on sameness and necessity

13
REVIEW ARTICLE ON SAMENESS AND NECESSITY PATRICIA HA"A NAMING AND NECESSITY, revised edition By S a u l K r i p k e (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1980, pp. 172) Since its initial publication in 1972, Naming and Necessity has exerted an enormous influence on discussions in philosophy of language, epistemology, and metaphysics. Perhaps its greatest impact has been on issues concerning reference and essentialism. form the basis for the causal theory of names, which is alleged to overturn description theories. His defense of essentialism has occasioned its philo- sophical revival. Kripke's views on reference Kripke's influence is due partly to the nature of his claims: philos- ophers are often captivated by a vigorous defense of prima facie implausible positions. Substantively, Naming and necessity offers discussions of the theoretical foundations of philosophy of language, epistemology, and meta- physics. Consequently, Kripke's work is of the greatest interest to anyone interested in the foundations of philosophical inquiry, despite (or perhaps even because of) the fact that he is more concerned to consider the con- ceptual requirements of theories than to provide fully developed theories of his own. The present volume is a lightly revised edition of the original lec- tures. There are no substantive alterations, beyond a brief preface which offers several clarifications and an account of the genesis of Kripke's ideas. tures have provoked comment and criticism, but their availability has been limited b the substantial cost of the volume in which they initially appeared;I indeed part of Kripke's aim in preparing a second edition has been to produce a less expensive and more widely distributed version of the lec- tures. A heavily revised edition would thus have reduced its value to those seeking to understand the controversies generated by the original lectures. This absence of substantive revision is a virtue. Kripke's lec- The variety of topics which Kripke addresses is almost staggering; his discussions include remarks on names, reference, meaning, identity 91

Upload: patricia-hanna

Post on 02-Oct-2016

215 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: ON SAMENESS AND NECESSITY

REVIEW ARTICLE

ON SAMENESS AND NECESSITY

PATRICIA H A " A

NAMING AND NECESSITY, r ev i sed e d i t i o n By Saul Kripke (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard Univers i ty P r e s s , 1980, pp. 172)

Since i ts i n i t i a l pub l i ca t ion i n 1972, Naming and Necessity has exe r t ed a n enormous in f luence on d i scuss ions i n philosophy of language, epistemology, and metaphysics. Perhaps i t s g r e a t e s t impact has been on i s s u e s concerning r e fe rence and e s sen t i a l i sm. form t h e b a s i s f o r t he causa l theory of names, which i s a l l e g e d t o over turn d e s c r i p t i o n t h e o r i e s . H i s defense of e s s e n t i a l i s m has occasioned i t s phi lo- soph ica l r e v i v a l .

Kripke 's views on r e fe rence

Kripke 's i n f luence is due p a r t l y t o t h e n a t u r e of h i s claims: phi los- ophers are o f t e n cap t iva t ed by a vigorous defense of prima f a c i e implaus ib le p o s i t i o n s . Subs tan t ive ly , Naming and necessity o f f e r s d i scuss ions of t h e t h e o r e t i c a l foundat ions of phi losophy of language, epistemology, and meta- physics . Consequently, Kripke 's work is of t h e g r e a t e s t i n t e r e s t t o anyone i n t e r e s t e d i n the foundat ions of ph i losoph ica l i nqu i ry , d e s p i t e (o r perhaps even because o f ) t he f a c t t h a t he is more concerned t o cons ider t h e con- cep tua l requirements of t h e o r i e s than t o provide f u l l y developed t h e o r i e s of h i s own.

The p resen t volume is a l i g h t l y r ev i sed e d i t i o n of t h e o r i g i n a l lec- t u r e s . There a r e no subs t an t ive a l t e r a t i o n s , beyond a b r i e f p re face which o f f e r s s e v e r a l c l a r i f i c a t i o n s and an account of t he genes i s of Kripke 's i deas . t u r e s have provoked comment and cr i t ic ism, b u t t h e i r a v a i l a b i l i t y has been l i m i t e d b t h e s u b s t a n t i a l cos t of t h e volume i n which they i n i t i a l l y appeared; I indeed p a r t of Kripke 's aim i n prepar ing a second e d i t i o n has been t o produce a less expensive and more widely d i s t r i b u t e d vers ion of t h e lec- t u r e s . A heav i ly r ev i sed e d i t i o n would thus have reduced its va lue t o those seeking t o understand the con t rove r s i e s generated by the o r i g i n a l l e c t u r e s .

This absence of subs t an t ive r e v i s i o n i s a v i r t u e . Kripke 's lec-

The v a r i e t y of t o p i c s which Kripke addresses is almost s t agge r ing ; h i s d i scuss ions inc lude remarks on names, re ference , meaning, i d e n t i t y

91

Page 2: ON SAMENESS AND NECESSITY

92

PATRICIA HANNA

s t a t e m e n t s , cont ingency and n e c e s s i t y , t h e a p r i o r i and t h e a p o s t e r i o r i , p o s s i b i l i t y , c o u n t e r f a c t u a l s , e s s e n t i a l i s m , and materialism. It would b e impossible i n l i m i t e d space t o d i s c u s s a l l o r even most of t h e s e t o p i c s i n d e t a i l , and I s h a l l n o t a t tempt t o do so. I n s t e a d I s h a l l focus on two of Kripke 's most provoca t ive d i s c u s s i o n s , namely t h o s e concerning e s s e n t i a l i s m and t h e s t a n d a r d meter.

