middle-range theory as hermeneutics

Upload: billwadal-bhattacharjee

Post on 07-Jul-2018

228 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/18/2019 Middle-Range Theory as Hermeneutics

    1/8

     Society for American Archaeology is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to American Antiquity.

    http://www.jstor.org

    Society for merican rchaeology

    Method in Archaeology: Middle-Range Theory as HermeneuticsAuthor(s): Peter KossoSource: American Antiquity, Vol. 56, No. 4 (Oct., 1991), pp. 621-627Published by: Society for American ArchaeologyStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/281540

    Accessed: 28-07-2015 20:20 UTC

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/  info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of contentin a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship.For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    This content downloaded from 14.139.109.99 on Tue, 28 Jul 2015 20:20:30 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=samhttp://www.jstor.org/stable/281540http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/281540http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=samhttp://www.jstor.org/

  • 8/18/2019 Middle-Range Theory as Hermeneutics

    2/8

    METHOD

    IN ARCHAEOLOGY:

    MIDDLE-RANGE

    THEORY

    AS

    HERMENEUTICS

    Peter Kosso

    Disagreements

    bout

    methodology

    n

    archaeology

    re

    often

    ocated n terms

    of

    the

    middle-range-theory

    pproach

    of

    Lewis

    Binford

    and the

    hermeneutic,

    ontextual

    archaeology

    f

    Ian Hodder.These

    positions

    are

    usually

    presented

    in

    opposition

    o

    each

    other,

    but here

    they

    are

    shown to

    present

    very

    much the same

    methodological icture

    of

    archaeology.

    This

    specificanalysis

    s more

    generally nformative

    f

    the

    methodological

    elationbetween he

    natural

    and social

    sciences.

    Desacuerdos

    cerca

    de

    metodologia

    en

    arqueologia

    on

    frecuentemente

    lanteados

    en

    terminos

    del

    enfoque

    de

    teoriade

    rango

    medio

    de

    Lewis

    Binford

    la

    perspectiva

    ermeneutica

    contextualde Ian Hodder.

    Estas

    posiciones

    son

    presentadas

    normalmenteen

    oposici6n,pero

    en el

    presente

    articulose

    demuestra

    que

    ambas

    ofrecen

    una

    imagen metodol6gicasimilar de la arqueologia.Este analisis resulta mds informativoen terminosgenerales

    acercade la

    relaci6n

    metodolo6gica

    ntre las

    ciencias

    naturales

    y

    las ciencias

    sociales.

    On a

    map

    of the

    sciences,

    archaeology

    would be a

    border state

    between the natural and

    social

    sciences. It is

    like a

    social

    science

    in

    that

    the

    objects

    of

    interest are

    people,

    human

    culture,

    and

    artifacts

    created

    under the

    influence of ideas

    and

    social norms.

    Evidence

    in

    archaeology

    is

    often

    symbolic,

    meaningful,

    and

    intentional,

    and the

    archaeologist

    must

    be sensitive

    to

    this

    unnatural

    content.

    But

    archaeology

    is also

    like

    a

    natural science

    in

    that its

    focus

    is

    on

    the material remains

    of

    people

    in

    the

    past

    and on their

    relation with

    he

    natural

    environment.

    Not o

    he

    atural

    environment.

    Not

    only

    are the artifacts

    often

    the

    products

    of

    coping

    with

    nature,

    they

    are

    always

    altered

    by

    natural

    processes

    of

    aging,

    material

    degradation,

    erosion,

    and

    the

    like,

    thus

    making

    aspects

    of

    natural

    sciences

    appropriate

    resources for

    getting

    information

    about the

    past. Even under a mandate of paying attention to ideas

    and

    symbols,

    the

    text

    from which

    this

    information is

    read is

    the

    material

    record. Linda Patrik

    (1985:

    34)

    notes

    thisthis

    ual

    nature of

    archaeology

    by

    describing

    two

    ways

    of

    dealing

    with the

    archaeological

    record:

    Because

    archaeological

    evidence is

    presumably

    the

    product

    of

    both

    natural

    processes

    and

    behavioral

    processes,

    rather

    than the

    product

    of

    either

    one of

    these

    alone,

    there

    is

    disagreement

    amongst

    archaeologists

    over what

    kind of

    record

    archaeological

    evidence

    forms.

    Located at

    this

    interface,

    archaeology

    is

    especially prone

    to

    disagreements

    over

    method. There is

    a rich

    variety

    of

    positions

    among

    archaeologists

    regarding

    the

    appropriate

    methods

    for their

    dis-

    cipline,

    and the

    positions

    are

    often

    presented

    in

    terms

    of

    just

    how

    like a

    natural

    science or a

    social

    science

    archaeology ought

    to

    be.

    In

    wht

    follows

    here,

    two

    of

    these

    positions,

    chosen

    for

    their

    high

    profile

    in

    the

    profession

    and

    because

    they

    are

    reference

    points

    for

    the two

    ends of

    the

    spectrum,

    will

    be

    compared.

    The

    point

    I

    want to

    make is

    simple.

    Though

    these

    two

    methodological

    ap-

    proaches-the middle-range-theory concept of Lewis Binford and the model of contextual archae-

    ology

    advocated

    by

    Ian

    Hodder-are

    originally presented

    in

    strong opposition,

    they

    are

    really

    very

    similar.

    Binford's model

    of

    good

    archaeological

    method

    (outlined

    in

    Binford

    [1977, 1982a,

    and

    elsewhere])

    has it

    that

    archaeology

    should

    be much

    like

    natural

    science. It

    deals

    in

    theories and

    evidence

    and

    carries

    out a

    regimen

    of

    testing by

    exploiting

    the

    causal

    connections

    between

    things

    in

    the

    past

    and

    their

    remains

    found

    in

    the

    present.

