murphy, mark. custom, and the common good in aquin as's account of political authority.pdf

Upload: odir-fontoura

Post on 04-Feb-2018

219 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/21/2019 MURPHY, Mark. Custom, and the Common Good in Aquin as's Account of Political Authority.pdf

    1/29

    Consent, Custom, and the Common Good in Aquinas's Account of Political AuthorityAuthor(s): Mark C. MurphySource: The Review of Politics, Vol. 59, No. 2 (Spring, 1997), pp. 323-350Published by: Cambridge University Pressfor the University of Notre Dame du lac on behalf ofReview of PoliticsStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1408092.

    Accessed: 09/12/2014 11:38

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at.http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    .JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of

    content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms

    of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    .

    Cambridge University Pressand University of Notre Dame du lac on behalf of Review of Politicsare

    collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Review of Politics.

    http://www.jstor.org

    This content downloaded from 200.12.179.118 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 11:38:39 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=cuphttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=notredamepoliticshttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=notredamepoliticshttp://www.jstor.org/stable/1408092?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/1408092?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=notredamepoliticshttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=notredamepoliticshttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=cup
  • 7/21/2019 MURPHY, Mark. Custom, and the Common Good in Aquin as's Account of Political Authority.pdf

    2/29

    Consent, Custom,

    and

    the

    Common

    Good

    in

    Aquinas's

    Account

    of

    Political

    Authority

    Mark C.

    Murphy

    According

    to

    Aquinas's

    view,

    while the mandatethat

    political authority

    be

    instituted and

    exercised

    is an

    immediate

    consequence

    of the natural law

    precept

    that

    the common

    good

    be

    promoted,

    the

    question

    of

    who

    possesses political

    authority

    s settled

    by customary

    aw. Samuel

    Beer's

    rival

    interpretation,

    ne of

    the

    few

    attempts

    o discern

    Aquinas's

    view

    on

    political

    authority,

    s

    incompatible

    with

    Aquinas's

    explicit

    remarkson these matters.

    The

    present

    account

    provides

    an

    interpretation

    hat

    both

    fits

    Aquinas's

    few

    explicit

    remarksabout the

    source and

    form

    of

    political authority

    nd

    explains

    the

    tersenessof his

    remarks

    n

    that

    subject.

    Although

    there

    have been

    innumerable

    writings

    on

    Aquinas's

    definition

    of

    law- [Law]

    is

    nothing

    other than an ordinance of

    reason for

    the

    common

    good,

    issued

    by

    one

    who

    has

    care

    of the

    community,

    and

    promulgated '-there

    has been

    very

    little

    com-

    mentary

    on what

    Aquinas

    means when

    he

    says

    that law

    must

    proceed

    from one

    who

    has

    care

    of the

    community.

    In

    the case of

    the

    eternal,

    natural,

    and

    divine

    laws,

    it is

    quite

    clear who

    has

    care

    of the community:God, who governs the entire community of

    the

    universe 2

    by ordering

    all creatures to their ends.3

    Aquinas

    provides

    little

    guidance,

    however,

    with

    regard

    to the

    question

    of

    who has

    the

    authority

    o

    lay

    down

    dictates

    for

    the

    human

    politi-

    cal

    community;

    I.

    T.

    Eschmann has

    remarked that

    Aquinas

    often seems to

    have

    irritated,

    as it

    were,

    his later

    readers

    by

    his

    laconic

    statements

    n

    this

    and

    similar matters

    regarding earthly

    I

    owe thanks to

    Alasdair

    Maclntyre

    and

    Paul

    Weithman or

    helpful

    criticism.

    I am

    also

    grateful

    to the

    Editors

    and

    the

    anonymous

    referees at

    the

    Review

    of

    Politics

    whose careful and extensive

    commentary

    n an earlier draft of

    this

    paper

    made

    it

    much

    better than

    it

    otherwise would have

    been.

    1.

    [Lex]

    nihil

    est

    aliud,

    quam

    quaedam

    ationis

    ordinatio

    ad bonum

    commune,

    ab

    eo,

    qui

    curam

    communitatis

    habet,

    promulgata

    Summa

    Theologiae

    Ialae,

    90,

    4. Hereafter ited

    as

    ST.)

    All

    translations rom

    Aquinas's

    texts are

    my

    own.

    2.

    tota

    communitasuniversi

    ST

    IaIIae

    91,

    1).

    3. See STIa

    22,

    1.

    This content downloaded from 200.12.179.118 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 11:38:39 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/21/2019 MURPHY, Mark. Custom, and the Common Good in Aquin as's Account of Political Authority.pdf

    3/29

    THE REVIEW

    OF POLITICS

    governance.4

    The

    aim

    of

    this article is show

    that for

    Aquinas

    political authorityis best understoodnot in terms of any natural

    hierarchy among

    humans

    but rather

    in

    terms of

    customary

    law

    that is established

    by

    the

    consent of the

    community.

    Beer

    on

    Aquinas's

    Account of Political

    Authority

    Samuel

    Beer has

    recentlyargued

    hat for

    Aquinas

    the

    authority

    to

    legislate

    resides

    by

    nature in

    certain members

    of the

    political

    community.5Beer's aim is to exhibit a mode of thinking about

    political

    authority

    hat is

    now

    quite

    uncommon,

    a

    political

    theory

    to

    which the American

    rebels turned heir backs

    in

    1776,6

    and

    which

    is

    most

    ably

    defended

    by

    Aquinas.7

    Beer

    holds that the

    key

    to

    understandingAquinas's

    account of

    political authority

    is the

    doctrine of

    the

    hierarchy

    of

    being

    which

    Aquinas

    advocated.

    The

    cosmos,

    created

    and

    providentially governed

    by

    the Perfect Be-

    ing,

    exhibits

    a

    gradation

    n

    levels of

    being

    from

    angels,

    humans,

    nonrational animals, vegetables, to inanimate beings. As for

    Aquinas,

    good

    is

    convertible

    with

    being-all

    things

    are

    good

    insofar as

    they

    exist8-the

    descending

    order of

    being

    is

    also a

    descending

    order of value. The

    hierarchy

    is

    inclusive in that

    those

    higher

    in the

    levels

    of

    being

    and

    goodness possess

    all the

    perfections

    of those

    who

    hold a lower

    place

    in the

    hierarchy.

    Now,

    each

    being

    in

    the

    hierarchy

    s such that it is

    subordinated

    to that

    which is above

    it in

    the

    hierarchy,

    and is such that

    its

    proper

    activity preserves

    that which

    is below

    it in the

    hierarchy.

    All these

    different

    orders of

    beings

    are directed

    to

    the

    perfection

    of the whole of the

    cosmos;

    the whole constitutes

    an

    economy 9

    in which those

    farther

    up

    in

    the

    chain of

    being

    rule over

    that

    which is lower.

    This

    kind of

    inclusive

    hierarchy

    of value

    is

    also seen within

    the human

    order,

    for Different men ... have

    reason

    in

    different

    4.

    I. T.

    Eschmann,

    St. Thomas

    Aquinas

    on the Two

    Powers,

    Mediaeval

    Studies20

    (1958):

    201.

    5. Samuel

    H.

    Beer,

    The Rule of the Wise and

    the

    Holy:

    Hierarchy

    n

    the

    Thomistic

    System,

    Political

    Theory

    14

    (1986):

    391.

    6.

    Beer,

    Rule

    of the

    Wise

    and

    the

    Holy,

    p.

    391.

    7.

    Ibid.,

    p.

    393.

    8. See

    ST

    Ia

    5,

    1

    and

    5,

    3.

    9.

    Beer,

    Ruleof the Wise and the

    Holy, p.

    399.

    324

    This content downloaded from 200.12.179.118 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 11:38:39 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/21/2019 MURPHY, Mark. Custom, and the Common Good in Aquin as's Account of Political Authority.pdf

    4/29

    AQUINAS

    ON

    POLITICALAUTHORITY

    degrees

    with

    the result that the

    higher

    use and command

    the

    lower

    while

    the lower serve and defer to the

    higher. '0

    The

    basis

    of the ruler's

    authority

    within a

    human

    political community

    is

    his

    or her intellectual

    power, whereby

    he or

    she is

    naturally

    fitted to

    rule those who have such

    power

    to a lesser

    degree.

    The

    ruler's

    virtue is both to know what is

    good

    for the

    ruled and

    to

    understand

    that

    good

    as

    a harmonious

    part

    of the

    common

    good. '2

    Hence,

    Beer writes that

    knowledge

    of

    this

    kind,

    arising

    from the

    ontological

    tatusof

    the

    ruler,

    cannot

    be reduced to modern notions

    of

    greater intelligence,

    more

    good

    will,

    or

    greaterexpertise.

