morality and art 2

Upload: mariaalexandra

Post on 03-Jun-2018

216 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/12/2019 Morality and Art 2

    1/33

    Art and MoralityAuthor(s): James LaingSource: International Journal of Ethics,Vol. 14, No. 1 (ct., 1!"#), $$. %%&''

    ulished y: *he +niersity o- hicago ressStale +/L: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2376022Accessed: "'0"#0"14 11:4'

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of

    content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms

    of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=ucpresshttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=ucpresshttp://www.jstor.org/stable/2376022?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/stable/2376022?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/2376022?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=ucpress
  • 8/12/2019 Morality and Art 2

    2/33

    The University of Chicago Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to

    International Journal of Ethics.

    http://www.jstor.org

    This content downloaded from 92.87.204.90 on Thu, 6 Mar 2014 11:46:51 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms andConditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/12/2019 Morality and Art 2

    3/33

    55

  • 8/12/2019 Morality and Art 2

    4/33

    ART AND MORALITY.

    IT goes without saying, that it is impossible within the limitsof an article, to deal exhaustively with the relations of

    Ethic and Aesthetic. An entirely adequate discussion of the subject could be accomplished only by a thorough

    examination of the question as to whether there be an essential connection between the human instinct that finds

    expression in strictly moral phe-nomena, and that which reflects itself in the forms of Art. We should, of course, have

    to examine and settle the difficult prob-lem as to the precise sphere of Aesthetic properly so called, and to say whether

    and how far Art, by its nature, is essentially a mode for the manifestation of moral ideas and aspirations; we should

    have to decide whether there be a Good outside of the Beautiful, or a Beautiful outside of the Good.

    But approaching the subject from a somewhat popular stand-point and making the very simple assumption that

    Aesthetic and Moral or Social phenomena are essentially modes of spirit-ual manifestation, one may endeavor to

    show that the Art impulse, when it has issued in Creation, as opposed to mere Imitation, has been, in one or two

    strongly marked phases of social development, a correct and accurate exponent of the moral movement of the period

    to which it belongs.

    Spirit, from time to time in human history, has set its seal upon Nature in the form of Art. How far has the impress

    been morally significant?Want of definiteness is the characteristic of all primitive forms of spiritual expression. Necessarily it is in the

    domain of Art that the earliest record of this want is left for posterity to read. Long ere poetry, politics, religion, have

    found ade-quate media, through which the thought they contain may live as history, the creative instinct has found

    means to imprint upon the world imperishable traces of the results of its activity. Through these, and often through

    these alone, can future ages guess at the poetic, the social, the political and the religious ideas that moulded and

    mastered the development of prehis-toric man.

    This content downloaded from 92.87.204.90 on Thu, 6 Mar 2014 11:46:51 AM All use subject

    to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/12/2019 Morality and Art 2

    5/33

    56 International Journal of Ethics.

  • 8/12/2019 Morality and Art 2

    6/33

    57

  • 8/12/2019 Morality and Art 2

    7/33

    ethical phenomena manifested by the history of their descend-ants,

    as that history is reflected for example in such a writer as

    Hlerodotus, we find that Art, however inarticulate, was a very fair

    reflection of such moral instincts as were yet awake. Lofty enoughconceptions of the value and dignity of law and order, of reverence

    for authority human and Divine, for age and wis-dom and genius,

    of submission to fate, of the need for propiti-ating offended deities

    by sacrifice and ritual, sometimes an exaggerated humaneness,

    sometimes a superstitious recognition of the sanctity of human life,-

    all this often consisting with the most chaotic disregard of

    individual moral relations, the most monstrous sexuality and the

    most revolting cruelty. Mor-ality like Art is here purposeless,

    inarticulate. It is impossible to deny the existence of an ethical

    consciousness, but the half articulate voice of moral obligation is

    drowned in the clash of the cymbals that accompanies a mere

    quantitative atonement for moral failures, just as the bright grace

    of the Spirit of Beauty is quenched amid the awful gloom of the

    Temple, or killed by the ugly mass of the pyramid.

