the

    uses

    of

    logic

    in

    law,

    or,

    to

    call it with

    its

    per

    tinent

    name,

    of

    the

    nature of

    deontic

    logic.

    If,

    as

    Mr. Anderson

    puts

    it,

    those

    who

    engage

    in

    it do not

    propose

    to

    offer

    support

    for

    any

    particular

    system,

    but

    "to

    test

    its

    internal

    consistency,

    to

    verify

    its

    logical

    adequacy

    to

    its

    declared

    purpose,

    and

    to isolate

    and

    clarify

    the

    assumptions

    on

    which it rests"

    13?I

    confess that

    I cannot see how their premiss and aims substantially differ from

    the

    "ethical

    neutrality"

    of

    the

    positivist.

    But

    there

    is,

    I

    believe,

    also

    another

    and

    more

    substantial

    justification

    for

    the

    adherence

    of Continental

    lawyers

    to

    the

    tenets

    of

    positivism.

    The

    underlying

    reasons

    for their attitude

    were

    brought

    into

    full

    light

    during

    an

    amicable

    discussion

    held

    at

    Bel

    lagio

    two

    years

    ago,

    under

    the

    auspices

    of

    the Rockefeller

    Foun

    dation,

    by

    a

    small

    party

    of

    legal philosophers,

    old and

    young,

    from

    both

    Europe

    and America. The

    purpose

    of

    the

    meeting

    was

    to

    assess

    the basic

    features of

    legal

    positivism.

    It

    was

    only

    on

    the

    closing

    days

    of the

    conference

    that the

    English

    and

    American

    participants

    discovered the

    causes

    of

    what

    seemed

    to them the

    obdurate

    adherence

    of

    the Italians

    to

    the

    Kelsenian

    brand of

    posi

    tivism.

    I

    would

    like

    to

    quote

    a

    significant

    passage

    from

    the

    excellent

    summary

    of

    the discussions

    which

    Professors Samuel

    Shuman

    and

    Richard

    Falk

    have

    written for

    the

    Journal

    of

    Legal

    Education.

    "The Kelsenian

    abstractness,"

    they

    write,

    "smoke

    screened

    [on

    the

    part

    of

    the

    Italian

    participants]

    a

    strong

    commit

    ment

    to

    certain

    common

    socio-political

    positions.

    Broadly

    speaking, the character of these positions is liberal-democratic,

    especially

    in

    regard

    to

    the

    proper

    connection

    between

    Church

    and

    State.

    .

    .

    .

    Especially

    did

    it

    become

    evident that

    in

    the

    background

    of

    many

    Italian

    presentations

    was

    a

    desire

    to

    strengthen

    the

    legal

    order

    against

    interference

    from the Catholic

    Church,

    either

    directly

    by

    institutional interference

    or

    indirectly

    through

    its

    advocacy

    of

    natural law.

    Kelsenian

    positivism

    provides

    a

    powerful

    instrument

    to

    establish

    in

    a

    neutral

    manner

    the

    autonomy

    of

    the

    13 A. R. Anderson, "Logic, Norms, and Roles," forthcoming in Ratio.

    Significantly,

    Mr.

    Anderson

    borrows

    these

    words from

    Church's

    Introduction

    to

    Mathematical

    Logic.

    This content downloaded from 200.75.10.74 on Wed, 7 Jan 2015 13:14:22 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 passerin.pdf

    11/17

    696

    ALEXANDER

    P.

    D'ENTR?VES

    legal

    order. The

    narrowing

    of

    discretion

    to

    introduce

    external

    moral

    considerations

    into the

    legal

    process

    [was]

    said

    also

    to

    have

    had

    a

    beneficial

    impact

    upon

    judicial

    practice during

    the

    Fascist

    period,

    helping

    the

    judges

    to

    resist

    pressure

    from

    the

    Government

    to

    distort the

    pattern

    of

    decision.

