original position vol-2

5
the world’s known oil reserves. In addition, since the 1970s, the price of oil has fluctuated dramatically, often to the detriment of revenues of OPEC members. Given the fact that OPEC is comprised of Third World states, its members claim that the criticisms leveled against it are thinly dis- guised efforts of developed western states to maintain eco- nomic colonialism. Critics of OPEC deny this charge and argue that the concerns they express about OPEC’s practices are focused on its domination of the oil market. With respect to concerns of global justice, OPEC has been and continues to be enwrapped with controversy. On the one hand, it has been portrayed by critics as a powerful player in international markets, focused on its own inter- ests at the expense of any globally recognized sense of a fair distribution of an important natural resource. On the other hand, it has been portrayed by its supporters as an important barrier to even greater domination by devel- oped western economies. After all, they say, OPEC is constituted by Third World countries and economies that now control a crucial natural resource, one which was once controlled by the exploitation of colonial pow- ers, powers that used that resource for their own interests. The just distribution, in terms of who does benefit and who should benefit from the availability of oil, remains a crucial issue both in itself as well as in its role in inter- national and global actions (such as political or military policies and decisions). Related Topics Capitalism Colonialism Free Trade Global Democracy Global Egalitarianism Global Justice Global Resource Distribution Globalization International Organizations Multinational Corporations Post-Colonialism Third World Resistance References Amuzegar J (2001) Managing the oil wealth: OPEC’s windfalls and pitfalls. IB Tauris, London Campbell KM, Price J (eds) (2008) The global politics of energy. The Aspen Institute, Queenstown Falola T, Genova A (2008) The politics of the global oil industry: an introduction. Praeger, New York Parra FR (2004) Oil politics: a modern history of petroleum. IB Tauris, London Skeet I (1991) OPEC: twenty-five years of prices and politics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge Original Position ALYSSA R. BERNSTEIN Department of Philosophy, Ohio University, Athens, OH, USA Much of the writing about global justice that has been published since the 1970s has either used or criticized the central ideas of John Rawls’s conceptions of domestic and international social justice, including in particular the “original position.” Charles Beitz and Thomas Pogge ini- tially developed their own cosmopolitan positions partly by criticizing Rawls’s use of the original position in justice as fairness (JF), the conception of a just society Rawls presented in A Theory of Justice (1971; henceforth “TJ”), and arguing for a globalized original position instead (see the entries on Law of Peoples and Political Cosmo- politanism in this encyclopedia). Michael Blake (2005) devotes more than one-quarter of his long Stanford Ency- clopedia of Philosophy article on international justice to discussing the Law of Peoples (LP), Rawls’s conception of a just international order, and most of this discussion involves Blake’s interpretation of Rawls’s contractarian methodology, to which the original position is central. Many criticisms of LP fail due to misinterpretations of the original position and its use in Rawls’s conceptions of domestic and international justice. The original position is a structure of ideas that John Rawls uses as a theoretical device for testing the fairness (and thus, in his view, the justice) of principles for orga- nizing political, social, and economic cooperation. To test principles, one carries out a kind of thought experiment. If participants in cooperation use the original position and refer to it in their discussions, it may lead them to agree- ment about justice, international as well as domestic, or so Rawls hopes. The original position develops the familiar idea that terms of cooperation are unfair if some of the participants in the cooperation have good reasons, deriving from their fundamental interests, not to agree to them. Since people often do agree to unfair terms despite having good reasons not to agree, actual agreement is not an adequate criterion of fairness. Fear and ignorance, among other factors, can lead people to accept unfair terms; prejudice-based hostile attitudes and possession of power over others, among other factors, can lead people to propose or support unfair terms. Therefore, a more adequate criterion of fairness refers not to actual but to hypothetical agreement: the terms to which people would agree if they all were well 786 O Original Position

Upload: theodorejosephjumamil

Post on 29-Sep-2015

3 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

DESCRIPTION

Dowrkin. Original Position. LegTheo. Law117. ProfBatongbacal

TRANSCRIPT

  • the worlds known oil reserves. In addition, since the 1970s,

    the price of oil has fluctuated dramatically, often to the

    detriment of revenues of OPEC members. Given the fact

    that OPEC is comprised of ThirdWorld states, its members

    claim that the criticisms leveled against it are thinly dis-

    guised efforts of developed western states to maintain eco-

    nomic colonialism. Critics of OPEC deny this charge andargue that the concerns they express aboutOPECs practices

    are focused on its domination of the oil market.

