modern phil critique

Upload: ali-rizvi

Post on 04-Apr-2018

213 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/29/2019 Modern phil Critique

    1/45

    1

    A critique of modern philosophy

    Abstract: In this paper I challenge modernphilosophys self-conception as an absolute critique (i.e., a

    critique of everything/anything). I argue that such a conception is not only misconceived, it is also

    ideological in character. Looking back to its origins, I develop a genealogy of modern philosophys self-

    understanding in order to deconstruct it and disassociate it from possible alternative conceptions of

    philosophy, arguing for a more modest conception of philosophy as a subject which provides tools for

    developing human powers of reflection.

    The wise in every age conclude, what Pyrrho taught and Hume renewed, that

    dogmatists are fools.

    Thomas Blacklock1

    This is an essay (exercise/askesis) in the philosophy of philosophy, and not

    merely in metaphilosophy, to paraphrase the opening lines ofTimothy Williamsons

    recent book. As Williamson rightly claims, to talk about philosophy is itself doing

    philosophy (Williamson, 2007, pp. ix-x). In this sense, a discourse about philosophy

    cannot be metaphilosophy, done from beyond and above (from an Archimedean vantage

    point beyond the bounds of specific space and time) (cf. Heidegger, 1956, pp. 21ff.).

    Willard Quine, following Otto Neurath, has likened science (and) philosophy to a boat

    which, if we are to rebuild it, we must rebuild plank by plankwhile staying afloat in it

    (Quine, 1960, p. 3). Quine uses this metaphor principally to demonstrate the piecemeal

    character of philosophy, but it can also be invoked (as I do here) to allude to its immanent

    Acknowledgements:

    1 Quoted in Popkin, 1993, p. 517.

  • 7/29/2019 Modern phil Critique

    2/45

    2

    character. This discussion is closely connected to the nature of philosophy (or at least to

    the prominent part of it). Philosophy is not only a reflective but also a self-reflective

    enterprise;2

    in it, reflection and self-reflection are intertwined in a unique way.

    Sociologist and philosopher Jrgen Habermas has connected this double reflexive

    character of philosophy to the essence of natural language itself:

    Because of the reflexive character of natural languages, speaking about what

    has been spoken, direct or indirect mention of speech components, belongs to

    the normal linguistic process of reaching understanding. The expression

    metalinguistic judgments in a natural language about sentences of the same

    language suggests a difference in level that does not exist. It is one of the

    most interesting features of natural languages that they can be used as their

    own languages of explication.

    (Habermas, 1998, p. 39)

    What Habermas says about natural language applies to philosophy as well, and it is

    intimately connected to the reflective character of philosophy.

    Philosophy has existed in many cultures, and it can be safely said that, in a sense,

    if the properties of reflection and self-reflection are coterminous with human life,

    philosophy is also coterminous with it. Such reflective attitudes towards the self, the

    universe, and the other can be found in various places across space and time, and the

    2 Reflection involves distance from the object of enquiry, while self-reflection requires that the subject

    maintain a certain distance from herself.

  • 7/29/2019 Modern phil Critique

    3/45

    3

    commonality among them can be observed (v. Cohen, 1995; Moore, 1995; Saksena,

    1995; Mei, 1995). However, this slight, almost banal, observation should not lead one to

    conclude that philosophical reflection has taken the same form across space and time, and

    thus elide the distinctions and specificities which give particular attempts at reflection

    and self-reflection their unique flavour.3

    Modern philosophy4

    shares general characteristics with the philosophical activity

    of other eras and epochs of human civilisation, but that is not what is interesting in

    understanding its essence: what is interesting is its uniqueness, that which gives it its

    differential characteristics (in the lingua of Aristotelian logic, what we are interested in is

    not its genus but its specific difference).

    Modern philosophy emerged during a revolutionary epoch in the history of

    Europe, an epoch defined by a transition from the medieval worldview to the modern

    worldview (so-called modernity). This specific development not only defines (at least in

    part) the modern world (and especially its view), but also the self-image of philosophy

    itself: the self-image that philosophy is debating intensely as the distance from the

    founding act is becoming remote (v. Williams, 2000; Cottingham, 2009; Solomon,

    2001).

    3 Of course, many philosophers deny that philosophy has existed or can exist in any culture. For them,

    philosophy needs the fulfilment of specific social conditions in order to exist. Its safe to say, however, that

    in making such claims they have a very specific conception of philosophy in mind, and not philosophy in

    general (Barry Stroud is one such philosopher: see Stroud, 2001, p. 28. Cf. Cohen, 1995).

    4Although I use the term modern philosophy throughout the paper, it should be clear that my critique is

    focused on certain specific conception of it (as represented by Graham Pirest, for example); thus, my

    claims about modern philosophy should be read this in mind.

  • 7/29/2019 Modern phil Critique

    4/45

    4

    The revolutionary character of modern philosophy is most manifest in the

    writings of its undisputed father, the Frenchman Ren Descartes,5

    who claimed that all

    knowledge needs a radical new beginning and new foundations.6

    Descartes was writing

    in a period (and the same is true of Francis Bacon) when:

    . . . familiar teachings of centuries about religion, politics, and science

    were publicly questioned and sharply disputed across a war-torn Europe. The

    Protestant Reformation of the sixteenth century and the on-going Catholic

    Counter Reformation, together with the proliferation of religious sects and the

    foundation of new religious orders, highlighted the fragile intellectual

    foundations on which the apparent unity of Christianity had relied.

    (Clarke, 2006, p. 69)

    This points to the important fact that modern philosophy emerged in a milieu in which

    Christianity was still a dominant and ruling force, but was nonetheless finding itself

    increasingly on the defensive, and was losing ground to the new emerging forces of

    rational debate. Philosophy7

    was one of those forces, and this helped define the self-

    5 Some have suggested two fathers, one for the French side and the other for the English side; the English

    one is Francis Bacon (Copleston, 1994, p. 1).

    6 For my perspective in this paper, what is of primary importance is the idea of a radical new beginning in

    Descartes, and not the specific method (that is, the method of radical doubt) which he uses to accomplish it.

    7 Of course, philosophy at the time was not separated from science, and the founding fathers especially.

    Descartes was a great scientist and mathematician (especially the latter) in his own right, and had a crucial

  • 7/29/2019 Modern phil Critique

    5/45

    5

    image of philosophy as the revolutionary force without parallel, which corresponds to,

    and is attested by, the notion of philosophy as a new beginning (at times an absolute

    beginning) put forth by both Descartes and Bacon. Just like Francis Bacon, his

    contemporary in England, Descartes thought that a new beginning had to be made in

    human knowledge. The old philosophy of schools could not be reformed: Aristotelianism

    had to be rejected in toto (Matthews, 1989, p. 88, emphasis in the original; v. Copleston,

    1994, 1).8

    Similarly, Francis Bacon saw in the emergence of the new philosophy and the

    new sciences the prospect of an entirely new age, which would be quantitatively and

    qualitatively different from its predecessor.

    The issue here is not whether they were justified in their assumption that they

    were making a complete break with the past; it suffices for my argument to establish that

    this is how they saw things. Moreover, as Frederick Copleston aptly notes, they were not

    entirely unjustified in this self perception: Men such as Bacon and Descartes were

    doubtless unaware of the extent to which their minds were influenced by former ways of

    impact on the early development and orientation of Sir Isaac Newtons thought. This also partially explains

    mainstream philosophys partiality towards science.

    8Hence Descartesprejudiceagainst preconceived opinions (praejudicia) (Cottingham, 1998a, 8; cf.

    Gadamer, 2004 [1975], pp. 276-277). For the theme of an absolute new beginning one should of course

    consult DescartesDiscourse on Method(see Descartes, 1985, pp. 111-151). Descartes often couches his

    argument in terms of not relying on others opinions, and thinking through the matter for oneself, and he

    claims that common sense is often a better guide than scholarly tomes. This can legitimately be taken as an

    expression of modern individual self-determination, but, more crucially, Descartes is trying to establish a

    new tradition, a new common sense (as opposed to the dominant but receding tradition and idea of common

    sense).

  • 7/29/2019 Modern phil Critique

    6/45

    6

    thought; but their consciousness of standing at the threshold of a new era is not

    unjustified (Copleston, 1994, p. 10).

    Thus, modern philosophy began its life aspartof a revolutionary movement that

    heralded a new age, different from the one it was aiming to replace. Furthermore, it

    started its life in an environment in which it was a minority view, albeit one which was

    growing.9

    These two facts make it natural that the critique10

    of dominant worldviews11

    (medieval civilisation and its remnants in this instance) became the main vocation of

    modern philosophy and part and parcel of its self-imagenot critique in general, as in

    the critique that must accompany any philosophical reflection, but aspecific conception

    of critique, which characterises (and understands) itself as limitless and absolute. The

    great German philosopher Immanuel Kant famously articulated this notion when he

    wrote:

    Our age is the genuine age of criticism, to which everything must submit.