    Similarly,

    it

    [was]

    considered

    by

    the

    Italians

    to

    be

    a

    muzzle of

    liberal effects

    upon

    reactionary

    judges

    who

    would

    use

    a

    widened discretion

    to

    move

    the

    law in

    a

    regressive direction. One learnfed] in this way that wide differ

    ences

    in

    legal

    theory

    may

    rest

    upon

    a

    shared

    and

    rational

    pursuit

    of

    similar

    values;

    hence,

    one

    befcame]

    chary

    about

    criticizing

    'an

    approach'

    to

    legal

    philosophy

    without

    a

    familiarity

    with

    the

    social

    situation within

    which

    it

    flourishes."

    14

    I have

    dwelt

    at

    length

    on

    the character

    and

    implications

    of

    the Continental

    approach

    to

    law,

    in

    order

    to account

    for and

    explain

    the

    reasons

    of

    the

    Continental

    concern

    for

    legality

    rather

    than

    for

    legitimacy.

    It

    would

    appear

    that

    in

    countries

    where there

    are

    wide

    ideological

    discrepancies,

    radical contrasts

    of

    interests,

    and little

    or

    no

    agreement

    on

    basic

    values,

    the

    issue

    of

    legitimacy

    is

    bound

    to

    be

    put,

    at

    it

    were,

    within

    brackets,

    or

    explained

    away

    by paying lip-service

    to

    the

    principle

    of

    popular

    sovereignty

    as

    a

    kind

    of deus

    ex

    machina. Ethical

    neutrality

    provides

    the

    lawyer

    with the

    ivory

    tower

    where

    he

    can

    stand aloof

    from

    the

    turmoil

    of

    politics.

    Legality,

    the

    certainty

    of

    law,

    is

    the

    polar

    star

    that

    enables

    him

    to

    steer

    a

    safe

    course

    amid

    the

    widely

    conflicting

    claims

    of

    opposing

    ideologies.

    Let

    me

    say

    now

    that

    I

    consider

    the

    price

    paid

    for

    such

    life-saving

    devices

    too

    high,

    and

    one

    tbat

    has

    proved

    to

    be in the end self-defeating. The formal approach to the law is

    the

    reason

    why

    the Continental

    idea

    of

    legality

    is

    something

    intrinsically

    different

    from

    the

    Anglo-American

    notion

    of

    the

    rule

    of

    law.

    It is

    also the

    reason

    why

    it

    has

    not

    proved

    to

    be

    a

    suf

    ficient

    guarantee

    of

    the

    values which

    you

    associate with

    that

    notion. One

    cannot

    help

    being

    reminded

    here

    of

    the fate

    that

    befell

    the

    great

    German

    doctrine

    of the

    Rechtsstaat

    in

    the

    years

    that

    preceded

    the

    advent

    of

    Nazism.

    That

    doctrine had been

    care

    fully

    and

    even

    lovingly

    tended

    by

    generation

    after

    generation

    of

    14

    R.

    A.

    Falk

    and

    S.

    I.

    Shuman,

    "The

    Bellagio

    Conference

    on

    Legal

    Positivism,"

    in

    14 Journal

    of Legal

    Education,

    No.

    2,

    1961.

    This content downloaded from 200.75.10.74 on Wed, 7 Jan 2015 13:14:22 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 passerin.pdf

    12/17

    LEGALITY

    AND

    LEGITIMACY

    697

    scholars.

    It

    spread

    from its

    native

    land

    to

    different

    parts

    of

    Europe,

    and

    was

    particularly

    successful in

    Italy.

    In

    my

    young

    days,

    it

    was

    the

    official

    doctrine

    of

    our

    law

    schools,

    and

    I

    have

    no

    doubt

    that

    those who

    expounded

    it

    were

    sincerely

    convinced of

    its

    inseparable

    links

    with

    the

    political

    ideals

    of

    liberty

    and

    democracy.

    But

    under the

    influence

    of

    the

    positivist

    concept

    of

    law,

    the

    doc

    trine

    of

    the

    Rechtsstaat

    was

    gradually

    and

    irreparably

    altered.