    In one aspect of ancient Art, however, there is both ethical and

    artistic possibility. In the idea of the Sphinx, the spirit of the

    ancient world found a partial articulation. Here the struggle with

    nature is most manifest, here where victory and defeat so strangely

    mingle. The divine womanhood of the head and bust, the

    contemplative power of the broad mas-sive brow, the soul of

    eternity that sleeps in the calm wakeful-ness of the eyes, the depthof emotion wedded to indomitable will in the full firm lips, and

    below all this, and supporting it, and linked with it as indissoluble

    part of one organism, the lion's body with its virile force of muscle

    in shoulder and thigh and haunch,-such are the elements in this,

    the most marvel-ous aesthetic conception of the genius of antiquity.

    What need is there to point out the ethical import of such a

    conception or to show that here a moral consciousness strug-gles,

    not altogether in vain, to give birth to the very deepest of moral

    ideas?

    It is the dualism of Nature and Spirit, the eternal war of the

    actual and the ideal of the moral life. To a later age of Art

    This content downloaded from 92.87.204.90 on Thu, 6 Mar 2014 11:46:51 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms

    and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/12/2019 Morality and Art 2

    8/33

  • 8/12/2019 Morality and Art 2

    9/33

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/12/2019 Morality and Art 2

    10/33

  • 8/12/2019 Morality and Art 2

    11/33

    was left the task of disclosing the inherent inadequacy of the half

    beast, half human creation, to express, with a clear articu-lateness,

    the conflict of matter and mind; an age which, in the complete

    human form, should find the balance of the antithesis, and in

    finding it should lose it and itself be lost in the growing light of itsown thought, no less than in the darkness of its extinction by a

    world conquering alien. In Barbaric Art and in Barbaric Ethics,

    Spirit was inarticulate because it could not find in matter an

    adequate medium for its expression. It is to the sculpture of Greece

    and to the thought and life of Athens in the age of Pericles that we

    must go for the records of a race who gloried in finding such a

    medium, and who paid the pen-alty of believing that its adequacywas permanent.

    In Athenian Art and in Athenian Society and Politics, we find an

    atmosphere illumined by the light of self-conscious de-finiteness.

    Freedom in order, liberty under law, thought cloth-ing itself infinite

    embodiment and for the time unconscious of its limitation, finding

    indeed in the idea of limit the fullest ex-pression of its highest aims

    and aspirations,-such were some of the characteristic springs of the

    Greek life at its loftiest reach of achievement. Spirit seemed to have

    lost, in the pliancy of matter, the sense of Infinitude; matter seemed

    to have be-come instinct with all spiritual possibility. Did

    intelligence ever conceive of any form in which more truly and

    simply dwells the soul of an Infinite Beauty than in the rhythmic

    curves of the Theseus? Before the most time mutilated remains of

    that age, we breathe the air not of the studio but of the shrine: any

    sense of admiration at the rare possibilities of skill of hand andbrain is instinctively checked as a profaneness, and we all but

    believe that a marble bosom did heave into glowing life beneath the

    last loving touches of Pygmalion's chisel.

    Turn where you will amid the surviving fragments of the

    creative energy of the Greek imagination, you find the same

    marvelous idealization of matter, the same conviction that the hardrind of Nature has for once been broken through, that Nature has

    given up its foreignness and willingly yielded to the interpretative

    insight of Art; that man has risen clear of the brute; that the

    human form is, even to the eye of sense, divine.

    This content downloaded from 92.87.204.90 on Thu, 6 Mar 2014 11:46:51 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms

    and Conditions

  • 8/12/2019 Morality and Art 2

    12/33

    59

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/12/2019 Morality and Art 2

    13/33

    The ideas thus reflected in this golden age of plastic Art were

    precisely the ideas that moulded the social life of Athens. To make

    the life of its citizens free, happy, beautiful, pur-poseful, naturally

    artistic, as well as artistically natural, was the aim of the loftyleading spirits whom the genius of the Greek life inspired. The

    actual of that life came so near to the ideal, that that aim was all

    but realized. The self-conscious-ness of that realization constituted

    at once the serene sunlight of the Attic Spirit and the darkness of

    the Fate in which ere long it was swallowed up.

    The artistic and the ethical ideals were, as if for a moment, one.