    To

    try

    to do

    so would

    gravely

    distort

    the vision

    and

    sadly

    diminish

    ts

    grandeur... Exemplifying

    he law

    of

    the

    cosmos,

    the

    higher

    order

    differs from the lower order

    among

    men

    not

    merely

    because ts members

    are more

    intelligent

    or more

    expert

    or

    more

    altruistic,

    but

    because

    they

    embracea

    higher

    order

    of

    being,

    a

    more

    comprehensive ange

    of

    the

    stuff of

    ultimate

    reality.'3

    What

    is

    the

    status of

    consent in

    a world in which

    those

    who

    excel in intellect are

    naturally

    rulers ?'4

    Obviously,

    it

    must

    play

    a

    very

    limited

    role.

    Beer,

    though

    not

    doubting

    hat

    the

    good

    consent

    voluntarily

    to the rule of the

    wise, '5

    considers the

    possibility

    that the ruled consent because

    they

    already accept

    what

    the

    rulers

    will

    ask

    of

    them;

    he

    rejects

    this

    interpretation,

    hough,

    for

    it would

    deny

    the hierarchical

    principle

    to hold

    that all can

    recognize what is necessary for the common good. On Beer's

    view,

    the

    governed

    consent to the

    legitimacy

    of

    the source of

    the

    dictates, '6

    ot the dictates themselves.

    But once

    more,

    a

    difficulty

    appears:

    how are

    the

    governed, being

    less

    perfect,

    to

    recognize

    the

    superiority

    of the ruler?Beer's

    answer

    is

    that

    it

    is

    through

    the

    charisma

    of the

    ruler,

    manifested

    in

    his or

    her

    being

    clothed in

    more

    precious

    garments

    and

    possessing

    more beautiful

    abodes,

    that

    the

    governed

    come to

    recognize

    the

    authoritative status

    of

    10.

    Ibid.,

    p.

    400.

    11. Ibid.

    12.

    Ibid.,

    p.

    401.

    13. bid.

    14.

    Aquinas,

    Summa

    Contra

    Gentiles,

    III, 81,

    cited in

    Beer,

    Rule

    of

    the

    Wise

    and the

    Holy,

    at

    p.

    410.

    15.

    Beer,

    Rule

    of the Wise

    and

    the

    Holy, p.

    414.

    16.Ibid.,p. 415.

    325

    This content downloaded from 200.12.179.118 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 11:38:39 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/21/2019 MURPHY, Mark. Custom, and the Common Good in Aquin as's Account of Political Authority.pdf

    5/29

    326

    THE REVIEWOF POLITICS

    the ruler.17 t should further be

    noted

    that,

    on Beer's

    account,

    consent

    plays

    no causal role in the

    generation

    of

    authority;

    ather,

    consent

    consists

    merely

    of

    recognition

    of

    and

    deference to the

    ruler's

    natural

    authority.'8 Though necessary

    for the ruler's

    authority

    o be

    efficacious,

    consent does not

    grant

    a

    right

    to

    rule;

    the

    right

    to rule

    is held

    by

    certain

    persons by

    virtue of their

    having

    a more

    comprehensive

    range

    of the stuff of

    ultimate

    reality.

    Brian Tiemey has argued both that Aquinas's account, even

    if

    interpreted ccuratelyby

    Beer,

    is

    not

    representative

    f

    medieval

    political theory

    in

    general,

    and that Beer's

    interpretation

    n

    terms

    of

    natural

    hierarchy

    is a

    very

    one-sided

    picture

    of

    Aquinas's

    thought. 19

    Unfortunately

    or our

    purposes,

    the bulk of

    Tierney's

    article is devoted

    to

    showing

    that

    even

    if

    consent is not an

    important

    element

    of

    Aquinas's

    political

    theory,

    it

    plays

    a

    much

    more

    important

    role in the whole

    of medieval

    thought

    than Beer

    accords it. He does raise a few important onsiderations, hough,

    against

    Beer's

    interpretation.Aquinas's

    claim

    that in

    any political

    community

    all should have

    some

    share

    in

    governance

    seems to

    fit

    poorly

    with Beer's

    view that for

    Aquinas

    political authority

    s

    naturally

    vested

    in but a

    few members

    of the

    community;20

    nd

    Beer's

    emphasis

    on the

    ignorance

    of the

    governed

    does not sit

    well

    with

    Aquinas's

    insistence that

    subjects

    are

    obligated

    to

    disobey any

    civil

    law

    that is

    contrary

    to the

    law of

    God.21On

    Tierney's

    view,

    though,

    these considerations

    against

    Beer's

    interpretation

    are

    not

    very

    weighty:

    I

    do

    not

    want to labor these

    points

    too much.

    The work of

    Aquinas

    is

    like

    the

    Bible

    in

    this,

    that

    one

    can

    prove

    anything

    out of it

    by

    an

    adroit

    selection

    of texts. The

    interpretation

    of

    Aquinas's political theory

    remains

    controversial;

    and his

    thought certainly

    did contain the

    hierarchical doctrines

    that

    Beer

    emphasizes.22

    17. ST

    Iallae

    102, 4,

    cited in

    Beer,

    Ruleof the Wise and the

    Holy,

    at

    p.

    417.

    18.

    Beer,

    Rule

    of

    the

    Wise and

    the

    Holy, p.

    417.

    19. Brian

    Tierney, Hierarchy,

    Consent,

    and the

    'Western

    Tradition, '

    Political

    Theory

    15

    (1987):

    646.

    20. See ST

    laIIae

    105,

    1.

    21.

    See

    STIaIIae

    96,

    4.

    22.

    Tierney,

    Hierarchy,

    Consent,

    and

    the

    'Western

    Tradition, '

    p.

    647.

    This content downloaded from 200.12.179.118 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 11:38:39 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/21/2019 MURPHY, Mark. Custom, and the Common Good in Aquin as's Account of Political Authority.pdf

    6/29

  • 7/21/2019 MURPHY, Mark. Custom, and the Common Good in Aquin as's Account of Political Authority.pdf

    7/29

    THE REVIEWOF POLITICS

    necessarily

    carries

    with it

    inequality-that

    places

    the demons in

    an orderof

    authority.28

    ut

    Aquinas says

    that such an order does

    not exist

    with

    regard

    to humans: the demons are not

    equal

    with

    regard

    to their

    natures,

    and thus

    there is

    in them a

    naturalorder

    of

    authority;

    his does not

    happen

    in

    humans,

    who are

    naturally

    equal. 29

    Thus,

    although

    some

    humans

    are

    superior

    to others in

    virtue,

    Aquinas

    holds that their

    being

    of the same

    species

    precludes

    any

    human from

    having

    natural

    authority

    over

    another.

    Aquinasalso denies that those who have authorityare always

    superior

    in

    goodness

    in

    his

    important

    discussion of

    political

    au-

    thority

    in

    his

    commentary

    on the Sentences of Peter

    Lombard.In

    that

    commentary

    Aquinas poses

    the

    question

    whether

    Christians

    are bound

    to

    obey

    the secular

    authorities.

    Aquinas

    answers that

    the

    duty

    of obedience arises because of

    authority

    which

    has

    constraining

    force,

    not

    merely

    temporally

    but also

    spiritually

    on

    account

    of

    conscience. 30

    ow,

    there are three

    aspects

    to

    consider

    in determining whether an authority has the power to bind in

    conscience:

    mode,

    origin,

    and

    use.31The mode

    of

    authority-that

    of

    the

    ordering

    of

    superior

    to

    inferior-is

    always good,

    and

    hence

    all authorities have

    something

    in them that

    is

    capable

    of

    binding.32

    Authority

    can be

    deficient,

    though,

    in terms

    of

    origin

    and use.

    The

    origin

    of

    authority may

    be

    deficient

    in

    that the

    person

    who

    attains

    authority

    is

    unworthy

    or

    in that

    the manner

    in which

    he

    or

    she attains

    authority

    is

    illicit;33

    and the

    use

    of

    authority

    may

    be deficient in

    that

    the

    authority

    commands what

    is

    outside

    his

    or

    her

    jurisdiction

    r in thathe

    or she

    commands

    what is

    contrary

    o

    the

    purpose

    or which the

    authority

    was

    established.34

    28.

    See

    ST

    la

    47,

    2.

    29. Daemonesnon sunt

    aequales

    secundumnaturam: nde

    in

    eis est

    naturalis

    praelatio:

    quod

    in

    hominibusnon

    contingit,qui

    natura unt

    pares

    ST

    Ia

    109,

    2

    ad

    3).

