nonhuman rights and climate change

Upload: arunesh-a-chand

Post on 03-Jun-2018

230 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    1/112

    Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    Foundations in Early European Natural Justice

    Vanessa Burns

    A thesis submitted in fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of

    Masters of Arts (Research)

    University of New South Wales

    !"##

  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    2/112

  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    3/112

    %

    Copyright Statement

    I hereby grant to the University of New South Wales or its agents the right to archive

    and to make available my thesis or dissertation in whole or part in the University

    libraries in all forms of media, now or hereafter known, subject to the provisions of

    the Copyright Act 1968. I retain all proprietary rights, such as patent rights. I also

    retain the right to use in future works (such as articles or books) all or part of this

    thesis or dissertation. I also authorise University Microfilms to use the abstract of my

    thesis in Dissertations Abstract International (this is applicable to doctoral theses

    only). I have either used no substantial portions of copyright material in my thesis or I

    have obtained permission to use copyright material; where permission has not been

    granted I have applied/will apply for a partial restriction of the digital copy of my

    thesis or dissertation.

    Signed ..............................................................................

    Date ..............................................................................

  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    4/112

    &

    Authenticity Statement

    I certify that the Library deposit digital copy is a direct equivalent of the final

    officially approved version of my thesis. No emendation of content has occurred and

    if there are any minor variations in formatting, they are the result of the conversion to

    digital format.

    Signed ................................................................

    '()* ++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++

  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    5/112

    ,

    Acknowledgements

    The production of this thesis was achieved with the help of a number of

    people whom I would like to acknowledge and thank for their contributions.

    I have appreciated the help and professionalism of the staff of various research

    institutions including the National Library of Australia, the Mitchell Library

    and State Library of NSW. Particular thanks go to staff of the British Library in

    London and the various Bodleian libraries in Oxford, UK. I would also like to

    extend my thanks to the archivists at the Inns of Court in London and the

    British National Archives in Richmond, UK.

    I would particularly like to thank Stephen Gapps for editorial comments and

    proofreading, and Beth Stone for her invaluable support through the writing

    stages. I would also especially like to thank my son Solomon for being so

    understanding, supportive and independent while I was away doing research.

    And finally, my supervisors Stephen Muecke and Stephen Healy have been

    crucial to this thesis. Most importantly, their insightful comments,

    suggestions and intellectual discussion have been invigorating and inspiring

    and I warmly thank both for their contributions to this project.

  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    6/112

    -

    Table of Contents

    Originality Statement """""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""" #Copyright Statement """"""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""" $

    Authenticity Statement """"""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""" %

    &'()*+,-./-0-)12 """""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""" 3

    Glossary of Legal Terms """""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""" 4

    Introduction"""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""" 5Archives and Research Methodologies""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""6#

    Literature Review""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""63

    Roman Texts """""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""63 English Medieval Texts """""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""63 English Legal History John Seldon and the Seldon Society Publications""""""""""""""""""64 Contemporary Legal Theory"""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""67 International Environmental Law """""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""65Contemporary Social Theory """"""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""#8 Divine Law"""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""#7

    Res Sanctus- City Walls ++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++!. Res Sacrae Sacred Things and Places ++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++%# Res ReligiosaeTombs, Funerals and Burial Grounds.++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++%&

    Chapter Two: The Right to Stand? Nonhumans in Early Legal Procedure """"""""%#

    Introduction"""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""%# Pauperies Four-footed Animals """""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""%3 Substitution in Roman Law """""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""36 Towards Due Process: Analysis of Roman Procedure"""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""3$ Medieval European Procedure """""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""37Religion and the Natural World """""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""9# Procedure in Medieval England """""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""9% The Symbolic Use of Objects in English Legal Procedure""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""94 Conclusion """""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""48 An Historical overview of Natural Law """"""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""43 Roman Legacies in Medieval English Law"""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""78

    Gratian ++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++.%

    Bracton +++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++.& Customary Law """"""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""5# Secularisation""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""53 Establishing a New Source of Natural Law"""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""55

    In Conclusion: Latours Parliament of Thingsand the Problem of

    Anthropocentrism in Global Climate Governance """""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""686

    Bibliography"""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""""" 687

  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    7/112

    /

    Glossary of Legal Terms

    0123* 4 1(5* 267389*9 9*:262)2;6< ;: 3*=(3 )*>?< )1>;8=1;8) )1* )1**;(9 (69 )2783(> )*>?< )1() 6**9 26)>;987)2;6+

    damages: The money paid or awarded to a claimant (in the UK) or a plaintiff (in the

    US) in a civil action.

    decretum:A decree of the senate.

    defendant: In civil proceedings, the party responding to the complaint; one who is

    sued and called upon to make satisfaction for a wrong complained of by another. In

    criminal proceedings, the accused.divinis jurisor divine law: Divine law was a division of Roman legal instruments

    under the law of things, further catagorised under res nullius (things belonging to no-

    one). It can be thought of as a form of natural justice, given by God, and ruling over

    specific things (set out in the corpis juris civilis) that were understood as particularly

    sacred or important in some way. Divine law was, in some primary sources, also

    conflated with natural justice as the theoretical basis for natural law practice.

    due process: This term is used in two ways. Firstly in its legal context it denotes an

    order of procedure set out under law. This can apply to any kind of procedure related

    to the practice of law including court procedure, or punishments. Latour also uses the

    term due process in a different sense as an empirical methodology that might

    implement his political theory of things at an institutional level.

    extra-patrimonium: Things that are not in commerce, or are owned commonly

    inter alia: "Among other things." Used in pleadings before a court or opinions of a

    court. ie. "The defendant claims, inter alia, that the plaintiff fails to establish . . ."

    iura in rem: Latin the rights of things

    iuris or juris: Latin law

    jurisprudence: Theory and philosophy of law, which determines appropriate goals

    and methods of justice.

    jus civile: Latincivil law.

    jus gentium: Latin, the law of nations.

    locus standi: The right to stand before a court of law and bring or participate in

    proceedings.

  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    8/112

    .

    natural justice: In its Roman context natural justice was an early form of

    jurisprudence that argued for the existence of moral ways of behaving that were given

    by various sources, including God and logic. This is different from the modern

    interpretation of natural justice as the duty to act fairly that is effectively conflated

    with natural law. When I refer to natural justice I use it in its original sense. The word

    natural in this context is not associated with the modern term nature. Instead it

    denotes a logic of right action or responsibility that was understood to be already in

    existence and therefore not a product of human society.

    natural law: natural law can be understood in early jurisprudence as a response to the

    responsibilities set out by natural justice, expressed in the form of rules and laws that

    govern right and just action.

    patrimonio: Latin belonging to someone

    plaintiff: A party bringing a suit in civil law against a defendant; accusers.

    plea: A statement made by the defendant as to his/her guilt or innocence to the charge

    made against him or her.

    positive law: Man-made law, that is, law established by governmental authority,

    especially that which has been codified into a written form (statutory law).

    precedent: Judicial decision that serves as an example for how to rule in similar cases

    prima facie: Latin for "At first sight." Self-evident; obvious. A prima facie case is

    where the plaintiff presents enough evidence to win outright barring any defences or

    additional evidence presented by the defendant.

    res: Latin thing

    res nullius: Things belonging to no one.

  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    9/112

    C

    In your opinion, then, it is not in the edict of the magistrate, as the majority of

    modern lawyers pretend, nor in the Twelve Tables, as the ancients maintained, but in

    the sublimest doctrines of philosophy, that we must seek for the true source and

    obligation of jurisprudence Cicero1

    Introduction

    Theorists Bruno Latour and Alfred North Whitehead have both criticised the

    conceptual separation of Nature and Society as something to be remedied in political

    theory. Latour and Whitehead argue that the historical origins and development of this

    separation reveal a way of viewing the world - from a human centre - that isproblematic. From a theoretical position this problem concerns social organisation.