1. E s s e n t i a l i s m

Kripke 's views on e s s e n t i a l i s m are connected w i t h h i s concept ion of r i g i d d e s i g n a t i o n , i t s e l f impor tan t ly r e l a t e d t o complex i s s u e s of r e f e r e n c e and t ransworld i d e n t i f i c a t i o n . t h a t d e s i g n a t e s t h e same o b j e c t i n a l l p o s s i b l e worlds";2 hence h i s i n t u i t i v e test of r i g i d i t y : " L e t ' s c a l l something a r i g i d d e s i g n a t o r i f i n every p o s s i b l e world i t d e s i g n a t e s t h e same o b j e c t , a n o n r i g i d o r a c c i d e n t a l d e s i g n a t o r i f t h a t is n o t t h e c a ~ e . " ~ Now on t h e assumption t h a t names and g e n e r a l terms d e s i g n a t i n g n a t u r a l k inds ( h e r e a f t e r , kind terms) are r i g i d d e s i g n a t o r s , i t is r e l a t i v e l y easy t o see how one might conclude t h a t a s t r o n g , n o n - t r i v i a l vernion of e s s e n t i a l i s m must be t r u e . Names desi;:nate t h e same o b j e c t i n a l l p o s s i b l e worlds , whi le kind terms d e s i g n a t e t h e same kind of o b j e c t in a l l p o s s i b l e worlds . Thus, f o r example, "Kripke" must always denote Kripke, and " t i g e r " must always denote t i g e r s , j u s t as "Kripke" cannot denote W i t t g e n s t e i n , and " t i g e r " cannot denote f i s h o r dogs (though of course W i t t g e n s t e i n might have been named "Kripke" o r t h e word " t i g e r " used as t h e kind term f o r dogs) . i t seems t h a t t h e r e must be some f e a t u r e ( o r set of f e a t u r e s ) i n v i r t u e of which Kripke and t i g e r s are ( o r i n theory could be) marked o f f from Wittgen- s t e i n and dogs r e s p e c t i v e l y , i .e., each must have some p r o p e r t i e s e s s e n t i a l l y . Moreover, t h e s e p r o p e r t i e s cannot be exhausted by such t r i v i a l l y e s s e n t i a l p r o p e r t i e s as being s e l f - i d e n t i c a l , be ing four-s ided i f square , be ing warm- blooded o r n o t warm-blooded, o r be ing t h e same weight as o n e s e l f . erties" can b e taken as e s s e n t i a l t o an o b j e c t i n t h e s e n s e t h a t t h e o b j e c t w i l l possess them i n every p o s s i b l e wor ld ; they are only t r i v i a l l y essent ia l , however, s i n c e e v e r y t h i n g has t h e s e p r o p e r t i e s e s s e n t i a l l y . I n consequence, t h i s s o r t o f proper ty cannot s e r v e t o d i s t i n g u i s h one o b j e c t o r kind of o b j e c t from a n o t h e r , and cannot t h e r e f o r e be r e l e v a n t t o t h e i s s u e of terms as r i g i d d e s i g n a t o r s .

By a r i g i d d e s i g n a t o r Kripke means "a tern

Hence

Such "prop-

I n view of t h e foregoing , i t is n o t s u r p r i s i n g t h a t Kripke defends a s t r o n g v e r s i o n of e s s e n t i a l i s m in Naming and Necessity. sugges t t h e c h a r a c t e r of h i s p o s i t i o n :

The fo l lowing passages

. . . f o r a l though t h e man (Nixon) might n o t have been P r e s i d e n t , i t is n o t t h e case t h a t he might no t have been Nixon (though he might n o t have been c a l l e d "Nixon"). (NN 49)

Perhaps i n some p o s s i b l e world Mr. and Mrs. Truman even had a c h i l d which a c t u a l l y became t h e queen of England and w a s passed o f f as t h e c h i l d of o t h e r p a r e n t s . This still would n o t b e a s i t u a t i o n i n

Page 3: ON SAMENESS AND NECESSITY

93

REVIEW ARTICLE

which this very woman whom w e cal l El izabe th the Second w a s t h e c h i l d of M r . and Mrs. Truman, o r so i t seems t o me. (NN 112-13)

L e t us suppose t h a t s c i e n t i s t s have inves t iga t ed the na tu re of gold and found t h a t i t is p a r t of t h e very. na tu re of t h i s subs tance , so t o speak, t h a t i t have the atomic number 79. . . . Suppose [ coun te r f ac tua l ly ] t h a t a l l the a reas which a c t u a l l y conta in gold now, contained i r o n p y r i t e s i n s t ead , o r some o t h e r substance which coun te r f e i t ed the s u p e r f i c i a l p r o p e r t i e s of gold but lacked its atomic s t r u c t u r e . Would w e say , of t h i s counter fac tua l s i t u a t i o n , t h a t i n t h a t s i t u a t i o n gold would not even have been an element (because p y r i t e s is no t an element)? It seems t o me t h a t w e would no t . . . . One would not say t h a t i t would s t i l l be gold i n t h i s poss ib l e world, though gold would then l ack t h e atomic number 79. It would be some o the r s t u f f , some o the r substance. (NN 124)

Kripke's e s sen t i a l i sm is no t only a s t r o n g (non- t r iv ia l ) e s sen t i a l i sm, bu t a s c i e n t i f i c a l l y based e s sen t i a l i sm as w e l l . Kripke t o be e s s e n t i a l i nva r i ab ly t u r n o u t t o be p rope r t i e s d i scoverable by s c i e n t i f i c i nves t iga t ion and (somehow) recognizable as "pa r t of t he nature" of the ob jec t o r kind i n ques t ion . I s h a l l at tempt t o raise some doubts about t h i s s c i e n t i f i c b i a s , and about Kripke's e s s e n t i a l i s t p r o j e c t as a whole, by focusing on h i s claim t h a t t he o r i g i n of an o b j e c t is e s s e n t i a l t o t he o b j e c t ; my remarks w i l l be capable of ex tens ion t o o t h e r purported e s s e n t i a l f e a t u r e s , such as molecular s t r u c t u r e , atomic number, and so on (though I s h a l l no t so extend them e x p l i c i t l y ) . The reason f o r t h i s focus is twofold. F i r s t , t ak ing an ind iv idua l ' s o r i g i n as e s s e n t i a l is i n t u i t i v e l y very p l aus ib l e , and is perhaps t h e most i n t u i t i v e l y convincing of Kripke's e s s e n t i a l i s t claims. Second, Kripke's t h e s i s of t h e necess i ty of o r i g i n h i g h l i g h t s a problem i n h i s treatment of e s sen t i a l i sm as a whole, namely h i s f a i l u r e t o take adequate account of cons idera t ions of context and purpose. By concent ra t ing on t h i s t h e s i s , t he re fo re , i t is poss ib l e t o expose a genera l problem f o r t he essen- t ial ist pos i t i on .

To f i x ideas , w e may note a passage from Colin McGinn's "On t h e

The p rope r t i e s he ld by

Necessity of Origin," i n which Kripke's t h e s i s of the necess i ty of o r i g i n is vigorously defended:

. . . a d u l t s are commonly i d e n t i c a l wi th ch i ld ren , and ch i ld ren with i n f a n t s , i n f a n t s wi th f e t u s e s , and f e t u s e s wi th zygotes. Any attempt t o break t h i s obvious b io logi - c a l cont inui ty he re would su re ly be a r b i t r a r y .