    With respect to concerns of global justice, OPEC has

    been and continues to be enwrapped with controversy. On

    the one hand, it has been portrayed by critics as a powerful

    player in international markets, focused on its own inter-

    ests at the expense of any globally recognized sense of a fair

    distribution of an important natural resource. On theother hand, it has been portrayed by its supporters as an

    important barrier to even greater domination by devel-

    oped western economies. After all, they say, OPEC is

    constituted by Third World countries and economies

    that now control a crucial natural resource, one which

    was once controlled by the exploitation of colonial pow-

    ers, powers that used that resource for their own interests.

    The just distribution, in terms of who does benefit andwho should benefit from the availability of oil, remains

    a crucial issue both in itself as well as in its role in inter-

    national and global actions (such as political or military

    policies and decisions).

    Related TopicsCapitalismColonialism Free TradeGlobal DemocracyGlobal EgalitarianismGlobal JusticeGlobal Resource DistributionGlobalization International OrganizationsMultinational CorporationsPost-ColonialismThird World Resistance

    ReferencesAmuzegar J (2001) Managing the oil wealth: OPECs windfalls and

    pitfalls. IB Tauris, London

    Campbell KM, Price J (eds) (2008) The global politics of energy. The

    Aspen Institute, Queenstown

    Falola T, Genova A (2008) The politics of the global oil industry: an

    introduction. Praeger, New York

    Parra FR (2004) Oil politics: a modern history of petroleum. IB Tauris,

    London

    Skeet I (1991) OPEC: twenty-five years of prices and politics. Cambridge

    University Press, Cambridge

    Original Position

    ALYSSA R. BERNSTEIN

    Department of Philosophy, Ohio University,

    Athens, OH, USA

    Much of the writing about global justice that has been

    published since the 1970s has either used or criticized the

    central ideas of John Rawlss conceptions of domestic and

    international social justice, including in particular theoriginal position. Charles Beitz and Thomas Pogge ini-

    tially developed their own cosmopolitan positions partly

    by criticizing Rawlss use of the original position in justice

    as fairness (JF), the conception of a just society Rawls

    presented in A Theory of Justice (1971; henceforth TJ),

    and arguing for a globalized original position instead (see

    the entries on Law of Peoples and Political Cosmo-politanism in this encyclopedia). Michael Blake (2005)devotes more than one-quarter of his long Stanford Ency-

    clopedia of Philosophy article on international justice to

    discussing the Law of Peoples (LP), Rawlss conception

    of a just international order, and most of this discussion

    involves Blakes interpretation of Rawlss contractarian

    methodology, to which the original position is central.

    Many criticisms of LP fail due to misinterpretations of

    the original position and its use in Rawlss conceptions ofdomestic and international justice.

    The original position is a structure of ideas that John

    Rawls uses as a theoretical device for testing the fairness

    (and thus, in his view, the justice) of principles for orga-

    nizing political, social, and economic cooperation. To test

    principles, one carries out a kind of thought experiment.

    If participants in cooperation use the original position and

    refer to it in their discussions, it may lead them to agree-ment about justice, international as well as domestic, or so

    Rawls hopes.