    30. Virtutem oactivam

    habet,

    non

    tantum

    emporaliter

    ed

    etiam

    spiritualiter

    propter

    conscientiam.

    See

    Aquinas, Scriptum uper

    Libros Sententiarum

    Magistri

    Petri

    Lombardi

    Episcopi

    Parisiensis

    Commentary

    n

    the

    Sentences

    of

    Peter

    Lombard),

    Book

    II,

    Distinction

    44,

    Question

    2,

    Article 2.

    Hereafter ited as

    Commentary.

    31. See

    Commentary,

    I

    44, 1,

    2.

    32.

    I

    will

    consider

    why

    the mode

    of

    authority

    s

    always good

    in

    the

    following

    section.

    33. See

    Commentary,

    I

    44,

    2,

    2.

    34. See Commentary,I44, 2, 2.

    328

    This content downloaded from 200.12.179.118 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 11:38:39 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/21/2019 MURPHY, Mark. Custom, and the Common Good in Aquin as's Account of Political Authority.pdf

    8/29

    AQUINAS

    ON POLITICAL

    AUTHORITY

    When

    a certain

    authority

    exhibits

    a defect

    in

    one of these

    aspects,

    it

    may

    cease

    in some

    way

    to have

    constraining

    force.

    Now,

    if

    Beer's

    interpretation

    s

    right,

    then

    those who attain to

    authority

    who are

    unworthy-who

    are too low in

    the

    hierarchy

    of

    being,

    to

    put

    it

    in

    Beer's terms-are not

    deserving

    of obedi-

    ence,

    and hence

    one would not be

    obligated

    to

    obey

    laws issued

    by

    them.

    However,

    this conclusion

    is not drawn

    by Aquinas.

    With

    regard

    to one

    who is

    unworthy

    of

    obtainingauthority,

    he

    writes:

    [he

    or

    she]

    is not

    precluded

    from

    attaining

    the

    right

    of

    authority,

    and

    because

    authority

    with

    regard

    to its form is

    always

    from God

    (which

    generates

    the

    debt of

    obedience),

    subjects

    must

    obey

    such

    authorities,

    though unworthy.3

    Unlike

    the other defect

    in

    the

    origin

    of

    authority,

    in

    which au-

    thority

    is obtained

    improperly,

    he

    unfitness of the ruler does not

    release the

    subject

    from

    his

    obligation

    to

    obey.

    Thus,

    Beer's

    inter-

    pretation

    of

    Aquinas

    is

    explicitly rejected

    by Aquinas

    himself.

    Beer

    might,

    of

    course,

    respond

    to

    these

    objections

    that one

    ought

    not

    rely

    on

    Aquinas's

    early writings,

    among

    which the

    commentary

    on the

    Sentences is

    obviously

    included,

    in

    order to

    make

    claims

    against

    Beer's

    interpretation

    f

    Aquinas's

    later and

    more

    mature view.

    To this

    response

    it

    may

    be

    said that

    nowhere

    in the Summa

    does

    Aquinas

    repudiate

    this account

    of the

    three-

    fold aspect of authority and the ways that defects in one or

    another of these

    aspects

    affect the authoritative status

    of the

    ruler.

    Further,

    much of

    his

    discussion of

    political

    authority

    n

    the

    sentential

    commentary

    hows

    up

    in

    the

    Summa,

    where

    its content

    is

    for

    the

    most

    part

    identical

    to

    the discussion

    in

    the

    commentary

    on the Sentences.

    Finally,

    the

    account of the

    threefold mode

    of

    authority

    does

    appear

    n

    Aquinas's

    commentary

    n

    Paul's

    epistle

    to

    the

    Romans-a

    commentary

    which

    belongs

    to the

    period

    in which

    Aquinaswas at work on the Summa-and that accountis substan-

    tially

    the same

    as that offeredin the

    commentary

    n the Sentences.3

    35.

    Non

    impeditur

    quin jus praelationis

    ei

    acquiratur;

    t

    quoniam praelatio

    secundum suam formam

    semper

    a

    Deo

    est

    (quod

    debitum

    obedientiae

    causat);

    ideo talibus

    praelatis, quamvis

    indignis,

    obedire tenentur subditi

    (Commentary,

    II,

    44,

    2,

    2).

    36.

    See

    Aquinas's

    commentary

    n

    Paul's

    Epistle

    to the Romans 13:1-7.

    329

    This content downloaded from 200.12.179.118 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 11:38:39 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/21/2019 MURPHY, Mark. Custom, and the Common Good in Aquin as's Account of Political Authority.pdf

    9/29

    THE REVIEW

    OF POLITICS

    In addition

    to

    these

    explicit

    rejections

    of

    Beer's

    thesis,

    Aquinas's

    discussion of the

    proper

    definition of law

    makes

    that

    interpretation

    more

    implausible.

    There

    Aquinas says

    that to

    or-

    der

    things

    to the common

    good

    belongs

    to

    the

    people

    or the

    viceregent

    of

    the

    people,

    and therefore

    legislating

    pertains

    ei-

    ther to the whole

    people

    or to

    the

    public

    person

    who has care of

    the whole

    people. 37

    Now,

    on Beer's

    view,

    the notion of

    having

    the care

    of the

    people

    must be

    interpreted

    n

    terms

    of

    deference

    to

    already existing natural authority. But in what sense can the

    making

    of

    law ever

    pertain

    to the

    people,

    if Beer

    is

    right?

    Would

    not the

    making

    of law

    belong by

    nature

    o certainmembers

    of the

    community,

    the

    only

    pressing

    issue

    being

    the

    epistemic

    problem

    of

    discovering

    to which members this

    power

    belongs?

    As the

    directing

    of

    something

    to an end

    belongs

    to the

    one to whom

    the

    end

    belongs, 38

    t must be

    that

    Aquinas

    holds that the

    power

    to

    make

    laws

    belongs primarily

    in

    the

    political community,

    not in

    certainmembersthereof. And, finally, as to Beer's claim that the

    populace

    recognizes

    the

    superiority

    of

    the

    natural

    ruler

    by

    his

    or

    her

    possession

    of

    beautiful

    dwellings

    and

    garments,

    we

    may

    simply

    note

    the

    absence

    of

    anything

    n

    Aquinas's

    texts that would

    support

    this claim.39

    Beer's

    interpretation

    f

    Aquinas

    on

    political authority

    is un-

    tenable,

    but it is clear that he

    is

    right

    to

    say

    that there exists

    within human communities some order of

    goodness.

    What

    I

    want

    to

    suggest

    is that

    two

    questions

    are

    kept

    distinct

    by

    Aquinas

    that are not

    distinguishedby

    Beer: Whatkinds of

    persons

    should

    hold

    authority

    within

    a

    political community?

    and How

    does

    a

    person

    come to hold

    authority

    within

    a

    political community?

    Beer's

    interpretation

    seems to

    provide

    an accurate

    reading

    of

    Aquinas's

    answer

    to the

    former

    question:

    those who are

    natu-

    rally

    fitted to be rulers should have the

    lawmaking

    authority.

    Hence, Aquinas affirms that those who excel in intellect are

    37.

    Ideo

    condere

    legem

    vel

    pertinet

    ad

    totam

    multitudinem,

    el

    pertinet

    ad

    personampublicam,

    quae

    totius multitudinis uram

    habet

    (ST

    IaIIae

    90,

    3).

    38.

    Est

    ejus, cujus

    est

    proprius

    lle finis

    (ST

    Iallae

    90,

    3).

    39. The text that

    Beer

    cites

    in

    favor of this view-ST

    laIIae

    102,

    4-provides

    no evidence that

    Aquinas thought

    that the

    ruler's

    having

    such

    possessions

    is

    a

    sign

    of natural

    authority.

    330

    This content downloaded from 200.12.179.118 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 11:38:39 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/21/2019 MURPHY, Mark. Custom, and the Common Good in Aquin as's Account of Political Authority.pdf

    10/29

    AQUINAS

    ON POLITICALAUTHORITY

    naturally

    ulers.But the sense

    in which

    those who

    excel

    in

    intellect

    are

    naturally

    rulers

    is the same sense in

    which,

    for

    example,

    those

    who excel

    physically

    are

    naturally Olympic

    champions.

    Their

    physical prowess

    is

    such that

    it

    makes them

    particularly

    apt

    to

    excel in athletic

    activities,

    but more than

    physical

    prowess

    is

    required

    or one to be

    an

    Olympic champion: just

    as

    Olympic

    prizes

    are not

    for

    the finest and

    strongest,

    but

    for

    contestants,

    since it is

    only

    these who

    win, 40

    t is not the

    intelligent

    who hold

    political authority,but those who attain to political authority in

    the

    proper

    way.