. . . What of gametes and zygotes (and hence persons)? We cannot, i t seems, a v a i l ourse lves of the necess i ty of i d e n t i t y aga in , f o r gametes a r e two and persons are one. But n e i t h e r can w e s t o p s h o r t a t t he zygote, s i n c e i t seems e s s e n t i a l t h a t you come from t h e gametes you

Page 4: ON SAMENESS AND NECESSITY

94

PATRICIA HANNA

ac tua l ly come from, as the following t r a i n of thought makes p la in , Come from Nixon's a c t u a l gametes, i .e., consider a world i n which t h i s occurs. with the f i r s t supposit ion, add my ac tua l gametes t o the aforementioned world and suppose they dewlop i n t o an adu l t . t i t l e t o be m e ? the la t ter individual.

McGinn's idea, then, is t h a t a person's o r i g i n is cons t i t u t ed by the

Suppose, with a view t o z d u c t i o , t h a t I

Now, what is su re ly cornpossible

Which of these individuals has the s t ronger My i n t u i t i o n s seem decis ively t o favor

"actual gametes" from which the person comes, and t h a t o r ig in so conceived is an e s s e n t i a l property of the individual i n question. rendering of the i n t e n t behind Kripke's proposal. idea?

This seem a p rec i se But m u s t we accept t h i s

Before doing so, i t i s worth considering some remarks of Wittgenstein 's:

" A l l r i gh t : the concept of number is defined f o r you as the l o g i c a l sum of these individual i n t e r r e l a t e d con- cepts: cardinal numbers, r a t i o n a l numbers, real numbers, etc.; and i n the same way the concept of a game as the log ica l sum of a corresponding set of sub-concepts."-- It need not be so. For I can give the concept "number" r i g i d limits i n t h i s way, t h a t is , use the word "number" f o r a r i g i d l y l imited concept, but I can a l s o use i t so t h a t the extension of the concept 18 not closed by a f r o n t i e r . And t h i s is how w e do use the word "game." For how is the concept of a game bounded? What s t i l l counts as a game and what no longer does? Can you give the boundary? No. You can draw one; f o r none has so f a r been drawn.5

Wittgenstein 's remarks might seem of doubtful relevance t o a b s t r a c t i s sues of transworld iden t i f i ca t ion . But I think they are very relevant . For on examination it appears t h a t o r ig in essent ia l ism rests on j u s t such a decision t o draw a boundary--in the case under consideration, for the concept of the same person--quite i n general , i .e., without regard fo r t he s p e c i a l purpose which would render the concept usable (cf . P I 6 9 ) . I n the absence of such a purpose, o r ig in essent ia l ism must not only be a r b i t r a r y but is bound t o appear a r b i t r a r y as w e l l . This may be i l l u s t r a t e d as follows.

L e t us consider a case i n which two possible (counterfactual) individ- uals , X and Y, are to be compared with H i t l e r . We w i l l place Hitler's o r ig in a t to. X, w e imagine, l ikewise o r ig ina t e s (from Hitler's gametes) a t to, and from to t o tl has a l i f e which resembles ilitler's i n a l l respects . however, X's l i f e diverges dramatically from Hitler's: l e t us imagine t h a t k i eventually converts t o Judaism, is ordained as a rabbi, and devotes his t i m e , enezgy, and resources t o the f i g h t against anti-Semitism. By con t r a s t , Y does not o r ig ina t e a t t but instead appears on the scene a t tl. But a f t e r tl, w e imagine, Y's l i f e Ps indis t inguishable from Hitler's: he serves i n the Austrian army i n World War I, becomes p o l i t i c a l l y ac t ive , rises t o power i n Germany, succeeds in exterminating mil l ions of J e w s , and so on.

After t

Page 5: ON SAMENESS AND NECESSITY

95

REVIEW ARTICLE

Both X and Y represent coun te r f ac tua l ly poss ib le persons. The important question is whether we can i n t e l l i g i b l y d i scuss counter fac tua l s i t u a t i o n s involving Hitler i n which Hit ler ' s l i f e i s i d e n t i c a l i n a l l r e spec t s t o X ' s l i f e o r t o Y's l i f e . represents such a p o s s i b i l i t y f o r H i t l e r , and t o a f f i rming t h a t X's l i f e represents such a p o s s i b i l i t y i n every relevant contex t (i.e., i n every poss ib l e world i n which H i t l e r e x i s t s a t a l l ) . H i t l e r i n v i r t u e of o r i g i n , while Y cannot be so i den t i f i ed . descr ibed , our counter fac tua l case sugges ts t h a t t h i s is coun te r in tu i t i ve a t b e s t ; and two var i a t ions on the case may expla in why t h i s is so.

Kripke's e s s e n t i a l i s t views commit him t o denying t h a t Y

On t h i s view, i n o the r words, X must be But as so f a r

(1) I f w e imagine t h a t X and Y a r e considered i n sepa ra t e and inde- pendent contex ts ( d i f f e r e n t poss ib l e wor lds) , then i t is easy t o understand the p o s s i b i l i t y of i den t i fy ing each ind iv idua l wi th H i t l e r . Suppose, f o r example, t h a t one's i n t e r e s t i s i n considering what Hitler's l i f e would have been l i k e had he found i n Judaism a source of i n s p i r a t i o n and comfort; he re it may be poss ib le t o i d e n t i f y X wi th Hitler (or i t may n o t , depending on y e t f u r t h e r contex tua l cons idera t ions) . By c o n t r a s t , Y might e a s i l y represent a poss ib l e Hitler i n a context i n which one wishes t o consider a poss ib l e world where l l i t l e r is somewhat younger than he i n f a c t w a s .

(2) If both X and Y are pos i t ed i n a s i n g l e counter fac tua l contex t , i t might s e e m t h a t only one of them could be i d e n t i f i e d wi th Hitler. I n a sense t h i s is t r i v i a l l y t r u e , bu t i t should n o t be allowed t o obscure t h e f a c t t h a t w e cannot decide i n advance which of them i s Hit ler . Indeed, t he re is nothing t o be decided absolutely--or i n general--at a l l . the purpose f o r which the counter fac tua l s i t u a t i o n is being employed is required f o r any such dec is ion . Depending on the po in t of our i nves t iga t ion , i t might turn out t h a t o r i g i n i s over r id ing , i n which case ( i n the absence of f u r t h e r competitors) X would be H i t l e r ; o r t he charac te r of Hitler's subsequent a c t i v i - t ies might be over r id ing , i n which case Y could be so i d e n t i f i e d .