    Objectivity

    is

    the

    methodological

    goal. Hodder,

    in

    explicit

    Peter

    Kosso,

    Department

    of

    Philosophy,

    Northern

    Arizona

    University,

    lagstaff,

    AZ

    86011

    American

    Antiquity, 56(4),

    1991,

    pp.

    621-627.

    Copyright

    ? 1991

    by

    the

    Society

    for

    American

    Archaeology

    621

    This content downloaded from 14.139.109.99 on Tue, 28 Jul 2015 20:20:30 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/18/2019 Middle-Range Theory as Hermeneutics

    3/8

    AMERICAN

    ANTIQUITY

    opposition

    to

    this,

    claims

    that natural

    science

    is

    an

    inappropriate

    model for

    archaeology

    in that it

    is

    incorrigibly

    insensitive to ideas. Artifacts can be understood

    only

    when viewed

    in

    the context

    of

    the ideas and norms

    during

    their manufacture and use. This

    suggests

    a

    method

    of

    study

    that is less

    like

    natural science and more like

    reading

    and

    interpreting

    a

    text,

    where the connection

    between

    evidence

    and

    object

    of interest is one

    of

    signification

    rather than of causation.

    A

    look at the substance behind the

    slogans

    of these two

    positions

    will

    reveal that there

    is little

    methodological

    difference.

    In

    showing

    this,

    the

    focus

    will

    always

    be

    on

    methodology

    and not

    on

    issues of the

    proper

    aims of

    archaeology

    nor on the differences between the

    objects

    studied

    by

    social

    and

    natural

    sciences. Even

    if

    the kinds of

    objects

    are

    significantly

    different,

    this does

    not entail

    the

    need for

    significantly

    different

    methods.

    And

    granting

    the two dissimilar

    models

    of the

    archaeological

    record

    as

    described

    by

    Patrik

    (1985),

    it

    does

    not follow that these demand

    two dissimilar

    methods

    for

    exploiting

    the information

    in

    the

    record and for

    using

    it

    to

    support knowledge

    of

    the

    past.

    The

    plan

    of

    presentation

    is

    to first

    briefly

    describe Binford's

    application

    of

    middle-range

    theories

    to

    archaeology

    and Hodder's

    approach

    of

    reading

    the

    past.

    Once out of their

    packages,

    these

    models

    of

    archaeology

    will be seen as

    presenting essentially

    the

    same

    methodological

    picture.

    The

    hope

    is

    that this focused analysis of archaeological method will be more generally informative of the meth-

    odological

    relation between the

    natural and social

    sciences.

    MIDDLE-RANGE

    THEORIES

    This

    will

    be

    a

    very

    brief account

    of

    middle-range

    theory,

    an account

    that

    ignores

    much

    variety

    of

    detail

    in

    the

    concept

    but

    that is

    sufficient for

    my

    subsequent argument.

    The

    concept

    of middle-

    range theory,

    as it

    is

    applied

    to

    archaeology by

    Binford

    (1977, 1982a)

    and

    by

    Schiffer

    (1988)

    is

    useful

    in

    any

    science.

    In

    understanding just

    what

    the idea is

    and how

    it

    works,

    it

    will be more

    important

    to

    analyze

    the notion

    of middle

    range

    than that

    of

    theory.

    Start

    by

    asking

    what

    is

    middling

    about

    a

    middle-range

    theory.

    There

    are

    differences between

    Schiffer

    and

    Binford

    on the details

    of

    middle-range

    theories,

    and

    in

    my

    characterization

    I

    will

    try

    to honor

    the task

    set

    by

    Binford for

    middle-range

    theories,

    with

    a

    sensitivity

    to the

    epistemic predicament

    of

    archaeology.

    I will

    point

    out the crucial

    characteristics

    for a

    middle-range theory

    to

    function

    as

    Binford

    intends.

    In Binford's

    (1977:6)

    use of

    the

    concept, middle-range

    theories

    are

    descriptive

    claims

    that

    fall

    between

    observational

    descriptions

    of what

    the

    archaeologists

    find

    in the

    present,

    that

    is,

    site

    and

    field

    reports,

    and the

    descriptive

    reconstructions

    of the

    past.

    The material

    remains

    that are

    found

    in

    the

    present

    function

    as

    evidence

    for

    the claims

    made

    about

    the

    past,

    w ther those

    claims

    are

    specific,

    as about

    the

    shape

    of a

    particular

    pot,

    or

    more

    general,

    as about

    the

    emergence

    of

    civilization.

    Middle-range

    theories

    are

    used

    to make

    the

    informational

    link between

    present

    and

    past,

    and

    to

    say

    of what

    the

    material

    remains

    are

    evidence.

    They

    do

    this

    by

    describing

    the formation

    of

    the

    archaeological

    record as

    it

    is

    today.

    This

    description

    will include

    general

    theories

    about

    how

    artifacts

    are used and

    subsequently

    deposited by

    burial,

    neglect,

    or

    intentional

    discard,

    and

    general

    theories

    about the alteration of deposited artifacts by both natural and cultural activities. It will also include

    specific

    claims

    about

    the

    area,

    its

    propensity

    for

    erosion,

    for

    example,

    and the

    local

    people.