    Yet these theoretical contexts only begin to elucidate the empirical project - one of

    addressing this separation in new methodologies at an institutional level.2

    #D27*>;@ E+ F+ !"# !%#&'()#) *+ ,- !- .(/#%* *0 !"# 1&'2%# *+ !"# 3*4)5 60 7(8(0&'(*05 60 9&'#5 60

    '"# :#;2=* I*33 (69 N;6O N) D;5*6) M(>9*6 #./-+

    !K();8>@ P#CC%@ !""&Q+ Whitehead, (1968, p. 74)Latour suggests that the terms nature and society do not designate domains of reality; instead,

    they refer to a quite specific form of public organization. Latour terms this way of historically

  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    10/112

    #"

    Anthropocentrism has recently been acknowledged as a problem affecting the fields

    of environmental law and global climate governance. Existing methodologies are

    criticised as incapable of protecting nonhuman interests in areas such as resource

    management and climate change governance. In light of this, emergent legal theory

    argues for the development of legal instruments that give rights to nonhumans.

    Legal theorist Christopher Stone suggests that this method of decentering the human

    in legal frameworks has the potential to achieve greater environmental justice through

    broader (more democratic) representation of the interests - both human and nonhuman

    - in legal frameworks.3

    This thesis presents an historical survey of nonhuman rights, procedures and legal

    ethics in early western law aimed at informing such projects. Evidence from the

    Roman and medieval periods show that early Western societies had a more connected

    and inclusive understanding of humans and things (res) in methods of social

    organisation. The legal evidence examined in this thesis shows that this inclusivity of

    nonhuman interests is reflected in both the jurisprudence and legal instruments of

    both periods. Early jurisprudence included nonhumans in ideas of justice, in their own

    right. This meant that nonhuman interests could be considered independently of

    human interests. Evidence shows that this understanding in jurisprudence also

    underpinned the development of legal instruments, and due process in court, that

    allowed for nonhuman representation, trial and punishment. This sets out an important

    precedent in Western law for emerging theory and practice in the fields of

    environmental law and climate governance.

    While Roman and medieval history might seem a remote source for a comparative

    analysis of contemporary environmental law and governance, there are certainly

    similarities between the jurisprudence (in relation to natural justice), legal instruments

    and due process used in early societies, and those being considered in emergent legal

    theory to implement rights for the environment.4While these histories certainly do

    organising public life between things and people the old Constitution, arguing that by dividing

    public life into two incommensurable houses, the old Constitution led only to paralysis. p. 53.%R*9=S*33@ Catherine (1996, 99). Stone, Christopher (1972, 2010).&Stone, 2010.

  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    11/112

  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    12/112

    #!

    frameworks. I argue that the move towards (re)establishing contemporary legal

    instruments, that give some rights to nonhumans, calls for many of the same uses and

    principles found under the historical examples of early law. I contextualise these ideas

    within a political ecology framework (Bruno Latour, Jane Bennett and others), and

    make an argument for how greater representation of things (res) in policy and law

    will benefit the broader project of environmental governance. Moreover, I consider

    the agency of things, how this contributed to their inclusion in premodern law, and

    what their reemergence in contemporary legal theory might mean. These

    considerations are engaged with political theorist Jane Bennetts question: 1;S

    S;839 B;32)27(3 >** S* ); )(O* 2;8

  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    13/112

  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    14/112

  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    15/112

    #,

    Literature Review

    Roman Texts

    Various attempts were made throughout the Roman era to gather and simplify

    existing laws, beginning with the law of the Twelve Tables. The Twelve Tables arethe first known written records of Roman law and dated from the mid fifth century

    BC. The original ivory tablets were destroyed when the Gauls sacked Rome in 390BC

    and reconstructions are based on unofficial editions, the format of which is generally

    considered unreliable.

    While the reconstruction of the Twelve Tables forms an important basis for Roman

    legal ideas, by far the most successful effort to collate Roman laws was that of

    Justinian I, whose code superseded all previous laws and formed the Roman Empires

    legal legacy. Justinians Code, formerly known as the Corpus Jus Civilis(Body of

    Civil Law) is made up of four books examined here; The Codex Constitutionum

    (Codex) a reconsolidation of all known Roman laws written by ten Roman jurists;

    theDigestaor Pandectae(the Digest) drawn in 530-533 c.e. - consisting of the jurists

    comments; theInstitutiones(The Institutes) - a complete exposition of the elements of

    Roman law; and theNovellae Constitutiones Post Codicem(The Novels) - containing

    several collections of new regulations issued by Justinian himself.

    Matters of inheritance, contracts, property and persons remained the main categories

    of a revised English use of Roman law in the eleventh century. However, Justinians

    Code contains books on other important categories such as some under the law of

    things (of which property law is a part) and divine law. These concepts found

    primarily within theDigest contain the main body of laws involving nonhuman rights

    and standing.

    English Medieval Texts

    The establishment of early English law in the twelfth and thirteenth centuries

    produced a regular demand for what became the standard texts of study. These were

    the Roman Corpus Iuris Civilis (introduced above) and the Corpus Iuris Canonica

    (body of canon law). The later consisted of the Twelfth centuryDecretum collected

    by Gratian to theDecretalsof Gregory IX (1234) as well as theLiber sextus,

  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    16/112

    #-

    Constitutiones Clementinae, Extravagantes Johannis XXII,andExtravagantes

    communes of his successors.

    Around these texts, various layers of commentary were built up during the thirteenth

    and fourteenth centuries, whether as marginal glosses or as separate volumes.

    Scholars such as Azo and Accursius in civil law, and the canonists Bernardus de

    Botone of Parma and Johannes Andreas produced commentaries which achieved their

    own status as the standard supplementation to the main texts.

    The first collections of English Law include the twelfth century text (exact date

    unknown) Treatise on the laws and customs of the Kingdom of England written by

    justice to the court of Henry the II Ranulf Glanville as well as BractonsDe Legibus

    et Consuetudinibus Angliae(The Laws and Customs of England), composed primarily

    before 1235.9These are the two main texts attributed with establishing a system of

    English law. Both exhibit careful study of the main Roman texts and therefore act as

    intermediaries between the earlier interpretation of the Roman texts and the later

    development of English law. The differences between the two (written roughly one

    hundred years apart) are that Bracton shows an interest in interpreting Roman law in

    the creation of English legal practice, while Glanville is mainly concerned with

    replicating Roman ideas and practices.

    Also important to the literature on English medieval law were the yearbooks, which

    were books of legal cases or reports published annually in England from the thirteenth

    to the sixteenth century. The development of English common law was based on the

    law of the case something similar in premise to the legal principle of precedent.

    Lawyers and courts relied on previous court decisions that involved similar issues of

    law and fact. The law of the case could not take hold, however, until cases were

    recorded, reported, and eventually published. The English Year Books, which were

    created in about 1290, are the first example of a reporting system. Though they were

    informal and often contained running commentary about the judges' personalities and

    CM+'+M+ V(33 PW9+Q #C-, !"# !%#&'()# *0 '"# >&?) &04 .2)'*D) *+ '"# :#&=D *+ E0A=&04 .*DD*0=F.&==#4 3=&08(==#D3(>*69;6 X>** 867*>)(26 1;S*5*> 2) 2< 32O*3G ); 1(5* A**6S>2))*6 26 )1* )2?* ;: V*6>G 44 A*)S**6 )1* 9()*< ;: ##./].C+

  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    17/112

    #/

    the lawyers' quips, the Year Books were referred to increasingly by judges and

    lawyers.

    During the reign of King Edward I (1272-1307) legal material began to be collected

    into separate books for each year. During this early period the Year Books were very

    informal. They contained accounts by anonymous scribes and law students of

    courtroom proceedings and arguments that helped explain the judicial decision. The

    quality of the reports varied according to the abilities of the note takers. Despite these

    shortcomings, the reports conveyed basic procedural information to lawyers and

    students, but they stated few rules of law.

    The Summa Aureawas another important work written by the academic and

    ecclesiastical lawyer William of Drogheda in the 13th century. It is concerned solely

    with legal practice, procedures and forms for canon law, and presenting and winning a

    case. The Summais very incomplete, and appears to consist of the first of the six

    projected books of the work.

    English Legal History John Seldon and the Seldon Society Publications

    The publications of The Seldon Society, established under the patronage of Queen

    Victoria in 1887, makes up the main historiography of early English law. The society

    has published prolifically since its establishment, mainly with the aim of printing

    extensive edited collections of manuscripts from various archives, including the

    national archives and many borough archives. The focus of the collections vary and

    include the history of the law, the development of legal ideas, the legal profession, the

    courts and legal institutions, individual judges and lawyers, as well as legal literature

    and records.