    Art reflected life and educated it; the moral impulse found in Art

    its truest and fullest expression, until the idea of "Art for Art"

    became an ethical as well as an aesthetic aspira-tion, destroying the

    deepest life of the former, and depriving Art of its moral

    significance. Why, it has often been asked, did Greek Morality

    degenerate most, precisely at the moment when Greek Art

    achieved its noblest triumphs? The question has been variously

    answered; doubtless there must be various elements in the answer.

    When Socrates says that Ethics, to be truly such, must be

    purposeful, self-conscious, he indicates the source of the moral

    weakness of the spirit of his time.

    So long as the ideal of the State was a vital thing for the in-

    dividual citizen, so long as the Athenian cultivated his body and

    exercised his intelligence in the service of the Genius of his City, he

    escaped the worst consequences of that exclusive-ness which theSociety of the City enforced. Till then he could be socially self-

    denying, publicly brave and privately honorable and virtuous,

    according to his ideas of honor and virtue. But, with the dawn of

    the ambition, begotten of the age of Pericles, to make the individual

    life under the strong underlying aes-thetic impulse of the Athenian

    spirit, a work of art, came the end of the Greek Ethics and the

    degradation of the Greek Art. To aim at the acquirement of beauty,

    physical and moral, with a view not to the service of Athene but to

    individual self-com-placence and individual blessedness, to strive

    after a statuesque completeness in the individual life, with only the

    vaguest refer-ence to a correspondingly increased value in the

    aggregate of

    This content downloaded from 92.87.204.90 on Thu, 6 Mar 2014 11:46:51 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms

    and Conditions

  • 8/12/2019 Morality and Art 2

    14/33

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/12/2019 Morality and Art 2

    15/33

  • 8/12/2019 Morality and Art 2

    16/33

    social relations, this was the fatal moral mistake of the philo-

    sophically grounded life of the most perfect of ancient com-

    munities. In the course of the development of such a mistake, it was

    but natural that the State, less and less an object of de-votion,

    should lose its cohesiveness and cease to be. In the sphere of Art,

    the like degeneracy was not less real because it is more difficult to

    trace. It is true that public spirit, patriotism, glad, or at the lowest

    ungrudging self-sacrifice to duty, clear-ness of moral discernment,

    the fidelity of friendship, the sancti-ty of domestic relations, that

    these had vanished as facts of po-litical and social life, long ere the

    bloom was shed or even the fair bud had fully unfolded itself in the

    flower of Greek crea-tive Art. That flower derived its quality from aroot and soil to which the glorious past of Athens had most largely

    contrib-uted. The growth of the Greek idea, especially in its

    degener-acy, was characterized by a rapidity unexampled in

    history. Hence the Art of its last days, that is the noblest forms of

    that Art did not strictly belong to the short and fleeting epoch in

    which it appeared, save perhaps in a certain self-conscious pride of

    technique, which is not altogether undiscernible even in the very

    purest of its creations. Whatever exception we must here allow to

    the general principle that the results of the creative impulse

    correctly reflect the ethical life of the time, must be grounded upon

    the unique swiftness of the Athenian social development, upon the

    wide application of the words, "Ars longa vita brevis" and upon the

    fact proved by all history that the highest products of thought and

    imagination are often reaped in periods of incipient national and

    social decay. Yet speaking broadly, the defects' of the ethical

    conceptions of Greece were essentially the defects of her Art. The

    Greek State, like the Greek religion of which its Art was the

    nominal exponent, was based upon a doctrine of natural selection.

    It rested upon the belief, practical at once and theoretic, that the

    choice specimens of mankind alone should inherit the earth. It

    lifted some human qualities into the Divine, but not hu-manity as

    such. It found no place or voice for the infinite pa-thos that gives tomodern Morality and Art of the highest types whatever of value or

    permanence or beauty they possess. It

    This content downloaded from 92.87.204.90 on Thu, 6 Mar 2014 11:46:51 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms

    and Conditions

  • 8/12/2019 Morality and Art 2

    17/33

    6i

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/12/2019 Morality and Art 2

    18/33

    found no expression for the wail of the slave or the claim to

    compassion of the physically, morally, or intellectually weak. It cast

    out from it all shapes of deformity, or misery, or mis-fortune, as an

    ugliness, which its refined ethical and artistic taste could neitheruse nor tolerate. Hence, beyond all the sun-light of an ideal life of