    All

    of

    these

    claims

    are

    middle-range

    theories

    in

    that

    they

    contribute

    to

    the

    description

    of

    the causal

    lineage

    of

    the

    debris

    that

    is observed

    today. Being

    of

    general

    or universal

    scope

    is

    not

    a

    necessary

    feature

    of

    a

    theory

    as

    it is used

    in the

    middle-range strategy

    to cross

    the

    epistemic

    gap

    between

    available

    data

    in

    the

    present

    and

    interesting

    phenomena

    he

    resent

    and

    interesting phenomena

    in he

    past.

    The distinction

    of

    middle-range

    theories

    is

    in

    giving

    meaning

    to our

    contemporary

    observations

    made

    on the

    archaeological

    record

    (Binford

    1982b:161),

    and to

    do

    this

    by describing

    the

    formation

    process

    of

    the

    archaeological

    record

    (Binford

    1977:7).

    The

    debris

    is

    an

    archaeological

    record

    of

    something

    of

    interest

    in the

    past,

    but

    we

    can

    know what

    it is

    a

    record of

    only

    with

    a theoretical

    reconstruction

    of how

    it was

    formed,

    and

    this account

    of

    the

    formation

    of the

    archaeological

    record

    is

    the burden

    of

    middle-range

    theory,

    a

    burden

    that

    will be carried

    by

    a combination

    of

    general

    and

    particular

    claims.

    Any

    theory

    could be used in the role of being middle range. Being middle range is not a feature

    of the

    content

    of a

    theory

    but

    of its

    use

    in

    a

    particular

    instance.

    The relevant

    middle

    in this

    sense

    is not

    meant to

    be

    of

    mid-generality

    or

    of

    mid-empirical

    content.

    This

    disregard

    for

    generality

    or

    622

    [Vol.

    56,

    No.

    4,

    1991

    This content downloaded from 14.139.109.99 on Tue, 28 Jul 2015 20:20:30 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/18/2019 Middle-Range Theory as Hermeneutics

    4/8

    MIDDLE-RANGETHEORY

    AS

    HERMENEUTICS

    empirical

    content

    differs

    from

    chiffere's account of

    middle-range

    theories,

    according

    to

    which,

    any

    theory

    can function

    as

    method,

    depending

    on context

    (Schiffer

    1988:436),

    but

    genuinely

    middle-

    range

    theories

    are

    those

    of

    mid-comprehensiveness

    and

    mid-range empirical

    content

    (Schiffer

    1988:

    465).

    Thus,

    for

    Schiffer,

    middle-range

    theories are

    distinctive as to their

    content.

    This

    is often

    true

    in other studies of science

    (see,

    for

    example,

    Schaffer

    [1980]

    about

    biological

    middle-range

    theories

    as

    theories

    of

    mid-generality),

    where the

    terminology

    of middle

    range

    is used

    to indicate one

    of

    these

    features

    of

    content,

    but what is

    key

    to realize Binford's

    intent is the role

    a

    theory

    plays

    in

    processes

    of

    interpreting

    evidence

    and

    testing

    claims

    about the

    past.

    There are no

    special

    theories

    that are

    of

    use

    only

    for

    testing

    other

    claims,

    nor

    should

    any

    be antecedent

    ly

    excluded from

    use

    in

    testing.

    A

    theory

    will

    in one

    context ble

    theory,

    but in

    another

    will

    be

    regarded

    as itself

    the

    interesting,

    finished

    product,

    answerable

    to tests

    against

    the evidence.

    In

    other

    words,

    the

    observations in

    archaeology,

    as

    in

    any

    other

    interesting

    business

    of

    empirical

    knowledge,

    are

    theory laden,

    and

    middle-range

    theories

    are

    a

    large part

    of

    the

    load.

    Insofar

    as

    observations in

    the

    present

    are

    to be relevant

    as evidence

    for theories about

    the

    past,

    we

    must

    identify

    information

    of

    the

    past

    in

    the

    present

    remains.

    The

    tracking

    of

    the

    flow

    of

    information

    from interesting past to observable present is done by the middle-range theories.

    Here

    is an

    example

    of

    middle-range

    theories

    in

    action,

    taken from

    archaeological

    studies of

    ancient

    Greece.

    One

    thing

    ththat

    archaeologists

    and historians

    want to

    know about

    ancient

    Greece

    is

    the

    structure and

    genesis

    of

    socioeconomic

    systems.

    Part of

    the

    evidence

    for claims

    about

    such

    things

    will

    come

    through

    an

    understanding

    of

    cultivated farmland in

    ancient

    times,

    a

    picture

    of

    the

    sizes,

    locations,

    and

    changes

    of

    fields under

    cultivation.

    But we do

    not see the

    cultivation.

    What the

    archaeologist

    finds

    are remains

    of terrace

    walls,

    sparse

    scatterings

    of

    potsherds,

    and

    other

    indirect

    traces of

    past

    agricultural

    activity.

    The

    light

    scatter

    of sherds can

    be taken

    as

    evidence of

    cultivation

    in

    light

    of

    middle-range

    theories

    that

    describe a

    pattern

    of

    rural Greeks

    discarding

    old

    pots

    near

    their

    houses where

    the broken

    bits

    get

    inadvertently

    mixed

    into

    the manure of

    farm

    animals

    kept

    at the

    place

    of residence.

    The manure

    is

    spread

    as fertilizer

    on cultivated

    fields and

    the mix

    of

    sherds

    is

    scattered,

    leaving

    a

    lasting

    trace of

    the activities

    of

    cultivation.

    Areas once

    under

    cultivation

    may

    now be scattered with sherds, while areas not cultivated will not be, and insofar as the sherds can

    be

    dated,

    the cultivation

    activity

    can be

    dated. In

    this

    way

    the sherd

    scatter

    is a

    kind of

    image

    of

    the

    agricultural

    activities.

    It

    is

    certainly

    not an

    obvious

    likeness of

    cultivation,

    and

    the

    image

    has

    been

    distorted

    through repeated

    use of the

    land,

    erosion,

    and

    other

    natural

    and

    cultural

    forces,

    but

    such

    distortions

    can be taken

    into account in

    the

    descriptive

    reconstruction

    of

    the

    past.

    This

    is

    by

    no means

    a certain

    or

    universally

    accepted

    inference

    from

    contemporary

    data

    (sherd

    scatter)

    to

    past

    activities

    (manuring

    and

    cultivation),

    but it

    does

    have

    significant

    support

    (e.g.,

    Bintliff

    and

    Snodgrass

    1988:507-508)

    and

    credible

    evidence in its

    own

    right (Wilkinson

    1982).

    There

    is

    reason

    to doubt

    that

    manuring

    was a

    universal

    practice,

    characteristic

    to all

    agricultural

    settings

    in

    the

    ancient

    Mediterranean

    (Cherry

    et

    al. 1991

    :Chapter

    3),

    but

    this

    indicates

    not

    that it

    is

    inappropriate

    as

    a

    middle-range theory

    but

    that

    extra work

    is

    called

    for to know

    the

    circumstances,

    such

    as

    availability

    of

    water,

    in

    which

    the

    theory

    of

    manuring is likely to apply. Where manuring has been

    done,

    the

    link

    between

    off-site

    sherds

    and

    cultivation

    can be

    exploited

    as

    a

    middle-range

    theory.

    Middle-range

    theories

    of

    this

    kind are

    commonplace

    in

    the

    natural

    sciences.

    They

    are the

    imaging

    theories

    that

    describe

    the

    informational

    connection

    between

    what is

    seen

    and

    its

    causal

    antecedent

    of which

    it

    is

    evidence.

    Again,

    these are

    not a

    special

    kind of

    theory.

    It is

    simply

    a

    special

    kind

    of

    use for

    ordinary

    theories.

    Consider,

    for

    example,

    the theoretical

    account of

    how

    an

    optical

    microscope

    works.

    General

    theories

    from

    optics,

    describing

    the

    diffraction

    and

    interference of

    light,

    the

    behavior

    of

    lenses and

    so

    on,

    are

    invoked

    to

    describe

    how

    the

    image

    is

    formed

    and

    to

    keep

    track

    of

    any

    instrumental

    distortions.

    This is

    the

    source of

    confidence

    that

    features

    of

    the

    image

    are

    reliably

    informative

    of

    features

    of

    the

    specimen,

    and

    these

    are

    middle-range

    theories,

    used

    as

    they

    are

    to

    describe

    the

    formation

    of the

    image

    and

    thereby

    make

    it

    evidence

    of

    something

    interesting.

    Another

    example

    comes

    out in

    Shapere's

    (1982)

    account

    of

    observing

    the

    interior

    of

    the

    sun.

    Neutrinos

    observed on the earth, or more strictly, the detector-clicks caused by beta emissions from radioactive

    argon

    produced

    by

    neutrino

    interactions,

    are

    evidence

    for

    theories

    about

    solar

    processes.

    But

    the

    neutrinos

    (or

    the

    clicks)

    are

    informative

    of the

    solar

    interior

    only

    by

    way

    of

    a

    theoretical

    account

    Kosso]

    623

    This content downloaded from 14.139.109.99 on Tue, 28 Jul 2015 20:20:30 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/18/2019 Middle-Range Theory as Hermeneutics

    5/8

    AMERICAN

    ANTIQUITY

    of

    the

    causal chain from the sun

    to the

    clicks,

    that

    is,

    by way

    of theoretical neutrino

    physics,

    radiochemistry,

    and

    more,

    middle-range

    theories all.

    Thus,

    Binford's

    application

    of

    middle-range

    theories to

    archaeology puts

    it

    in

    close

    company

    with standard

    practice

    in natural

    science.

    CONTEXTUAL

    ARCHAEOLOGY

    Hodder

    (1986:12, 29)

    argues

    that this

    methodological

    association with natural science

    puts

    ar-

    chaeology

    in

    with the

    wrong company. Middle-range

    theories

    and

    their natural-science methods are

    inappropriate

    to the

    study

    of human culture

    because,

    he

    claims,

    as theories

    they

    make cross-cultural

    generalizations. They

    are

    insensitive,

    that

    is,

    to

    peoples'

    ideas, intentions,

    and

    meanings,

    and

    thereby

    they

    miss an

    important

    aspect

    of the

    past,

    an

    aspect

    which is

    essential for

    understanding any

    part

    of

    past

    human

    culture. Since ideas and

    norms are

    often culture

    specific

    and

    even

    individual

    specific,

    they

    will

    be

    missed

    by

    a

    method that bases its evidence on

    cross-cultural

    middle-range

    theories.

    If

    there are

    any

    general

    theories

    they

    must be the result of information from the

    evidence,

    that

    is,

    they

    must be

    proven,

    but

    they

    cannot be assumed and invoked to

    support

    the

    informational content

    in

    the

    evidence.

    Methodological

    sensitivity

    to ideas and intentions is

    crucial,

    Hodder

    (1985:12,

    1986:3-4) argues,

    because all material culture

    is

    mediated

    by

    the beliefs of

    the makers

    and

    users

    (as

    well

    as the

    finders)

    and the

    meanings

    intended.

    All

    artifacts reflect either

    conscious or unconscious

    ideas and

    norms.

    Everything,

    not

    just

    artistic,

    linguistic,

    and ceremonial

    behavior,

    is

    symbolic.

    The

    patterns

    of

    use

    and the

    spatial

    arrangement

    of

    everyday

    stuff reflect

    the

    attitudes

    and tacit norms

    of

    thought

    of

    the

    individuals and

    their culture. These basic

    material

    objects

    and their

    organization

    are

    indicative

    of

    ideas

    on,

    for

    example,

    the

    importance

    of

    particular

    things,

    the ro

    herthey

    play,

    relations

    between

    people

    and to the environment.

    The

    influence

    of

    ideology

    is

    in

    everything

    an

    archaeologist

    studies.

    In

    other

    words,

    the

    system,

    that

    is,

    the material

    things

    and

    their

    physical organization,

    is a

    mani-

    festation

    of

    the

    structure,

    the

    nonphysical

    factors

    such as social norms

    and

    individuals'

    ideas

    and

    intentions.

    Thus,

    an

    understanding

    of structure

    is achieved

    through

    an

    understanding

    of

    system.

    But a system cannot be properly understood without knowing something about the structure. Insofar

    as the material

    objects

    are

    symbolic they

    are

    signifiers

    of

    ideas,

    but there

    is

    no

    link

    between

    signifier

    and

    signified

    without

    an

    understanding

    of

    the

    ideological

    context

    and

    the intentions

    behind

    the

    meaningful

    activities.

    We need

    some

    appreciation

    of

    the actors'

    ideas,

    for

    example,

    to

    group

    com-

    ponents

    of

    the

    system

    into kinds

    in

    a

    way

    that

    is

    relevant

    to their

    worldview.

    Given

    this

    relation

    between

    system

    and

    structure,

    the

    individuals

    and

    cultures of

    the

    past

    can

    only

    be

    understood,

    as

    Hodder

    says

    in

    agreement

    with

    Collingwood's

    approach

    to

    history,

    from

    inside

    (Hodder

    1986:30).

    The

    archaeologist

    cannot

    get

    anywhere

    without some

    preliminary

    knowl-

    edge

    of

    structure,

    what

    is

    going

    on inside

    the

    peoples'

    minds

    and

    inside

    society.

    There

    is

    then

    a

    circularity

    in the

    process

    of

    knowing

    the

    past

    in

    that

    system

    is the

    source

    for

    understanding

    structure,

    and structure

    is

    the

    background

    for

    understanding

    the

    system.

    It is

    a hermeneutic

    circle,

    hence

    the

    method

    of

    reading

    the

    past.

    As Hodder

    sees

    it,

    the method

    is unlike

    the sort

    of linear

    inference

    back

    along

    a causal chain as is the approach when middle-range theories are invoked. All aspects

    of

    archaeological

    knowledge

    will

    require

    some

    initial

    knowledge

    of

    intentions

    and

    the

    meanings

    of

    things

    as

    a

    way

    to break

    into the

    hermeneutic

    circle.

    In

    fact,

    It

    is

    only

    when

    we make

    assumptions

    about

    the

    subjective

    meanings

    in

    the

    minds

    of

    people long

    dead

    that

    we can

    begin

    to do

    archaeology

    (Hodder

    1986:79).

    It

    is

    important

    to realize

    that these

    are

    not

    wild, irresponsible,

    or

    irreversible

    speculations. They

    are

    accountable

    to a kind of

    testing

    in that the

    assumptions

    of

    meaning

    must

    lead to

    sensible,

    consistent

    system

    and

    structure.

    Individual

    assumptions

    are

    evaluated

    by

    inter-

    preting

    general

    understanding

    or

    foreknowledge

    in

    relation

    to our

    understanding

    of

    particular

    con-

    texts

    (Hodder

    1991:8),

    and

    are

    inadmissible

    unless

    they

    show

    coherence

    with other

    ideas

    attributed

    to

    the

    people long

    dead,

    and

    unless

    they

    provide

    correspondence

    to

    the

    evidence

    (Hodder

    1986:

    95),

    that

    is,

    allow an

    easy,

    rational

    link

    between

    intentions

    and

    material

    behavior.

    Hodder's account of archaeological

    method

    seems

    to

    have shifted

    the

    burden

    of

    proof.

    Cross-

    cultural

    generalizations,

    as

    would be

    found

    among

    middle-range

    theories,

    have

    to

    be

    proven,

    not

    assumed

    (Hodder

    1986:80), though

    he admits

    that there

    are some

    simple

    rules

    underlying

    all

    624

    [Vol.

    56,

    No.

    4,

    1991

    This content downloaded from 14.139.109.99 on Tue, 28 Jul 2015 20:20:30 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/18/2019 Middle-Range Theory as Hermeneutics

    6/8

    MIDDLE-RANGE

    THEORY AS HERMENEUTICS

    languages (Hodder 1986:123)

    that can be

    used to understand

    the

    past.

    Cross-cultural

    generalities

    cannot

    be assumed but

    subjective

    meanings

    can.

    This

    apparently

    differential treatment is a

    feature of the

    advertising

    of

    the

    methodological position

    that does

    not

    accurately

    reflect the

    product.

    The distinction between

    assumption

    and

    proof

    works

    only

    to

    confuse both

    Binford's and Hodder's

    models of

    archaeological knowledge

    since

    in

    both

    models,

    what

    may

    be

    initially

    assumed is

    accountable to

    subsequent

    proof.

    Whether it is of a

    cross-

    cultural

    generalization

    or of a

    subjective meaning,

    an

    assumption

    is

    tentative and

    revisable. It is

    a

    hypothesis

    in

    need of

    justification.

    In

    the

    methodological

    scheme of

    things, middle-range

    theories

    function

    as do claims

    about

    ideas,

    hypothetical

    in

    activities of

    discovery,

    and

    in

    need of

    proof

    in

    activities of

    justification.

    A

    look

    at how these

    things

    are

    justified

    will

    reveal

    greater similarity

    between

    middle-range

    theories

    and claims

    ndclaims about

    structure,

    and between the two

    archaeological

    methods in

    which

    they

    function.

    The

    suggestion

    at this

    point

    is that

    instead of

    opposing

    Binford's and

    Hodder's

    methodological

    models

    by saying

    that

    contextual

    structuring

    ring

    ciples

    intervene

    (Hodder

    1986:116), meaning

    that the

    structuring

    principles replace

    middle-range

    theories,

    it is more

    accurate to

    regard

    the

    structural principles as part of the theories. Recall that the operative notion of a middle-range theory

    places

    no

    restrictions

    on the

    content or

    degree

    of

    generality

    of

    the

    claim,

    only

    on

    its use for

    making

    sense

    of

    (finding

    information

    in)

    the

    evidence.

    MIDDLE-RANGE

    THEORY AS

    CONTEXTUAL

    METHOD

    The

    distinctive

    feature

    of

    Hodder's

    contextual

    method is

    its

    affinity

    to

    hermeneutics

    in

    the

    relation

    of

    mutual

    support

    between

    evidential

    claims about

    system

    and

    claims about

    structure.

    A

    description

    of

    the

    confirmation of

    middle-range

    theories

    will

    show

    that

    Binford's

    methodological

    account shares

    this

    affinity.

    Middle-range theories, recall,

    are

    just

    ordinary

    theories.

    They

    are

    tested and

    justified

    like

    any

    other

    theory,

    including

    the

    ones

    whose

    observational

    evidence

    they

    laden.

    Middle-range

    theories

    are tested and justified by comparison to evidence, that is, to observations. There is then a kind of

    circularity.

    Theories

    in

    general

    (including

    theories

    used as

    middle-range theories)

    are

    confirmed and

    understood

    through

    an

    appeal

    to

    observations,

    and

    observations

    in

    general

    are understood and

    verified with

    the

    support

    of

    theories.

    This

    second

    half of the

    cycle,

    the

    theory

    ladenness of

    obser-

    vation,

    represents

    a

    blurring

    of

    the

    distinction

    between

    fact and

    theory, exactly

    as Hodder

    advocates.

    Observations

    are

    theoretically

    influenced

    claims about

    local

    and

    specific situations,

    closely

    linked

    to

    perception.

    They

    are

    similar

    to

    claims

    about

    the

    meanings

    of

    specific

    passages

    in

    an

    unfamiliar

    text,

    claims

    motivated from

    specific

    marks on

    the

    page.

    Theories are

    observationally

    influenced

    claims

    about

    more

    global

    processes

    that

    are not

    directly

    linked to

    particular perceptions.

    They

    are

    the

    developing

    account of the

    plot

    of

    the

    story.

    Just

    as

    individual

    passages

    of

    text are

    interpreted

    by

    their

    context

    in

    the

    larger message

    of

    a book

    while the

    larger

    message

    is itself

    put

    together

    from

    an

    understanding

    of

    the

    parts,

    so

    too are

    individual

    observations

    interpreted

    by

    appeal

    to

    theories

    that are themselves put together and supported by observations. That is, the content and justification

    of

    theories

    are

    strongly

    influenced

    by observations,

    and

    in

    turn

    the

    informational

    content

    and

    justification

    of

    observations are

    influenced

    by

    theories.

    This is

    exactly

    the

    structure of the

    herme-

    neutic

    circle.

    And

    middle-range

    theories

    participate

    on both

    sides of this

    dialogue

    between

    theory

    and

    observation.

    Middle-range

    theories

    are

    hermeneutic

    tools.

    This is

    not

    to

    say

    that

    the

    objects

    of

    study

    that

    Binford

    advocates as

    important

    for

    archaeology

    are

    the

    same as

    those

    stressed

    by

    Hodder

    and

    contextualist

    archaeologists.

    To

    point

    out

    that the

    methodological

    structure

    of

    middle-range theorizing

    is

    similar

    to the

    hermeneutics of

    contextual

    archaeology

    is not

    to

    force

    the

    former

    into a

    study

    of

    the

    mental

    component

    of

    the

    archaeological

    record.

    The

    point

    is

    rather

    that

    the

    two

    different

    concerns

    and different

    objects

    of

    study

    are in a

    similar

    epistemic

    predicament

    that

    calls for

    a

    shared

    method.

    The

    point

    is

    relevant

    beyond archaeology. Natural science in general, role model for middle-range

    theorizing,

    includes a

    hermeneutic

    component

    in

    the

    dialectic

    between

    theory

    and

    evidence. The

    hermeneutic

    structure

    shown

    above

    for

    Binford's

    middle-range theories,

    the

    reciprocating

    influence

    Kosso]

    625

    This content downloaded from 14.139.109.99 on Tue, 28 Jul 2015 20:20:30 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/18/2019 Middle-Range Theory as Hermeneutics

    7/8

    AMERICAN ANTIQUITY

    between theories about the whole

    and observations of the

    parts,

    would

    apply

    as

    well to

    the astro-

    physics example

    discussed above. This indicates that

    differences

    between for-science and

    against-

    science

    approaches

    to

    archaeology

    have been

    based

    in

    part

    on an

    incomplete

    and inaccurate

    image

    of

    science

    in

    general.

    Science must read nature

    just

    as Hodder

    points

    out

    archaeology

    must read

    the

    past.

    The

    unity

    of the two

    approaches

    then comes in

    realizing

    that

    doing archaeology

    in a

    scientific,

    middle-range-theory way

    is

    doing

    it

    in

    a

    contextual,

    hermeneutic

    way.

    Some

    assumptions

    need to be made to break into

    the circular

    association between

    theory

    and

    observation. There

    will

    be neither

    meaningful

    evidence nor theoretical

    understanding

    without initial

    hypotheses

    and

    preliminary

    middle-range

    theories.

    All

    of these

    assumptions

    are revisable. That

    is

    exactly

    the sort of

    epistemic

    responsibility

    we demand of science.

    They

    are revisable

    against

    the

    standards of

    coherence

    with other

    theories,

    that

    is,

    an internal

    plausibility

    in the

    context

    of other

    theories,

    and

    correspondence

    with

    the

    data,

    that

    is,

    with

    the

    evidential

    claims

    aden with

    other

    theories. The

    revisions

    are answerable

    to,

    as Alison

    Wylie (1982:42)

    puts

    it,

    two sets

    of con-

    straints ...

    plausibility

    considerations

    ... and

    empirical

    constraints.

    The

    requirement

    that evidential claims

    should be

    influenced

    by

    heories

    hould be influenceotherdhaby

    the

    one for

    which they are evidence is important and it is the foundation of Binford's idea of objectivity. He

    advocates

    a

    view

    of'objectivity'

    developed

    within the

    sciences. That

    was the view that

    it was

    not

    the status

    of

    the observer

    that

    yielded objectivity

    but the

    status

    of logical

    or intellectual

    independence

    between the ideas

    being

    evaluated,

    on the one

    hand,

    and the intellectual

    tools

    employed

    in the evaluated

    investigations,

    on the other

    (Binford

    1982a:128, emphasis

    in

    original).

    Furthermore,

    this

    require-

    ment of

    independence

    between

    object theory

    and

    middle-range theory

    can

    be used to

    answer

    ob-

    jections

    of

    circularity

    in

    the

    testing

    of

    theory against

    theory-laden

    evidence,

    as

    put

    by

    contextualists

    such as Shanks

    and

    Tilley,

    who

    say,

    If

    all observation

    is

    to

    a

    certain

    extent

    theoretical,

    ..

    .

    it

    is

    illogical

    to maintain

    that

    theories can be

    independently

    tested

    against

    observation

    (Shanks

    and

    Tilley

    1987:40-41).

    While

    the antecedent

    of this

    is

    true

    (all

    observation

    is

    theoretical),

    the

    consequent

    is not

    (theories

    can be tested

    against

    independently

    secured

    evidence),

    and it

    is the insistence

    on

    independence

    that breaks

    any

    problematic, self-serving circularity

    of

    theory

    and

    evidence.

    Obser-

    vations can serve as objective evidence for theories even though observations are indelibly theo-

    retical.

    In

    general

    then,

    the

    acceptability

    of

    middle-range

    theories

    and

    the evidential

    and

    theoretical

    claims

    they

    support

    is

    governed

    by

    a

    requirement

    of

    consistency

    and coherence

    and a constraint

    of

    independence

    in

    the

    accounting

    for evidential

    claims.

    No

    claims,

    whether

    preliminary

    assumptions

    of

    meaning

    or

    middle-range

    theories,

    are

    acceptable

    if

    they

    lead to

    contradiction.

    We assume

    that

    the book

    makes

    sense,

    hence

    an

    interpretation

    that

    introduces

    contradiction

    must

    be

    mistaken.

    Interestingly,

    independence

    is

    also

    the answer

    to

    objections

    of

    circularity

    and

    unverifiability

    directed

    against

    the

    contextual,

    hermeneutic

    approach

    (Binford 1989).

    The

    assumptions

    about

    subjective

    meanings (Hodder

    1986:79)

    that

    influence

    our observations

    of the

    material record

    are

    themselves

    accountable

    to other

    evidence

    that

    is

    influenced

    by

    other

    independent

    hypotheses

    of

    subjective meaning. This contextual method need not be problematically circular

    or left to

    unsub-

    stantiated

    speculation

    as

    long

    as

    one insists

    on a coherence

    among

    independently

    arrived at

    claims

    about the

    past.

    It is no coincidence

    that the

    key

    to

    objectivity

    is the

    same

    in the

    middle-range

    theory

    and

    hermeneutic

    approaches.

    It is

    the result

    of their

    common

    structure

    and

    the fact

    that

    they

    are

    fundamentally

    the same

    method.

    CONCLUSION

    The

    original

    presentation

    of

    Binford's

    and

    Hodder's

    models

    of

    archaeological

    method cast

    them

    as

    being

    in

    opposition.

    Archaeology by

    Hodder's

    contextual

    account

    is

    as

    reading

    a

    book

    written

    in an unfamiliar

    language.

    It

    involves

    a

    hermeneutic

    circle

    of

    analysis

    that

    requires

    some

    initial

    assumptions

    to

    break

    in

    and

    get

    started.

    Binford's

    middle-range- theory

    account

    portrays

    archaeology

    as

    being methodologically

    like

    the

    natural

    sciences.

    Responsible

    archaeology

    demands

    observational

    evidence

    as tests

    for

    theories

    about

    the

    past,

    and

    informative

    observation

    requires

    theories

    that

    describe

    the formation

    of

    the

    evidence.

    626

    [Vol.

    56,

    No.

    4,

    1991

    This content downloaded from 14.139.109.99 on Tue, 28 Jul 2015 20:20:30 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/18/2019 Middle-Range Theory as Hermeneutics

    8/8

    MIDDLE-RANGEHEORY

    S HERMENEUTICS

    They

    are both

    right.

    It is not that

    archaeology

    is a

    rigid

    and

    segregated

    system

    of theories

    and

    observations in

    which brute facts are used

    to test theories. It is rather

    that the methods of

    natural

    science,

    and those advocated

    by

    Binford for

    archaeology,

    are more like the

    contextual,

    hermeneutic,

    back-and-forth

    model

    than Hodder's

    original

    opposition

    seemed to

    recognize.

    The

    argument

    for

    this

    similarity

    is

    in

    the

    display

    of the nature of claims about the

    past

    and claims

    of

    evidence,

    and

    the

    structure of confirmation

    as advocated

    by

    each

    approach.

    It is not the content

    of claims that

    is

    shared

    but

    the

    method

    of

    justification

    and the standard of

    objectivity.

    It is

    important

    to

    display

    this

    point

    of

    similarity

    between

    the

    processualist

    and contextualist

    views

    of

    archaeology

    to show that the

    opposition

    between the

    two cannot be located

    on basic issues

    of

    method.

    Methodological

    complaints

    such as

    circularity

    and

    speculativeness,

    made from one

    position

    about

    the

    other,

    are seen as

    pointing

    out

    potential

    weakness

    that

    both have and both must

    cover

    with the insistence

    on coherence

    under

    the constraint of

    independence

    among

    claims.

    Hermeneutics,

    as

    a method of

    acquiring knowledge

    beyond

    the most

    manifest is

    seen to be

    appropriate

    for

    more

    than

    just uncovering

    meanings, ideas,

    and intentions. It

    is

    the

    method as well of natural

    science.

    Acknowledgements.I am gratefulto CynthiaKosso for help with the facts and to the National Science

    Foundation

    for

    support

    (DIR

    89-17989)

    during part

    of

    my

    work

    on this

    project.

    REFERENCES

    CITED

    Binford,

    L.

    1977

    General

    Introduction.

    In

    For

    Theory Building

    in

    Archaeology,

    edited

    by

    L.

    Binford, pp.

    1-10.

    Academic

    Press,

    New

    York.

    1982a

    Objectivity-Explanation-Archaeology

    1981.

    In

    Theory

    and

    Explanation

    in

    Archaeology,

    edited

    by

    C.

    Renfrew,

    M.

    Rowlands,

    and B.

    Seagraves,

    pp.

    125-138.

    Academic

    Press,

    New

    York.

    1982b

    Meaning,

    Inference

    and the Material

    Record. In

    Ranking,

    Resource

    and

    Exchange,

    edited

    by

    C.

    Renfrew

    and S.

    Shennan,

    pp. 160-163.

    Cambridge

    University Press,

    Cambridge.

    1989

    Review of

    Reading

    the

    Past,

    by

    Ian

    Hodder.

    American

    Antiquity

    53:875-876.

    Bintliff,

    J.,

    and

    A.

    Snodgrass

    1988 Off-Site Pottery Distributions: A Regional and Interregional Perspective. Current Anthropology 29:

    506-513.

    Cherry, J.,

    J.

    Davis,

    and E.

    Mantzourani

    1991

    Landscape

    Archaeology

    As

    Long-Term

    History:

    Northern

    Keos in

    the

    Cycladic

    Islands.

    UCLA

    Press,

    Los

    Angeles,

    in

    press.

    Hodder,

    I.

    1985

    Postprocessualist

    Archaeology.

    In

    Advances

    in

    Archaeological

    Method

    and

    Theory,

    vol.

    8,

    edited

    by

    M.

    B.

    Schiffer,

    pp.

    1-26.

    Academic

    Press,

    New

    York.

    1986

    Reading

    the

    Past.

    Cambridge

    University Press,

    Cambridge.

    1991

    Interpretive

    Archaeology

    and its

    Role.

    American

    Antiquity

    56:7-18.

    Patrik,

    L.

    1985

    Is

    There an

    Archaeological

    Record? In

    Advances

    in

    Archaeological

    Method

    and

    Theory,

    vol.

    8,

    edited

    by

    M. B.

    Schiffer,

    pp.

    27-62.

    Academic

    Press,

    New

    York.

    Schaffer,

    K.

    1980 Theory Structure in the Biochemical Sciences. The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 5:57-95.

    Schiffer,

    M.

    B.

    1988

    The

    Structure

    of

    Archaeological

    Theory.

    American

    Antiquity

    53:461-485.

    Shanks,

    M.,

    and C.

    Tilley

    1987

    Re-constructing

    Archaeology.

    Cambridge

    University

    Press,

    Cambridge.

    Shapere,

    D.

    1982

    The

    Concept

    of

    Observation in

    Science and

    Philosophy.

    Philosophy of

    Science

    49:485-525.

    Wilkinson,

    T.

    1982

    The

    Definition

    of

    Ancient

    Manured

    Zones

    by

    Means

    of

    Extensive

    Sherd-Sampling

    Techniques.

    Journal

    of

    Field

    Archaeology

    9:323-333.

    Wylie,

    M.

    A.

    1982

    Epistemological

    Issues

    Raised

    by

    a

    Structuralist

    Archaeology.

    In

    Symbolic

    and

    StructuralArchaeology,

    edited

    by

    I.

    Hodder,

    pp.

    39-46.

    Cambridge

    University

    Press,

    Cambridge.

    Received

    May

    30,

    1990;

    accepted

    May

    28,

    1991

    Kosso]

    627

    This content downloaded from 14.139.109.99 on Tue, 28 Jul 2015 20:20:30 UTC