    Religion through its holiness and legislation through its majesty commonly

    seek to exempt themselves from it. But in this way they excite a just

    suspicion against themselves, and cannot lay claim to that unfeigned respect

    9 It is interesting to note that almost none of the founders of modern philosophy were professional

    philosophers based in universities (only Kant, who is a much later author), and almost all of them wrote in

    the vernacular and not in Latin, the scholarly language of the day (Copleston, 1994, p. 5). Descartes and

    Bacon did both write in Latin, and also in French and English respectively. Locke and Hume wrote all their

    major works in English; subsequently, Kant wrote mainly in German.

    10In this paper I use the terms critique and criticism interchangeably.

    11 Be they actually dominant or imagined to be so.

  • 7/29/2019 Modern phil Critique

    7/45

    7

    that reason grants only to that which has been able to withstand its free and

    public examination.

    (Kant, 1999, p. A xii n, emphasis in the original)

    Note here that it is reason which grants the sought-afterunfeigned respectreason is

    the sole authority which decides which other authorities deserve respect, and to what

    extent. On the other hand, although we find similar requirements for reason elaborated on

    later in the Critique (A 738-B 766), its clear that in order to gain respect reason doesnt

    need to (shouldnt) submit to any other authority but itself; reason, in the Kantian

    conception, is self-justificatory in a way in which no other faculty or authority is.

    What is of further interest (from our perspective) in this paper is Kants use of the

    universal quantifier to determine the range of criticism (everything). There are no

    exceptions; the critique is total.12

    True, Kant was writing in an age considerably different

    from that of Descartes and Baconif not already the Age of Enlightenment, it was at

    least much nearer to it than that of Descartes and Bacon. Here is how Kant himself saw

    things:

    If it is now asked whether we live in an enlightenedage, the answer is: No,

    but we do live in an age of enlightenment. As matters now stand, a good deal

    more is required for people on the whole to be in the position, or even able to

    12Critique is total, but this totality doesnt necessarily imply a wholesale critique (that is, a cri tique of

    everything at once)it can be carried out piecemeal. Thus the totality of critique in the sense used here

    shouldnt be confused with wholesale critique; a total critique can take either piecemeal or wholesale

    routes (more on this in the main body text, below).

  • 7/29/2019 Modern phil Critique

    8/45

    8

    be put in the position, of using their own understanding confidently and well

    in religious matters, without anothers guidance. But we do have distinct

    intimations that the field is now being opened for them to work freely in this

    direction and the hindrances to universal enlightenment or to humankinds

    emergence from its self-incurred tutelage are gradually becoming fewer.

    (Kant, 1999, p. 21, emphasis in the original; translation slightly amended)

    And here we can see that the self-conception of philosophy has already started to become

    detached from the founding act (as something which is universal irrespective of space

    and time).

    A word or two must be said about Kants notion of critique and its relation to that

    of Descartes. Kants enterprise is clearly very different from that of Descartes in many

    respects, and not only in the fact that Kant was living much nearer to the actual Age of

    Enlightenment than Descartes. Kant, crucially, doesnt share Descartes commitment to

    the methodic doubt as a way to establish absolute and certain foundations of

    knowledge.13

    He doesnt share Descartes search for absolute certainty either (in this he is

    much closer to Nietzsche than to Descartes);14

    Kant instinctively realises that the demise

    of the medieval Christian world also meant the demise of the idea of absolute certainty,

    13On Descartes methodic doubt and its revolutionary character see Williams, 1998, pp. 28 -49.

    14

    Kantas is well knowndoes claim apodictic certainty for his system (see for example Kuehn, 2006,

    especially p. 655), but such a claim is limited to cognitive knowledge and its conditions, and does not

    encompass reason and its territory as a whole. There is a vast grey area outside this, which will always

    remain as long as we are humans. In this, Kant is much closer to John Locke than to Descartes, although

    comparatively speaking John Locke is more agnostic than Kant.

  • 7/29/2019 Modern phil Critique

    9/45

    9

    and as a true believer in reason he was willing to sacrifice certainty as a price for

    believing in reason and reason alone, and believing in it in its own terms.

    Kant also differs from Descartes in his rejection of presuppositionless knowledge;

    for Kant, belief in reason is not presuppositionless (although he does think that reason

    must justify its presuppositions in its own manner if its to retain its authority). With

    these qualifications, Kant retains Descartes notion of absolute critique in the following

    substantial sense: every authority and every source of knowledge must justify itself on

    the altar of reason in order to deserve consideration and legitimacy, and there is no

    authority which has a right to compete with the authority of reason. Kants oft-talked

    about humility is not about this point at all; he doesnt concede anything as far as the

    absolute authority of reason is concerned. His humility is related, rather, to another point.

    What he does concede is that in order to retain its authority, reason has to justify it, even

    if in its own terms, and that this justification cannot be based on presuppositionless15

    and

    absolute grounds, but is an ongoing project.16

    His humility pertains to the fact that his

    positive estimate of the powers of reason in certain aspects is much weaker than that of

    Descartes.

    15 Thus critique can be total (in its relation to external worldviews) without being presuppositionless

    (internally) as long as the presuppositions are justified (internally). Also, total critique is not necessarily

    opposed to piecemeal critique (a critique can be total in its intentions but piecemeal in its execution; or,

    alternatively, it can be total externally but piecemeal internally). For a critique to be total (critique of

    anything/everything) it only needs to hold that in principle everything is amenable to critique.

    16The construction of reason is to be seen as process rather than product, as practices of connection and

    integration rather than as once and for all laying foundations (ONeill, 1992, p. 292, also p. 303).

  • 7/29/2019 Modern phil Critique

    10/45

    10

    Thus, Kants notion of critique is not aimed at absolute certainty, and it doesnt

    arise from scepticism. The attitude of questioning is to be differentiated from scepticism.

    The attitude of questioning is aimed at alien17

    authoritiesthe authorities that are not

    vindicated by reason. Reason is absolute, but not in the sense of being presuppositionless:

    it is only absolute in the sense that every authority must justify itself in front of it in order

    to be considered a legitimate authority (be it a theoretical or practical authority). Again,

    reason itself needs vindication, but in its own terms, while everything else be justified in

    reasons terms. As Kant puts it:

    This is evidently the effect not of the thoughtlessness of our age [i.e., the Age

    of Enlightenment or age of criticism], but of its ripened power of judgment,

    which will no longer be put off with illusory knowledge, and which demands

    that reason take on anew the most difficult of all its tasks, namely, that of

    17For Kant, the essence of reason is freedom: [t]hevery existence of reason depends upon freedom

    (Kant, 1999, p. A738/B766). The authorities which rely on coercion or dictatorial powers (such as God,

    Church, State, religion, nature, etc.), whose dictates are givens that cannot be questioned, are term ed by

    Kant alien authorities because their nature is alien to the essence of reason, i.e., freedom. Kant also terms

    these authorities arbitrary because, even in principle, their dictates cannot be shared by everyone (the

    Christian Churchs commands make sense only to its devotees, for example); reasons dictates are at least

    in principle sharable by everyone. Obviously, this argument is valid only if Kant is working here with a

    very thin conception of reason, which is the common property of all (mature) humans. In my opinion,

    however, Kants argument fails precisely because he presupposes a very substantive conception of reason

    that hinges on and presumes the notion of autonomy (self determination). (My interpretation here is heavily

    indebted to ONeill, 1992, p. 293 andpassim, though ONeill doesnt make the objection I allude to at the

    end; also, see her other seminal works, referenced below in the text. Cf. Schneewind, 1998, pp. 483-507).

  • 7/29/2019 Modern phil Critique

    11/45

    11

    self-knowledge, and to institute a court of justice, by which reason may

    secure its rightful claims while dismissing all its groundless pretensions, and

    this not by mere decrees but according to its own eternal and unchangeable

    laws; and this court is none other than the critique of pure reason itself.

    (Kant, 1991, pp. A xi-xii, emphasis in the original)

    While everything else is answerable to reason and its authority, reason is answerable only

    to itself.

    Hence, Kant differs from Descartes not in delegetimising all authorities, which

    are in potential or actual competition with reason, but in determining how to justify the

    rational enterprise and how to build the edifice of reason once the negative work has been

    performed. Here we can see that Kant clearly comes to differentiate between what is

    revolutionary and what is conservative in the modern philosophical enterprise. The

    negative critique (critique of competing (alien) authorities) is absolute and revolutionary,

    while the positive enterprise is conservative (and constructive).18

    Kants notion of critique is much more complex than can be fully explored here,

    but it can be claimed with some justification that his notion of philosophy as the

    custodian of reason, as the critique of everything, has remained. This is clearly evident

    in a recent attempt at delimiting the essence (specific difference) of philosophy by a well-

    known and well-respected contemporary philosopher and logician, Graham Priest. The

    following two passages are pertinent to our discussion:

    18 For an elaboration on these points, see the seminal works of Onora ONeill (1989, 1992, 2004).

  • 7/29/2019 Modern phil Critique

    12/45

    12

    What distinguishes the role of criticism in philosophy is, I think, precisely

    that there is nothing that may not be challenged. Anything is a fit topic for

    critical scrutiny and potential rejection, including . . . even the efficacy of

    critical reasoning itself.