    The society was based around the work of its namesake, the 17 thcentury English legal

    historian John Seldon. Many of Seldons original works are held in the Duke

    Humphries reading room at the Bodleian in Oxford. Seldons collection of works give

    a detailed account of English legal history with particular interest given to the period

    prior to the Norman conquest of England in 1066. The value of the texts, for my

    purposes, were their close accounts of the transitions in legal thought over the

    medieval period. They also form an important compilation of English law from its

  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    18/112

    #.

    formal origins in the twelfth century to around the fifteenth century when legal ideas

    and practices had begun to be influenced by Renaissance thought.

    Interestingly, the broader body of Seldon Society publications consulted during

    research contained no evidence of a continuation of nonhuman rights or standing in

    English law: this despite primary sources of early English jurisprudence (Bracton and

    Glanville) containing many references to the Roman law of things. 10In Bractons

    The Laws and Customs of Englandthis included a complete reproduction of the

    Roman categories under the law of things, alongside original interpretations of natural

    justice and its application to nonhumans (see Chapter Three, pp. 80-89).

    The absence of any case notes or evidence of legal procedures reflecting these aspects

    of early English jurisprudence in the extensive Seldon Society publications certainly

    suggest substantial inconsistencies either in the empirical use of these ideas in

    jurisprudence, or in the Society publications themselves (see Chapter Two, pp. 62-

    64). As indicated in several of the editors prefaces (reference here), the Society

    publications may have been selective in the material published in order to maintain an

    editorial focus on the development of laws and practices that have more contemporary

    relevance.

    Although it is likely that there was a decrease in the practice of nonhuman standing,

    further research may reveal a writing out of this practice from English legal

    historiographies. Although outside the scope of this thesis, establishing such a claim

    would involve revisiting the archives holding the primary sources translated and

    published by The Seldon Society - in particular the borough archives where

    customary practices would most likely to have been mentioned in records.

    Contemporary Legal Theory

    Contemporary environmental legal theory could be thought of as starting with

    Christopher Stones 1972 edition of Should Trees Have Standing: and other essays on

    law, morals and the environment. This pivotal text generated a body of work from

    various authors questioning the anthropocentrism of Western legal frameworks. Most

    #"F1* N*39;6 N;72*)G B8A327()2;6< 52*S*9 267389*9 (6G S;>O< >*3()26= ); )1* ##)1^ #&)17*6)8>GP(B1G :;> ( :833 32

  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    19/112

    #C

    notably was the work of Professor of International Law, Catherine Redgwell

    (University College London) and Professor of International Law and Human Rights,

    Francesco Francioni (European University Institute). Redgwell (1996, 99) and

    Francioni (1996, 2006, 2008) both argue for legal instruments in international

    environmental law that rely on inherent rights for nonhumans under law in order to

    better protect natural and cultural heritage. This work spurred my original interest in

    early law instruments and the evidence of nonhuman rights existing in early western

    legal frameworks. My interest was also based in an understanding that throughout

    history the law has reflected normative social values.

    Thus I formed my research question; are Redgwell and Francionis calls for new legal

    instruments plausible when we consider these instruments must be based in ideas that

    are contrary to social norms? And, is the emergence of this and other theory (Latour,

    Whitehead), which calls for a decentring of the human in public life, a sign of

    ecological actors forcing social change?

    International Environmental Law

    The surviving manuscripts and documents of early law are not just the domain oflegal history. They are also important as empirical evidence for other disciplinary

    analysis, particularly the social sciences. As the Seldon Society has noted of English

    history the only continuous records have been legal records, [and] there is in them a

    wealth of incidental information on every aspect of contemporary life and conditions

    to be found in no other source.11Legal historiographies are already familiar with

    interdisciplinary approaches to the extensive body of legal historical material.

    Any comparative analysis of this material with contemporary law requires an

    extensive survey of the main fields of environmental law. This is critical in assessing

    the legal instruments used in cultural and natural heritage laws and treaties, as well as

    contemporary jurisprudence, and in contextualising the emergent legal theory

    discussed above.

    11http://www.selden-society.qmw.ac.uk/ accessed 30/10/11.

    http://www.selden-society.qmw.ac.uk/http://www.selden-society.qmw.ac.uk/
  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    20/112

    !"

    My reading here was based around the following themes: international environmental

    law and law-making (including international politics of the environment); the

    principles of environmental law; the implementation and enforcement of international

    environmental law; non-compliance procedures; nature conservation and biodiversity

    with specific reading on the Ramsar convention on wetlands (Ramsar, Iran, 1971),

    the World Heritage Convention (UNESCO, 1972), the Biodiversity Convention (Rio

    de Janiero, 1992) and its supplementary convention, the Cartagena Protocol on

    Biosafety (2000); and lastly, climate change, with specific analysis of the United

    Nations Framework Convention on Climate Change (FCCC,1992), the Kyoto

    Protocol, 1997, the FCCC Conference of Parties in Bali, (2007), the 15th Conference

    of Parties (COP-15) in Copenhagen (2009), and the COP Cancun Agreements (2010)

    which together form the main basis of international climate regime.

    Contemporary Social Theory

    I have already mentioned the work of Bruno Latour and Alfred North Whitehead as

    important in guiding the conceptual approach of the thesis. More recent work includes

    that of Isabelle Stengers (2010), Jane Bennett (2010), Donna Haraway (2008) and

    Nigel Clarke (2011). In engaging with Latours Politics of Nature (2004) which

    may be generally considered as a politics of things - Stengers and Bennett set out a

    broad theoretical framework for political theory that develops some of Latours key

    ideas. They move Latours connectedness of things into political thought as a way of

    reforming institutional practice. This is highly relevant to my comparative analysis of

    legal instruments based in nonhuman rights and to any call for these rights to be

    institutionalised in international law practice.

    Haraway develops an argument for an ethics of participation and inclusion of

    nonhumans that is in fact a useful basis for thinking about the inclusion of nonhumans

    in the ethical frameworks not just of contemporary society, but how this might have

    operated in past societies. Clarke takes Latours re-constitution of people and things

    further and considers this in an environmental context of earth processes such as

    climate change and natural disaster. These theoretical developments were most useful

    in framing the conclusion of my thesis where I consider how early law - because of its

  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    21/112

    !#

    more inclusive politics around nonhumans - could prove significant in reforming the

    current institutional governance of environmental concerns.

  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    22/112

    !!

    Chapter One - The Law of Things: Nonhuman Rights in Roman Law

    Introduction

    The eleventh century saw the first production of scholarly, legal texts that defined an

    English system of civil and canon law. This process was aimed at consolidating and

    revising Roman laws and integrating them with the customary laws of Indigenous

    Britons. This project continued throughout the medieval period and underpinned the

    legal frameworks of Britain, its expanding colonial empire, and much of the worlds

    legal systems.12

    Yet while many of the legal institutions and instruments developed by the Romans

    persisted in English civil law, many other laws that applied to nonhumans did not.

    The main English legal texts after the Norman Conquest of 1066, and other related

    manuscripts, show that this was particularly true as secularisation developed during

    the early Renaissance in Europe. 13The gradual separation of Church and State and

    the rise of positive law saw nonhuman rights (that had been protected under divine

    law) and some ethical concepts that underpinned natural law abolished.14

    #!X>2;> ); )1* >*92G ;: _826= )1* ##)1D*6)8>G@ W6=32*32*9 ;6 ( ?2Z ;: )1* R;?(6 F1*;9;

  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    23/112

    !%

    Roman law had made provisions for the various roles and functions of nonhumans in

    early Roman society under the so-called law of things. This codification of laws

    relating to the nonhuman world included inanimate objects and animals, and was

    underpinned by concepts of rights for nonhumans in natural jurisprudence. 15While

    contemporary law is still familiar with the law of things (res) it now relates almost

    exclusively to real and personal property. What has been lost from modern

    adaptations of Roman law is the right of a thing to stand before the court or to hold

    rights of its own.