    If

    my reply

    to Beer rests on an

    accurate

    interpretation

    of

    Aquinas,

    then

    it

    follows that the

    possession

    of

    political

    authority

    results

    from

    receiving

    it

    by

    a lawful

    method.

    If

    not,

    both

    Aquinas's

    insistence on

    the

    importance

    of

    the

    way

    that

    authority

    is ac-

    quired

    in

    determining

    whether

    one

    is

    bound

    by

    a ruler's dictates

    and

    his claim that

    those

    who

    acquire

    authority by

    an

    illicit

    method are not deserving of obedience would be mysterious.41

    Further,

    given

    that

    Aquinas speaks

    of

    political

    authority

    as a

    right

    (jus

    praelationis),

    and for

    Aquinas every

    right

    is

    derivative

    from some

    law

    (either

    natural or

    human),

    it would

    seem that

    it

    must be some

    law that

    provides

    the

    basis

    for

    a

    particular

    ruler's

    holding political

    authority.

    The

    remainder of this

    article is de-

    voted to

    making good

    this

    claim.

    40.

    Aristotle,

    Nicomachean

    Ethics,

    trans.

    TerenceIrwin

    (Indianapolis:

    Hackett,

    1985),

    1099a3-5.

    41.

    See

    Commentary,

    I

    44,

    2,

    2. A

    rejoinder

    similar in

    form can be made

    against

    those who hold that for

    Aquinas

    the

    legitimate

    title to

    authority

    rests on

    the

    authority's

    ssuing proper

    dictates, i.e.,

    those

    that are directed at

    the common

    good.

    (Arthur

    Monahan

    approaches

    this view when

    he

    claims,

    Aquinas

    could

    afford o be

    indifferent-seeming

    n

    this matter

    of

    how one

    comes

    to

    hold

    legislative

    authority]...Whatdid interesthim was how a ruler exercised his authority, ather

    than how

    he

    came

    by

    it

    (Monahan,

    Consent, Coercion,

    and Limit:

    The

    Medieval

    Origins of ParliamentaryDemocracy [Montreal:McGill-Queen's

    University

    Press,

    1987],

    p.

    172).

    If

    the title to

    authority

    ested

    wholly

    on substantive

    onsiderations-

    the

    quality

    of a

    king's

    rule-rather than

    partly

    on

    procedural

    onsiderations-the

    method

    by

    which one

    comes

    to

    hold the

    right

    to rule-then no sense

    could

    be

    made of

    Aquinas's

    references in

    the

    commentary

    on

    the Sentences to both

    the

    origin

    and the use of

    authority

    as

    determining

    actors of

    whether such

    authority

    has the

    power

    to bind

    in

    conscience.

    331

    This content downloaded from 200.12.179.118 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 11:38:39 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/21/2019 MURPHY, Mark. Custom, and the Common Good in Aquin as's Account of Political Authority.pdf

    11/29

    THE REVIEWOF POLITICS

    Political

    Authority,

    the

    Common

    Good,

    and the Law of Nations

    Consider the

    following

    claim

    that

    Aquinas

    makes concern-

    ing

    political

    authority:

    it

    is

    of

    the law

    of

    nations,

    which is a

    human law. 42What

    is the law

    of nations

    (jus

    gentium)?

    Ulpian

    had

    distinguished

    between the

    natural

    law,

    the

    law

    of

    nations,

    and the civil

    law

    on the basis of the breadth

    of their

    respective

    jurisdictions:

    the natural law

    is that

    which

    nature teaches all

    animals; the law of nations is the law which is common to all

    nations;

    the civil law is the law which is

    particular

    o a certain

    political community.43

    Although

    this

    tripartite

    division was al-

    tered

    by

    Isidore in the

    compilation

    of his

    Etymology-natural

    law

    is no

    longer

    seen

    as

    governing

    nonrational

    animals-the

    division

    of the human aw

    into the law of

    nationsand the civil

    law,

    and

    the

    justification

    for that division

    based

    on

    the breadthof

    jurisdiction,

    remained intact.44

    n

    treating

    of

    human

    law,

    Aquinas

    turns

    to

    the

    question

    of whetheror not the divisionof human law into the law

    of nations and

    the civil law as

    proposed

    by

    Isidore

    is

    appropriate.45

    Aquinas accepts

    the

    division and

    agrees

    that the breadth of

    jurisdiction

    of each is as Isidore

    describes

    it,

    but

    he

    rejects

    the

    use

    of

    the breadth

    of

    jurisdiction

    as the

    differentia

    by

    which

    the

    genus

    of human law is divided into the law of nations and the

    civil law.

    Rather,

    he

    distinguishes

    the

    law of

    nations and civil

    law on the basis of the procedure whereby these precepts are

    derived

    from the first

    principles

    of the natural

    law:

    to the law

    of

    nations

    pertain

    those

    things

    which

    are derived

    from

    the

    natural law as conclusions from

    principles,

    such as

    just purchases

    and

    sales,

    and other

    things

    of

    this

    sort,

    without

    which

    humans cannot live a

    common

    life. This

    belongs

    to

    the

    natural

    law,

    because man

    is

    by

    nature

    a social

    animal,

    as is

    proven

    in

    the first book of the

    Politics.

    Those

    things,

    however,

    which are derived from the natural law

    by way

    of

    particular determination pertain to the civil law, inasmuch as each

    community

    determines what

    is

    suitable to itself.46

    42. Est

    de

    jure gentium,

    quod

    est

    jus

    humanum

    ST

    IIallae

    12,

    2).

    43.

    For a

    perspicuous

    discussion

    of

    Ulpian's

    account

    see

    M.

    B.

    Crowe,

    The

    Changing

    Profile

    of

    the Natural

    Law

    (The

    Hague:

    Martinus

    Nijhoff,

    1977),

    p.

    45.

    44.

    Ibid.,

    p.

    69.

    45. See

    ST

    IaIIae

    95,

    4.

    46. Ad jus gentium pertinent ea quae derivanturex lege naturae, sicut

    conclusiones

    ex

    principiis;

    ut

    justae emptiones,

    venditiones,

    et

    alia

    huiusmodi,

    I I

    I

    332

    This content downloaded from 200.12.179.118 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 11:38:39 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/21/2019 MURPHY, Mark. Custom, and the Common Good in Aquin as's Account of Political Authority.pdf

    12/29

    AQUINAS

    ON POLITICAL

    AUTHORITY

    The

    distinction

    between

    the law

    of nations and the civil

    law,

    then, corresponds o the distinction between those preceptswhich

    are derived

    from the

    natural

    aw

    by way

    of

    logical

    deduction and

    by way

    of

    determination,

    respectively.

    In

    logical

    deduction,

    one

    derives

    precepts

    from the natural law

    in

    a

    way

    similar

    to that

    method

    in the sciences

    by

    which demonstrative

    conclusions are

    drawn from

    first

    principles ;47 quinas

    cites as an

    example

    of the

    former

    type

    of derivation

    the

    conclusion that one must not kill

    from

    the

    principle

    that one should do harm to no

    one.

    In

    determination, one derives precepts from the natural law in a

    way

    similar to

    that

    method

    in

    the arts

    by

    which

    general

    forms

    are

    determined

    with

    regard

    to

    detail ;48

    Aquinas

    cites as an

    example

    of determinationthe

    specification

    of what

    punishment

    should be

    given

    to

    a

    convicted evildoer.49

    Aquinas,

    then,

    preserves

    the views of

    Ulpian

    and Isidore that the

    law

    of

    nations

    is

    com-

    mon to all nations and

    that

    the

    civil

    law is

    peculiar

    to

    a certain

    community by relying

    on

    the distinction between

    precepts

    that

    are

    derived

    by way

    of deduction and

    those

    that

    are derived

    by

    way

    of determination:

    s the

    law of nations is derived from

    the

    natural

    aw

    by way

    of a

    conclusion

    that

    is not

    far

    removed from

    its

    principles, 50

    umans

    easily recognize

    it as

    binding,

    and thus

    great

    uniformity

    n this kind

    of law is to be

    expected;5'although

    Aquinas

    does not

    provide

    a

    similar

    explanation

    in

    the case

    of

    civil

    law,

    we

    can

    safely say

    that

    his

    account of

    why

    nations

    do

    not agree in civil law would refer to the differingconditionsthat

    obtain

    in

    different communities.52

    sine

    quibus

    homines ad invicem

    convivere

    non

    possunt:quod

    est de

    lege

    naturae;

    quia

    homo

    est naturaliter

    animal

    sociabile,

    ut

    probatur

    n

    I. Polit.:

    quae

    vero

    derivantura

    lege

    naturae

    per

    modum

    particularis

    determinationis,

    pertinent

    ad

    jus

    civile,

    secundum

    quod quaelibet

    civitas

    aliquid

    sibi

    accommode determinat

    (ST

    IaIIae

    95,

    4).