    If

    law is nothing else than the formal structure of power, that

    formal

    structure

    is

    present

    in

    any

    State,

    whatever

    political,

    social

    or

    moral

    aims

    are

    embodied

    in

    the

    legal system:

    every

    State

    is,

    by

    definition,

    a

    Rechtsstaat.

    If

    in

    the

    name

    of

    neutrality

    the

    lawyer

    must

    abstain

    from

    passing judgment

    on

    the

    content

    of

    the

    law,

    if

    his

    only

    concern

    is

    with its

    formal

    correctness:

    then

    all

    that

    mat

    ters to

    him is that

    the

    legal

    order

    should

    be

    preserved,

    that

    formal

    procedures

    should

    be

    respected.

    Tocqueville's

    prophecy

    was

    ful

    filled

    many

    times.

    From the

    second

    Napoleon

    to

    Mussolini

    and

    Hitler

    the

    appearance

    of

    legality

    was

    maintained in

    the

    setting

    up

    of

    plebiscitar?an

    dictatorships.

    But

    if

    on

    one

    hand

    the

    myth

    of

    legality

    could

    provide

    the basis

    for

    the

    subversion

    of

    the

    old

    liberal and

    democratic

    order,

    the

    notion of

    legitimacy

    on

    the other

    hand

    was

    itself

    deeply

    affected

    by

    the

    positivist approach

    and

    the

    positivist

    method.

    Legitimacy

    was

    made

    to

    depend ultimately solely

    on

    a

    question

    of

    effectiveness.

    In

    the

    words

    of

    one

    of

    the

    greatest

    Italian

    scholars of

    the

    period,

    "an

    illegitimate legal

    order is

    a

    contradiction

    in

    terms:

    its exist

    ence

    and its

    legitimacy

    are

    the

    same

    thing."

    Santi

    Romano,

    who

    wrote these lines, was

    an

    adept of the Theorie de l'Institution not

    of

    the Reine Rechtslehre.15

    Yet

    his

    conclusion

    is

    strikingly

    similar

    to

    that of

    Kelsen's.

    The

    "principle

    of

    legitimacy"

    means

    to

    Kelsen

    that the

    "validity

    (of

    a

    given

    system

    of

    norms)

    is

    deter

    mined

    only

    by

    the

    order

    to

    which

    they

    belong,"

    and

    that

    'they

    remain

    valid

    as

    long

    as

    they

    have

    not

    been

    invalidated

    in the

    way

    in

    which the

    legal

    order itself

    determines."

    When,

    as

    is the

    case

    with

    a

    successful

    revolution,

    "the

    total

    legal

    order,

    of

    which

    that

    norm

    is

    an

    integral part,

    has

    lost

    its

    efficacy,"

    this

    only

    indicates

    15

    S.

    Romano,

    Corso

    di

    diritto

    costituzionale

    gen?rale (Milan,

    2nd

    ed.,

    1946),

    pp.

    192-193.

    This content downloaded from 200.75.10.74 on Wed, 7 Jan 2015 13:14:22 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 passerin.pdf

    13/17

    698

    ALEXANDER

    P.

    D'ENTR?VES

    that

    a

    new

    legitimacy

    has

    set

    in,

    in

    so

    far

    as

    "the

    actual

    behaviour

    of

    individuals is

    [now]

    interpreted

    as

    legal

    or

    illegal

    .

    .

    .

    according

    to

    this

    new

    order."

    Thus,

    according

    to

    Kelsen,

    "the

    principle

    of

    legitimacy

    is

    restricted

    by

    the

    principle

    of effectiveness."

    16

    Now it

    would be

    easy

    indeed?and

    it

    has

    been

    done

    many

    times?to level

    at

    such

    interpretations

    of

    legality

    and

    legitimacy

    the

    accusation

    of

    being

    nothing

    else

    than

    an

    elaborate

    form of

    jus

    tification of the

    fait

    accompli,

    and that

    they

    end

    by

    making

    force,

    not

    justice,

    the last

    resort

    of

    legal

    as

    well

    as

    of

    political theory.