    In contemporary Western law the nonhuman exists in legal frameworks only in

    relation to human rights. Importantly, this poses significant problems in contemporary

    environmental law whereby a thing cannot be protected in its own right, unless it

    can be aligned with human uses or values.16Legal mechanisms that maintain a

    dependence on human interests in order to uphold the interests of a thing (such as a

    rainforest or glacier) struggle to adapt the logic of human interest to the more

    remote ecologies of climate geographies, among other concerns. There are no legal

    instruments in place that can protect ecologies critical to the global environment in

    their own right even given the implications for human societies if these ecological

    systems were to fail.

    This has been one of the reasons that the question of nonhuman rights, including

    rights to stand before the court, has once again emerged as a theme in jurisprudence.

    Among others, legal scholars Christopher Stone and Catherine Redgwell have been

    interested in new mechanisms that rely on the concept of nonhuman rights. Stone

    explores these ideas in a recontextualised sense of natural justice. Redgewell asks

    how nonhuman rights might be used to expand and strengthen natural and cultural

    heritage laws. Stone and Redgwell both argue for a mechanism that does not rely on

    human rights frameworks, but instead establishes the intrinsic rights of nonhumans in

    certain contexts. 17 Such concepts of nonhuman rights might provide the basis for

    theorising the rights of ecological and earth systems (such as those driving global

    #,_8>289*67* 869*>B26626= )1* 9*5*3;B?*6) ;: 6()8>(3 3(S P2)(=* 3(S< >*]=*6*>()2;6(3 >2=1)< )1() B>;)*7) )1* 18?(6 8(3 ;> 783)8>(3 >*7* 26 )1* :8)8>*+

  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    24/112

    !&

    climate) that are more remotely connected to human interests. This would potentially

    give environmental law a rights based framework able to protect natural systems

    critical to global climate, and address questions of human (and nonhuman)

    intergenerational justice.

    From this position concerned with environmental protection, early Western law

    informs contemporary legal thought by providing evidence of arguments within

    jurisprudence, and the development of legal procedures, that included the concept of

    nonhuman rights. This chapter interrogates the logic underpinning laws relating to

    nonhumans in the main Roman texts through an analysis of legal frameworks and

    language. It highlights historical evidence from this period of three important facets Iargue are relevant to contemporary legal theory: a more inclusive and functional

    understanding of the law of things; evidence of nonhuman rights in institutional

    practices; and evidence of a more integrated concept of humans and nonhumans.

    Early Roman Law: An Overview

    Roman law dealt with matters of succession (or inheritance), obligations (including

    contracts), property (including slaves), and persons. Although the rulings of

    magistrates were important, most laws were passed by assemblies dominated by the

    patrician families or Roman nobility. Later, Emperors bypassed these forms and

    issued their own decrees. As legal frameworks further developed under the early

    Roman Imperial era (44 BC to 117AD) the interpretations of individual jurists also

    became important in shaping law, and many of the texts compiled towards the fall of

    the Empire (395-476 AD) were contributed to, or overseen by, prominent jurists.18

    Over the course of Roman history, from the Republic to the Empire, there were many

    phases of legalistic development.Jus civile,or civil law, developed during the period

    of the Republic (75331 BC) and was based on custom (unwritten laws) or legislation

    (written laws). While civil law applied only to Roman citizens, the expansion of the

    Roman Empire gave rise to the other major legal framework inherited by modern

    #/R*9=S*33@ D()1*>26* P#CC-@ CCQ+ N);6*@ D1>2 P#C/!@ !"#"Q+#.0+ 0+ I87O3(69@ P#C!#Q+

  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    25/112

    !,

    Western law -jus gentium, or the law of nations, which applied to matters of justice

    involving foreigners.

    Roman legal texts were consolidated in two major commissions; the first under

    Theodosius II published in 438AD, and later under Justinian I published in 534AD.19

    Together these major works documented Roman law as it was practiced from the

    time of the founding of the city in 753BC until the fall of the Western Empire in the

    fifth century AD.20They hold a comprehensive and comparative history of Roman

    jurisprudence that now forms the basis for the law codes of most countries of

    continental Europe and derivative systems elsewhere.21

    The Law of Things

    The Roman law of things (res) was divided into the law of property (things in a

    restricted sense), the law of succession and the law of obligations.22While the law of

    things survives today as a cardinal feature of modern civil law, things are

    understood as economic assets only, showing a greatly reduced set of principles far

    removed from their original jurisprudence. An examination of the Roman law of

    things reveals a broader, more complex set of principals, and a logic that sort to

    include concepts of nonhuman rights as a mechanism that could be used to protect or

    manage broader social interests.

    Legal historian William Buckland notes that main classifications used in the Corpus

    Juris Civilisgroups things according to the rights existing over them. They were

    eitherpatrimonio(belonging to someone) or extra-patrimonium, meaning things that

    are not in commerce, or are owned commonly.23Within the grouping extra-

    patrimoniumthere are the following classifications:

    19Sirks, A. J. B., (2007).

    20However it remained in use in the Eastern, or Byzantine, Empire until 1453. Buckland, W.W. (1921)

    pp. 33-41.21Roman law also forms the basis of legal frameworks in some countries, such as Germany, that were

    never part of the Roman Empire. Ibid22http://www.notarypublic.ie/download/Roman%20Law.pdf

    http://www.notarypublic.ie/download/Roman%20Law.pdfhttp://www.notarypublic.ie/download/Roman%20Law.pdfhttp://www.notarypublic.ie/download/Roman%20Law.pdf
  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    26/112

    !-

    Table 1. First Categorisation ofRes from Justinians Corpus Juris Civilis.

    Category Translation

    Res communes common propertyRes publicae public property

    Res universitatis property of a corporation

    Res nullius property belonging to no one

    Buckland notes that Justinian also gives a second classification of resbelow:

    Table 2. Second Categorisation ofRes from Justinians Corpus Juris Civilis.

    Category Examples

    res corporales que tangi possunt things which can be touched

    for e.g. physical objects.

    res incorporales que tangi non possunt - things which cannot be

    touched for e.g. abstract conceptions, notional

    things and rights.24

    The later categorisations are closer to those definitions given by the pagan jurist Gaius

    who, writing circa 161AD, distinguished between things subject to either divine or

    human right - further categorised as corporeal and incorporeal things.25

    Buckland

    notes of the second classification, above, that res incorporalesdid not include rights

    relating to humans but instead iura in rem, or the rights of things. However, it is the

    first system of classification that is more consistently referred to throughout the

    Corpus Civilis.WhileIura in remis not referred to directly under this classification, I

    argue that the concept of nonhuman rights is established under the various

    subcategories of divine law, itself a subcategory of res nullius, as set out below:

    !%

    I87O3(69@ P#C!#Q+!&Ibid,p.187.

  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    27/112

    !/

    Table 3. Categories ofRes Nulliusin Justinians Corpus Civilis

    Category Subcategory Examples

    res sacrae Things consecrated by priests, like

    churches, their contents and sites.res sanctus The gates and walls of a city.

    divini iuris

    [divine law]

    res religiosae Tombs and burial grounds.

    Wild animalshumani iuris

    (Relates to the

    acquisition of things

    formerly res nullius)

    No subcategories

    Abandoned property

    The way laws were categorised provides some important insights into the social

    structures and cultural logics of the time. In particular, it highlights the conceptual

    approaches used in the development of early jurisprudence and their complexity -

    challenging the widespread idea that early law was irrational. The following

    sections address each category of divini iuris(divine law), from Table 3., and pay

    close attention to the ways in which laws under these catagories were applied in

    different scenarios.

    This comparative analysis develops a detailed study of the roles nonhumans were

    understood to have in Roman in society, and how jurisprudence and the law

    developed to reflect these roles and their associated rights. This section also builds a

    basis for examining how these ideas influenced the establishment of English law,

    which is explored further in Chapter Two. Given the remoteness of early law to

    contemporary legal logic it is important to focus on the cultural relativity of early law

    - on how the law resolved conflicts and managed the social concerns of the time. As

    the broad aim of this thesis is to consider how early law might inform contemporary

    legal theory, there is a greater focus on material that highlights the conceptual

    approaches toward addressing social and political concerns, rather than the concerns

    themselves.