    47. Similis est ei, quo in scientiis ex principiisconclusiones demonstrativae

    producuntur

    ST

    IaIIae

    95,

    2).

    48. Simile

    est,

    quod

    in

    artibus

    formae communes

    determinantur

    d

    aliquid

    speciale

    ST

    IaIIae

    95,

    2).

    49. For an

    interesting contemporary

    discussion of determination

    see John

    Finnis,

    Natural Law and

    Natural

    Rights

    (Oxford:

    Oxford

    University

    Press,

    1980),

    pp.

    284-89.

    50.

    Derivatur

    lege

    naturali

    per

    modum

    conclusionis,

    quae

    non est multum

    remota

    a

    principiis.

    51. See ST IaIIae95, 4 ad 1.

    52. See

    ST

    IaIIae

    95,

    3.

    333

    This content downloaded from 200.12.179.118 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 11:38:39 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/21/2019 MURPHY, Mark. Custom, and the Common Good in Aquin as's Account of Political Authority.pdf

    13/29

    THE REVIEW

    OF POLITICS

    What

    Aquinas

    means

    by

    saying

    that

    political authority

    exists

    by the law of nations, then, is that it is such a straightforward

    implication

    of

    the natural law that

    political

    authority

    be insti-

    tuted

    and exercised that such

    institutions of

    governance

    are

    features of

    almost

    every

    known

    human

    community.

    For the

    natural law

    dictates not

    only

    that each

    of us

    pursue

    his

    or her

    particular

    good

    but also that

    we

    promote

    the common

    good

    of

    our

    communities.

    But

    the

    institution

    and exercise of

    political

    authority

    are

    necessary

    for the

    achievement

    of

    the common

    good.

    Thus,

    political

    authority

    s of the law

    of nations.

    Why,

    precisely,

    is

    political authority

    necessary

    for

    the achieve-

    ment

    of

    the common

    good,

    and therefore

    part

    of

    the law

    of

    nations?

    Aquinas

    writes that even had there

    been

    no

    Fall,53

    politi-

    cal

    authority

    would have come into

    existence,

    for

    Humans

    are

    naturally

    social

    animals;

    thus,

    in

    the state of

    innocence,

    they

    would have

    lived

    socially. However,

    a

    social life cannot be had

    by

    many

    unless there

    is

    someone

    in

    charge

    who aims at the

    common

    good:

    for

    many,

    as

    such,

    aim at

    many things,

    whereas one aims

    at one.54

    53.

    Aquinas's

    view on

    political authority

    thus

    contrasts with

    Augustine's,

    who had held that

    political authority

    is

    a

    product

    of human

    sinfulness. The

    entrance

    of sin into the

    world

    brought

    with

    it

    as

    punishment

    the institution of

    slavery,

    and it

    is

    difficult

    not to read

    Augustine

    as

    likening

    the

    condition of

    slavery to that of being subject to political authority.Althoughthis condition of

    servitude

    is much worse than the

    freedom

    that would

    have

    existed

    had

    the Fall

    not

    occurred,

    it does have

    one

    beneficial

    result,

    and that

    is

    the

    fostering

    of

    humility,

    which is as

    salutary

    or the

    servantsas

    pride

    is harmful

    o

    the

    masters ;

    Augustine

    admonishes hose

    in

    such a condition o maketheir

    slavery,

    in

    a

    sense,

    free,

    by

    serving

    not with the

    slyness

    of

    fear,

    but with the

    fidelity

    of

    affection,

    until

    all

    injustice

    disappears

    and all human

    lordship

    and

    power

    is annihilated

    City

    of

    God,

    trans.

    Henry

    Bettenson

    [New

    York:

    Penguin

    Books, 1984],

    bk.

    XIX,

    chap.

    5).

    Although

    Augustine

    emphasizes

    the

    punitive

    aspect

    of

    political authority,

    he also

    ascribes

    to

    authority

    another

    purpose:

    he

    preservation

    f

    a kind of

    earthly peace,

    which,

    though perhaps

    unstable and

    uncertain,

    s the best

    that can be had

    in

    this

    life

    (City of

    God,

    XIX.

    6).

    To securethis

    aim,

    politicalauthority ttempts

    o

    generate

    a

    kind of

    compromise

    among

    citizens

    concerning emporal

    goods (City of

    God,

    XIX.

    17).

    This

    purpose

    of

    political authority

    would also not have

    existed had the

    Fall not

    occurred;

    he

    conditionsthat

    make

    earthly

    peace

    so

    precarious

    came into

    being

    with

    sin.

    For a fuller discussionof these

    issues,

    see Paul

    Weithman,

    Aquinas

    and

    Augustine

    on

    Original

    Sin

    and the Functionof Political

    Authority,

    ournal

    of

    the

    History

    of Philosophy

    30

    (1992):

    353-76.

    54.

    Homo naturaliter st animal sociale: unde homines

    in

    statu innocentiae

    socialiter vixissent: socialis autem vita multorum esse non

    posset,

    nisi

    aliquis

    l

    334

    This content downloaded from 200.12.179.118 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 11:38:39 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/21/2019 MURPHY, Mark. Custom, and the Common Good in Aquin as's Account of Political Authority.pdf

    14/29

    AQUINAS

    ON

    POLITICALAUTHORITY

    Insofar as humans

    are individual

    beings,

    each

    with

    his

    or her

    own

    proper

    good

    to

    pursue, they

    will seek

    many

    ends. But

    to

    seek

    a

    good

    which is

    common

    to

    all

    requires

    something

    which

    directs

    all

    these

    individuals

    to that end.

    Hence,

    Aquinas

    writes

    that if

    persons

    were to live

    alone,

    Each would be a

    king

    unto

    him- or herself. 5

    But

    this condition is not

    natural to

    humans;

    humans

    naturally

    live

    socially.

    Therefore,

    It is

    proper

    that

    there

    be

    something,

    beyond

    that which

    directs toward

    the

    particular

    good of each, that directstowardthe commongood of the many. 56

    Political

    authority,

    hen,

    is needed to direct

    individuals

    in

    pursuit

    of a

    good

    that is not

    particular

    o

    any

    of

    them.

    The considerations that have been

    adduced so far seem

    to

    show

    merely

    that the institution

    and

    exercise of

    political

    author-

    ity

    are

    instrumentalmeans

    to

    the

    promotion

    and

    preservation

    of

    the common

    good. Authority

    is needed

    if

    persons

    with their

    own

    particulargoods

    to

    seek

    are to be

    directed to the common

    good.

    But while this instrumentalustification for political authorityis

    plain,

    the role of

    political

    authority

    with

    regard

    to the

    common

    good

    is for

    Aquinas

    more

    extensive than these remarks

    suggest.

    It is

    compatible

    with

    an

    instrumentalist

    ustification

    of

    political

    authority

    that the end that

    political authority

    promotes

    be

    wholly

    specifiable

    independently

    of the

    institution and

    exercise of

    that

    authority.

    But this is not

    Aquinas's

    view. On

    Aquinas's

    view,

    one

    cannot

    specify

    what the

    common

    good

    of

    a

    politicalcommunity

    s

    without

    making

    reference to

    political authority.

    Thus,

    the need

    for

    political authority

    n

    the achievementof the

    common

    good

    is

    far

    more radical on a

    Thomistic view than

    the

    instrumentalist

    justification implies.

    In

    order to see

    why

    the

    common

    good

    is

    dependent

    in

    this

    more extreme

    way

    on the

    institution and

    exercise of

    political

    authority,

    we need to

    get

    a

    clearer idea of what

    Aquinas

    takes the

    common good of a political community to be. Contemporary

    commentators have

    complained

    that

    although

    Aquinas

    often

    praesideret,qui

    ad bonum

    commune

    intenderet:multi enim

    per

    se intenduntad

    multa,

    unus

    vero

    ad unum

    ST

    Ia

    96,

    4).

    55.

    Ipse

    sibi

    unusquisque

    sset rex

    (De

    Regno

    ad

    regem

    Cypri

    On

    Kingship],

    bk.

    I,

    chap.

    1).

    56.

    Oportet

    gitur, praeter

    d

    quod

    movet ad

    proprium

    bonum

    uniuscuiusque,

    esse aliquid, quod movet ad bonumcommunemultorum De Regno, I. 1).