A f u l l e r s p e c i f i c a t i o n of

The poin t of t hese cases i s simply t h i s : what counts as the same ob jec t (or kind of ob jec t ) can be determined only wi th in the context i n which the question of sameness i s r a i sed . contex t , then it i s l i k e l y t h a t they w i l l be s e t t l e d i n accordance wi th the s t r i c t u r e s of sc ience ; w i th in such a contex t , f o r example, o r i g i n (e.g., gametes), atomic weight, o r molecular o r gene t ic s t r u c t u r e w i l l l i k e l y decide the i s sue . I n such contexts w e can d i scuss , e.g., persons i n terms of a " r i g i d l y l imi t ed concept," j u s t as the concept of number can be thus l imi t ed f o r a p a r t i c u l a r purpose. But s c i e n t i f i c contex ts are not t he only contexts wi th in which w e can l eg i t ima te ly raise t h e ques t ion whether a is t h e same ob jec t as b, and s c i e n t i f i c purposes are accordingly n o t t he only purposes f o r which counter fac tua l v a r i a t i o n s on the a c t u a l world may be en ter ta ined . Once t h i s i s seen. w e remove the temptation t o view counter fac tua l inqui ry as d is - c los ing e s s e n t i a l f ea tu re s of ob jec t s witliout regard t o the context of such inquiry i t o e l f . To bel ieve i n A pr iv i leged d i sc losu re of t h l s eort is anal- ogous t o be l iev ing t h a t a person whose s p e c i a l i n t e r e s t is i n board games can cha rac t e r i ze games i general by a de f in i c ion t a i l o r e d t o those of h i s own i n t e r e s t ( c f . P I 3).

I f such ques t ions are r a i sed i n a b io log ica l

2 The language of "disclosure" i s , however, misleading; t h e cons idera t ion

Page 6: ON SAMENESS AND NECESSITY

96

PATRICIA HANNA

of counterfactual contexts need be no more mysterious than t h e consideration of Wittgenstein's bui lders i n P I 2. than anyone t o remove the sense of mystery of ten associated with t a l k of possible worlds: as he i n s i s t s , "[pJossible worlds are s t i p u l a t e d , not d i s c o v e m d . . .'I (NN 44). But although w e are thereby disabused of the notion t h a t t he propert ies of possible worlds are t o be discovered by a raeta- physical journey, Kripke's e s s e n t i a l i s t s t i pu la t ions seem confined t o what is s c i e n t i f i c a l l y discoverable i n the actual world. And he appears t o have been l e d to h i s e s s e n t i a l i s t views by the way i n which he conceives of r i g i d desig- nation, when the latter is viewed as an adequacy condition of theories of prop- er names and kind tenus. important passage on names i n Philosophical I n v e s t i g a t i o n s :

Kripke himself has perhaps done more

In explaining t h i s i t v i l l be useful t o cite M

Consider t h i s example. I f one says "Moses did not ex i s t " , t h i s may mean various things. It may mean: t he Israelite@ did not have a s i n g l e leader when they with- drew from Egypt--or: t h e i r leader w a s not ca l l ed Moses-- or: t he re cannot have been anyone who accomplished a l l t h a t the Bible relates of Moses--or: etc., etc.--We may say, following Russell: the name '!Moses'' can be defined by various descriptions. l e d the Israelites through the wilderness", "the man who l ived a t t h a t t i m e and place and was then ca l l ed 'Moses'", "the man who as a ch i ld w a s taken out of the N i l e by Pharaoh's daughter" and so on. And according as w e assume one de f in i t i on o r another t h e proposit ion "Moses did not exist ' ' acquires a d i f f e ren t sense, and so does every other proposit ion about Moses. . . . ready t o s u b s t i t u t e some one of these descriptions f o r "Moses"? I s h a l l perhaps say: By "Moses" I understand the man who did what the B i b l e relates of Moses, o r a t any rate a good deal of i t . But how much? H a v e I decided how much m u s t be proved f a l s e f o r me t o give up my propomition as f a l s e ? H a s t he name "Moses" got a fixed and unequivocal use f o r me i n a l l possible cases?-- Is i t not the case t h a t I have, so t o speak, a whole series of props i n readiness, and am ready t o lean on one i f another should be taken from under m e and vice versa?

For example, as "the man who

But when I make a statement about Moses,--am I always

. . . Should it be s a i d t h a t I am using a word whose meaning

I don't know, and so am t a lk ing nonsense?--Say what you choose, so long as it does not prevent you from seeing the f ac t s . (PI 79)

Russell 's "s ingle description" theory i s obviously implaueible, both f o r reasons developed by Kripke and f o r those suggested by Wittgenstein him- se l f . i t s e l f a theory, i s recognizably r e l a t ed t o the "cluster concept theory" of names which Kripke g r i t i c i z e s a t length.7 Although Kripke's criticism eeem to me unsuccessful, Instead I wish

Wittgenstein 's view likewise emphasizes descr ipt ions and, while not

I s h a l l not discuss t h e point d i r ec t ly .

Page 7: ON SAMENESS AND NECESSITY

97

REVIEW ARTICLE

t o no te the e s s e n t i a l i s t b i a s i n Kripke's use of t h e concept of r i g i d desig- na t ion . E a r l i e r w e no t i ced how one might conclude t h a t a non- t r iv i a l ve r s ion of e s sen t i a l i sm must be t r u e : i f names, f o r example, des igna te the same ob jec t i n every poss ib l e world, i t i s tempting t o conclude t h a t Moses, e .g . , must have some p r o p e r t i e s e s s e n t i a l l y . our previous remarks concerning con tex t , w e can sugges t a way of r e s i s t i n g t h i s temptation.