    !,Gaius@ The Institutes, Book 2.

  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    28/112

  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    29/112

  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    30/112

    %"

    to play in the pre-Roman era but particularly as borders between conflicting ideas

    sets the precedent for their specific mention under the Roman law of things. The later

    Roman evidence suggests that these historically established functions of city walls

    became increasingly important evident in the specific laws dealing with public acts

    of violation against them. An expanded understanding developed that included, as

    Sabinus suggests, the concept of the city walls being inherently sacred in an

    autonomous and representative sense, that warranted protection under res sanctus.

    While the evidence shows that the legal principle of res sanctusdeveloped because of

    political and cultural ideas to do with social boundaries, the principle itself had a

    unique function. It acted as an instrument that could protect the city walls a

    nonhuman entity - without relying on laws pertaining to human rights. While the city

    walls certainly represented ideas that were important to human society, in practice

    these interests were relatively remote. Subject to the principals under res nullius, city

    walls were classified as belonging to no one entity or indeed, even a common entity.

    Buckland has noted how there are no obvious reasons why the ownership of walls

    might not have been regarded as vested in the city.

    Therefore, in practice, the law protected city walls in their own right. A lack of

    concept of ownership in this particular example is consistent with other objects

    protected under divine law (as discussed below) that rationalised the integral rights

    and autonomous status of these structures under law.33Yet distinct from other

    principles under divine law,Res sanctuscould be understood as an instrument that

    protected important human interests, such as security. If one considers the possibility

    that the ultimate purpose of the instrument was to protect human these interests, then

    the logic of res sanctusprotects these interests by removing all legal recourse to them.

    I suggest this forms an important example of how legal instruments that engage with

    concepts of nonhuman rights, such as those being considered in contemporary

    environmental theory, might be used to protect nonhuman entities. Furthermore,

    protecting these entities in their own right, could be central to protecting human

    %!

    N*(3*G (99< )1() the idea of pollution is a secondary elaboration upon the primary desire forretribution P!""-Q B+ !,+%%I87O3(69@ 0+ 0+@(1921) p. 42.

  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    31/112

    %#

    interests. On this basis, I suggest that res sanctuscould inform the development of

    new legal instruments in environmental law for particular use in the governance of

    climate change. Evidence shows that the principal of res sanctus is particularly robust

    in situations where the rights of the nonhuman conflict with human interests or

    rights (such as the right of passage and building rights). I suggest this is an important

    historical precedent in Western law that could also inform the dilemma of either;

    protecting nonhuman entities that cannot be directly linked to human interests or

    rights under law; or protecting nonhuman entities whose rights or interests conflict

    with human rights and interests.

    Res Sacrae Sacred Things and Places

    While res sanctusshows that structures could maintain independent rights under

    Roman law, res sacrae shows not only sites and objects holding rights of their own,

    but in many cases these rights taking precedence over human rights. This is

    particularly evident when private property rights were overridden. Once a site had

    been sanctified it ceased to be in commerce and could no longer be owned, either

    privately or collectively. Furthermore, if through sanctification a site became

    significant to the public, the owner of the surrounding land was required under law to

    provide access.34

    Firstly, it is important to consider the legal guidelines for sanctification under Roman

    law. For example the third century Roman jurist Ulpian states that it must be

    understood that a public place only becomes a sacred one when the Emperor has

    dedicated it or has granted a power of dedicating it. This statement contradicts that

    made by Roman Emperor Martian (450457AD) that things sacred must be made so

    by an act of the whole people rather than an individual... this would instead make the

    thing profane.35

    While these accounts do vary, they both point to res sacraeas a legal instrument that

    protects the public use of such sites through the creation of what is effectively a

    %&_8

  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    32/112

    %!

    commons. Ulpian adds that sacred places are those which are dedicated to the people

    whether within the civitasor in the countryside.36

    Yet, unlike a commons that protects a site as the common property of a select group,

    inBook IIIof The Institutes(Corpus Juris Civilis)an excerpt from Martian refers to

    buildings such as churches, consecrated sites and objects as things sacred or religious

    or sanctified are no ones property. So while a sacred place might in effect behave

    like a commons in terms of public access, divine law provides an instrument that

    protects the site from misuse by institutionalising the site as res nullius.

    Distinct from the legal concept of terra nullius, orunclaimed land, a sacred site

    protected under res nullius is claimed on behalf of no-one as a proxy to absolve

    human rights over a site or thing. This is a unique instrument that protects a

    nonhuman by separating this right of ownership from the framework of human

    rights. Yet as consecration was understood as permanent, and importantly could be

    transient across different sites (as referred to below), this instrument both establishes

    itself as autonomous, while also being firmly included within the common legal

    frameworks used for everyday matters of human society.

    It is worthwhile considering the commons as a legal instrument under res nullius in

    relation to what later became known by ecologist Garrett Hardin as the tragedy of the

    commons. In short, this tragedy was the depletion of a finite common resource by

    its collective owners based on each individual acting in self-interest, and without

    regard for the sustainability of the resource as a whole. While a commons is often

    aligned with ideas of social justice because of equitable access to the resource, there is

    no legal instrument in place that protects the resource itself. A comparison between a

    sacred site sanctioned under res sacrae as no-ones property, and a site owned

    commonly such as grazing lands, shows that while the resource of the two differs

    considerably, both allow human access and use of that resource. Yet, only the

    instrument under res sacraehas the power to protect the resource itself because it has

    effectively established the autonomous rights of that resource.

    %-Edict, Book 68.

  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    33/112

    %%

    Obviously, the Roman concept of divine law is defunct in a modern context. However

    the principle of an institutionalised lack of ownership or res nulliuscould be

    extended in useful ways in environmental law. Whether ownership of a site or thing

    (or resource) under divine law in its original context could ultimately be seen to rest

    in God or not is irrelevant. What is important is that a human institution established

    the integral rights of nonhumans under law, while at the same time irrevocably

    removing human rights (at least within that society) as a measure to control human

    use of a site or thing. Given the historically close relationship between religion and

    politics, the obligations of the Roman state to preserve sanctified sites or objects was

    likely coupled with a political pragmatism. It seems likely then that this relationship

    was in part at least, the mobilisation of religious beliefs in upholding the pragmatic

    functions of this clever and highly effective legal instrument.

    One of the most interesting principals ofres sacraeis that the agency of a sacred

    object or building to remove property rights remains even once the object or building

    has been removed.For example, Martian states that once a building is consecrated

    even if it is destroyed, the site on which it stood remains sacred. 37This suggests that

    ideas of sacredness were conceived in both the building/object and its space.

    Sacredness was understood as an entity in itself that maintained ownership.

    In terms of environmental law and climate change, Pomponius (Readings, Book 2)

    statements on public property are an interesting comparison here. Pomponius stated

    that just as a building erected in the sea becomes private property, so too one which

    has been overrun by the sea becomes public property. This shows a complicated

    understanding of what constitutes ownership and property rights. While an area of the

    sea cannot be privately owned, a space can be erected and claimed above it. Yet the

    sea, as public property, can reclaim private land on shore. This fluid notion of

    ownership and the transience of public and private space contrasts starkly to the

    comparative permanence of a sites status as res nulliusunder the legal instruments of

    res sacrae.

    %/_8

  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    34/112

    %&

    In another example, there is a distinction made between a sacred place and a

    sacrarium, where sacred objects are housed. A sacrariumcan be created even on

    privately owned land and to those who wish to free such a place from its religious tie

    do so customarily by evocation of the sacred things there from.38

    Therefore, the

    rights effectively rest with the objects themselves that have the power vested in them

    to remove the property rights held over whichever piece of land they are housed. The

    fact that this right is understood to be transient only increases the objects agency.

    Most importantly, the right is an inherent right what might be understood as a

    natural right independent of the dedication of an Emperor or other public

    dedication.

    Ulpian offers a third distinction stating that things need not be either sacred or

    profane (as Martian suggests), but only confirmed by some sort of sanction even

    though it be not consecrated to a god, as is the case with city walls. 39Importantly

    Ulpian adds that a sacred thing is not subject to pecuniary valuation. Similar to

    sacred sites, sacred objects are outside commerce and therefore inconsistent with

    other categories under the law of things that deal with things or sites in monetary

    terms.