    (Priest, 2006, p. 201, emphasis in the original)

    I suggest, then, that philosophy is precisely that intellectual inquiry in which

    anythingis open to critical challenge and scrutiny.

    (Ibid., p. 202, emphasis in the original)

    As a good logician, Priest qualifies his claims carefully: he says he does not mean to

    suggest that every philosophy (or philosopher) actually criticisesanything/everything;19

    he is only claiming that if they wanted to they could do so. Philosophers qua philosophers

    and philosophy qua philosophy can potentially criticise everything and anything; nothing

    issacrosanct. Priest considers the counterexample of medieval philosophers, who

    typically did not question the claim that God exists, and insists that this does not violate

    their status as philosophers because if they had wanted to question the existence of God

    they could have done so (p. 201)! This is a bizarre example, and a poor one at that.

    Barring physical impossibility, and barring logical impossibility, anyone could

    potentially do anything. What is special about philosophy in that? Such a thin conception

    of potentiality dilutes the notion of criticism to such an extent that it becomes trivial.

    19 Henceforth, where possible, I shall refer to criticism of anything/everything simply as absolute critique or

    absolute criticisms.

  • 7/29/2019 Modern phil Critique

    13/45

    13

    Priests dilemma here corresponds to the one faced by modern political theorists,

    who, in order to make room for a diversity of beliefs, have put forth the idea ofreasons

    that all can accept as the final arbitrator of disputes in the political arena. James Bohman

    and Henry Richardson (2009) have justifiably taken them to task by pressing them to

    come up with an example of reasons that a person could not accept. As they write:

    To be sure, there are plenty of reasons that, as it may be, a person does not

    accept. Perhaps not caring about flowers, you do not take the presence of

    famous orchid garden to be a reason to visit Fiji. With a sufficient effort of

    imagination and enlarged thinking, however, surely you could come to

    accept that as a reason to go there. That is an empirical possibility.

    (p. 257, emphasis in the original)

    They conclude: [t]he important question, for our purposes, is really whether it is ever the

    case that a reason that one single person intelligibly accepts is not also that could be

    intelligibly accepted by each and every person (p. 258). Surely the answer should be a

    resounding no. With such a thin conception of potentiality, if one person can accept

    something, then surely anyone else should (in principle) be able to do so. In a similar

    vein, like his modern counterpart, the medieval philosopherqua philosopher (and I would

    say qua human being) could surely (in principle) have rejected or doubted the existence

    of God (and some actually did).20

    The dilemma faced by Priest is that if he works with a

    20 In both the Christian and Islamic discourses in the Middle Ages one occasionally finds the names of

    authors who questioned the idea of God altogether. In general, the discussion of the arguments for the proof

  • 7/29/2019 Modern phil Critique

    14/45

    14

    thin conception of the possibility of criticism, this dilutes the uniqueness of the

    philosophy he wants to establish. If he works with a robustconception of the possibility

    of criticism (however defined), then he cannot claim that there was equal (or near equal)

    possibility of denying the existence of God in medieval philosophy qua philosophy, as in

    modern philosophy (and in fact in modern philosophy it is the exact opposite: it is

    becoming increasingly difficult to be a robust theist doing philosophy in our time). One

    could avoid this dilemma by either denying that medieval philosophy, by Priests lights,

    was really a philosophy (one could claim that it was, rather, a theology in disguise).21

    Perhaps Priest would not like to take this route because he is eager to preserve the

    universality of philosophy. Or, one can take the route of distinguishing between

    philosophy in general and the specific forms it takes, in which case Priests description

    would fit modern philosophy (especially its self-image) but not philosophy as such.

    I have so far differentiated between philosophy as such and the specific forms it

    takes, and I would argue that modern philosophy (at least its self-conception) as an

    absolute critique22 is one conception of philosophy among many, and it is the product of

    of the existence of God by Christian and Islamic philosophers of the Middle Ages on their own are

    sufficient to establish that such a group of people existed, even though, naturally enough (and consistent

    with my theory) their names have largely gone unmentioned in the dominant discourses of the age.

    21According to a different conception of philosophy than Priests, such a dilemma would not necessarily

    arise. Thus, one can define philosophy as a conceptual analysis at the highest level of generality and

    abstraction: in which case, one can find much to admire in medieval philosophy despite the many

    substantive claims about reality, which we no longer find persuasive.

    22As should be clear from the body text as a whole, I am not claiming that Priests conception of modern

    philosophy is a majority view in todays mainstream philosophy. In fact, I believe it is not.

  • 7/29/2019 Modern phil Critique

    15/45

    15

    the specific circumstances in which modern philosophy emerged as a revolutionary force

    in the 16th

    and 17th

    centuries in Western Europe. This specific form cannot be

    universalised without confusing philosophy in general with one of the specific forms it

    (historically) took. Insistence on accepting a self-conception of modern philosophy as the

    philosophy, I would argue, is against the spirit of philosophy itself (and against the spirit

    of reflection and critique in general). It would be tantamount to closing off the openings

    for thinking, because one of the things crucial for thought and its prosperity is to always

    keep open alternativesthe avenues of thinking differently. Difference is crucial not for

    its own sake but because it is our only panacea against the tyranny of the same. As

    Michael Foucault puts it:

    But then, what is philosophy todayphilosophical activity, I mean if it is

    not the critical work of thought on itself? And if it does not consist in the

    endeavour of knowing how and to what extent it might be possible to think

    differently, rather than legitimating what is already known? There is always

    something ludicrous in philosophical discourse when it tries, from the

    outside, to dictate to others, to tell them where their truth is and how to find

    it, or when it presumes to give them naively positivistic instruction. But it is

    its right to explore what might be changed, in its own thought, through the

    practice of a knowledge that is foreign to it. The essay which should be

    understood as the test by means of which one modifies oneself through the

    play of truth and not as the simplistic appropriation of others for the purpose

    of communication is the living body of philosophy, at least if we assume

  • 7/29/2019 Modern phil Critique

    16/45

    16

    that philosophy is still what it was in times past, i.e., an ascesis, an exercise

    of the self, in thought.

    (Foucault, 1992, pp. 8-9)

    23

    This is not to claim that difference is value in itself; it is only to say that without the

    possibility of real alternatives there is no thinking. Thus, when we press and question a

    specific philosophy which claims to be universal,24

    we do so in the interest of thinking,

    reflection, and critiquein sum, in the interest of philosophy itself.

    But thinking also needs particularity, specificity, and situatedness within

    particular traditions in order to prosper. By denying its own specificity,25

    its own

    situatedness, modern philosophy26

    also denies the very source of its own life because

    there is no thinking without thinking in a particular space and time. Thinking transcends

    particularity only by locating itself surely and securely within its own particularity (and

    23 I have used here the modified translation by Professor Clare OFarrell, found on her website

    http://www.michel-foucault.com/quote/2001q.html [accessed on 27 November 2010].

    24 The philosophy which in so doing denies (hides from) and forgets its specific origins. Of course, its

    possible to universalise such a philosophy, but thats another matter. Also, my objection is not to the

    claim to universality; my contention is, rather, that the claim is false.

    25 Again, my problem with the conception of modern philosophy in question is not its claim to universality

    as such, but its specific claim that its critical in a way in which other traditions (including philosophical

    traditions) are not. Basically, in my opinion, the claim to absolute critique (taken on face value and without

    explanation provided in the text) is self-contradictory (or at least incoherent).

    26As should be clear from the paper overall, I dont make any claims about modern philosophy as a whole;

    my argument is only against certain interpretations of what modern philosophy is, as exemplified by the

    specific authors I discuss in the text.