By combining Wit tgens te in ' s view of names wi th

Put somewhat s t a r k l y , i t is a mistake t o suppose t h a t t h e no t ion of r i g i d des igna t ion , when taken a lone , has any impl i ca t ions f o r e s sen t i a l i sm. It appears t o e n t a i l e s sen t i a l i sm i n t h e context of Kripke's d i scuss ion ; bu t t h i s appearance is due t o t h e e s s e n t i a l i s t i n t e r p r e t a t i o n i m p l i c i t i n t h e d iscuss ion i t s e l f . S p e c i f i c a l l y , i t can seem impossible t o s a t i s f y t h e require- ment of r i g i d i t y without e s sen t i a l i sm only i f we read "objec t of t he same essence" f o r " the same objec t . " f o r we a r e a p t t o seek a guarantee of sameness of des igna t ion across p o s s i b l e worlds; and i f a l l cons idera t ions of purpose and contex t are l e f t ou t of account, we a r e l ikewise a p t t o p o s i t contex t - f ree p r o p e r t i e s of th ings which cha rac t e r i ze them abso lu te ly ( i . e . , e s sences ) , Now considered i n i s o l a t i o n , t he search f o r a guarantee of sameness i s no t wi thout motivation. From the f a c t t h a t "Moses" has no f ixed meaning, o r t h a t "game" has no f ixed boundary, i t does no t follow t h a t anything can count a s Moses o r as a game; the re are l i m i t s of i n t e l l i g i b i l i t y on our purposes, however s p e c i a l they may be i n a given contex t . But t h e reading of "objec t of t h e same essence" f o r " the same object ' ' is emphatically not re- qui red , f o r i f we have enough of Wi t tgens te in ' s "descr ip t ions" of Moses, then w e have Moses. And the re is no reason t o suppose t h a t some i n v a r i a n t desc r ip t ion o r set of desc r ip t ions i s necessary t o in su re r i g i d i t y of des igna t ion , any more than us ing the word "game" commits us t o a set of necessary and s u f f i c i e n t con- d i t i o n s governing i t s use. For a s Kripke himself is aware, the s o r t s of th ings we can say of poss ib l e worlds are t h e s o r t s of th ings w e can say of t h e a c t u a l world.

Th i s reading can indeed appear t o be requi red ,

Our conclusion, then, is t h a t i f r i g i d des igna t ion is given a non-

Indeed one's theory may be question-begging i n t e r p r e t a t i o n , i t is poss ib l e t o s a t i s f y the requirement of r i g i d i t y wi thout a commitment t o e s sen t i a l i sm. q u i t e a n t i - e s s e n t i a l i s t , as is i l l u s t r a t e d by Russe l l ' s s i m p l i s t i c s i n g l e desc r ip t ion theory. For although t h i s theory is untenable, i ts d e f e c t s are not t r aceab le t o e r r o r s about r i g i d des igna t ion . For desc r ip t ion t h e o r i e s , sameness is determined by desc r ip t ions . Thus i f our desc r ip t ion of A r i s t o t l e is " the last g r e a t philosopher of an t iqu i ty , ' ' then i f some ind iv idua l is t he l a s t g rea t philosopher of a n t i q u i t y , t h a t person is ( i d e n t i c a l wi th) A r i s t o t l e . To oper- a t e w i th such an impoverished desc r ip t ion may be p o i n t l e s s i n most contex ts , bu t one does not thereby s i n aga ins t t h e requirement of r i g i d des igna t ion , nor incur an ob l iga t ion t o produce an essence.

Thus Kripke's claims concerning e s sen t i a l i sm and r i g i d des igna t ion seem t o me very doubtful. There is, however, i i c e r t a i n c l a s s of terms covered by Kripke's account which is of s p e c i a l i n t e r e s t . These are what might be c a l l e d "standard" (or"paradigm") terms , such a s "one meter"; and Kripke's views regarding such terms have important ep is temologica l impl ica t ions , s p e c i f i c a l l y f o r h i s claim t h a t t he re is contingent a p r i o r i knowledge. I n the next s ec t ion I s h a l l consider h i s i n t e r e s t i n g and con t rove r s i a l d i scuss ion of t he s tandard meter bar.

Page 8: ON SAMENESS AND NECESSITY

98

PATRICIA H A " A

2 . The Standard Neter Bar

Kripke's d i scuss ion of t he s tandard meter i s of i n t e r e s t f o r many For example, he has argued elsewhere9 t h a t s t rong e s s e n t i a l i s t reasons.

theses depend on preserv ing a sharp d i s t i n c t i o n between the ep is temologica l no t ions of a p o s t e r i o r i and a p r i o r i on t h e one hand, and the metaphysical no t ions of necess i ty and contingency on t h e o the r . t he ex i s t ence of contingent a p r i o r i knowledge, he w i l l obviously have sus- ta ined t h i s sharp d i s t i n c t i o n . Again, h i 3 d iscuss ion provides an i l l u s t r a t i o n of how t h e re ference of c e r t a i n r i g i d des igna tors is f ixed ; i f success fu l , his ana lys i s au tomat ica l ly c a s t s doubt on r i v a l desc r ip t ion accounts. F i n a l l y , Kripke's d i scuss ion of t h e s tandard meter raises independent i s s u e s concerning s tandards and t h e i r r o l e i n language which a r e of ph i losophica l i n t e r e s t i n themselves.

Thus i f he can e s t a b l i s h

Kripke's d i scuss ion of the s tandard meter ba r i s based on a well-known passage i n Philosophical I n v e s t i g a t i o n s . Wittgenstein writes :

There is one t h ing of which one can say n e i t h e r t h a t i t is one metre long, nor t h a t i t is n o t one metre long, and t h a t is t h e s tandard m e t r e i n Paris-but t h i s , of course , i s not t o a s c r i b e any ex t raord inary proper ty t o i t , bu t only t o mark its p e c u l i a r r o l e i n t h e language-game of measuring wi th a metre-rule. ( P I 50)

Kripke, however, remarks: "This seems t o be a very ' ex t raord inary proper ty , ' a c t u a l l y , f o r any s t i c k t o have. I th ink he m u s t be wrong" (NN 5 4 ) . Several i s s u e s seem t o d iv ide Kripke and Wit tgens te in on t h i s p o i n t , which I s h a l l t r y t o d i s t i n g u i s h and treat sepa ra t e ly as f a r as poss ib l e .

Of Wit tgens te in ' s conten t ion , Kripke f i r s t asks : " I f t he s t i c k is a s t i c k , f o r example, 39.37 inches long ( I assume w e have some d i f f e r e n t s tandard f o r i nches ) , why i s n ' t i t one meter long?" (NN 54). is assuming no t merely t h a t w e have some d i f f e r e n t s tandard f o r inches , bu t t h a t t h i s s tandard may se rve as an independent s tandard of t h e meter. Now a necessary condi t ion of i ts func t ioning i n t h i s capac i ty is t h a t i t be capable i n p r i n c i p l e of ove r r id ing judgments a r r ived a t through measurement by the meter bar . But t h e l a t te r w i l l then f a i l t o represent t h e s tandard meter i n t h e (perhaps s p e c i a l o r a r t i f i c i a l ) sense Wittgenstein seems t o in tend: its "pecul ia r r o l e i n t h e language-game" w i l l be assumable by a q u i t e d i f f e r e n t s tandard , and hence not be p e c u l i a r a t a l l .