    But

    I

    know

    my

    positivists

    well,

    and

    I

    think

    I

    know too

    the

    answer

    which

    they

    would offer

    to

    this

    kind

    of criticism. To

    them,

    the

    problem

    of

    justice

    is

    a

    problem

    of

    value,

    a

    moral rather than

    a

    legal

    problem.

    They

    do

    not

    deny

    its relevance:

    they simply

    rele

    gate

    it

    outside

    the

    realm and the

    competence

    of

    the

    lawyer.

    Many

    of

    my

    positivist

    friends

    are

    men

    of

    high

    moral convictions.

    There

    can

    be

    no

    doubt of

    their

    being?as

    the

    phrase

    now

    goes?ethically

    as

    well

    as

    politically

    "committed."

    Yet

    they obstinately cling

    to

    the views

    which

    I

    have

    described,

    and

    deem

    it

    a

    token

    of intel

    lectual

    honesty

    to

    profess

    them.

    They

    will

    repeat

    with

    Austin

    that

    "the

    existence of

    law

    is

    one

    thing;

    its

    merit

    or

    demerit

    another."

    The

    question

    of

    the

    validity

    of

    law

    is

    to

    them

    a

    different

    question

    from that

    of its

    moral

    obligatoriness.

    Hart

    puts

    their

    case

    very

    well

    when

    he asks:

    in what

    way

    is

    it

    better,

    when

    faced

    with

    an

    iniquitous

    law

    or

    with

    an

    iniquitous

    State,

    to

    say,

    this

    is

    not

    law,

    this

    is

    not

    a

    State,

    rather

    than,

    this

    is

    law,

    this is

    a

    State,

    but

    too

    iniquitous

    to be

    obeyed

    or

    respected?

    "The

    certification

    of

    something as legally valid," Hart remarks, "is not conclusive of

    the

    question

    of

    obedience."

    1T

    Surely

    this

    seems

    to

    indicate

    that

    there

    are

    standards

    by

    which the

    legal

    order

    can

    be

    appraised

    other

    than that

    of

    mere

    factual existence.

    Could it

    not

    be

    the

    case

    that

    this

    is

    precisely

    what

    is

    meant

    when

    one

    speaks

    of

    legitimacy

    ?

    Rather than

    attacking

    the

    positivists

    on

    this

    ground,

    I

    believe

    that

    the

    question

    which

    must

    finally

    be

    asked

    is:

    does

    their

    view

    of

    legality

    correspond

    to

    the

    notion of

    the

    rule

    of

    law,

    of

    govern

    16 H. Kelsen, General

    Theory of

    Law and State (tr. Anders

    Wedberg)

    (Cambridge,

    Mass.,

    1945-1948), pp.

    115-122.

    17

    Hart, op. cit.,

    p.

    206.

    This content downloaded from 200.75.10.74 on Wed, 7 Jan 2015 13:14:22 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 passerin.pdf

    14/17

    LEGALITY

    ND

    LEGITIMACY

    699

    ment

    under

    law,

    such

    at

    any

    rate

    as

    it

    is

    usually

    understood

    in the

    Anglo-American

    tradition,

    and

    is

    gradually

    beginning

    to

    be

    under

    stood

    in most

    civilized

    countries?

    This is

    a

    big

    question,

    and

    I

    would like

    to

    end

    with

    some

    personal impressions

    rather

    than

    with

    a

    clear

    and definite

    conclusion. In

    his

    Digest

    of

    the

    discussions

    on

    the rule of law which

    were

    held

    in

    Chicago

    in

    1957,

    Mr.

    J.

    A.