  • 7/29/2019 Modern phil Critique

    17/45

    17

    by self-consciously recognising this). Thus, it is in the interest of thinking that we expose

    the fallacy of modern philosophys claim to universality (which involves the denial of its

    own particularity). It is also in the interest of thinking itself that we defend various

    minority traditions of thinking against the imperialistic onslaught of modern

    philosophy.27

    The mistake behind the claim that philosophy is absolute critique is to ignore two

    distinct but interrelated aspects of criticism. Let us call them internal (positive) criticism

    and negative (external) criticism respectively. Internal criticism is a form of self-criticism

    in which one critiques ones own ideas orones own world view (at the level of the

    system).28

    In external criticism, on the other hand, one criticises another worldview at the

    level of individual ideas, or at the system level. Internal criticism can also either be an

    immanent criticism where one acts and argues within the framework of[her] own

    ideas, or it can be carried out as the philosophical activity of reflecting on those ideas at

    a more general level and trying to make sense of them (Williams, 2000, p. 491). The

    latter activity still remains within the ambit of immanent criticism as long as this making

    sense of stops at the points which are essential to our view (without which our view

    would lose its rationale and collapse as a coherent and self-evident whole for us). If we

    transit to that latter option, internal criticism loses its immanent status and becomes a

    27 Every critique is self-interested. Philosophy teaches us self-reflection and enhances our powers of

    reflection, imagination, and alternative thinking, but how we use those powers is not determined by

    philosophy, its determined by us, our interests, and the wider social conditions.

    28 There is also a possibility for internal critique of worldviews other than our own for example,

    empathising with them to such an extent that we internalise them, although whether such identification is

    possible is controversial.

  • 7/29/2019 Modern phil Critique

    18/45

    18

    transcendent29

    criticism, and no longer remains internal; it transforms itself into a species

    of external criticism, since now were reflecting on our fundamental ideas in a neutral or

    impartial way (as if from the viewpoint of someone outside our worldviewwe become

    strangers to our own view), in the same way in which we criticise a view which is

    external to our view.

    To put this categorisation in the context of the birth of modern philosophy: as we

    have seen, its self conception as absolute criticism emerged at the particular juncture of

    history when philosophy (and her allies) was a minority activity pitted against the still-

    dominant but receding and retreating worldview that had prevailed in Europe since the

    Middle Ages (whether it goes under the name of feudalism, or Christendom, or Christian

    civilisation). At the time, philosophy naturally criticised everything/anything it could lay

    its hand on precisely because it was a minority view aiming to destroy and overcome the

    prevalent worldview. But the same cannot be true today, when modern philosophy (and

    her allies) is without doubt a dominant force (although this obviously does not imply that

    they have absolute power).30 Even today, modern philosophy is at its best when it takes

    aim at the remnants of the old forces. But it is a totally different ballgame when

    29Kant uses transcendent to refer to objects (Objects) that cannot be encountered in experience

    (quoted in Kant, 1999, p. 717 n6; original quote is from Kants gesammelte Schriften, edited by the Royal

    Prussian (later German) Academy of Sciences (Berlin: Georg Reiner, later Walter de Gruyter & Co., 1900-

    ), vol. 18, p. 10 ). My use of transcendent here is different from that of Kant, and merely alludes to the

    fact that in transcendent criticism, relation of immanence with the object of criticism is totally severed.

    30For my argument here I dont need to presume that philosophy itself is a dominant force in todays

    world; its sufficient to suppose that the worldview presupposed by the modern philosophical enterprise is

    dominant today.

  • 7/29/2019 Modern phil Critique

    19/45

    19

    philosophy indulges in positive criticism. Self-criticism when it is transcendent criticism

    (that is, a species of external criticism) is always much harder than criticising others, and

    in this, modern philosophy is no different than other traditions. As Bernard Williams,

    one of the most outstanding and perceptive of post-war British philosophers, writes:

    History presents alternatives only in terms of a wider us: it presents

    alternative ways, that is to say various ways, in which human beings have

    lived and hence can live. Indeed, in those terms we may be able to conceive,

    if only schematically and with difficulty, other ways in which human beings

    might live in the future. But that is not the point. What in this connection

    seem to be simply there, to carry no alternatives with them, are elements of

    our ethical and political outlook, and in those terms there are no alternatives

    for us. Those elements are indeed unhintergehbar . . . we can identify with

    the process that led to our outlook because we can identify with its outcome.

    But we cannot in our thought go beyond our outlook into the future and

    remain identified with the result: that is to say, we cannot overcome our

    outlook.

    (Williams, 2000, p. 494, emphasis in the original)

    The point is not that we cannot factually overcome our outlook. That would be

    empirically wrong; people overcome their outlooks all the time (even if such people are

  • 7/29/2019 Modern phil Critique

    20/45

    20

    essentially always a minority in non-revolutionary ornormal times).31

    Moreover, not

    only can individuals factually overcome their outlook, civilisations can transform

    themselves entirely into radically different ones (something comparable to what

    happened in the transformation of medieval civilisation into modern Western

    civilisation).

    The latter, however, is much rarer: civilisational shifts dont occur everyday.

    What Williams is claiming is that in normal circumstances (be it on an individual level or

    on a civilisational level), fundamental precepts of a worldview are immune from criticism

    in a way in which non-fundamental precepts or precepts of another system are not.

    32

    Its

    31 Straightforward examples of this are conversions: people converting from one religion to another,

    atheists becoming religious, religious people becoming non-religious, secular, or atheists, and so on.

    32This essentially corresponds to Quines view about the types of statements which can be revised easily

    (without much disturbance to the system as a whole in which they are embedded), and the types of

    statements that cannot be so revised (without drastic changes in the system as a whole) (see Quine, 1961,

    pp. 20-46). For Quine, some beliefs are more fundamental or important than others, in the sense that

    revising or giving them up would involve many more far-reaching changes elsewhere in our belief system

    in order to maintain their coherence. But for Quine this is a continuum that is, a matter of degree and

    even at the most fundamental area of the continuum there are no beliefs that are so fundamental that they

    are immune to potential revision. One group that Quine has in his sights are the empiricists/positivists who

    thought you could start with foundations of sense data of which you were absolutely certain, and then build

    up all knowledge from those foundations (akin to the way that Descartes thought you could build up

    knowledge, although his foundation was of course different from the empiricists sense data). There is,

    however, no fundamental difference between Quines and my position here; in my opinion, one does not

    need to subscribe to foundationalism in order to preserve Williams distinction between essential and

    non-essential elements of a worldview. Quines distinction between elements which require wide -ranging

    adjustments if rejected, and elements which do not require wide-ranging changes, will suffice. Thus, when

  • 7/29/2019 Modern phil Critique

    21/45

    21

    only in times of crisis (the crisis of explanation, as Williams calls it) that fundamental

    precepts become amenable to criticism.33

    But the crisis of explanation itself can be

    divided into two types: the crisis which can be resolved by internal revisions without any

    fundamental changes, and the crisis which cannot be resolved without revising (or giving

    up) some or all of our fundamental precepts. If most of the fundamental precepts of our

    worldview become suspect, or lose their hold on us, then the crisis of explanation can be

    termed a fundamental crisis.

    There are two possible ways to overcome a fundamental crisis. The civilisation

    concerned can reinvigorate/rejuvenate itself without giving up any of the fundamental

    preceptsthis can happen, for example, by giving a new rationale or new justification to

    the old ideasor it becomes unable to hold on to the old ideas, in which case it

    Williams talks about essential elements of our worldview, I take him to mean those elements the rejection

    of which would require wide-ranging adjustments to our worldview.

    33Michel Foucault explains the same point in his distinction between the history of ideas and the history

    of thought: I would like to distinguish between the history of ideas and the history of thought. Most of

    the time a historian of ideas tries to determine when a specific concept appears, and this moment is often

    identified by the appearance of a new word. But what I am attempting to do as a historian of thought is

    something different. I am trying to analyze the way institutions, practices, habits, and behavior become a

    problem for people who behave in specific sorts of ways, who have certain types of habits, who engage in

    certain kinds of practices, and who put to work specific kinds of institutions. . . . The history of thought is

    the analysis of the way an unproblematic field of experience, or a set of practices which were accepted

    without question, which were familiar and out of discussion, becomes a problem, raises discussion and

    debate, incites new reactions, and induces a crisis in the previously silent behavior, habits, practices, and

    institutions (Foucault, 2001, p. 74). What Foucault calls here problematisation is the same thing that

    Williams calls crisis of explanation.

  • 7/29/2019 Modern phil Critique

    22/45

    22

    ultimately gives way to a new set of fundamental precepts and transforms itself into a

    new civilisation (there are, of course, many other options, like extinction or assimilation

    into another dominant civilisation, a prospect faced by many civilisations today vis--vis

    the dominant modern Western civilisation). The transformation into a new civilisation,

    however, doesnt mean that the civilisation totally abandons its erstwhile ideaswhats

    required is only that the fundamental precepts are rejected and/or their internal

    configuration is changed, and, with that in place, previous ideas can still retain their role,

    albeit with changed emphases, reinterpretations, and reconfigurations (all of these are

    empirical points).