    Res ReligiosaeTombs, Funerals and Burial Grounds.

    The third subcategory of divini iuris is res religiosae, or laws presiding over tombs,

    funeral processions and burial grounds. Similar to the sanctification of land or objects

    under res sacrae, a burial rendered a site res nullius. Burial rights were complex and

    took precedence over other laws, again overriding public and private property laws.

    Furthermore, the Twelve Tablesof Roman law (Law XVII, Table X) states that No

    one can acquire by usucaption [a method by which ownership of property can be

    gained by lapse of time] either the vestibule or approach to a tomb, or the tomb itself.

    This means that as was the case with sacred sites under res sacrae the site was

    permanently removed from any future commerce.

    %.Justinians Digest, Vol. 1, p. 26.%CIbidp. 26.

  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    35/112

    %,

    Corpses also held special rights of passage. For example, people were restricted by

    the provincial governor from obstructing the transport of a body in any way.40The

    second century Roman jurist Papinian refers to both the burial and transport of

    corpses in the following statement:

    There are persons who, although they cannot make a place religious,

    nevertheless are entitled to seek an interdict concerning the carrying of a dead

    man for burial there, for example, if the holder of the title carries or wishes to

    carry a dead man for burial to a farm whose fruits belong to someone else. If

    he is prevented, he is entitled to seek an interdict, as a result of which there

    will be an inquiry into the rights of ownership. The same applies to a partnerwho wants to carry a dead man for burial to a common farm against the wishes

    of the other partner. For in the public interest, in order that corpses should not

    lie unburied, we ignore the strict principle, which is quite often left out ofaccount in doubtful religious disputes, because the highest principle of all is

    that which serves the interests of religion.41

    While there are public health concerns here, it is important to note that the pragmatic

    and political uses of divine law also means that religious principle took precedence

    over conflicting interests such as property disputes. A corpse, like an object under res

    sacrae,could also be moved for a number of reasons creating a dilemma of how to

    zone the land it had previously occupied.42JustiniansDigeststates that the better

    view is that a cenotaph [an empty tomb] also is a religious place, Virgil being a

    witness to this point.43Of note here is the similar logic that underpins res sacrae,

    whereby the site of a consecrated building remained under res sacraeeven if the

    building had been removed.

    All these examples raise questions around what appears to have been shifting ideas of

    divinity operating across transient spaces. While I have suggested that sacredness

    was understood as an entity in itself that could effectively own a site under law, as

    an entity it also touched and remained in the objects and sites in which it was

    40Ulpian,All Seats of Judgment, Book 9.

    For example, Marcian,Institutes, book 3states that corpses that were lawfully buried are not to be

    disturbed or transported, although it may be possible to move the sarcophagus itself to a more suitable

    place.JustiniansDigest, Questions, Book 8.&!4) ?(3 A8>2(3 1(9 ;778>>*9 ;

  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    36/112

    %-

    invested. However the inconsistencies between practices, while quite possibly

    bureaucratic, also suggest the existence of a hierarchy of cultural importance that

    connects these various sites and objects. This raises the question of whether the

    corpse, the ritual or the site takes precedence over the other in rendering another, or

    remaining itself sacred. Furthermore, this inconsistency suggests that sanctity is a

    legal entity that can shift inside this hierarchy of sites and objects giving and taking

    away a things rights under divini iuris.

    A comparison with a modern context is useful here. Clause 9 of the 1847 British

    Cemeteries Causes Act (1847) states that:

    the company shall not sell or dispose of any land which shall have been

    consecrated or used for the burial of the dead, or make use of such land for

    any purpose except such as shall be authorised by this or the special Act, or

    any Act incorporated therewith (and) the company shall define by suitable

    marks the consecrated and unconsecrated portions of the cemetery (Clause24).

    While ideas of sacredness are still evident in modern secular law, the removal of

    bodies and de-consecration of land can return it to public or private use. Thus in the

    modern context, sacredness is not considered to permanently remain in a site once it

    has been consecrated and consecration is understood as performed by a priest rather

    than the corpse itself. In its most practical form sacredness is simply attributed to a

    site, or not, as a matter of town planning. Yet it does highlight how in modern law

    concepts of divine law were indeed used for diplomatic and social reasons.

    The fact that corpses were categorised under res nullius is intriguing. In death, a

    human body becomes nonhuman or a thing (res). This has remained the case in

    modern Western law. Legally, we do not own our bodies. They remain technically

    nonhuman or no-ones thing. Medical ethicist Donna Dickenson suggests that the

    historical precedent of this legal categorisation of the human body under res nullius

    developed because human tissue had no commercial value attached to it and so the

    issue simply did not arise. With recent advances in medicine this is no longer the case

    and if we lose a limb or if an organ is taken from our bodies, Dickenson points out

    &%p. 25.

  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    37/112

    %/

    that it is in fact not ours under law because of its technical lack of ownership under

    res nullius.44

    Still, in death, a corpse is not completely disconnected from human frameworks. As

    noted previously, corpses and sacred objects had their own power under Roman law

    that established a site as sacred and they maintained this status even after they had

    been exhumed or moved. Interestingly, Ulpian extends this same law to slaves. He

    states that a place where a slave is buried is religious, highlighting a consistency of

    legal interpretation across class groups.45

    Yet this interpretation is by no means consistent. For example, Justinian notes in his

    Digestthat the body of no dead slave shall be anointed; nor shall any drinking take

    place at his funeral, nor a banquet of any kind be instituted in his honor.46

    So too,

    there were particular honours reserved, and represented by wreaths, that can appear

    not to have applied to slaves:

    Anyone who has rendered himself deserving of a wreath, as the reward of

    bravery in war, or through his having been the victor in public contests or

    games, whether he has obtained it through his own exertions or by means of

    others in his own name, and by his own money, through his horses, or his

    slaves, shall have a right to have the said wreath placed upon his dead body, orupon that of any of his ascendants, as long as the corpse is at his home, as well

    as when it is borne away; so that, during his obsequies, he may enjoy thehonor which in his lifetime he acquired by his bravery or his good fortune.47

    &&IID &@ !.)1N*B) !"#"@ H*D#0B) I*2%-&,UlpianBook 25.&-The Tables are understood to have been written primarily for the plebian or lower classes so thatthey would have knowledge of laws previously known exclusively within the patrician class.&/Twelve Tables, Law XIII, Table X.Table Xof theTwelve Tables,which refers to funeral rites more generally, makes similar restrictions

    without reference to slaves in particular through the following laws:

    No wine flavored with myrrh, or any other precious beverage shall be poured upon a corpse

    while it is burning; nor shall the funeral pile be sprinkled with wine (Law XI).

    Large wreaths shall not be borne at a funeral; nor shall perfumes be burned on the altars (Law

    XII).

  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    38/112

    %.

    Legal matters relating to slaves fell under the law of things because slaves were

    consideredpatrimonio,or property belonging to someone and having a monetary

    value.48

    Therefore slaves were not considered strictly human in this legal context.

    For example, while male and female slaves were dealt with equally in burial (which

    was not the case with freemen), funeral expenses were incurred by their owners under

    similar guidelines to the burial of animals.49

    Yet despite these inconsistencies in

    practice, it is clear that in death a human corpse attained some level of equality under

    the classification of reswhile still maintaining a connection to human frameworks

    such as class.

    In another example from JustiniansDigestUlpian states that anyone who spends

    something on a funeral is held to contract with the deceased, not with the heir. 50

    While a corpse as a nonhuman thing under res nullius is clearly not able to enter into

    an exchange, this example shows that a deceased (freeman) can still symbolically

    participate in a commercial transaction.

    This particular law suggests that divine law was exercised to restrict human rights for

    diplomatic purposes. In this case res nulliusprevented access to the deceased persons

    estate for the reimbursement of funeral expenses. The important point to note here is

    that all these examples around funerary practices all extend the definition of res

    nulliusand show how classifications of humans and nonhumans were at once flexible,

    yet in many ways closely connected.