    Jolo

    wicz

    concedes that

    "as

    a

    logical

    postulate,

    the

    rule

    of

    law

    has

    no

    necessary connection with any theory of fundamental values and

    can

    exist

    as

    well in

    an

    autocracy

    as

    in the

    most

    liberal

    of demo

    cracies."

    But

    he

    immediately

    goes

    on

    to

    say

    that

    "so

    formalistic

    a

    view of the

    rule

    of

    law

    did

    not

    commend

    itself

    to

    the

    participants

    in

    the

    Colloquium.

    On

    the

    contrary,

    it seemed

    to

    be

    generally

    agreed

    that

    'the

    Rule

    of

    Law

    as

    understood

    in

    the

    West' involved

    more

    than the

    mere

    compliance

    of

    the

    sovereign

    power

    in

    a

    State

    with

    the

    rules of the

    positive

    law

    of

    that

    State. There

    was,

    in

    fact,

    a

    large

    measure

    of

    agreement

    that

    the rule

    of

    law

    has

    some

    positive

    content

    capable

    of

    being

    expressed

    in

    terms of

    fundamental

    values."

    18

    Less

    than two

    years

    later,

    the International Commission

    of

    Jurists,

    in the

    Congress

    it

    held in New

    Delhi,

    agreed

    to

    define

    the

    rule

    of law

    as

    "the realization

    of

    the

    appropriate

    conditions

    for

    the

    development

    of

    human

    dignity."

    Clearly,

    the

    emphasis

    is

    here

    on

    the

    content of

    the

    law,

    on

    the

    purpose

    of

    the

    legal

    system.

    The

    request

    for

    legality

    is

    no

    longer

    one

    for the formal

    correctness of

    the

    particular

    rules

    or

    of

    the

    single

    decisions

    alone.

    It

    is

    a

    request

    for

    the

    conformity

    of

    these rules

    and decisions

    to

    the

    values

    that

    are

    posited

    as

    necessary

    for

    the

    existence

    of

    a

    free

    society.1'

    We

    are

    provided with

    a

    touchstone which enables

    us

    to evaluate the

    "legal

    quality"

    of

    law,

    the

    substantive

    aspect

    of

    legality.

    We

    are,

    in

    fact,

    identifying

    legality

    with

    legitimacy

    once

    again, though

    in

    a

    manner

    that is

    exactly

    opposite

    to

    that

    of the

    positivist.

    The

    positivists,

    as we

    have

    seen,

    had

    ended

    up

    by

    either

    reducing

    legit

    imacy

    to

    a mere

    question

    of

    fact,

    or

    transferring

    the

    appraisal

    of

    18

    J.

    A.

    Jolowicz,

    Digest

    of the

    Discussion,

    Chicago

    Colloquium

    on

    "The

    Rule of

    Law

    as

    understood

    in

    the

    West"

    (Sept.

    1957),

    in Annales

    de la

    Facult? de

    Droit

    d'Istanbul,

    t.

    IX,

    1959.

    19 N. S. Marsh, "The Rule of Law as a

    Supra-National

    Concept,"

    in

    Oxford

    Essays

    in

    Jurisprudence,

    ed.

    by.

    A.

    G.

    Guest

    (Oxford,

    1961),

    pp.

    240

    245.

    This content downloaded from 200.75.10.74 on Wed, 7 Jan 2015 13:14:22 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 passerin.pdf

    15/17

    700

    ALEXANDER P.

    D'ENTR?VES

    the

    obligatoriness

    of

    law

    to

    a

    different

    plane altogether.

    I

    am

    not

    sure

    that

    we are

    not

    faced

    now

    with

    a

    reduction

    of

    legitimacy

    to

    a

    question

    of

    natural

    law

    or

    natural

    rights,

    or

    at

    any

    rate

    to

    a

    ques

    tion

    of

    justice.

    I

    would

    like

    to conclude this

    paper

    with

    a

    few

    remarks

    about

    the

    conditions

    which

    alone

    seem

    to

    me

    to

    make

    that

    reduction

    possible.