    335

    This content downloaded from 200.12.179.118 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 11:38:39 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/21/2019 MURPHY, Mark. Custom, and the Common Good in Aquin as's Account of Political Authority.pdf

    15/29

    336

    THE

    REVIEWOF

    POLITICS

    invokes the

    common

    good

    in

    his moral and

    political theory,

    he

    does little to tell us what thatgood consists in;57Aquinas'sdoctrine

    of

    the common

    good

    must be

    gathered

    rom his terse and scattered

    remarks

    on the

    subject.

    One

    of

    the difficulties involved in

    gathering

    such

    a doctrine from

    Aquinas's

    remarks is that

    he

    refers

    to so

    many

    disparate

    items

    as

    common

    goods

    or the

    common

    good: money,

    honor,

    victory, justice, peace, happiness,

    the

    perpetuation

    f

    the

    species,

    the

    order

    of the

    universe,

    he

    good

    convertible

    with

    being,

    and even children are all labeled

    by

    Aquinas as bonumcommune or bona communia.58While Aquinas

    undoubtedly

    does

    employ

    the

    term common

    good

    in

    a number

    of

    analogous

    ways,

    the relevantsense of that term for our

    purposes

    concern those

    goods

    labelled

    by

    Gregory

    Froelich as

    goods

    common

    by

    way

    of

    causation,

    by

    which

    he

    means those

    goods

    which

    while

    remainingnumerically

    one extend

    to

    many

    effects. 59

    In this sense

    of common

    good,

    what is

    the

    common

    good

    of

    the

    political community?

    At one

    point Aquinas

    remarks

    that

    the

    common

    good

    consists of

    justice

    and

    peace

    (justitiae

    et

    pacis), 60

    and

    it

    seems clear that the sense of common

    good

    in

    57.

    [A]

    reader of

    Thomas's

    political

    works

    will find

    nothing resembling

    a

    Tractatus

    de

    bono

    communi.

    When the

    common

    good

    is referred o we are

    usually

    being

    presented

    with

    an

    example

    of it and are assumedto have

    already

    a

    grasp

    of

    its

    essential

    features

    Gregory

    Froelich,

    The

    Equivocal

    Statusof Bonum

    Commune,

    New Scholasticism63 (1989): 38-57). Froelich also rightly points out the stark

    contrast

    between

    Aquinas's

    detailed

    treatment of the individual

    good

    at the

    beginning

    of

    the

    Secunda

    Pars

    and

    his near

    silence on the issue of

    what

    the

    common

    good

    consists in.

    58.

    Ibid.,

    p.

    42.

    59.

    Ibid.,

    p.

    48. Froelich contrasts

    goods

    common

    by

    way

    of causationwith

    goods

    common

    by

    way

    of

    predication

    and

    goods

    common

    by way

    of distribution.

    Suppose,

    for

    example,

    that both

    you

    and

    I

    each have a

    twenty

    dollar bill. There is

    no

    actually

    existing good possessed

    by

    both of

    us;

    money

    is

    a

    good

    common to us

    by way of predication n that each of us possesses a good to which a common

    predicate

    a

    predicate

    relevantto the

    object's

    goodness)

    is attached.

    Next

    suppose

    that we have baked a

    pie

    that is

    sitting

    on the table before us:

    unless it is divided

    between

    us,

    neither of us

    can

    enjoy

    it.

    The

    pie

    is a

    good

    common

    by way

    of

    distribution:

    rior

    o

    division,

    its

    goodness

    is

    enjoyed by

    neitherof

    us;

    it

    is

    only

    by

    distribution

    that its

    goodness

    is

    available to us.

    A

    good

    common

    by

    way

    of

    causation

    s,

    by

    contrast,

    common

    precisely

    as it

    is

    individual

    ibid.,

    p.

    48):

    it is

    numerically

    one but

    good

    for

    more

    than one

    person.

    The

    victory

    by

    an

    army

    or

    athletic team

    might

    be

    an

    example

    of

    a

    good

    which extends to

    many

    in this

    way.

    60. ST

    IaIIae

    96,

    3.

    Aquinas

    also

    refers to

    justice

    as

    part

    of the common

    good

    at ST

    IaIIae

    19,

    10 and

    IIaIIae

    33,

    6;

    he

    refers to

    peace

    as

    the

    good

    of the

    This content downloaded from 200.12.179.118 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 11:38:39 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/21/2019 MURPHY, Mark. Custom, and the Common Good in Aquin as's Account of Political Authority.pdf

    16/29

    AQUINAS

    ON POLITICALAUTHORITY

    which

    justice

    and

    peace

    are constituentsof that

    good

    must

    be

    by

    way of causation.6 If we conceive of the common good of the

    political

    community

    as

    consisting,

    at least

    in

    part,

    of

    justice

    and

    peace,

    we are

    able to

    provide

    an

    explanation

    or the

    radical sense

    in which the institution and exercise

    of

    political

    authority

    is

    necessary

    for the achievementof

    the

    common

    good:

    the institution

    of

    political

    authority

    s itself a

    constituentof the common

    good

    as

    regards peace;

    and

    a

    particular

    kind

    of

    exercise of

    political

    authority-that

    of

    legislating-is

    needed

    to

    make

    determinate

    the content of the common good as regards ustice.

    Aquinas

    is

    quite

    explicit

    that the

    requirements

    of

    justice

    depend

    at least in

    part

    on human

    specification:

    he

    refers

    to

    the

    determination

    f those

    things

    that

    are

    just according

    to

    human or

    divine

    institution,

    nd makes

    it

    clear that it is

    contrary

    o

    justice

    to act

    against

    certain

    humanly

    determined norms

    of

    justice.62

    In

    order

    to understand

    why

    it would be the case

    that exercise of

    legislative authority

    within

    a

    political

    community

    would

    be

    required

    to

    specify

    the content of

    justice,

    it will be

    helpful

    to

    consider

    by

    comparison

    how for

    Aquinas

    the exercise of the

    virtue

    of

    prudence

    is related to the individual's

    proper good.

    On

    Aquinas's

    account,

    the

    end

    of

    the moral

    virtues is the human

    good,

    and as the human

    good

    is in accordance with

    reason,

    the

    end

    of the moral virtues

    pre-exists

    in

    reason;

    the

    manner in

    which these

    ends

    pre-exist

    in

    reason is

    through

    the natural

    habit

    of synderesis, which grasps the first principles of practical

    reasoning.63

    Hence,

    prudence,

    an

    intellectual

    virtue,

    does not

    determine the end of the moral

    virtues,

    but

    only

    determines the

    means

    for

    attaining

    hat end. Jean

    Porter

    has

    recently

    pointed

    out

    the

    ambiguity present

    in

    the claim

    that

    prudence

    determines

    only

    the means toward the human end.64On one

    reading

    of

    this

    multitude t ST Ia 103, 2, obj. 1 (not denied),and calls the peaceof the stategood

    in

    itself

    (and

    presumably

    common

    good)

    at ST

    IIaIIae

    123,

    5,

    ad

    3.

    61. We

    may

    also note that

    Aquinas

    mentions no other

    goods

    besides

    justice

    and

    peace

    that are common to

    persons by

    way

    of

    causationand are such that

    they

    pertain

    particularly

    o the

    political community.

    62. Determinatio orum

    quae

    sunt iusta secundum

    institutionemhumanum

    vel divinam

    ST

    IaIIae

    104,

    3,

    ad

    1).

    63. ST

    IIaIIae

    7, 6;

    see

    also ST

    Ia

    79,

    12

    and

    Quaestiones

    Disputatae

    de

    Veritate,

    Question

    16,

    Article

    1.

    64. Jean

    Porter,

    The

    Recoveryof

    Virtue:The

    Relevance

    of Aquinas or

    Christian

    Ethics

    (Louisville,

    KY:

    Westminster

    John

    Knox

    Press,

    1990),

    pp.

    156-62.

    337

    This content downloaded from 200.12.179.118 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 11:38:39 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/21/2019 MURPHY, Mark. Custom, and the Common Good in Aquin as's Account of Political Authority.pdf

    17/29

    THE REVIEWOF POLITICS

    claim,

    the end for which

    prudence

    seeks means is

    already fairly

    determinate...prior to the working of prudence itself. 65 On

    another,

    however,

    the

    end is not

    determinate

    n

    that

    way;

    the role

    of

    prudence

    would not be

    merely

    to

    figure

    out what sort of

    causal chain

    could

    produce

    an

    independently specifiable

    end,

    but would also determine

    what

    in

    concrete

    circumstanceswould

    count as

    achieving

    the end

    sought.

    Porter

    claims that

    for

    Aquinas,

    the latter

    reading

    must be the

    more accurate.