Here, however, Kripke

Kripke next a l l e g e s t h a t " [ p l a r t of t he problem which is bother ing Wit tgens te in is, of course, t h a t t h i s s t i c k serves as a s tandard of length and so w e can ' t a t t r i b u t e length t o it" (NN 5 4 ) . But once aga in i t is unclear whether t h i s is what is bother ing Wit tgens te in ; w e s h a l l address a few remarks t o tho guomtion b a l m . What W l t t g e t i a t e l n evidently dnea mnintaln I n t h a t WP

cannot i n t e l l i g i b l y asulgii a l r l i R t I i ( e , ~ . , one M L U r ) L o Lila ataiidard iibettar ba r , when the l a t t e r ir, conceived ati the (not a ) standard of measurement t h a t we a r e using.

Page 9: ON SAMENESS AND NECESSITY

99

REVIEW ARTICLE

Rripke himself seems t o view t h i s as the most basic and c ruc ia l In addressing i t he appeals t o h i s technical notion of "f ixing the issue.

reference" of a term:

We could make the de f in i t i on more precise by s t ipu- l a t i n g t h a t one meter is t o be the length of [ s t i c k ] S a t a fixed t i m e to. . . . [The def iner is] using t h i s de f in i t i on not t o give t h e meaning of what he cal led the 'meter, ' but t o fix t h e r e f e r e n c e . . . . There is a ce r t a in length which w e wants t o mark out. . . . Even i f t h i s i s the only standard of length t h a t he uses, t he re is an i m u i t i v e d i f f e r - ence between the phrase 'one meter' and the phrase ' t h e length of S a t to.' t o designate r i g i d l y a c e r t a i n length i n a l l pos- s i b l e worlds, which i n the ac tua l world happens t o be the length of t he s t i c k a t to. On the other hand, ' t he length of S at to' does not designate anything r i g i d l y . In some counterfactual s i t u a t i o n s the s t i c k might have been longer and i n some shor t e r i f various stresses and s t r a i n s had been applied t o i t . (NN 54-55)

These claim seem t o rest on a curious conception of using a standard I s h a l l examine these ques-

The f i r s t phrase is meant

of length, and on a s u b t l e equivocation as w e l l . t ions in turn.

Does Kripke's conception express a usable standard of length? L e t us

Although I have never seen t h i s s t i c k , and have consider a f anc i fu l case. there is a s t i c k i n my study. but the roughest idea of i ts length, I decide t o use i t t o pick ou t a length which is t o be my standard of measurement. I therefore pronounce t h a t "one Hanna" is t o be the length of t he s t i c k i n my study a t 11:OO P.M., 25 February 1981." i n the community.

Suppose t h a t I a m t o ld by a r e l i a b l e source t h a t

This standard is then general ly adopted i n view of my exal ted s t a t u e

Suppose now t h a t while I and my followers rush t o my study, with the aim of hermetically sea l ing the environment, my dog chews off p a r t of one end of t he s t i c k i n an a c t which is never detected. a t 1 1 : l O P.M., w e have not preserved a s t i c k which exemplifies the length of S a t 1 1 : O O P.M. W e must now ask whether a l l of our measurements made Subsequent to 1 1 : l O are necessar i ly mistaken, even though w e are completely unaware of it. Kripke's view seems c l e a r l y t o imply t h a t they are, no matter how extensive our p rac t i ce of measurement may become. But t h i s charge of e r r o r has no real force. Would its subsequent acknowledgement a l t e r any calculat ions, o r lead any buildings t o collapse?

Thus when w e seal up the s t i c k

Of course, t he case is f anc i fu l , and i n p rac t i ce a standard independent of t ha t o r ig ina l ly specif ied w i l l imp l i c i t l y be assumed. But nothing i n Kripke's remarks on r i g i d designation suggests the necessi ty of multiple standards. And t h i s point of p r inc ip l e is c ruc ia l where usable standards are a t issue, f o r Kripke's account provides no motivation f o r an important and common pract ice . In many contexts, w e treat our physical standards i n a very

Page 10: ON SAMENESS AND NECESSITY

100

PATRICIA HANNA

spec ia l fashion: w e would not allow j u s t any s t i c k t o serve as the standard meter; w e take spec ia l measures t o preserve a s t a b l e environment; we improve our means of securing constancy of measurement; and so on. W e could view t h i s p rac t i ce as an attempt t o remove the difference between, e.g., t h e expressions "one meter" and "the length of S a t to."

This difference cannot of course f i n a l l y be removed. indeed an i n t u i t i v e difference between the phrases "one meter" and "the length of S a t tot ' . B u t t h i s difference is not the difference Kripke requires f o r h i s argument, and therein l ies the s u b t l e equivocation previously referred to. The reason for the difference is t h i s : without an e x p l i c i t declarat ion t o the contrary, w e would not normally assume tha t the length of some given s t i c k S is the o n l y standard of the meter i n use. But t h i s assumption governs the hypothetical s i t u a t i o n which Kripke descr ibes; and once t h i s i s appreciated, Kripke's " i n t u i t i v e difference" disappears. In assessing h i s argument, i t i s v i t a l t o d i s t ingu i sh what Kripke terms a "cer ta in length"--namely the l e n g t h of S a t to--from the s t i c k which happens t o be of t h a t length. cannot vary with varying counterfactual s i t u a t i o n s ; f o r it is p rec i se ly t h i s l e n g t h which Kripke's def iner wishes t o mark out when f ix ing the reference of "one meter". The l a t t e r , harever--the s t i c k S which a t t o has t h a t length-- can of course vary i n length i n d i f f e ren t counterfactual contexts. And i t is i n terms of t h i s l a t t e r possible va r i a t ion t h a t Kripke ul t imately explains the i n t u i t i v e difference between the two phrases o r ig ina l ly c i ted. But h i s argu- ment requires an i n t u i t i v e difference between "one meter" and "the certain l e n g t h of S a t to," since the connection between these f ixes the reference of "one meter". He does not , however, o f f e r any reason whatever fo r assuming such a difference, nor does i t seem possible t h a t t he re could be any.