    34

    Thus, the point is not that we cant (may not) potentially or actually

    doubt the essentials of our worldview; the point is, rather, that the probability of it is very

    low as long as a worldview is dominant.35

    The insight behind all this is that every

    civilisation creates an intellectual climate (an intellectual milieu)36

    in which certain things

    seem obvious, self-evident, and more probable; and certain other things less so.37

    In the

    medieval Christian civilisation, the belief in God and its particular Christian

    34 Thus, both Descartes and Kant make good use of the concept of God in their positive system once the act

    of demolition is over, but their conception of God and its role in the worldview they erect is fundamentally

    different from that in the Christian civilisation of the Middle Ages. Kants idea of autonomy is a rejection

    of the idea of servitude and complete submission to God (found in classical Judaism, medieval Christianity,

    and Kants own days in Pietism) (for perceptive remarks see Kuehn, 2001, pp. 53-54). Its beside the point

    to say that Descartes or Kant dont reject the idea of God altogether; what really matters is their conception

    of God, and thats no doubt essentially different from the one predominant in the Middle Ages).

    35 This is almost a tautological claim, but its significance is often not fully realised.

    36 See Taylor (2007, pp. 2-4 and 25-28) on this point.

    37 In the beautiful words of Paul Feyerabend: . . . argument works only on people who have been

    properly prepared (Feyerabend, 1987, p. 299).

  • 7/29/2019 Modern phil Critique

    23/45

    23

    interpretation was a natural thought to occur, and thinking against it was normatively

    and factually difficult and improbable, but in the age of crisis (roughly from the 16th

    to

    the 19th

    centuries) such doubts became easier, and eventually lead to the collapse of

    medieval Christian civilisation as a whole. Muslim civilisation faced the same dilemma,

    with the advent of the age of colonialism, and still is in a transitional phase. The same

    rule applies to modern Western civilisation, including its philosophical schools, but since

    its so overwhelmingly dominant today, not only culturally, but economically and

    technologically, this situation is hard to see. Thus Williams point, as I see it, is not an

    argument for relativism, but about the way human rationality works.

    38

    It might be claimed at this point that the fundamental difference between modern

    philosophy and the civilisation it defends (and is associated with) is that, whereas in

    Christian or Jewish civilisations (for example) its normatively prohibited to critique their

    fundamental precepts ([i]n religion one is explicitly not allowed to question certain

    things Priest, 2006, p. 201), in modern philosophy (and, in the case of Priest, in

    philosophy as such), criticism of everything is normatively justified even if the factual

    constraints determine the actual possibility and extent of such criticisms. The point is

    powerful, but only on the surface. If we look at the actual philosophical practice of, say,

    Descartes or Kant (and their descendants), we realise that although philosophy (and

    modern civilisation in general) claims that its normatively permissible to criticise any of

    its precepts, in actual fact the odds of this happening are the same as criticising God in a

    Christian, Islamic, or Jewish civilisation. It might be normatively permissible to raise

    38 Hence I do not controvert truth claims made by modern civilisation. I only controvert its claim about its

    critical ethos.

  • 7/29/2019 Modern phil Critique

    24/45

    24

    fundamental questions about reason, autonomy,39

    etc., but in actual practice its almost

    always a normal criticism (internal criticism), and never a fundamental critique. The

    point will only be proven if we see fundamental critiques of reason or autonomy within

    modern philosophy and worldview as a normal practice (and I submit this is not only not

    the case but conceptually speaking can notbe the case).

    A word or two must also be said about the distinction between piecemeal

    criticism and wholesale criticism. It might be objected that there is an ambiguity here that

    Ive overlooked in my explication of Williams quote, above. It might be claimed that

    Williams (or I on his behalf) has failed to acknowledge ambiguity in his (or his and my)

    position. It is one thing to say that you cannot question everything all at once, and that all

    questioning has to be done from a fixed point or outlook that we take for granted, but it is

    another thing to say that there are some things that we cannot ever question, and that

    there are some fixed points or aspects of our outlook that we must always take for

    granted. The first could be true, while the second false. Going back to the Neurath/Quine

    analogy of the boat, our critic might add that it is one thing to say that you cannot rebuild

    all the bits of the boat all at once. If you are going to, e.g., rebuild or alter the left side of

    the boat, then for those purposes you have to take the right side of the boat as a given or

    fixed point in order to get anything done. But it would be quite another thing to say that

    there are some bits of the boat that cannot ever be changed or rebuilt: the right side of the

    39

    Just think of the rage and disgust poor fundamentalism (a term never properly defined and arbitrarily

    used) elicits at all intellectual levels. The reason is because fundamentalism presents a view of religion that

    supposedly transcends the well-defined limits of the Enlightenment tolerance of religion (see Habermas,

    2006, pp. 3-25, especially pp. 10-11; cf. Rawls, 1996, pp. 64ff. and passim). The list of gag rules keeps

    piling up.

  • 7/29/2019 Modern phil Critique

    25/45

    25

    boat could be altered or changed too.40

    But the criticism misses the point here. For my

    argument, the distinction between peicemeal and wholesale criticism is irrelevant. To

    start with, the boat analogy leaves many other options out of view; e.g., it might be the

    case that the boat is so rotten that there is no option for repairing at allpiecemeal or

    otherwise. In such cases the better option might be to jump to another available boat. But,

    aside from this, the more fundamental point is whether a criticism is fundamental or not,

    not whether its piecemeal or wholesale. A similar point applies to a crisis of explanation,

    which is fundamental if it requires abandoning our fundamental precepts; its only of

    secondary concern whether such abandonment is piecemeal or a wholesale.

    41

    A

    wholesale critique can be non-fundamental, for example, when one jettisons her precepts

    en masse, but the precepts involved dont belong to the core ofher worldview; or, a

    piecemeal critique can be fundamental when it progresses in piecemeal fashion, but

    pertains to the core of our worldview. Thus, the issue here is not whether criticism is

    piecemeal or wholesalethe issue is rather whether the critique pertains to fundamentals

    of our worldview or not.

    My claim in this paper is simply that modern philosophy is no different to any

    other worldview in the dynamics of change sketched above. Modern philosophy, which

    has the reputation of throwing everything upside down, taking nothing as sacrosanct,

    apparently has its own idols in front of which it trembles lest it utter any unwarranted

    words. I am not talking about the fringes here; I am thinking of mainstream modern

    40 Thanks to . . . for pressing me to clarify these points.

    41 Generally speaking, in civilisational transformations, piecemeal changes occur over long stretches of

    time and are followed by the event of wholesale transformation, the so-called revolutionary event. In this

    reading, piecemeal changes and wholesale changes are not contradictory (rather, they are complementary).

  • 7/29/2019 Modern phil Critique

    26/45

    26

    philosophy. In modern philosophy one would search in vain for any fundamental critique

    of the notions of autonomy, democracy, secularism, and science.42

    There are powerful

    internal critiques, internal debates, and rivalries regarding different interpretations of

    these concepts, but no fundamental critiques in the sense of the fundamental elaborated

    above. The typical response is expressed with atypical honesty and frankness by Burt

    Dreben (referring to John Rawls political liberalism):

    What Rawls is saying is that there is in a constitutional liberal democracy a

    tradition of thought which it is our job to explore and see whether it can be

    made coherent and consistent. . . . We are not arguing forsuch a society. We

    take for granted that today only a fool would not want to live in such a

    society. . . . If one cannot see the benefits of living in a liberal constitutional

    democracy, if one does not see the virtue of that ideal, then I do not know

    how to convince him. To be perfectly blunt, sometimes I am asked, when I go

    around speaking for Rawls, What do you say to an Adolf Hitler? The answer

    42 I think philosophers are justified in taking science seriously. What is missing is the distance from science

    (and a certain irreverence towards it) which should be natural for a view which prides itself on its open-

    ended and critical character. Thus, for example, I would like to see more persistent problematisation of

    science as a generic word or concept (what we should take seriously are facts and not science as such;

    there is also the sort of rubbish which goes along with the factual element in discourse about science).

    The same point goes for the other concepts mentioned above. It should be added here that I presume the

    veracity of the point made in the text without any real argument; if Im wrong in this assumption, my

    argument in this paper will collapse.

  • 7/29/2019 Modern phil Critique

    27/45

    27

    is [nothing]. You shoot him. You do not try to reason with him. Reason has

    no bearing on this question. So I do not want to discuss it.

    (Dreben, 2003, pp. 328-329)43

    A typical medieval philosopher would no doubt have held the same sentiments

    about an atheist, a diehard royalist in the early modern age would have harboured similar

    views about a democrat, and so on. What makes political philosophy (for example)

    remotely special in this regard? It is only modern philosophys self-conception as

    absolute critique that makes the otherwise understandable views of Williams and Dreben

    (however atrociously expressed by the latter) so bizarre. Again, I am not advocating any

    form of relativism and its cogency here. Recall that I have not denied the universality of

    philosophy as such; I am only disputing the specific self-understanding of modern

    philosophy as absolute critique.44

    What the above discussion makes clear is that modern

    philosophys claim to be an absolute critique is only true when it is engaged in external

    (negative) criticism; normally it is not true when it engages in internal criticism,

    especially when this internal criticism involves the fundamentals of the modern

    worldview.