    The first

    and essential condition

    seems

    to

    me

    to

    be

    that

    there

    should be a general agreement in a given society about basic values.

    I

    have

    already

    pointed

    out

    the

    reasons

    why,

    in

    societies

    where

    there

    is

    no

    such

    agreement,

    the

    safest

    course

    to

    the

    lawyer

    may

    seem

    that of

    entrenching

    himself

    behind

    the

    stronghold

    of

    legality.

    As

    Tocqueville

    pointed

    out,

    there

    may

    be

    good

    reasons

    for

    him

    to

    prize

    order

    more

    than

    liberty;

    there

    certainly

    are

    when

    the

    menace

    is

    at

    hand

    of the

    subversion

    of

    that

    order

    by

    deliberate

    enemies

    of

    freedom. The

    pre-condition

    for

    the

    rule

    of law is

    the

    existence

    of

    a

    free

    society,

    one

    in

    which

    opposition

    and

    dissent

    do

    not

    challenge

    the

    rules

    of

    the

    game,

    but

    accept

    them

    as

    beneficial

    and

    necessary.

    This,

    I

    need

    hardly

    add,

    seems

    to

    me

    to

    be

    the

    case

    in

    Britain and

    in

    the

    U.S.A.;

    I

    am

    not

    sure

    that it

    is

    so

    in

    several

    other

    contemporary

    societies.

    The

    second

    condition

    is

    that

    we

    abandon

    or

    at

    least

    modify

    that

    notion

    of law

    as

    the

    expression

    of

    a

    sovereign

    will which

    underlies

    the

    positivist

    's

    case

    and

    which,

    I

    am

    afraid,

    is

    deeply

    ingrained

    in the

    mind

    of

    those

    who

    have been

    reared

    in

    the Roman

    tradition.

    "Law,"

    Justice Frankfurter

    wrote,

    "is

    not

    a

    code

    of

    fettering

    restraints,

    a

    litany

    of

    prohibitions

    and restrictions.

    It

    is

    an enveloping and permeating habituation of behavior, reflecting

    the

    counsels

    of

    reason on

    the

    part

    of

    those

    entrusted

    with

    power

    in

    reconciling

    the

    pressure

    of

    conflicting

    interests. Once

    we

    con

    ceive

    of the

    'rule

    of law'

    as

    embracing

    the

    whole

    range

    of

    pre

    suppositions

    on

    which

    government

    is

    conducted and

    not

    as

    a

    technical

    doctrine of

    judicial

    authority,

    the relevant

    question

    is

    not

    has

    it

    been

    achieved,

    but

    is

    it

    conscientiously

    and

    systematically

    pursued.

    .

    .

    .

    What

    matters

    most

    is

    whether the

    standards

    of

    reason

    and

    fair

    dealing

    are

    bred

    in

    the

    bones

    of

    the

    people."

    20

    I

    20

    F.

    Frankfurter,

    Opening

    address

    for the

    Harvard Conference

    on

    Government under Law

    (Cambridge,

    Mass.,

    1956), p.

    228.

    This content downloaded from 200.75.10.74 on Wed, 7 Jan 2015 13:14:22 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 passerin.pdf

    16/17

    LEGALITY

    AND

    LEGITIMACY

    701

    am

    very

    fond of

    quoting

    this

    passage

    as

    the

    best

    summary

    I

    know

    of

    the American

    attitude toward

    law,

    as

    well

    as

    of

    the

    essential

    contribution

    of

    American

    realism

    to

    legal

    theory.

    Please

    do

    not

    take this

    to

    imply

    that

    I

    accept

    all

    the

    tenets

    of

    realism,

    nor

    that

    I

    think

    that

    they

    would

    be

    viable

    in

    Europe.

    I

    firmly

    believe

    that

    on

    several

    points

    our

    two

    traditions could

    profit

    from

    a

    mutual

    encounter,

    and for

    one

    thing

    I

    would

    not

    easily

    renounce

    the

    Continental view that legal science must, and cannot but be, ethi

    cally

    neutral.