For the re i s

The former

On t he main point a t i s sue , Wittgenstein appears t o hold a view whose t ru th i s unremarkable, namely t h a t where the standard meter bar is the standard of length w e are using, i t cannot be s a i d t o have a c e r t a i n length. For i f one aff i rms the contrary, one immediately confronts the question "What is i t s length?", which, i n the absence of some independent standard, has no c l ea r sense. (Such an aff i rmat ion seems t o presuppose t h a t the standard meter is not "a paradigm i n our language-game; something with which comparison is made" [ P I 501.) Of course, one might respond vacuously t h a t t he standard meter bar is whatever length it is; and oddly enough, Kripke becomes committed t o t h i s response i n h i s discussion of t he contingent a p r i o r i . a t i on of h i s discussion may iden t i fy more c l ea r ly h i s misapprehensions concern- ing the standard meter.

A b r i e f consider-

According t o Kripke, t he s t a t u s of "S is one meter long" is a p r i o r i ,

Kripke's idea, i n o the r words, i s t h a t h i s de f ine r (see the pre- epistemologically speaking; whereas metaphysically speaking i ts s t a t u s is contingent. viously quoted passage) can know a p r i o r i t h a t S is one meter long, but t h a t i t is nevertheless a contingent f a c t t h a t S is one meter long; f o r i f , e.g., heat had been applied to S a t t then a t to S would not have been one meter long. Focusing f i r s t on Kripke s "metaphysical" claim, w e may note t h a t h i s a rgmen t from counterfactual va r i a t ions i n the length of S requires t h i s construal of "S is one meter long": the s t i c k S has some s p e c i f i c length (e.g., 39.37 inches--not merely some length o r other) a t to. ce r t a in ly a contingent t r u t h .

0'

Now t h i s , i f t rue , is But c l ea r ly i t is not a t r u t h which Kripke's

Page 11: ON SAMENESS AND NECESSITY

101

REVIEW ARTICLE

d e f i n e r knows a p r i o r i . s t a n d a r d , i t may very w e l l be something which t h e d e f i n e r does n o t know a t a l l . Epis temologica l ly speaking, t h e n , what is known ( i f anyth ing) about t h e s p e c i f i c l e n g t h of S is known a p o s t e r i o r i .

Indeed, as sugges ted by our d i s c u s s i o n of a "Hanna"

What t h e r e f o r e does Kripke 's d e f i n e r know a p r i o r i when he knows t h a t "S is one meter long"? Merely t h i s : ( a ) t h a t S h a s whatever l e n g t h i t h a s , and (b) t h a t whatever i t s l e n g t h , t h i s l e n g t h w i l l ( through h i s own act of " d e f i n i t i o n " ) be h i s s t a n d a r d of one meter. On Kripke 's view, i n s h o r t , one can h e r e know a p r i o r i t h a t an o b j e c t i s one meter long wi thout knowing, n o r indeed having any i d e a , how long t h a t o b j e c t i s ; S can b e known a p r i o r i t o be one meter long, r e g a r d l e s s of i ts l e n g t h a t to, and i r r e s p e c t i v e of any changes i n l e n g t h i t may undergo a t any o t h e r t i m e s . T h i s , one might remark, i s an "ext raord inary proper ty" f o r anyone w i t h knowledge of t h e metric system t o p o s s e s s ; c e r t a i n l y t h e r e is an enormous " i n t u i t i v e d i f f e r e n c e " between t h i s and customary examples of knowing t h e l e n g t h of an o b j e c t . Kripke 's view t h u s seems t o come t o t h i s : t h a t t h e s t a n d a r d meter b a r is known t o b e as long as i t i s - - sure ly a paradigm case of a u s e l e s s p r o p o s i t i o n ( c f . P I 216).

Once aga in , t h e r e f o r e , Kripke seems t o g e n e r a t e confus ion by c o n f l a t i n g "having length" wi th "having a c e r t a i n length." unavoidable . For Kripke seems t o imply t h a t W i t t g e n s t e i n ' s a l t e r n a t i v e account conunits one t o t h e paradoxica l view t h a t w e cannot a t t r i b u t e l e n g t h t o t h e s t a n d a r d meter b a r , i .e . , t h a t i t i s a l t o g e t h e r wi thout l e n g t h ; and t h i s seems t o be a s t r a n g e s t a n d a r d indeed--a s t a n d a r d , wi thout l e n g t h , w i t h which com- p a r i s o n s of l e n g t h are t o b e made. But Wi t tgena te in is n o t so committed, as h i s r e l a t e d d i s c u s s i o n of c o l o r s t a n d a r d s makes clear :

But t h i s c o n f l a t i o n may seem

L e t us imagine samples of c o l o u r be ing preserved i n P a r i s l i k e t h e s t a n d a r d metre . W e d e f i n e : "sepia" means t h e co lour of t h e s t a n d a r d s e p i a which is t h e r e kept h e r m e t i c a l l y s e a l e d . Then i t w i l l make no s e n s e t o say of t h i s sample t h a t i t is of t h i s co lour o r t h a t i t is n o t . (P I 50)

Obviously Wit tgens te in is speaking of samples of c o l o r ( n o t , e . g . , of shape) ; n o r does he commit himself t o t h e c u r i o u s metaphysical s p e c t a c l e o f , e .g . , an o b j e c t ' s becoming i n v i s i b l e by i t s assuming t h e r o l e of s tandard . then , i s t h e obvious one, namely t h a t , e.g., "It makes no s e n s e t o s a y of t h e s t a n d a r d meter t h a t i t i s of t h i s l e n g t h o r t h a t " does n o t e n t a i l "The s t a n d a r d meter is wi thout length ."

The moral ,

But t h e r e i s a less obvious moral as w e l l . For W i t t g e n s t e i n ' s d i s - cuss ion of bo th t h e meter b a r and c o l o r samples i s h i g h l y c o n t r i v e d and a r t i f i c i a l . Earlier w e c h a r a c t e r i z e d , somewhat metaphor ica l ly , t h e common p r a c t i c e of s t r i v i n g t o remove t h e d i f f e r e n c e between "one meter" and " the l e n g t h of S a t to.'' s c i e n t i f i c o r t e c h n i c a l c o n t e x t s . But t h e s e are n o t t h e only c o n t e x t s , and as always o u r aims are d i v e r s e . d i s c u s s i o n is n e c e s s a r i l y a r t i f i c i a l ; b u t even more a r t i f i c i a l is t h e i d e a of s t i p u l a t i n g t h a t one meter is t o b e t h e l e n g t h of S a t a f i x e d t i m e t o . Once