    The

    goal

    of

    acting virtuously

    s not

    the sort

    of

    goal

    that lends itself to

    means/end

    analysis,

    because

    this

    goal

    cannot

    be

    specified

    indepen-

    dently

    of

    some

    specification

    f the kind

    of

    action or

    actionsthat would

    bring

    it about.

    Certainly,

    he individualwho wants to act

    virtuously

    n

    a

    given

    situation will

    presumably

    have

    a

    formal idea

    of

    what the

    virtues means and will

    thereforehave a

    general

    idea of what virtue

    would

    require

    in

    this

    particular

    ituation. But

    formal

    notions of the

    virtuesrelevant o

    a

    given

    situation

    will

    not

    necessarily

    be sufficient o

    determinewhat sort of

    action,

    concretely,

    will

    embody

    the

    virtue

    or

    virtuesin

    question.66

    Surely

    Porter

    is

    right

    to

    say

    that

    prudence

    is

    not

    merely

    instru-

    mental

    reasoning

    about a

    predetermined

    end. She

    prefers

    to

    contrast

    a means-end

    reading

    of

    Aquinas's

    account

    of

    prudence

    with an account

    in which

    prudence

    determines the course of

    action

    which

    counts

    as

    instantiating

    he virtues.

    I

    will

    contrast

    these

    by using

    the

    terms

    instrumentalmeans and constitutive

    means

    respectively,

    but

    this

    terminological

    difference of

    course

    does

    not affect

    my

    endorsementof Porter's claim.

    The role of

    prudence

    as

    determining

    constitutive means

    for

    the attainment

    of the individual's

    good

    can

    help

    us to see

    why

    the exercise

    of

    political authority

    determines

    constitutive

    means

    for

    the attainment

    of the common

    good.

    For

    Aquinas,

    prudence

    extends

    to the

    governing

    of

    many,

    and the

    end with which

    this

    kind of prudenceis concernedis the commongood;67t is called

    regnal prudence,

    denominated

    by

    the form of

    government

    which

    is

    unqualifiedly

    best.68

    Regnal prudence

    is

    exercised,

    then,

    by

    those

    that

    govern political

    communities.

    As we

    have

    seen,

    justice

    65.Ibid.,

    p.

    157.

    66.

    Ibid.,

    p.

    159.

    67.

    ST

    IIallae

    7,

    10.

    68.STIIaIIae0, 1,ad2.

    338

    This content downloaded from 200.12.179.118 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 11:38:39 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/21/2019 MURPHY, Mark. Custom, and the Common Good in Aquin as's Account of Political Authority.pdf

    18/29

    AQUINAS

    ON POLITICAL UTHORITY

    is

    one

    aspect

    of the

    common

    good.

    As

    prudence

    determines

    not

    only

    instrumentalbut also constitutive means of the individual

    good,

    then,

    it would seem

    that the

    exercise of

    regnal

    prudence

    would not be concerned

    merely

    with

    coming up

    with

    instrumental

    means

    to achieve

    justice,

    but also to some extent with determin-

    ing

    what is

    just.

    For

    Aquinas,

    the virtue of

    justice

    is

    what

    directs humans in

    their

    relations with

    others,

    in

    contrast

    to

    the other

    moral

    virtues,

    which perfect humansprimarily n relation to themselves.69What

    is

    right,

    then,

    as

    regards

    justice

    is what

    preserves

    the

    proper

    relation

    between

    different

    persons,

    and this

    proper

    relation

    consists

    in a kind of

    equality.70

    ow,

    the

    right

    or

    the

    just

    consists

    in

    a

    kind of

    equality;

    but there exists

    both natural and

    positive

    right.71

    A

    relation

    preserves

    equality by way

    of

    natural

    right

    if

    the

    equality

    holds

    by

    the

    very

    nature of

    the

    thing,

    as for

    example

    when one

    gives

    a certain amount so that he

    or she

    may

    receive

    just as much. 72On the other hand, a relationpreserves equality

    by

    way

    of

    positive right

    if

    the

    equality

    holds,

    not

    by

    nature,

    but

    by

    way

    of

    agreement,

    or

    common

    acceptance,

    such as when

    one

    considers

    him- or herself content

    to

    receive a certain

    amount. 73

    Positive

    right

    comes into

    being

    either

    by

    private

    agreement,

    as

    when two

    individuals make a

    contract,

    or

    by

    public

    agreement,

    such

    as when the whole

    people

    consent to a

    thing's

    being

    treated

    as

    if

    it were

    equal

    to

    and

    commensurate

    with

    another,

    or

    when such is ordained

    by

    the

    prince,

    who has care of the

    people

    and who acts

    in

    its stead. 74 ot

    every

    kind of

    proportion

    an be

    made

    by

    agreement

    into an

    object

    of

    positive right,

    though;

    a

    proportion

    can be

    just by way

    of

    positive right only

    if

    such a

    determination

    s

    in

    accordance

    with

    natural

    ustice.75

    The

    naturally

    69.

    ST

    IlIaIIae

    7,

    1.

    70. ST IIaIIae

    57,

    1.

    71.

    ST IIaIIae

    57,

    2.

    72.

    Ex

    ipsa

    natura

    rei;

    puta

    cum

    aliquis

    tantum

    dat,

    ut tantumdem

    ecipiat

    (ST

    IIalIae

    57,

    2).

    73.

    Ex

    condicto,

    sive ex communi

    placito; quando

    scilicet

    aliquis reputat

    se

    contentum,

    i tantum

    accipiat

    ST

    IIaIIae

    57,

    2).

    74. Puta cum totus

    populus

    consentit,

    quod

    aliquid

    habeatur

    quasi

    adaequatum,

    t commensuratum

    lteri;

    vel cum hoc

    ordinat

    Princeps,

    qui

    curam

    populi

    habet,

    et

    ejus personam

    gerit

    (ST

    IIaIIae

    57,

    2).

    75. STIIaIIae57, 2, ad2.

    339

    This content downloaded from 200.12.179.118 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 11:38:39 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/21/2019 MURPHY, Mark. Custom, and the Common Good in Aquin as's Account of Political Authority.pdf

    19/29

    340

    THE REVIEWOF

    POLITICS

    just

    alone

    would, however,

    be insufficient for

    ordering

    the

    relationships

    within a human

    community,

    and

    thus recourse to

    positive right

    is

    needed;

    if

    the

    common

    good

    of

    justice

    is

    to

    be

    achieved,

    that

    which is an instantiation

    f

    a

    just

    relation between

    individuals

    will have to be

    determined.

    Aquinas

    is

    most clear

    on

    the need for determination f

    principles

    of

    justice

    in his

    discussion

    of the

    judicial

    precepts

    of

    the Old Law.

    There

    was need

    for such

    precepts,

    writes

    Aquinas,

    because

    It

    belongs

    to the divine law to

    order humans to one

    another and to

    God.

    Both of

    these,

    however,

    pertain

    in

    general

    to

    the dictates of the

    natural

    law,

    to

    which

    the moral

    precepts

    are

    to

    be

    referred;

    yet

    both of

    these have to be determined

    by

    the

    divine

    and human

    law,

    because

    naturally

    known

    principles

    are

    general

    in both

    speculative

    and

    practi-

    cal matters.

    Therefore,

    just

    as the

    determination of

    the

    general

    precepts

    of divine

    worship

    is

    done

    by

    the ceremonial

    precepts,

    so

    also

    the

    determination

    of

    the

    general precepts

    of

    justice

    to

    be

    observed

    among

    humans is determined by the judicial precepts.76

    Hence,

    the

    exercise of

    regnal prudence,

    issuing

    in

    human

    laws,

    does

    not aim

    merely

    to secure means

    to

    an

    independentlyspeci-

    fiable

    end,

    but also to

    give

    content to that end.

    Because the

    common

    good

    is

    in

    part

    constituted

    by

    the

    securing

    of

    justice,

    and what

    just

    relations consist

    in must

    be

    determined

    by

    political

    authority,

    the

    legislative

    exercise

    of

    political

    authority

    is

    not

    merely an instrumentalmeans to the common good, but deter-

    mines the constitutive means thereof.77

    76. Ad

    legem

    divinam

    pertinet

    ut ordinet homines ad invicem et ad

    Deum.

    Utrumque

    autem

    horum in communi

    quidem

    pertinet

    ad dictamen

    legis

    naturae,

    ad

    quod

    referunturmoralia

    praecepta;

    sed

    oportet quod

    determinetur

    utrumque

    per legem

    divinam vel

    humanum,

    quia principia

    naturaliternota sunt communia

    tam

    in

    speculativis

    quam

    in activis. Sicut

    igitur

    determinatio ommunis

    praecepti

    de cultu divino fit per praeceptacaeremonialia,sic et determinatiocommunis

    praecepti

    de

    iustitia observanda inter

    homines,

    determinatur

    per

    praecepta

    iudicialia

    ST

    IaIIae

    99,

    4).