    All

    I want

    to

    say

    is

    that

    once

    you

    conceive

    of

    law,

    not in

    the

    Continental

    fashion

    as an

    abstract

    set of

    rules,

    but

    as

    a

    continuous

    and

    purposeful

    process,

    the

    whole

    question

    of

    the

    rule

    of

    law,

    of

    legality

    and

    legitimacy,

    is

    bound

    to

    appear

    in

    a

    new

    light,

    and

    certainly

    in

    a

    different

    one

    from

    that

    in

    which

    it

    appears

    to

    us

    in

    Europe.

    Some isolated but authoritative

    voices,

    I

    know,

    have

    recently

    been

    heard

    also here in

    the

    U.S.A.,

    stressing

    the

    necessity

    of

    "neutral

    principles"

    in

    judicial

    decision

    as

    well

    as

    in

    legal

    argumentation.21

    Some

    of

    the caveats

    of

    legal positivism

    may

    well

    serve

    to correct

    certain

    extremes

    of

    the

    realist

    approach

    and

    to

    introduce

    some

    rationalism in

    realism.

    But the

    point

    is?or

    so

    it

    appears

    to

    me?that

    rigid

    neutrality

    is

    necessarily

    ruled

    out

    by

    an

    approach

    to

    law such

    as

    yours,

    since,

    as

    Dean

    Rostow

    has

    pointed

    out

    in

    replying

    to

    Professor

    Wechsler,

    the

    "legitimacy"

    of

    a

    Court's

    decision

    does

    not,

    and

    cannot,

    rest

    with

    you

    only

    on

    "the

    element

    of

    rules,

    of

    precedent,

    of what

    [Professor

    Wechsler]

    calls

    'principle'

    or

    'reason'."

    22

    It

    rests,

    I

    guess,

    in

    Justice

    Frank

    furter's

    words,

    on

    "an

    enveloping

    and

    permeating

    habituation

    of

    behavior,"

    "bred

    in

    the

    bones"

    both of

    your

    Courts

    and of

    your

    people.

    Legitimacy

    will

    therefore

    never

    consist

    in

    legality

    alone;

    it

    lies,

    rather,

    in

    the constans et

    perpetua

    voluntas

    of

    making

    legal

    ity

    an

    adequate

    instrument

    of

    legitimacy.

    I

    have said

    enough,

    I

    fear,

    to

    make

    my

    whole

    argument

    self

    defeating.

    If

    my

    interpretation

    is

    correct,

    I

    have

    collected

    sufficient

    evidence

    to

    explain

    why

    my

    whole

    question

    about

    legality

    and

    21

    H.

    Wechsler,

    "Toward Neutral

    Principles

    of

    Constitutional

    Law"

    (The

    0.

    W.

    Holmes Lecture

    at

    the Harvard Law

    School,

    1959),

    in

    Principles,

    Politics and Fundamental Law (Cambridge, Mass., 1961).

    22

    E.

    V.

    Rostow,

    "American

    Legal

    Realism",

    in The

    Sovereign

    Pre

    rogative

    (New

    Haven,

    1962),

    pp.

    28

    ff.

    This content downloaded from 200.75.10.74 on Wed, 7 Jan 2015 13:14:22 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 passerin.pdf

    17/17

    702

    ALEXANDER

    P.

    D'ENTR?VES

    legitimacy

    is

    very

    likely

    to

    seem,

    to

    some,

    meaningless

    or

    pointless.

    Let

    me

    hope

    that

    I

    may

    have

    at

    least

    exposed

    some

    reasons

    for

    understanding

    why

    it

    is

    not

    so

    with

    us,

    and

    why

    it

    is

    bound

    to

    remain,

    so

    long

    at

    any

    rate

    as

    present

    conditions

    endure,

    much

    more

    than

    a

    merely

    academic

    question.

    University

    of

    Turin;

    Yale

    University,