This a i m can assume s i g n i f i c a n c e i n a v a r i e t y of

It is f o r t h i s reason t h a t W i t t g e n s t e i n ' s

Page 12: ON SAMENESS AND NECESSITY

102

PATRICIA HANNA

more the concept of r i g i d des igna t ion can lead us t o th ink t h a t such an exac t concept must be used; how otherwise can "one meter'' des igna te t h e same length i n every poss ib l e world? But w e do n o t use such a concept (normally). Nor can w e be requi red t o do so, unless " the same length" is s t i p u l a t e d , c i r c u l a r l y , t o car ry t h i s impl ica t ion of exac tness ( c f . our earlier d iscuss ion of "the same person"). I n P I 69 Wit tgens te in denies t h a t i t took t h e d e f i n i t i o n 1 pace = 75 cm. t o make the measure "one pace" usable. H i s e l abora t ion seema t o m e dec i s ive : "And i f you want t o say 'But s t i l l , be fo re t h a t i t wasn't an exac t measure', then I rep ly : very w e l l , it was an inexac t one.--Though you s t i l l owe m e a d e f i n i t i o n of exactness" ( P I 69).11

3 . Concluding Remarks

I n h i s preface t o t h e new e d i t i o n of Naming and N e c e s s i t y , Kripke sugges ts t h e c e n t r a l i t y of r i g i d des igna t ion t o t h e ideas developed i n the l e c t u r e s . I be l i eve t h a t i t is central, and I have suggested how flaws i n h i s d i scuss ions of e s sen t i a l i sm and t h e s tandard meter ba r may be t r aced to t h i s conception. But I have not attempted t o meet poss ib l e r e jo inde r s t o these c r i t i c i s m s , and I have d e a l t wi th only a few of t h e many top ic s discussed i n Kripke's r i c h and e x c i t i n g book. o r depth of h i s d i scuss ions , a l l of which repay d e t a i l e d examination. Kripke's concern is with i s s u e s which are abso lu te ly fundamental t o philosophy. His treatment of t hese i s s u e s is highly o r i g i n a l and inva r i ab ly i n t e r e s t i n g . I t is t he re fo re t o be hoped t h a t t h e p re sen t e d i t i o n of t h e l e c t u r e s secures a wide audience, f o r few philosophers could f a i l t o p r o f i t from t h i s outstand- ing con t r ibu t ion t o philosophy.12 9

Nor have I managed t o convey the complexity

DEPARTMENT OF PHIMSOPHY UNIVERSITY OF UTAH SALT LAKE CITY, UTAH 84112

Page 13: ON SAMENESS AND NECESSITY

103

REVIEW ARTICLE

NOTES

'The l e c t u r e s o r i g i n a l l y appeared i n Semantics of Natural Language, ed. Donald Davidson and G i l b e r t Harman, (Dordrecht-Holland: D. Re ide l P u b l i s h i n g Co., 1972) .

' " Ident i ty and Necess i ty ," i n I d e n t i t y and I n d i v i d u a t i o n , ed. Mil ton

3Naming and Necessity, p. 48; h e r e a f t e r a b b r e v i a t e d N N , succeeded by

4't0n t h e Neccesi ty of O r i g i n , " The Journal of Philosophy 73 (1976) : 132.

5Ludwig W i t t g e n s t e i n , Phi losohpical I n v e s t i g a t i o n s , 3d ed. , t r a n s .

Munitz, (New York: New York U n i v e r s i t y P r e s s , 1971) , p . 145.

page numbers.

G.E.M. Anscombe (New York: Macmillan, 1968) , sect . 68; h e r e a f t e r abbrevia ted P I , succeeded by paragraph numbers.

6I have developed t h i s type of cr i t ic ism a t g r e a t e r l e n g t h i n P a t r i c i a Johns ton , "Origin and Necess i ty ," Philosophical S t u d i e s 32 (1977). But t h i s earlier paper e x h i b i t s confusion about i d e n t i t y , which l e d m e t o underest imate Kripke 's e s s e n t i a l i s t commitment.

'The c l u s t e r concept theory is developed by John R. S e a r l e , "Proper

'1 f i n d myself i n s u b s t a n t i a l agreement w i t h Michael D u m m e t t ' s r e b u t t a l of t h e s e criticisms; see h i s F r e g e : Philosophy of Language (New York: Harper and Row, 1973). pp. 110-51.

Names , " Mind 67 (1958). Kr ipke ' s criticism occurs a t NN 71-97.

911dent i ty and Necessi ty , ' ' pp. 152-53.

"Lest t h i s seem t o v i o l a t e t h e s p l r i t o f Kripke 's account , i t is worth n o t i n g t h a t Kripke does n o t r e q u i r e t h e o b s e r v a t i o n of i t e m s i n terms of which r e f e r e n c e is f i x e d : see, e .g . , h i s d i s c u s s i o n of "Hesperus" a t NN 78.

"A few paragraphs of t h e foregoing d i s c u s s i o n are adapted from P a t r i c i a Hanna Johnson and T. M. Reed, "The Standard Meter Bar'' (1974, unpubl ished); t h i s material is used wi th permission of D r . Reed.

12My t rea tment of t h e t o p i c s cons idered h e r e h a s b e n e f i t e d from d i s - cuss ions w i t h T. M. Reed over a p e r i o d of many y e a r s ; more r e c e n t l y , d i s - cuss ions wi th Fred Hagen have improved my unders tanding of Wi t tgens te in on s e v e r a l p o i n t s . They are n o t , of course , r e s p o n s i b l e f o r any e r r o r s .

130n r e c e i p t of t h i s review a r t i c l e t h e E d i t o r of Philosophical Inves- t i g a t i o n s k i n d l y s e n t m e a pre-publ ica t ion copy of Norman Malcolm's "Kripke and t h e Standard Meter" (Phi losophical I n v e s t i g a t i o n s , Winter 1981). o f which I had been unaware, r e q u e s t i n g any c r i t i c a l comments I might deem a p p r o p r i a t e . Even t h e c a s u a l reader w i l l n o t i c e t h a t my c r i t i c i s m s over lap a t many p o i n t s w i t h Malcolm's, and n a t u r a l l y I a m i n agreement w i t h him a t t h e s e p o i n t s . I n a d d i t i o n , I f i n d t h a t I a g r e e w i t h Malcola 's e x c e l l e n t paper on every major p o i n t of subs tance , though t h e contex t of my d i s c u s s i o n y i e l d s d i f f e r e n c e s of emphasis o r formula t ion which may d i s g u i s e t h e e x t e n t of my agreement.