    healthy practical energy and contem-plative thought, there loomed

    ever the shadow of that fate, which, in the natural and necessary

    philanthropic reaction that preceded the assault of Rome upon its

    effete political life, wrapped Athens in the gloom in which so soon

    its exclusive freedom and its creative power were lost. The idea

    "Art for Art" consoling motto of the Greeks, who, when theircountry was enslaved, set up their studios in the Imperial City and

    amid the luxury of the voluptuous towns of the Campanian Coast,

    was neither new nor strange. We have said that it is difficult to

    connect the moral degeneracy of the most splendid phase of

    Athenian life with the noblest creative achievements which were

    contemporary with that degeneracy. It is not so difficult on a wide

    familiarity with some even of the most exquisite productions of

    Athenian Art. One of the most renowned works of the chisel of

    Praxiteles is the Aphrodite of Cnidos. No goddess more truly

    influenced the society of Ath-ens in her hour of most unquestioned

    supremacy. No altar was more duly honored by public offering or

    by private rite. No deity was ever more really worshipped in spirit

    and in truth. And, as he bowed before the shrine, the Athenian

    devotee paid his vows and presented his gifts, and poured out his

    prayers, to the idealized image of the most noted beauty and themost notorious profligate of the age. Phyrne, the courtesan for

    whose bought smile and favors the young noblesse of the city

    contended, had served as model to Praxiteles, mightiest master of

    Athenian Sculpture at its best.

    It was the belief in the ideal of the State as conceived by theGreek mind and all but realized in the Greek life, that de-stroyed

    the moral possibilities of Greece; it was the aesthetic faith that

    found in the sensuous perfectness of the human form an adequate

    medium for spiritual expression, that killed Athenian Art.

    This content downloaded from 92.87.204.90 on Thu, 6 Mar 2014 11:46:51 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms

    and Conditions

  • 8/12/2019 Morality and Art 2

    19/33

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/12/2019 Morality and Art 2

    20/33

  • 8/12/2019 Morality and Art 2

    21/33

    Space does not permit us to follow through decadence to death

    the future progress of either. The spiritual atmosphere of earlier

    imperial Rome is not healthy either for the student of Ethics or the

    student of Art; an atmosphere of more than half insane sensuality

    and cruelty. The grossness of morals and the prostitution of Art are

    reflected with a fearful clearness iii those sculptures and sketches

    from Pompeii, collected in amuseum at Naples, which women are

    not allowed to enter.

    In Rome the Greek Art found its grave; but in Rome also the Art

    spirit had its resurrection as reflector at once and teacher of a new

    ethic and a new life.

    Amid the vilest travesties of the speculative Greek Morality inits epicurean phase, there lived and grew the stoic ideal, which,

    with all its narrowness of conception, still contained the germ of an

    infinite Ethical possibility. To the latter it was given to speak the

    last word of the old world both for Art and Ethics, and

    unconsciously to announce the advent of a new era for both.

    The moral ideal of the earlier Roman Stoics revolted from Art.

    It wanted the touch of emotion to make it a religion, whose

    universal aspiration should recognize and include uni-versal needs.

    It was doubtless a preparation for Christian Art and Morality, but

    it is difficult to see how these could ever have been evolved from it.

    It felt the pathos of human life, but in its essential and practical

    pessimism it contained no idea of an optimism on the basis of

    pessimism, such as constituted the very deepest truth of

    Christianity. Its highest outlook was towards the dim suggestion of

    a life beyond the grave, "

  • 8/12/2019 Morality and Art 2

    22/33

    63

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/12/2019 Morality and Art 2

    23/33

    theses and its play of passion, was to combine the universalis-tic

    ideal of the Stoic with a purified enthusiasm for that beauty which

    the Stoic despised.