    The transformation of funeral expenses offers further insights here. Early twentieth

    century Roman scholar and translator Samuel P. Scott suggested that the "Long

    Coron" or large wreaths:

    would seem to refer to garlands of excessive size, exhibited by way of

    pomp and ostentation at the celebration of funeral rites. The greater part of thelegislation of this Table was evidently framed for the correction of the

    inordinate display of wealth and luxury already becoming prevalent at the

    &.I87O3(69@ B+#.!+&CUlpian,Edict, book 25, and Papian,Replies, book 3.However, free women had some particular laws pertaining to funeral expenses. The laws governing the

    burial of women were common to other property laws in that the expenses came from her dowry where

    possible, the onus lying with whichever of her husband or father had received the greater sum from herdowry after death, as per the agreements made when her husband received the dowry.,"Ibid.

  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    39/112

    %C

    burial of the dead.51

    The legal concern with ostentatious funerary practices was long standing. In 177 BC

    the Greek philosopher Celsus stated:

    one ought not to bury ornaments and such like with the body, as theuneducated do. This action, called the action for funeral expenses, is based on

    considerations of justice and fairness. It only covers expenses for the sake of

    the funeral.52

    In both these examples a law under res religiosaeis used to restrict cultural practices

    and religious ceremony. Although these restrictions were about the conservation of

    wealth, it is important to consider how they were connected to social values, rather

    than religious practices. Indeed, examples of these laws relating to funeral expenses

    seem to dismiss many religious practices altogether. For exampleLaw XV Table X

    discourages the use of precious beverages or the burying of precious ornaments that

    formed part of many Christian and pre-Christian burial ceremonies. It also states that:

    Gold, no matter in what form it may be present, shall, by all means, be

    removed from the corpse at the time of the funeral; but if anyone's teeth

    should be fastened with gold, it shall be lawful either to burn, or to bury it

    with the body.

    The social and cultural value placed on both precious objects and austerity in funeral

    rites often took precedence over religious ceremonial funerary practices. In effect,

    divine law had many pragmatic uses that could be quite separate from religious

    concerns. Although there was some inconsistency over different time periods, Roman

    attitudes as expressed through legal concepts of reverence towards the dead and the

    agency of corpses suggest that a hierarchy of nonhumans operated and that this

    hierarchy was understood in wider Roman society.

    Conclusion

    This chapter has investigated three aspects of Roman law that highlight how Roman

    society had a more inclusive understanding of nonhuman participation in the social

    and cultural aspects of everyday life. It has focused on how modern interpretations of

    Roman law have generally ignored evidence of a more inclusive and functional

    understanding of the law of things. This chapter has also drawn upon evidence in

    ,#Law XI, Table X.

  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    40/112

  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    41/112

    nonhuman by separating this right of ownership apart from the framework of human

    rights.

    Yet as consecration was understood as permanent and importantly, could be

    transient across different sites as I will discuss below this instrument both

    established an autonomy yet remained firmly included within the common legal

    frameworks used for everyday matters of human society. While a sacred place might

    behave like a commons in terms of public access, divine law provided an instrument

    that protected the site from misuse by institutionalising the site as res nullius.

    Finally, legal instruments under res religiosae mirror these principles. As was the

    case with sacred sites, under res sacrae the site itself was permanently removed from

    any future commerce.54

    It appears, particularly in the precedence of burial rights, that

    sacredness was understood as an entity in itself that could effectively own a site

    under law. It was also understood to touch and remain in the objects and sites in

    which it was invested. This suggests a complex hierarchy of cultural importance

    existed that connected these various sites and objects and positioned the instrument as

    adaptive over time to social needs. The idea of sanctity as a legal entity shifted

    along this hierarchy of sites and objects giving and taking away a things rights

    under divini iuris.

    Under res religiosaelaws relating to funeral expenses show that nonhumans could be

    under res nullius, while also remaining connected to human law or social

    frameworks, such as class. In this case, the shaping of cultural practices even the

    effective censoring of some religious ceremonies for the more magnanimous

    purposes of conserving precious resources, controlling crowds and influencing public

    behavior was related to both the human and the nonhuman.

    ,%

    C

  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    42/112

    &!

    Chapter Two: The Right to Stand? Nonhumans in Early Legal

    Procedure

    Introduction

    Standing or locus standi,is the legal term for the ability of a party to go before a

    court@

  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    43/112

    &%

    Historians and legal scholars have debated the various functions and intent of

    nonhuman standing before courts of law. Legal scholar Raphael Sealey has noted that

    Roman trials were often an important diplomatic gesture of retribution and a

    secondary consideration served to banish objects from social spaces that were

    considered polluted by acts of violence. Importantly, all of the functions of nonhuman

    standing are understood by Sealey to be symbolic in nature.57

    However these functions of retribution and diplomacy also indicate complex social

    mechanisms at work. Indeed, legal scholar Walter Hyde suggests nonhuman standing

    before the court was made possible because historically there was some

    acknowledgement of the participation of the nonhuman in the broader moral fabric of

    society.58

    The trial and punishment of nonhumans should not be seen as part of a pre-modern

    ignorance of Enlightenment scientific and rational thought. Such a teleological view

    discounts the logic at work in early legal philosophy a logic that was radically

    different to post-Enlightenment thinking. The historical legal procedures of locus

    standiare an important case in point here. They corroborate examples from chapter

    one of the widespread rationale operating in pre-modern Europe that assumed a

    greater inclusion of nonhumans in ideas of the social.

    In chapter one I suggested that legal instruments under res nulliusrelied on the

    autonomous rights of nonhumans to achieve various social and cultural aims. This

    chapter interrogates nonhuman standing before the court by comparing cases

    involving nonhuman defendants with the establishment of procedure in early English

    law. The legal procedures examined here show how nonhuman rights might

    translate empirically in early legal trials. The procedures will be examined based on

    the direct trial and punishment of nonhumans under such areas of law as the Roman

    laws relating to pauperies (damage caused by animals) as well as the symbolic use of

    nonhuman objects in customary procedures.

    57Sealey (2006) p. 36

    58Hyde, (1916) p. 54.

  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    44/112

    &&

    I also examine the transitions between the practice of Roman law and the

    establishment of English law in the twelfth century. The lack of evidence of a

    continuation of laws and procedures relating to nonhumans in English law points to a

    dramatic shift in the understanding (or lack of understanding) of nonhuman rights that

    underpinned the development of modern law. Historiographies suggest that as early as

    the twelfth century nonhuman rights and standing were effectively written out of

    English legal procedure (although some ideas remained in jurisprudence, for example

    Bractons The Laws and Customs of England).

    While this effacement was indeed quite sudden and widespread in terms of the

    continuity of legal texts and historical evidence, the point must be made that, given

    the long history of nonhuman standing, it is probable that forms of nonhuman rights

    continued in oral based customary law practices in England. If this was the case, it

    would have been a practice consistent with other countries such as France, Italy and

    Germany. The trial and punishment of nonhumans was in fact a widespread practice

    across Europe from Ancient Greece, to the establishment of Roman law, and

    examples occurred occasionally into the late seventeenth century.59

    Roman legal procedure still forms the basis for modern procedure in civil-law

    countries. While many of the Roman laws discussed here are no longer in use, a

    review of due process in cases involving nonhumans is important because it

    provides a precedent in Western law for the procedures followed around nonhuman

    rights discussed in chapter one. Furthermore, a review of due process in relation to

    nonhuman standing sheds light on the practicalities of institutional procedures that

    allowed the inclusion of these rights in legal frameworks.

    I suggest this historical process provides some important considerations for and

    connections with current dilemmas of nonhuman standing in contemporary

    environmental legal theory. In particular, the historical contexts of due process serve

    ,CDarren Oldridge notes for example that customary law in France, Italy and Germany permitted suchtrials and the cases were recorded in Handbooks on customary law, or customals . Oldridge adds

    that thirteenth century French jurist Philippe de Beaumanoir was the author of one of the earliestcustomals to mention the practice. p.44.