    77. The

    importance

    of

    political authority

    n

    determining

    he constitution

    of

    justice

    explains

    why

    Aquinas

    held

    that even

    though

    some

    persons

    are

    more

    worthy

    to

    govern

    than

    others,

    the

    unworthiness f some rulers does not

    ipso

    facto

    preclude

    their

    possessing

    legitimate

    authority.

    For there must be some

    determination

    f

    rules

    of

    justice

    if

    the common

    good

    of

    justice

    is

    to be

    achieved;

    so

    long

    as the ruler's

    prudence

    s sufficient

    for

    issuing

    at

    least

    minimally

    acceptable

    determinationsf justice,his or her rulershipwill be effective for the promotionof

    This content downloaded from 200.12.179.118 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 11:38:39 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/21/2019 MURPHY, Mark. Custom, and the Common Good in Aquin as's Account of Political Authority.pdf

    20/29

    AQUINAS

    ON

    POLITICALAUTHORITY 341

    Aquinas

    also holds that the

    institution of

    political authority

    is a

    constituent

    of the common

    good,

    that

    is,

    of

    peace.

    Why

    would one

    think that the existence of

    political authority

    is a

    component

    of

    peace,

    rather

    than,

    say,

    merely

    an

    instrument of

    peace?

    Peace

    within a

    human

    community,

    for

    Aquinas,

    is

    more

    than the absence

    of

    war,

    though

    it

    certainly

    is

    a

    necessary

    condi-

    tion of

    peace

    that such

    disturbance not

    be

    present.

    In

    order

    to

    understand

    what

    Aquinas

    takes

    peace

    within

    a human

    commu-

    nity to be, we shall first examinewhat Aquinastakes peace to be

    between one

    person

    and another. Concord between the

    two

    is

    necessary

    for

    peace-concord

    exists between two

    persons

    when

    they

    are such

    that the wills of

    distinct hearts unite

    in

    consent to

    the

    same

    thing 78-but

    such

    unity

    is not sufficient for

    peace.

    One

    can

    be

    at

    peace

    with

    another

    only

    when his

    or her

    appetites

    are

    not

    tending

    to diverse

    objects,

    so

    that

    they

    are not at war with

    each other. This

    sort of

    failure

    of

    peace

    can occur

    in

    two

    ways:

    in one

    way,

    with

    regard

    to

    diverse

    appetitive powers,

    as

    the sensitive

    appetite

    often tends to

    the

    contrary

    of that to which the

    rational

    appetite

    tends...in

    another

    way,

    insofar as one and the same

    appeti-

    tive

    power

    tends to different

    objects

    of

    appetite,

    which it cannot

    acquire

    at one

    time,

    with the result that there is

    necessarily

    strife in the

    move-

    ments of the

    appetite.79

    For

    peace

    to exist between two

    persons,

    then,

    each

    person's

    appetites

    must be ordered so that

    they

    do not tend to diverse

    things,

    and the two

    persons

    must

    be

    in

    concord. This inclusion of

    the

    ordering

    of

    the

    passions,

    it should be

    noted,

    excludes

    from

    peace

    any relationship

    in which

    the

    agreement

    between

    the

    two

    persons

    is

    coerced,

    for

    the common

    good.

    (If

    the ruler's

    prudence

    s

    radically

    deficient,

    however,

    it

    is

    not

    his or her unworthiness s such thatreleasesthe

    subject

    from

    being

    bound

    by

    their

    pronouncements,

    ut his or her

    poor

    use of the

    legislative power.)

    78.

    Diversorum

    ordium

    voluntates simul in unum consensum conveniunt

    (ST

    IIaIIae

    29,

    1).

    79. Uno

    quidem

    modo

    secundum

    diversas

    potentias

    appetitivas:

    sicut

    appetitus

    sensitivus

    plerumque

    endit

    in

    contrarium ationalis

    appetitus

    . . . alio

    modo,

    inquantum

    una

    et

    eadem

    vis

    appetitiva

    n

    diversa

    appetibilia

    tendit,

    quae

    simul

    assequi

    non

    potest;

    unde necesse

    est,

    esse

    repugnantiam

    motuum

    appetitus

    (ST

    IIaIIae

    29,

    1).

    This content downloaded from 200.12.179.118 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 11:38:39 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/21/2019 MURPHY, Mark. Custom, and the Common Good in Aquin as's Account of Political Authority.pdf

    21/29

    342

    THE REVIEWOF POLITICS

    if one

    person

    be

    in

    concord

    with

    another,

    not

    of his or

    her

    own

    volition,

    but is coerced, as it were, by fear of some imminent evil, such concord

    is not

    truly peace,

    because

    the

    order

    of

    the concordant

    persons

    is

    not

    preserved,

    but rather is disturbed

    by something

    fearsome.80

    All

    things

    desire

    peace,

    for

    from the

    very

    fact

    that a

    person

    desires

    something,

    it follows that that

    person

    desires to obtain

    that

    which

    he

    or she

    desires,

    and,

    it

    follows,

    to remove those

    things

    that

    prevent

    his or her

    obtaining

    it. 8'

    As

    having appetites

    which tend to diverse and incompatible objects precludes one

    from

    having

    all that

    one

    desires,

    one

    must of

    necessity

    desire

    peace.

    As the disorder

    of the

    appetites

    is

    a hindrance

    to

    peace,

    Aquinas

    follows

    Augustine

    in

    calling peace

    the

    tranquility

    of

    order

    (tranquillitatem

    ordinis). 82

    It is

    important

    to

    note

    the role that

    orderliness

    plays

    in

    Aquinas's

    account

    of

    peace.

    For

    one's

    appetites

    to be

    in

    agreement

    is for them

    to be

    well-ordered.

    As

    Augustine,

    whose discussion of

    peace Aquinas closely follows, writes:

    The

    peace

    of the

    body,

    we

    conclude,

    s a

    tempering

    f

    the

    component

    parts

    in

    duly

    ordered

    proportion;

    he

    peace

    of the irrational oul

    is a

    duly

    ordered

    repose

    of the

    appetites;

    he

    peace

    of the

    rationalsoul

    is

    the

    duly

    ordered

    ife and health of

    a

    living

    creature;

    peace

    between

    mortal man

    and God is an ordered

    obedience,

    in

    faith,

    in

    subjection

    to

    an

    everlasting

    law;

    peace

    between

    men is

    an

    ordered

    agreement

    of

    mind

    with

    mind;

    the

    peace

    of a home is the ordered

    agreement mong

    those who live

    together

    about

    giving

    and

    obeying

    orders;

    the

    peace

    of

    the

    Heavenly

    City

    is

    a

    perfectly

    ordered and

    perfectly

    harmonious

    fellowship

    in

    God;

    the

    peace

    of

    the

    whole universe is the

    tranquility

    of

    order-and

    order

    is the

    arrangement

    of

    things equal

    and

    unequal

    in

    a

    pattern

    which

    assigns

    to each its

    proper

    position.83

    The

    peace

    of a human

    community,

    then,

    includes both

    concord

    with

    other

    communities-the

    absence of war-as well as the

    80.

    Si enim homo concordatcum

    alio non

    spontanea

    voluntate,

    sed

    quasi

    coactus

    timore

    alicujus

    mali

    sibi

    imminentis,

    alis concordia

    non est vere

    pax:

    quia

    non servatur

    ordo

    utriusque

    concordantis,

    sed

    perturbatur

    ab

    aliquo

    timorem

    inferente

    ST

    IIaIIae

    29,

    1,

    ad

    1).

    81.

    Ex hoc

    ipso

    quod

    homo

    aliquid

    appetit, consequens

    est,

    ipsum

    appetere

    ejus quod appetit

    assecutionem,

    et

    per

    consequens

    remotionem

    eorum,

    quae

    assecutionem

    mpedirepossunt

    (ST

    IIaIIae

    29,

    2).

    82.

    ST

    IIaIIae

    29,

    2.

    83.CityofGod,XIX.13.

    This content downloaded from 200.12.179.118 on Tue, 9 Dec 2014 11:38:39 AMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/21/2019 MURPHY, Mark. Custom, and the Common Good in Aquin as's Account of Political Authority.pdf

    22/29

    AQUINAS

    ON

    POLITICAL

    AUTHORITY

    proper

    ordering

    within that

    community.

    And,

    if

    Aquinas

    does

    follow

    Augustine

    here,

    this