    43 Lest anyone think that these are isolated views of the characteristically combative Dreben, and not those

    of Rawls, one should be reminded that Rawls himself likens the views that reject constitutional democracy

    to war and disease: he talks about the practical task of containing them as they are war and disease

    (Rawls, 1996, pp. 64 n.19, also pp. 64ff.). But one does not just contain diseases, one tries to eradicate

    them!

    44 So, those philosophers who have a different conception of philosophy or modern philosophy are not my

    targets here. Although not all modern philosophers theorise about what modern philosophy is (in fact they

    rarely do), they might still have the same conception of philosophy or modern philosophy criticised here.

  • 7/29/2019 Modern phil Critique

    28/45

    28

    I have argued above (persuasively I hope) that Priests notion of philosophy as

    absolute critique is mistaken; it should rather be taken as a self-conception of modern

    philosophy only. I have argued further that modern philosophys self-conception as

    absolute critique mostly applies to its criticism of external forces, and not to the

    fundamentals of its own worldview. When it comes to this it is as meek as any other

    enterprise in modern society (and at times even more so because of the guilty

    consciousness that stems from the explicit claim of its own status as absolute criticism).

    Having accomplished the above, it is easy to summarily dispose of three corollaries that

    Priest derives from his notion of philosophy as absolute critique, viz: a) philosophy (read

    modern philosophy) is subversive; b) it is unsettling for students; c) it is universal in its

    import. I will briefly examine all these claims (and reject them as they standthe

    rejection emanates from my discussion in the paper up to this point).

    Subversiveness of philosophy. Modern philosophy indeed claims to be subversive; but it

    is subversive only when it critiques external forces (forces that are still lingering on from

    the dark ages, in its view). When it comes to its own internal matters, philosophy is not

    only notsubversive, but is in fact highly conservative in the original sense of the word

    (the contemporary supporters of the American Republican Party do not have exclusive

    copyright on the term). It is conservative in the sense that it is the custodian of the

    worldview and civilisation that replaced the medieval Christian civilisation of Europe,

    and which then imposed itself (through whatever means) on almost the entire world.45

    45 My analysis here and below is purely functional; I dont assume that philosophers or philosophy do any

    of this consciously. This should exclude any suspicion of a conspiracy theory approach.

  • 7/29/2019 Modern phil Critique

    29/45

    29

    There are, naturally, differences of interpretation and emphasis among its different foci,

    but generally speaking it is a civilisation based on a strong belief in secularism,

    constitutional democracy, human rights, capitalism,46

    and science. There are internal

    debates about these fundamentals within philosophy, but there is no dispute whatsoever

    about their desirability and the need to defend them singlehandedly. Philosophy today is

    part of a well-established, global university system;47

    most philosophy departments

    around the world follow the same sorts of topics, subjects, authors, and debates.

    Philosophers are not wandering outsiders. They write not in vernaculars as such, but in

    the official language of the empire (English) or in a few other main languages

    (predominantly French and German) which replaced Latin as the official languages of

    higher education in Europe during the 16th

    and 17th

    centuries and onwards.48

    Philosophers

    are, relatively speaking, highly paid professionals, and part of the ruling elite (defined

    broadly): responsible49

    for producing and reproducing the standard discourse about the

    self, the other, and the universe, and the relationship between them. Philosophy today has

    46 The bankruptcy of the so-called critical and innovative powers of modern thinking becomes starkly clear

    when one realises that, despite financial crises and pending environmental disaster, modern thinking

    (including philosophical thinking) has not gone beyond the dichotomy of capitalism and socialism (both

    part of Enlightenment thinkingone mainstream, the other maverick), and the most innovative one gets is

    to advocate a middle ground between the two!

    47 For the influence (economic, cultural, and social) of the university (and college) system especially the

    humanities and social sciencesin America (the most advanced capitalist country), for example, see Gross,

    2008, pp. vii-xvii.

    48 My claims here exclude the Eastern European scene, with which I have only very superficial

    acquaintance.

    49Responsibility construed in functional terms here.

  • 7/29/2019 Modern phil Critique

    30/45

    30

    almost the same role (perhaps combined with journalism and novel (fiction) writing, and

    now increasingly popular science writings) that religion played in the Middle Ages.50

    Philosophers are at the forefront of defending modern civilisation, and at the battlefront

    of science wars, religious wars, evolutionary wars, etc.51

    It is a travesty to consider

    philosophy as a subversive force in todays world; it is the prime conservative force

    today. In fact, it is the custodian of conservatism, as far as defending the basics of the

    prevailing secular capitalist worldview is concerned.52

    Philosophy as unsettling subject for students. As a reflective subject, philosophy

    questions our assumptions about ourselves, the other, and the universe (for example)

    there is no doubt about that. However, any reflective subject will do this; one can go

    50As Richard H. Popkin writes: Seventeenth-century epistemological and religious scepticism has left a

    legacy that continues to affect our twentieth-century world. (It would seem that one function of our present

    professional philosophers is to act as a new priestcraft, exorcising the sceptical demons as they turn up, day

    after day (Popkin, 1993, pp. 514-515). Note, however, that my construing of a sceptical problem is much

    broader than that of Popkin, and the quote here should be read in the context of the paper as a whole.

    51 Just notice the plethora of books in recent decades defending evolution, science, etc. authored by

    philosophers.

    52Again, I dont make any claim about the actual influence of philosophy today; my claim is primarily

    aboutphilosophys self-conception and, more fundamentally, its relation to the modern worldview.

    Philosophers generally tend to minimise their own influence (in line with their overall victimhood

    narrative), but my own impression of philosophys influence is that its much deeper, especially on the

    general humanities, social sciences and, through them, wider culture. This influence is augmented by the

    existence of public intellectuals like Jrgen Habermas, Richard Rorty, Michel Foucault, and others. Thanks

    to . . . for urging me to clarify this point.

  • 7/29/2019 Modern phil Critique

    31/45

    31

    through unsettling experiences reading history or physics, depending on the way they are

    taught and the way they are received. Where philosophy is the subject that makes

    reflection and its possibility its prime concern, it is bound to be more unsettling than any

    other subject studied within the modern university. But the unsettling experience Priest is

    referring to must be more fundamental than the sort of unsettling experiences I just

    mentioned; it is related to his notion of philosophy as absolute critiquehence, it must be

    conceived as the absolute unsettling experience. Is philosophy unsettling in the absolute

    sense? Perhaps, but principally only for students coming from backgrounds radically

    different from the secular modern worldview propagated by modern philosophy; it is not

    (typically) unsettling in the absolute sensebecause it doesnt challenge students with

    background beliefs mostly congruent with the modern worldview. Thus, a believing Jew,

    or Muslim, or Christian (to give a straightforward example) will generally feel the force

    of the absolutely unsettling nature of philosophy (if she lets herself be pulled by the lure

    of philosophy, that is), but a secular, progressive, animal loving, environment-cherishing

    liberal will be unlikely to experience any such discomfort.53 The reason is obvious from

    our discussion in this paper. Modern philosophy is absolute critique only vis--vistheviews which are external to its own preferred views; its venom and its cutting sword are

    reserved exclusively for the views which are historically challenged by her, and not the

    views which are constructively favoured by her (a different sort of critique is applied in

    that context).

    53 She would (typically) rather find confirmation of her views (and hence comfort and reassurance) in her

    experience with philosophy.

  • 7/29/2019 Modern phil Critique

    32/45

    32

    Philosophy as a universal pursuit. I believe in the universal import of philosophy, so I

    would not deny Priests claim that philosophy has this quality. But it is also clear from

    the context that what Priest is claiming is not the universal import of philosophy as such,

    but his specific conception of philosophy as absolute critique. But, as I have shown, this

    conception of philosophy is specific to a particular juncture in human history, and,

    furthermore, is true only as self-understanding of this specific philosophy, and not of its

    reality. In reality, even this specific philosophy is absolute critique only in the limited

    facets of its praxis.

    Modern philosophy emerged out of a revolutionary period in human history and

    as a revolutionary force, but it faces the dilemma that any revolutionary force must face.