  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    45/112

  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    46/112

    &-

    to seize the offending animal or slave, and hold it as security until his claimwas satisfied.64

    Scott noted that the emphasis on the primary responsibility of the offender was

    remedied by theLex Aquilia, thought to have been enacted in 286 BC. In this law, the

    responsibility was instead placed on the owner. For example,Law I, Table VIIof the

    Twelve Tables(concerning crimes) states that:

    If a quadruped causes injury to anyone, let the owner tender him the estimated

    amount of the damage; and if he is unwilling to accept it, the owner shall, by

    way of reparation, surrender the animal that caused the injury.

    In another example from theDigestit was pronounced that if an animal was in thecare of a person and the act connected to negligence, then proceedings should instead

    be brought against the person for wrongful damage:

    if an animal should upset its load onto someone because of the roughness of

    the ground or a mule drivers negligence or because it was overloaded, thisaction [pauperies] will not lie and proceedings should be brought [against the

    person] for wrongful damage. 65

    However, despite this shift in responsibility to the human, the earlier concept that the

    nonhuman itself could be accountable continued to appear in customary and civil law

    in Europe until the seventeenth century. The persistence of this concept, rather than its

    disappearance, demands further investigation.

    Roman laws about pauperies show a number of circumstantial distinctions that

    determine an animals level of accountability. These include the animals relationship

    with other parties involved in the incident, and interestingly, great emphasis is placed

    on perceptions of the animals wildness.

    For example Justinian stated that if a dog breaks loose on account of its wildness

    the person who had the dog on the lead will be liable. Justinian also refered to the

    jurist Alfenus who states that:

    64(1932), Vol. II, p. 67.

  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    47/112

    &/

    when a groom was leading a horse into the yard of an inn, it sniffed at a mule.The mule kicked out and broke the grooms leg. An opinion was sought as to

    whether the owner of the mule could be sued on the ground that his mule had

    committedpauperies. I answered: Yes.66

    These examples show a familiar logic not unlike many contemporary laws relating to

    pauperies. However despite the fact that throughout early legal philosophy animals

    are not thought to have been legally responsible for their actions, there are many early

    references in which wildness itself seems to be held accountable as something

    connected to, but not necessarily inherent in domestic animals. For example,

    JustiniansDigest notes thatthe action lies when a four-footed animal does harm

    because its wild nature has been excited, for example, when a horse given to kicking

    actually kicks someone. This makes a subtle distinction that allows the horse itself to

    be held accountable. TheDigest continues:

    the general rule is that this action lies whenever an animal commits

    pauperieswhen moved by some wildness contrary to the nature of its kind.

    Therefore if a horse kicks out because it is upset by pain the action will notlie but if the horse kicked someone who was stroking it or someone who

    was patting it, this action will be available.

    So while it is acknowledged that an animal cant be held responsible for its actions,

    and that in this example the horse has a wild nature that isaccounted for with some

    leniency under the law, the horse is still subject to this action when it exhibits

    wildness contrary to the nature of its kind.

    This logic depends on a subjective understanding of a horses nature. Additionally,

    the wildness contrary to nature is ultimately defined against the logic of human

    reactions. The possibility that a horses behavior may be underpinned by a logic that

    extends and is separate to human logic is not considered. Thus a certain type of

    wildness that which isnt understood within human frameworks is itself

    accountable, as though the horse was possessed by something unnatural. The animal

    is at once anthropomorphised, yet cast out of human frameworks when it exhibits

    nonhuman qualities.

    65Ibid, p. 32.

  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    48/112

    &.

    Animals were also liable for acts committed through a third person or object. Again,

    JustiniansDigestpronounced that:

    Thepauperiesaction lies regardless of whether the animal commitspauperies

    by means of its own body or by means of some other thing with which it came

    into contact as for example of an ox rushes someone with a cart or overturns

    something on him.67

    It was also the case that if one animal provokes another into doing damage, action

    must be brought on account of the one which did the provoking.68

    It should be noted that these examples refer to domesticated animals, which may

    explain their high level of accountability within the moral codes of human society. By

    contrast, the wildness considered unnatural and uncharacteristic in domesticated

    animals was thought an acceptable part of an animals nature if it was seen as truly

    wild.

    For example, JustiniansDigeststates that the action:

    does not lie in the case of beasts which are wild by nature: therefore, if abear breaks loose and so causes harm, its former owners cannot be sued

    because he ceased to be an owner as soon as the wild animal escaped.

    Accordingly, if I kill the bear, the corpse is mine.

    Here the wild animal, once returned to the wild, is ostensibly outside the moral fabric

    of society and is therefore effectively outlawed free from any obligations under

    law. Unlike a domesticated animal, the actions of a wild animal do not make its

    captors liable under the pauperies action, unless the animal is contained. Therefore,

    compared to the distinctions made around domesticated animals, this shows that the

    presence of wildness itself absolved the captor of any legal responsibilities.

    Later examples found in the laws of the Lombards, a Germanic tribe who ruled a

    Kingdom in Italy from 568 to 774, show similar ideas relating to the hunting of wild

    animals. Law 309. on wild animals states that:

    66

    Digest, Book 2.67p. 276.

    68Ibid.

  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    49/112

  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    50/112

    ,"

    B*>

  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    51/112

    ,#

    While the animals in the case cited above are brought under law in their status as

    property, other examples show an accountability that lay with the animal that was the

    aggressor, rather then its owner:

    liability for damage attaches to the physical corpus which caused the

    damage even in the case of animals, this action lies not against the owner of

    the beast at the time the damage was caused, but against whoever owns itwhen action is brought. Clearly, therefore, if the animal dies before joinder of

    issue, the right of action dies with it.73

    The idea that legal recourse lies with the corpse and cannot be pursued against the

    animals former owner is consistent with previously cited cases of funeral expenses

    held in contract with the deceased. The animal in this case assumes a legal status indeath, connected with certain actions. Again, a similar logic underpins laws relating to

    both humans and nonhumans.

    These cases all show how animals have some form of independent recourse to the

    law. Evidence of this right to stand suggests that nonhumans were intricately

    connected to the everyday lives of humans they were considered important,

    independent social participants. The fact that some laws pertaining to animals and

    humans followed a similar procedure highlights a substitutive logic at work in

    jurisprudence at the time. Yet importantly, the pragmatic legal frameworks of Roman

    pauperies made provisions for a much broader concept of citizenship under law. It

    was an approach to jurisprudence that sought to reflect everyday life in a way that

    recognised a greater number of participants, both human and nonhuman.

    Substitution in Roman Law

    The trial and punishment of an inanimate object seems an outmoded, almost non-

    sensical procedure by contemporary standards. However this should not be simply

    dismissed as a pre-rational concept as it holds interesting information about how an

    object was understood to have some connection with, and agency in, any human

    action. Under Roman law, nonhumans involved in a criminal incident could stand

    /%Ibid.

  • 8/12/2019 Nonhuman Rights and Climate Change

    52/112

    ,!

    before the court in the absence of a human defendant. The trial of inanimate objects

    highlights a substitutive logic that operated during this period.

    Prominent cases under Roman law include the trial of a murder weapon, such as a

    dagger, after the authorities had failed to apprehend the murderer. Animals also

    received retributive style punishments for less serious crimes. Table VII,Law XIIIof

    The Twelve Tablesstated that:

    If anyone knowingly and maliciously kills a freeman, he shall be guilty of a

    capital crime. If he kills him by accident, without malice and unintentionally,

    let him substitute a ram to be sacrificed publicly by way of expiation for thehomicide of the deceased, and for the purpose of appeasing the children of the

    latter.

    Similarly, Plato wrote about the trial of inanimate objects:

    If an inanimate thing deprives a man of life when the thing has been defeatedin the trial, let it be expelled beyond the borders just as in the case of animals. 74

    As suggested, the logic of substitution in early jurisprudence reflects a different, more

    integrated understanding of nonhumans. It also reveals a number of interesting legal

    ideas that relate to the social structures of Roman society. Firstly, substitution allows

    certain retributive and symbolic procedures, which scholars such as Sealey have

    argued had important social functions, to be carried out even in the absence of a

    human. They had a perceived purifying effect over a social actor or space that was

    considered polluted by certain crimes. When a murder weapon was expelled beyond

    the city walls it was in itself symbolic of the polluted matter that was the byproduct

    of the crime. This still achieved without a human agent the symbolic purification

    of the social space, which is, as Sealey has suggested, the most important socialo