    The original position develops the familiar idea that

    terms of cooperation are unfair if some of the participants

    in the cooperation have good reasons, deriving from their

    fundamental interests, not to agree to them. Since people

    often do agree to unfair terms despite having good reasons

    not to agree, actual agreement is not an adequate criterionof fairness. Fear and ignorance, among other factors, can

    lead people to accept unfair terms; prejudice-based hostile

    attitudes and possession of power over others, among

    other factors, can lead people to propose or support unfair

    terms. Therefore, a more adequate criterion of fairness

    refers not to actual but to hypothetical agreement: the

    terms to which people would agree if they all were well

    786 O Original Position

  • informed and rational, and if they all were on an equal

    footing. Clarifying such a criterion requires listing all of

    the relevant if-clauses, or the conditions they state. In JF

    Rawls draws up a list of such conditions and uses it,

    together with other considerations, to devise a way of

    testing proposed principles of domestic social justice.

    The test involves imagining rational people in a hypothet-

    ical, non-historical situation who must choose amongalternative proposed principles. Actual people who care

    about fairness can use the test to clarify their own judg-

    ment, when trying to determine whether anyone would

    (if well-informed and rational, if on an equal footing, etc.)

    have good reasons not to agree to a proposed principle. In

    LP Rawls uses a different version of the original position in

    order to test proposed principles of international justice

    (See below, and see the entries on Second OriginalPosition and Law of Peoples in this encyclopedia).

    In JF Rawls analyzes social justice in terms of an

    agreement on the basic terms of social cooperation made

    by those engaged in it, as do the social contract theories of

    Locke, Rousseau, and Kant. (See Rawls (2007) for the

    differences among his own, Lockes, and Rousseaus

    views. For the similarities and differences between Rawlss

    and Kants views, see Bernstein 2009.) According to Rawls,an agreement on the terms of social cooperation that is

    entered into under conditions that situate free and equal

    persons fairly is valid: the conditions must exclude coer-

    cion and deception, andmust disallow unequal bargaining

    advantages. In everyday life, agreements are made within

    the context of societys basic structure and may be

    distorted by it. In any society, cumulative historical devel-

    opments of the basic structure inevitably give rise tocontingent bargaining advantages. These must not be

    allowed to affect the agreement on the principles for

    regulating these institutions, Rawls argues. Therefore he

    conceives a hypothetical agreement.

    In JF Rawls stipulates that each of the parties in the

    imagined original position is a rational agent responsible

    for the fundamental interests of a free and equal citizen.

    He situates all of the parties symmetrically: all have equalrights in the procedure for reaching agreement on princi-

    ples, and all have (and lack) the same knowledge. They

    have relevant general knowledge, but a veil of ignorance

    prevents them from knowing specifics, including the

    social status or class position of the particular citizens

    they each represent, and also the citizens other individual

    characteristics, including race, ethnicity, sex, gender,

    native endowments (strength, intelligence, etc.), and reli-gious or secular comprehensive doctrine (moral outlook

    and value system). This restriction models one of Rawlss

    considered convictions, which he (explicitly) assumes is

    shared by himself and his readers: the fact that we occupy

    a particular social position (or have a certain skin color,

    etc.) is not a good reason for us to propose, or to expect

    others to accept, a conception of justice that favors the

    people who are in this position (or who have the particular

    characteristic). The veil of ignorance prevents the parties

    from specially tailoring proposed principles and from

    bargaining in the usual sense: in Rawlss words, it nullifiesthe effects of the contingent natural and social advantages

    that might otherwise tempt citizens to exploit them to

    their own advantage (Rawls 1971).

    Rawls distinguishes between three points of view:

    that of the parties in the original position, that of citizens

    in a well-ordered society, and (in his words) that of

    ourselves of you and me who are elaborating justice as

    fairness and examining it as a political conception ofjustice (Rawls 1993). When Rawls speaks of you and

    me, he is addressing any reader who shares his concern

    that, as he says, there is no public agreement on how basic

    institutions are to be arranged so as to bemost appropriate

    to the freedom and equality of democratic citizenship.

    An especially important root of this disagreement is

    citizens conflicting conceptions of freedom and equality.