    Once it is successful, every revolution must abolish any possibility of further revolution

    or counter-revolution (recall Kafka: Every revolution evaporates and leaves behind only

    the slime of a new bureaucracy. The chains of tormented mankind are made out of red

    tape. Janouch, 1971, pp. 119-20). Any revolutionary force, once successful, must

    become fundamentally a non-revolutionary and conservative force;54 its main purpose

    becomes safeguarding the house it has successfully built. Its revolutionary venom

    expresses itself mainly in safeguarding its victory against opposing forces. This is

    something very natural, and we cannot blame modern philosophy, or any other

    54 Even capitalism (or the bourgeois class, to be specific), which was hailed by Karl Marx as a

    revolutionary force par excellence, became conservative once it established its hegemony; we have only to

    look at its current dilemma, where the systems imperatives require it to move on from an oil -based

    economy, but self-entrenched interests refuse to go along with it. This is something part and parcel of

    human nature conjoined with the human condition. For a very perceptive review of the future of capitalism

    see Lanchester, 2012, pp. 7-10.

  • 7/29/2019 Modern phil Critique

    33/45

    33

    revolutionary force, on that account. What we can blame modern philosophy for, though,

    is its pretension that even after the victory it remains some sort of a revolutionary

    minority pitted against endless powerful enemies that are threatening to engulf it from

    every direction. This is just not true.

    One of the fundamental problems with Priests conception of philosophy is that he

    sees philosophy as a permanent revolutionary force (see Priest, 2006, p. 202).55

    Thus,

    although he admits that there is a difference between normal and revolutionary science, in

    factfollowing Khunhe claims that a certain dogmatism is essential to both the

    teaching of science and to its progress (ibid.). On the contrary, philosophy, claims Priest,

    is always revolutionary! Priest thinks that a certain dogmatism that is essential to

    progress in science is not only not essential for philosophys progress, but in fact would

    undermine the very meaning and existence of philosophy (Priest thinks that when science

    is in its revolutionary phases the distinction between philosophy and science becomes

    blurred: ibid., p. 202). This stancethat philosophy is a quintessentially revolutionary

    enterpriseis not new to Priest, but one would have hoped that Wittgenstein56 and

    countless other philosophers might have educated us out of this nonsense. Alas, this is a

    vain hope. There is no end to revolutionary pretensions. Martin Wolfson, writing in 1958,

    claimed the following, which succinctly captures the mindset of those who believe

    philosophy to be inherently revolutionary:

    Philosophical interpretation is inherently a fighting stance for change. This is

    55 In this he is one with Heidegger (see Heidegger, op. cit.).

    56No wonder Priest has such a low view of Wittgensteins work, or at least his conception of philosophy.

  • 7/29/2019 Modern phil Critique

    34/45

    34

    why the intellectual life in its true self can be nothing but revolutionary. It is

    tragic to the intellectual life when intellectuals forget this. Philosophy,

    therefore, is a revolutionary enterprise. If philosophy purports not to be, it is

    either apologetics or counterrevolutionary.

    (Wolfson, 1958, p. 323)

    But even old Kant, who made revolution central to his philosophical enterprise, knew

    thats not true. As he puts it:

    Criticism is not opposed to the dogmatic procedure of reason in its pure

    cognition as science (for science must always be dogmatic, i.e., it must prove

    its conclusions strictly a priori from secure principles); rather, it is opposed

    only to dogmatism, i.e., to the presumption of getting on solely with pure

    cognition from (philosophical) concepts according to principles, which reason

    has been using for a long time without first inquiring in what way and by

    what right it has obtained them. Dogmatism is therefore the dogmatic

    procedure of pure reason, without an antecedent critique of its own

    capacity.

    (Kant, 1999, Bxxxv, emphasis in the original)

    Once the initial revolutionary task is accomplished, its all back to normal. The

    argument of this paper has been that philosophy, like any other human activity, can be

    revolutionary, counterrevolutionary, and/or apologetic depending on the time and

  • 7/29/2019 Modern phil Critique

    35/45

    35

    conditions. Descartes and Kant were true revolutionaries because they were living in an

    age of revolution. But the heirs of Descartes and Kant cant claim the same, because their

    revolution has long-since succeeded, and today they are necessarily apologists of that

    system. Again, this not to deny the existence of true revolutionary philosophical

    individuals, ideas, and minority traditions, but, firstly, those traditions are by definition

    not norms, and, secondly, they dont belong to the tradition of Descartes and Kant.57

    Thus, the idea of philosophy as a permanent revolutionary activity is just a

    figment of Priests imagination, and an expression of modern philosophys propensity for

    self-aggrandisement; it does not correspond to reality. Priests ambition to become the

    Trotsky of philosophy is doomed. Like any other human activity, philosophy has its

    normal and revolutionary periods; what is normal is normal philosophy, and not a

    revolutionary philosophy.58

    Like the sciences, and like human civilisations, revolutionary

    57Its no wonder that works likeAfter Virtue (McIntyre, 2007 [1981]) belong to the Thomistic tradition and

    not to the Cartesian or Kantian traditions.

    58 It is hardly surprising, then, that those who consider philosophy to be a permanent revolutionary activity

    are compelled to continuously hark back to presumed revolutionary periods of their discipline for

    Heidegger it was going back to the Pre-Socratics, for example. It also explains the certain infatuation with

    the mythic figure of Socrates, the martyr of philosophy. But, if we take my account as the correct

    interpretation then we can accommodate such figures from the past and in the present without making

    philosophy into what it is not: that is, a timeless revolutionary force. Compare this with Karsten Harries,

    2001, pp. 47-73, who claims that the origin of philosophy lies in a sense of homelessness, and that

    [t]hose who are secure in the knowledge of their place have little need for philosophy, just as those who

    think themselves at home are not likely to suffer from homesickness (p. 61). I can agree with Harries on

    this if we add two clauses to his definition: a) that it applies in revolutionary times only; b) such philosophy

    is not restricted to any particular content. Modern philosophy and its proponents felt a sense of

  • 7/29/2019 Modern phil Critique

    36/45

    36

    periods in philosophy are exceptional and far apart. The only way philosophers can

    maintain the aura of perpetual revolutionary activity for their trade is by falsely claiming

    that, even today, they are a minority, often a persecuted minority (even though the

    persecution is not as bad as it used to be: it mainly consists of the occasional closure of

    philosophy departments, and in the belief that the philosopher kings of our age are not

    given their due or share of power, or those in power dont heed to their advice as often as

    they should). This self-perception of philosophers that they are a permanent minority

    comes out in the following quote from a prominent Kantian, Allen Wood:

    The obstacle, now as in the eighteenth century, is simply that the world is

    ruled by enemies of this enlightened ethos [i.e., the life of reason and self

    reflection, in other words life according to philosophical idealsAli], and

    hence those who in it cannot integrate what Foucault . . . calls the

    philosophical life into their real lives. This in turn is because, as Diderots

    dialogue already made dramatically clear, even the most enlightened

    individuals do not belong to a society whose practical life coheres even

    minimally with demands of reflective reason.

    (Wood, 2001, p. 116)

    homelessness in the late Middle Ages because they were in fact not at home in that world, and wanted to

    build a new world in which they would be at home. But today, when they have built the home, philosophers

    cant pretend that they are still homeless. At most they can worry about the condition of the home, and its

    viability in the face of future challenges. On the other hand, those who feel homeless in the modern world

    are true revolutionaries today even if the content of their ideas is very conservative by the lights of the

    proponents of modern philosophy, or the modern worldview in general.

  • 7/29/2019 Modern phil Critique

    37/45

    37

    One can say only two things about Woods claim here: either his conception of

    philosophy is so hopelessly idealistic that it cannot be fulfilled, by definition; or, if he is

    talking about philosophy in more historical and realistic terms, the claim that

    Enlightenment ideals are not ruling force today (at least in the developed world) seems to

    me not just not true. Of course, these ideals arent absolutely dominant, but absolute

    dominance is itself another unrealistic ideal. Of course, the claim that philosophy today

    belongs to the ruling party doesnt mean that there are no internal conflicts between

    different groups within the party, and is not to deny that philosophy is a minority within

    the ruling party. Gary Malinas explains one form that these internal conflicts take and its

    nature succinctly:

    Philosophers reflect the interests of masters to whom philosophers are

    beholden. . . . At their best, philosophers identify the fundamental

    presuppositions and assumptions of the societies and institutions to which

    they belong. They explore their consequences, test them for consistency, and

    compare them with alternatives. At their best, the only master that

    philosophers serve is reason itself, while recognising that norms of good

    reasoning carry their own presuppositions and assumptions that are not

    exempt from scrutiny. The reluctance of philosophers to shackle their

    examinations of social and institutional norms and the practices based upon

    them can put them in conflict with the aims and projects of the institutions

    that employ them. These conflicts become poignant when institutions are

  • 7/29/2019 Modern phil Critique

    38/45

    38

    committed to parochial aims that define boundaries philosophers are prone to

    ignore.

    (Malinas, 2011, p. 65)

    This, in my view, properly explains some of the internal conflicts that some philosophers

    get into from time to time, but they are precisely internal conflicts; alternatives and

    strategies which are in contention are almost as a rule internal as well. Such conflicts are

    part and parcel of any living system, and there is nothing unique about the modern system

    of governance, and philosophy as a party to that system.