    Passing over the attractive field of inquiry, that would invite toan attempt to trace the development of the new birth of Art and

    Morals which belongs to the early Christian centuries, the

    emergence above ground from the catacombs of the Christian

    Spirit and its evolution as manifested in the Roman, the By-zantine,

    the Lombard, and the Gothic Architecture and Sculp-ture, let it

    suffice to glance at that form of Art which most distinctively

    belongs to Christianity-Painting, and at the moral life whichcorresponded with it. In Christianity Spirit never found its

    adequate expression in Art; even from the first the moral ideal

    transcended full infinite manifestation; it could be no longer

    expressed through matter: Barbaric inarticulate-ness and Classic

    balance alike lay behind it; it did indeed take up into self the

    artistic impulse, in so far as form and color were concerned, and

    use it for its own high ends, but in so do-ing it glorified, exalted,

    transfigured, satisfied, it until, like the Greek Morality, it lost it,

    though unlike the Greek Morality it survived the loss.

    In the perfection of pictorial Art under the Christian im-pulse,

    we have, of course, the reflection of some of the deepest ethical

    truths of which Christianity was the source. Under our present

    limits a glance at one or two outstanding features must suffice.

    One of the central ideas of this Age of Art was the Madon-na.

    This was perhaps the greatest ethical, as it was the great-est

    esthetic conception of the Middle Ages. In Classical Art it has no

    counterpart. Jetvov -o ore'xireelea-ev,says Sopho-cles, but the idea is

    a mere casual reflection. The divinity of Motherhood simply did

    not influence practically the Athenian life or the Athenian Art.

    In the moral culture, the moral regeneration of Christen-dom,

    what force has played a more, resultful part? In the Magdalene, the

    divinity of Repentance found its earliest utter-ance, a conception

    which was or would have been most as-suredly "foolishness" to the

    Greek philosophic mind, even

    This content downloaded from 92.87.204.90 on Thu, 6 Mar 2014 11:46:51 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms

    and Conditions

  • 8/12/2019 Morality and Art 2

    24/33

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/12/2019 Morality and Art 2

    25/33

  • 8/12/2019 Morality and Art 2

    26/33

    under its deepest and truest moral mood. To trace the power of

    these two artistic, as well as religious creations, to the uni-versal

    popularity of female deities in every age, as shown in the worship

    of Diana, Astarte, or Isis, is not only to rationalize Christianity; it is

    to miss the ethical import of the most es-sential of its ideas. In the

    Christ of Mediaeval Painting, the divinity of Sorrow and the worth

    of Man as Man give the full-est expression to the spirit of Stoicism,

    while they add to that spirit the element of passion, without which

    abstract self-re-nunciation, no less than abstract universalism,

    could never fas-cinate or renovate mankind. It was not the Greek

    idea of God in the image of man, it was no apotheosis of the rarest

    intellec-tual and physical human beauty; no artificial divinehumanity formed by the palaestra and the School, with eyes that

    had looked on no ugliness and ears which discordance had never

    entered. It was a figure whose humanity had been worn and spent

    in service, and whose divinity had become perfect through

    suffering.

    The forms of an Art like this, so long as it was true to itself, werenever self-consciously adequate to the ideas that inspired it. It was

    an Aesthetic Age, in which "Art for Art" was never a motive;

    whose half unconscious motto was "Art for Re-ligion," when

    Religion and Morality were one. In its noblest remains we are

    invariably struck by the mighty force of one idea; there is no

    slovenly slurring of details, yet there is no self-complacent pride of

    technique; while, from the ethical point of view, we are taught

    without being lectured, and our aesthetic enjoyment is seldom if

    ever less, because it is the ve-hide of moral teaching. The greatest

    religious painters, per-haps, never painted in order to teach, yet the

    essence of the purest Ethics of their time was most unquestionably

    very largely inspired by their work. Paradoxical though at first

    sight it seems, it is just as unquestionable that, in the deca-dence of

    the sixteenth century, the dawn of the idea of "Art for Art" was

    precisely the point at which Art and Morals ceased to have anessential connection.

    The growth of Pictorial Art in the service of the Church

    corresponded with a broadening ethical outlook. More than

    This content downloaded from 92.87.204.90 on Thu, 6 Mar 2014 11:46:51 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms

    and Conditions

  • 8/12/2019 Morality and Art 2

    27/33

    65

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/12/2019 Morality and Art 2

    28/33

    any other agent it unfolded to the world the universalism which

    only half consciously inspired it. The abstract form in Sculp-ture

    tended to stereotype the ideas it expressed. In Painting, the

    principles of shadow and perspective formed the elements of aninfinite progress, while they interpreted the pathos and the

    universality of the Christian conceptions of Humanity and of

    Moral relation. The inadequacy of Painting, even for ten-tative

    spiritual expression, disclosed itself just before the Ref-ormation.