    Rawls aims to provide, he says, an acceptable philosoph-ical and moral basis for the basic structure of a democratic

    society, understood as excluding a caste, slave, racist,

    confessional, or aristocratic state, by interpreting freedom

    and equality (Rawls 2001).

    The original position in JF models the freedom and

    equality of citizens of a democratic society, which Rawls

    views not as a fixed natural order but as structured by

    values and principles, rules and procedures. A just demo-cratic society is, in Rawlss view, a fair system of social

    cooperation guided by publicly recognized rules and pro-

    cedures which those cooperating accept as appropriate to

    regulate their conduct. Each citizen rationally seeks to

    advance his or her own good, but all do so on terms each

    can accept as fair according to an agreed-upon public

    standard. According to Rawls, reasonable, as distinct

    from merely rational, persons are ready to propose, orto acknowledge when proposed by others, the princi-

    ples needed to specify what can be seen by all as fair

    terms of cooperation (Rawls 2001). Such citizens have

    the requisite mental and psychological capacities, namely,

    (1) the capacity to have, revise, and rationally pursue

    a conception of the good, and (2) the capacity to under-

    stand, apply, and act from (not merely in accordance with)

    the principles of justice that specify the fair terms of socialcooperation. According to Rawls, having these two moral

    powers (of rationality and reasonableness) to the requi-

    site threshold degree is both necessary and sufficient for

    Original Position O 787

    O

  • the status of equal citizen (Rawls 2001). Rawls regards each

    citizen as a free person in two respects: (a) a citizens public

    or legal identity as a free person is not affected by changes

    over time in his or her determinate conception of the

    good, and (b) citizens are self-authenticating sources of

    valid claims, that is, they are entitled to make claims on

    their institutions so as to advance their own conceptionsof the good (Rawls 2001). According to nondemocratic

    views, only claims derived from members ascribed roles

    in a social hierarchy justified by religious or aristocratic

    values, or from their duties and obligations to society, have

    weight. In developing JF, Rawls uses a political conception

    of the person that is based, he says, on the way citizens are

    regarded in the public political culture of a liberal-

    democratic society, in its basic political texts (constitu-tions and declarations of human rights), and in the his-

    torical tradition of interpretation of those texts (Rawls

    2001). In developing LP, however, Rawls avoids using

    this liberal political conception of the person (See the

    entries on Second Original Position and Law ofPeoples in this encyclopedia).

    Recall the three points of view Rawls distinguishes:

    (1) that of ourselves, you and me in the present,(2) that of citizens in a just society (perhaps a future,

    reformed version of ones own society), and (3) that of

    the parties in the original position. In describing the

    parties, we are not describing persons as we find them,

    Rawls says, but instead according to how we want to

    model rational representatives of free and equal citizens

    (Rawls 2001). As Rawls models the parties in the original

    position in JF, each is rational, all are symmetrically situ-ated behind the veil of ignorance, each is responsible for

    the fundamental interests of a free and equal citizen, each

    evaluates alternative principles by estimating how well

    they secure the primary goods essential to realize the

    higher-order interests of the citizen for whom each acts

    as a trustee, and all have equal rights in the procedure for

    reaching agreement and choosing a conception of justice

    from the available alternatives (Rawls 1993). Thus Rawlssets up the original position in JF to model citizens

    freedom and equality. In LP, since he is developing basic

    principles for a just international order, Rawls stipulates

    that each of the parties in the original position is respon-

    sible for the fundamental interests of a society that

    respects human rights (see the entries on Law of Peoplesand Second Original Position in this encyclopedia).

    Using the original position, Rawls argues in JF for thefollowing principles: (1) Each person has the same inde-

    feasible claim to a fully adequate scheme of equal basic

    liberties, which scheme is compatible with the same

    scheme of liberties for all; and (2) social and economic

    inequalities are to satisfy two conditions: (a) they are to be

    attached to offices and positions open to all under condi-

    tions of fair equality of opportunity; and (b) they are to

    be to the greatest benefit of the least-advantaged members

    of society. Principle (2b) is the difference principle

    (Rawls 2001).

    Rawls says he characterizes the original position of JFby various stipulations, each with its own reasoned back-

    ing, so that the agreement that would be reached can be

    worked out deductively by reasoning from how the parties

    are situated and described, the information available to

    them, the alternatives open to them, and what they count

    as reasons. The parties are only rational, not reasonable (in

    the sense given above), but (due to the stipulations,

    including the veil of ignorance and the parties task ofsecuring the primary goods) they are subject to reasonable

    restrictions (imposed by Rawls) on the reasons they can

    give each other for favoring one principle or rejecting

    another. The principles that would be chosen unani-

    mously by the parties in the original position (namely,

    Rawls argues, the pair he proposes) are the ones that can

    best secure the fundamental interests of every citizen, if

    their societys basic structure is reformed according tothese principles (Rawls 2001). Therefore, reasonable citi-

    zens of such a society would support these principles, and

    people in nondemocratic or non-well-ordered democratic

    societies, who are reasonable and want their society to be

    a just democratic society of free and equal citizens, will

    want to know which principles would be chosen by the

    (rational, not reasonable) parties in the original position,

    and will be ready to propose and abide by these principles.Similarly, when developing the principles and norms

    of a just international order in LP, Rawls characterizes

    the original position by various stipulations. The parties

    are only rational, not reasonable, but due to the veil of

    ignorance and the parties task, they are subject to reason-

    able restrictions (imposed by Rawls) on the reasons they

    can offer each other when advocating or opposing princi-

    ples. The principles that would be chosen unanimously bythe parties are the ones that can best secure the funda-

    mental interests of every people and best secure basic

    human rights globally, if peoples establish a Society of

    Peoples based on these principles. (See the entries on

    Second Original Position and Law of Peoples in thisencyclopedia).

    In JF Rawls assumes that a democratic society of free

    and equal citizens will be pluralistic. If all citizens are toendorse the conception of justice freely, it must, he says, be

    able to gain the support of citizens who affirm different

    and opposing though reasonable comprehensive doc-

    trines, in which case there would be an overlapping

    788 O Original Position

  • consensus (see Rawls (1993, 1999), as well as the entries

    on Political Liberalism and Public Reason in thisencyclopedia). Rawls structures the original position and

    formulates his principles and his argument so as to show

    that the content of a defensible conception of justice can

    be derived from certain ideas drawn from the public

    political culture of a democratic society. He does not, he

    emphasizes, look to the comprehensive doctrines that infact exist and then frame a political conception that strikes

    a balance between them expressly designed to gain their

    allegiance (Rawls 2001). Instead, he puts citizens compre-

    hensive doctrines behind the veil of ignorance. This makes

    it possible, he says, to find a political conception of justice

    that can be the focus of an overlapping consensus and

    thereby serve as a public basis of justification in a society

    marked by the fact of reasonable pluralism (Rawls 1993).Similarly, in LP, Rawls does not survey the globes com-

    prehensive doctrines and then frame a political concep-

    tion that strikes a compromise among them. However, he

    does develop a political conception of international justice

    that can be the focus of an overlapping consensus among

    reasonable peoples. (See the entry on Law of Peoples inthis encyclopedia).

    Rawls stipulates in JF that the parties in the originalposition are mutually disinterested (Rawls 1971). This is

    another way he both models citizens as free and equal and

    avoids building in assumptions about their conceptions of

    the good. If each party focuses only on securing the fun-

    damental interests of one citizen, then no citizen will be

    either double-counted or discounted, and every citizens

    fundamental interests will get secured. The stipulation of

    mutual disinterest does not, he emphasizes, mean thatthe parties or the citizens they represent are egoists, that

    is, individuals with only certain kinds of interests, for

    example, in wealth, prestige, and domination. Instead, he

    explains, it avoids ruling out the possibility that their

    spiritual aims may be opposed, in the way that the aims

    of those of different religions may be opposed (Rawls

    1971). Even though Rawls recognizes that citizens in soci-

    ety will of course have ties of sentiment and affection, andwant to advance the interests of others and to see their

    ends attained, he stipulates that the parties in the original

    position are not moved by affection or esteem to confer

    benefits on any others, nor moved by envy or rancor to

    deny benefits to any others; he stipulates mutual disinter-

    est in order to ensure that the principles of justice do not

    depend upon what he calls strong assumptions (Rawls

    1971). The veil of ignorance ensures that the mutuallydisinterested parties, each aiming to secure the fundamen-

    tal interests of one citizen, do not know the specific values

    or aims of the citizen they each represent. It forces each

    party to consider how each principle might affect every-

    one, especially the people who would end up in the least

    advantaged positions. Each partys best option is the prin-

    ciple(s) that will best enable the (represented) citizen to

    pursue his or her goals, whatever these goals turn out to be

    and whatever position the citizen turns out to occupy.

    Similarly, in LP an analogous stipulation that the parties

    in the original position are mutually disinterested ensuresthat every peoples fundamental interests will get secured

    in the Society of Peoples.

    The question Rawls tries to answer in JF is the follow-

    ing, he says: Which principles are most appropriate

    for a democratic society that not only professes but

    wants to take seriously the idea that citizens are free and

    equal, and tries to realize that idea in its main institutions?

    He rephrases this question as follows: Once we view ademocratic society as a fair system of social cooperation

    between citizens regarded as free and equal, what princi-

    ples are most appropriate to it? (Rawls 2001). The prin-

    ciples are to specify basic rights and liberties and to

    regulate fundamental social and economic inequalities,

    namely, Rawls says, the differences in citizens prospects

    over a complete life, as these are affected by such things as

    their social class of origin, their native endowments, theiropportunities for education, and their good or ill fortune

    over the course of life. These inequalities are, he says, his

    primary concern in JF (Rawls 2001). After arguing for the

    first principle (which ascribes equal basic liberties), Rawls

    considers whether any differences in citizens life prospects

    can be consistent with the idea of free and equal citizen-

    ship in a society that is seen as a fair system of cooperation,

    and if so, what principles establish the legitimacy of thosedifferences.

    This question about legitimate inequalities requires an

    answer that appeals only to principles and values that each

    citizen can endorse, because as participants in a constitu-

    tional democracy, they will use the coercive power of their

    state to conform their societys institutions to these prin-

    ciples and values, thus wielding political power over one

    another. No answer is immediately evident to Rawls; hesays that his convictions about principles regulating social

    and economic inequalities are much less firm and assured

    than his firmest considered convictions about equal basic

    rights and liberties, the fair value of the political liberties

    and fair equality of opportunity (Rawls 2001). Therefore,

    Rawls considers the appropriate method for finding the

    guidance that is needed. He proposes taking guidance

    from his firmest considered convictions about the natureof a democratic society. In order to see whether the

    combined assertion of those convictions by means of the

    original position will help to identify an appropriate

    Original Position O 789

    O

  • distributive principle, he stipulates that the parties assume

    that the equal basic liberties and fair opportunities are

    already secured, and that they then decide how to regulate

    inequalities. Thus Rawls looks outside the sphere of dis-

    tributive justice more narrowly construed, he says, to see

    whether an appropriate distributive principle is singled

    out by his firmest convictions once their essential elementsare represented in the original position (Rawls 2001). In

    LP, when developing the principles of international justice,

    Rawls takes guidance from his firmest convictions about

    basic human rights.

    Rawls does not hold that the original position is in all

    cases the device most appropriate to use for answering

    questions about justice; indeed, he suggests otherwise, by

    showing how his specific question about principles fora democratic society guides him in specifying and using

    the original position in JF. Similarly, in LP Rawls shows

    how his specific question about the fundamental principles

    and norms of a reasonably just international order guides

    him in setting up and using the original position at the

    second level, that is, the level of relations among politically

    organized groups, which are more complex and thus logi-

    cally higher level than relations among individuals.One can use the original position to guide judgment

    when applying the principles of JF to constitutional

    arrangements, laws, and policies, Rawls says; each ques-

    tion is to be considered from the point of view of the

    original position, with its knowledge conditions appropri-

    ately modified for each case (Rawls 1971). Further, one can

    use the original position to determine principles for

    addressing injustice. The parties in the original positionof JF assume strict compliance, that is, that citizens can

    and will generally comply with the chosen principles; they

    assume that a just society can in due course be achieved,

    and they choose principles of justice suitable for favorable

    conditions (Rawls 1971). The conception of justice devel-

    oped on the assumption of strict compliance belongs to

    ideal theory and sets up the goal to guide social reform.

    Nonideal theory, including principles for addressinginjustice, can be worked out from the point of view of

    the original position, but only after the ideal is specified

    (Rawls 1971). The same holds for the Law of Peoples

    (Rawls 1999).

    Charles Beitz and Thomas Pogge criticize JFs original

    position, arguing that international interdependence has

    become so extensive, and international inequalities so

    extreme, that principles of social justice should applyglobally; and that therefore the parties in the original

    position must not represent a single societys citizens but

    the population of the entire globe, all matters of national

    citizenship being concealed by the veil of ignorance.

    A global original position would, they contend, yield glob-

    ally applicable analogues of the two principles of JF (See

    the entry on Law of Peoples in this encyclopedia).Amartya Sen (2009) criticizes Rawlss ideal theory as

    transcendental and of little practical use for addressing

    real-world injustices. In reply, Samuel Freeman (2010)

    notes that although consequentialists (including Sen)regard ideal theories as unnecessary, Rawls opposed

    consequentialism by arguing that justice restricts permis-

    sible means for promoting good consequences. Moreover,

    Freeman argues, idealizations designed to systematize our

    moral convictions can clarify ideas about justice, guide

    thinking about long-term or extensive reforms, and

    inspire action. If Freeman and Rawls are right, the original

    position can be of significant help in the effort to securejustice both domestically and globally.

    Related TopicsContractarianism Law of PeoplesPolitical LiberalismPublic ReasonRawls, John Second Original Position Social Contract

    ReferencesBernstein AR (2009) Kant, Rawls, and cosmopolitanism: toward perpet-

    ual peace and the law of peoples. Jb Recht Ethik Annu Rev Law Ethics

    17:352

    Blake M (2005) International justice. Stanford encyclopedia of philoso-

    phy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/international-justice/

    Cohen J (2003) For a democratic society. In: Freeman S (ed) The

    Cambridge companion to Rawls. Cambridge University Press,

    Cambridge

    Dworkin R (1973) The original position. Univ Chic Law Rev

    40(3):500533

    Freeman S (2010) A new theory of justice. New York Review of Books,

    New York, pp 5860

    Freeman S (2007) The burdens of public justification: constructivism,

    contractualism, and publicity. Polit Philos Econ 4:543

    Mandle J (2009) Rawlss A theory of justice: an introduction. Cambridge

    University Press, Cambridge

    Nagel T (1973) Rawls on justice. Philos Rev 82(2):220234

    Rawls J (1971) A theory of justice. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Rawls J (1993) Political liberalism. Columbia University Press, New York

    Rawls J (1999) The law of peoples. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Rawls J (2001) Justice as fairness: a restatement. Harvard University Press,

    Cambridge

    Rawls J (2007) Lectures on the history of political philosophy. Harvard

    University Press, Cambridge

    Scanlon TM (2003) Rawls on justification. In: Freeman S (ed) The

    Cambridge companion to Rawls. Cambridge University Press,

    Cambridge

    Sen A (2009) The idea of justice. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    790 O Original Position