    Modern philosophy is one of the ruling forces in the world today,

    59

    and when it

    denies its ruling character, its conservative function (conservative relative to the system

    as a whole, and not necessarily regarding internal alternatives within the system), it

    becomes an ideology; and it is modern philosophy qua ideology and not qua philosophy

    that must be rejected. All ideologies are dangerous; especially the ideologies with

    revolutionary pretensions. This is a lesson which we have (or should have) learnt from

    Paul Feyerabend, among others:

    All ideologies must be seen in perspective. One must not take them too

    seriously. One must read them like fairytales which have lots of interesting

    things to say but which also contain wicked lies, or like ethical prescriptions

    59Again, here Im not making any claim about the relative influence of philosophy in the modern world.

    My claim is that it is a group within the ruling party. The internal power struggle of the ruling party doesnt

    concern me here.

  • 7/29/2019 Modern phil Critique

    39/45

    39

    which may be useful rules of thumb but which are deadly when followed to

    the letter.

    (Feyerabend, 1981, p. 156)

    The notion of philosophy as absolute critique is one such fairytale today, and it is doubly

    dangerous because it is the custodian of other modern fairytales, such as science,

    constitutional democracy, etc. Again, this is not necessarily to reject philosophy, science,

    or constitutional democracy, but to reject the elements of them which have become

    ideological. There is nothing inherently good or liberating about philosophy or science.

    Feyerabends discussion ofscience in this context provides strong support for the

    view I have taken in this paper towards modern philosophy. Comparing the different

    roles that science played in the 17th

    and 18th

    centuries to the one it plays today, he writes:

    Any ideology that breaks the hold of a comprehensive system of thought has

    on the minds of men contributes to the liberation of man. Any ideology that

    makes man question inherited beliefs is an aid to enlightenment. A truth that

    reigns without checks and balances is a tyrant who must be overthrown, and

    any falsehood that can aid us in the overthrow of this tyrant is to be

    welcomed. It follows that 17th

    and 18th

    century science indeed was an

    instrument of liberation and enlightenment. It does not follow that science is

    bound to remain such an instrument. There is nothing inherent in science or

    any other ideology that makes it essentially liberating, Ideologies can

    deteriorate and become stupid religions.

  • 7/29/2019 Modern phil Critique

    40/45

    40

    (Feyerabend, 1981, pp. 156-157, emphasis in the original)60

    This exactly parallels my argument in this paper regarding modern philosophy, and

    especially the distinction between the role it played when it was a minority revolutionary

    force and the role it plays today, when it has become a dominant power (at least) in its

    own specific realm.

    I have argued that the conception of modern philosophy as absolute critique is

    only one among others; even still, it has its own limitations. I have also argued that the

    effort to universalise such a specific and narrow conception of philosophy is ideological

    in its character and inherently oppressive, especially in societies (and minority traditions

    within modern philosophy) which do not share the historical experiences of 17th

    - and

    18th

    -century Europe.61

    Without rejecting this ideologically driven notion of philosophy

    outright, philosophy in general as a liberating force has no future in the contemporary

    world.

    But I want to conclude by saying that such an ideologically driven notion of

    philosophy is not the whole philosophy; fortunately, it is only a small part of it as it is

    practiced throughout the world, including America and other first-world countries.62

    And

    60For an uncanny resemblance between Feyerabends argument here and Karl Poppers notion of scientific

    method as critique see Popper, 1969, pp. 190-192; the difference, however, is that Popper is still enthralled

    by the myth of absolute critique while Feyerabend is not: he merely uses it pragmatically.

    61 This last claim follows from my discussion of the different roles of internal and external criticism within

    modern philosophy.

    62One of the reasons for this might be that most philosophers do philosophy rather than philosophising

    about what it is; so, it might still be the case that they implicitly share the view of philosophy propounded

  • 7/29/2019 Modern phil Critique

    41/45

    41

    this is because philosophy as reflection on reflection, as thinking about thinking, is

    something universal and part of the human condition. Reflection and self-reflection,

    whether attributed to evolution or considered as God-granted gifts, are regarded by most

    cultures as the essence of humanity, differentiating humans from other beings, and

    philosophyas the study of this unique capacity and the impulse to develop instruments

    to enhance this capacityis an important human endeavour which is needed in every

    society and culture, in order for those communities to survive and develop a human

    civilisation imbued with the virtues of honour, courage, self-respect, and independence of

    mind.

    Despite the role of philosophy as a dominant ideology in todays world, the bulk

    of the philosophical enterprise is not ideological but constructive. This type of philosophy

    is necessary to develop the thinking and reflective capacities of individual, society, and

    culture. Every society and every culture needs these tools in order to deepen its

    understanding of itself and the other: reflectively, independently, and critically. In this

    paper, I have used Priests views as a foil to develop my argument, but, to be fair to him,

    most of his work in philosophy is not ideological at all. It is only when he attempts to

    develop his self-understanding of philosophy qua philosophy that part of it comes across

    as highly ideological. Priests work, especially in logic, is in fact revolutionary; and any

    culture would be impoverished if it were to be deprived of such a contribution. What we

    need is Priests great efforts in logic, not his ideological views about what philosophy is.

    by Priest, but are not bothered about it much. It might also be possible that Priests view is not a majority

    view. In a recent excellent collection of essays (perhaps with the exception of Nussbaum and Apels

    essays) at least Wood seems to share Priests view of philosophy (see Ragland and Heidt, 2001).

  • 7/29/2019 Modern phil Critique

    42/45

    42

    Similarly, just to give one more example, the counter-example method used by modern

    analytic philosophers should be learnt, and should be part and parcel of the modern

    university education system because it is a great tool in enhancing the power of the

    imagination,63

    which in turn is crucial for developing the capacity to see alternative

    scenarios when considering an issue, and consequently for assessing any issues regarding

    any subject matter critically and thoughtfully, and arriving at a considered judgement

    about it.

    We can add on particular examples here, but that is something to be left for

    another occasion. What I have tried to do in this paper is to make a case against a

    particular conception of philosophy, and to show that it is not the only conception of

    philosophy: this, I believe, is the first step towards reasserting the liberating role of

    philosophy in the contemporary world.

    References

    Bohman, James and Richardson, Henry S. (2009). Liberalism, Deliberative Democracy,

    and Reasons that All Can Accept. The Journal of Political Philosophy, 17: 3, 253-274.

    Clarke, Desmond M. (2006).Descartes: A Biography. Cambridge: Cambridge University

    Press.

    Cohen, Joseph W. (1995). The Role of Philosophy in Culture.Philosophy East and West,

    5: 2, 99-112.

    Copleston, Frederick S. J. (1994) [1963].A History of Philosophy. Vol. IVModern

    Philosophy: From Descartes to Leibniz. London: Image Books.

    Cottingham, John (Ed.) (1998a).Descartes. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Cottingham, John (1998b). Introduction. In J. Cottingham (Ed.)Descartes (pp. 1-27).

    Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    63 See Williamsons, 2010, for the importance of imagination for critical thinking.

  • 7/29/2019 Modern phil Critique

    43/45

    43

    Cottingham, John (2008). The Good Life and the Radical Contingency of the Ethical.

    In D. Callcut (Ed.)Reading Bernard Williams (pp. 25-43). London: Routledge.

    Cottingham, John (2009). What Is Humane Philosophy and Why Is It At Risk?

    Philosophy, Supplement 65, 1-23.

    Descartes, Rene (1985). The Philosophical Works of Descartes. Vol. 1. Translated by

    John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff, and Dugald Murdoch. Cambridge: Cambridge

    University Press.

    Dreben, Burton (2003). On Rawls and Political Liberalism. In Samuel Freeman (Ed.) The

    Cambridge Companion to Rawls (pp. 316-346). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Feyerabend, Paul (1981). How to Defend Society against Science. In Ian Hacking (Ed.)

    Scientific Revolutions (pp. 156-167). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Feyerabend, Paul (1987).Farewell to Reason. London: Verso.

    Foucault, Michel (1992) [1984]. The Use of Pleasure. The History of Sexuality Vol. 2.

    Harmondsworth, Middlesex: Penguin.

    Foucault, Michel (2001).Fearless Speech. Edited by Joseph Pearson. Los Angeles:

    Semiotext(e).

    Gadamer, Hans-Georg (2004) [1975]. Truth and Method. London: Continuum.

    Gross, Niel (2008).Richard Rorty: The Making of an American Philosopher. Chicago:University of Chicago Press.

    Habermas, Jrgen (2002) [1976]. What is Universal Pragmatics. In Maeve Cooke (Ed.)On the Pragmatics of Communication (pp. 21-103). Oxford: Polity Press.

    Habermas, Jrgen (2006). The Divided W