    Art lost its simplicity, its subordination of detail, its independence

    of technique, its reverence, its spirituality of conception, its purity

    of execution. Hence, it gave up Crea-tion for imitation, lovinginterpretation for sensuous idolatry, spirit for sense and freedom

    for license. It ceased to lend itself to the display of religious facts,

    and then and thereafter, as Ruskin says, "religious facts were

    employed for the display of Art," and by a gradual process Art

    degenerated, through the sensuousness of realistic flesh color, until

    it came to revel at last in the clever realism of technique displayed

    by the still life and domesticity of the Dutch School. "Ye have made

    the Virgin," says Savonarola to the painters of Florence, "Ye have

    made the Virgin to appear like a prostitute." What wonder that the

    Church of the Reformation disdained the Sisterhood of Art? The

    Reformation could not come while a genuine ar-tistic impulse

    promoted a pure worship and a lofty morality. It had to come when

    sensuousness took the place of aspiration, and spiritual adoration

    was exchanged for idolatry. The suc-cess of Medieval Art was

    unquestionably owing to the fact that genius was nourished in theatmosphere of a passionate social purity. When that atmosphere

    became contaminated, scenic Art could be no longer the essential

    handmaid of re-ligion.

    It is unnecessary, perhaps, to discuss at length the relation of

    Art and Ethics after the Renaissance and the Reformation, for it isin Music and in Poetry, rather than in the Plastic or Pictorial

    spheres of Art, that that relation is most clearly seen. The moral

    movement of post-Reformation society is, of course, from age to

    age, reflected in the portrait and the landscape, as well as in the

    spirit of the periodic modernizing

    Vol. XIV-No.i 5

    This content downloaded from 92.87.204.90 on Thu, 6 Mar 2014 11:46:51 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms

    and Conditions

  • 8/12/2019 Morality and Art 2

    29/33

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/12/2019 Morality and Art 2

    30/33

  • 8/12/2019 Morality and Art 2

    31/33

    or imitation of pagan Models; yet these are but accidental re-

    flections; they are not the creative impress of an ethical im-pulse.

    One instance of such an impress under such an impulse, we

    select in closing from the history of four centuries: one of the most

    obvious and one of the most suggestive. The social earthquake of

    the French Revolution had no concomitant and no result more

    significant for the Aesthetic or the Moral in-tcrests of mankind

    than the rise of that movement of thought of which Goethe and

    Wordsworth were the most outstanding exponents. In wide

    diversity of manner and form, yet with a perfect oneness in spirit

    and in originality, they expressed an idea which all the glory ofMediaeval Art at its highest point failed to reach. For the noblest

    thought of Leonardo, of Pe-rugino, of Raphael, was the mystic

    union of Earth and Heaven; to the poetic spirit of the nineteenth

    century it was given to grasp and realize the deeper conception of

    the Eternal and Essential unity of the Human and the Divine.

    JAMES LAING.

    DYSART, SCOTLAND.

    RELIGION AS AN IDEA.'

    RECENTphilosophical literature presents, among other

    note-worthy features, a peculiar handling of the subject ofrelig-ion. This peculiarity in treatment may be described as a

    more or less conscious commingling, even confusion, of

    elements. On the one hand, writers are concerned to make

    plain the bio-logical and sociological function of religion and

    they give defi-nitions accordingly:

    "Religion is a substitute in the rational world for instinct in the sub-rational world."'

    1 The -writer of this paper wishes to call attention to the fact that he is not

    concerned to establish any form of faith but simply to inquire whether the term

    "religion" does not demand a more exact connotation than is given it in recent

    discussions.

    2 Lester F. Ward: Article. "Essential Nature of Religion."

  • 8/12/2019 Morality and Art 2

    32/33

    This content downloaded from 92.87.204.90 on Thu, 6 Mar

    2014 11:46:51 AM All use subject to

    JSTOR Terms and Conditions

  • 8/12/2019 Morality and Art 2

    33/33

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp