meerson_put' against logos_the critique of kant and neo-kantianism by russian religious philosophers...

Upload: mehmetmsahin

Post on 02-Jun-2018

216 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/11/2019 Meerson_Put' against Logos_The Critique of Kant and Neo-Kantianism by Russian Religious Philosophers in the Beginning of the Twentieth Century_Weber

    1/20

    Put' against Logos: The Critique of Kant and Neo-Kantianism by Russian ReligiousPhilosophers in the Beginning of the Twentieth CenturyAuthor(s): Michael A. MeersonSource: Studies in East European Thought, Vol. 47, No. 3/4, Neo-Kantianism in RussianThought (Dec., 1995), pp. 225-243Published by: SpringerStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/20099584.

    Accessed: 09/10/2014 09:24

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at.http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    .JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of

    content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms

    of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    .

    Springeris collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Studies in East European

    Thought.

    http://www.jstor.org

    This content downloaded from 194.27.240.181 on Thu, 9 Oct 2014 09:24:05 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=springerhttp://www.jstor.org/stable/20099584?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/20099584?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=springer
  • 8/11/2019 Meerson_Put' against Logos_The Critique of Kant and Neo-Kantianism by Russian Religious Philosophers in the Beginning of the Twentieth Century_Weber

    2/20

    MICHAEL

    A.

    MEERSON

    PUT AGAINSTLOGOS:THECRITIQUEOFKANT AND

    NEO-KANTIANISM

    BY

    RUSSIAN

    RELIGIOUS

    PHILOSOPHERS

    NTHE

    BEGINNINGOF

    THE

    TWENTIETH

    CENTURY

    KEY WORDS:

    Puf,

    Logos,

    Kant,

    neo-Kantians, Berdiaev,

    Bulgakov,

    Trubetskoi

    HISTORICAL INTRODUCTION

    At

    the

    turn

    of

    the

    20th

    century

    Russian

    philosophical

    thought

    acquired

    new

    vitality through

    a

    polemical

    encounter

    with

    German

    neo-Kantianism.

    The central issue of the

    polemic

    concerned the

    nature

    of

    philosophy.

    The

    group

    of Russian

    thinkers

    gathered

    around

    Puf

    publishing

    house

    developed

    a new

    realist

    approach,

    while

    con

    testing

    the

    reduction of

    philosophy

    to

    methodology actually

    effected

    by

    German

    neo-Kantians.

    Confronting

    philosophy's

    reduction

    to

    methodology,

    Russian thinkers maintained that

    knowledge

    has

    an

    ontological

    and

    metaphysical

    basis.

    Puf

    's

    thinkers,

    different

    as

    they

    were,

    unanimously

    maintained that

    a

    gradual

    reduction of

    philosoph

    ical

    ontology

    to

    methodology

    resulted from

    Kant's

    emancipation

    of

    epistemology

    from

    metaphysics.

    The Russian

    argument

    with

    Kant and

    neo-Kantians

    at

    first

    took

    the form of a polemic between the religio-philosophical publishing

    house

    Puf

    (1910-1917)

    and

    the neo-Kantian

    journal

    Logos

    (1910

    1914)

    in

    Moscow.

    Both

    publishing

    enterprises

    reflected

    the

    philo

    sophical awakening

    of the Russian educated

    public

    and

    its

    growing

    need

    to

    develop

    self-consciousness

    on

    the

    one

    hand,

    and

    to

    achieve

    fuller

    integration

    into the intellectual life of

    contemporary

    Europe

    on

    the other.

    Puf

    pursued primarily

    the first

    task,

    while

    Logos

    was

    mainly

    designed

    to

    fulfill the second.

    Since,

    in

    fact,

    neither

    task

    could have been achieved separately, the fields o? Puf 'sand Logos's

    labor

    inevitably overlapped.

    Puf

    published

    translations of

    European

    philosophers

    and Russian studies

    on

    them,

    while

    Logos

    featured

    Studies

    inEast

    European Thought

    47:

    225-243,1995.

    ?

    1995

    Kluwer

    Academic

    Publishers. Printed

    in

    the

    Netherlands.

    This content downloaded from 194.27.240.181 on Thu, 9 Oct 2014 09:24:05 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Meerson_Put' against Logos_The Critique of Kant and Neo-Kantianism by Russian Religious Philosophers in the Beginning of the Twentieth Century_Weber

    3/20

    226

    MICHAEL

    A.

    MEERSON

    articles on indigenous Russian philosophical thought, both past and

    contemporary.

    Both

    groups

    emerged

    in

    the milieu of

    the Russian

    intelligentsia

    that

    was

    at

    best

    notoriously

    suspicious

    of,

    and

    at worst

    contemptuous

    of,

    and

    even

    hostile

    to,

    both

    religious

    and

    theoretical

    philosophy.

    Both

    Puf and

    Logos

    were

    therefore

    small

    and

    exotic,

    and

    felt,

    especially

    in

    the

    beginning,

    as

    outcasts

    among

    their kin.

    Often the

    same

    authors

    contributed

    to

    both

    Logos

    and

    Put\

    and

    since

    both

    groups

    ventured

    into

    a

    rather elite

    field,

    they

    served

    as

    necessary

    interlocutors

    and

    contenders

    to

    each other.

    Puf

    had the

    advantage

    of

    having

    a

    domestic

    philosophical

    forum

    of

    its

    own.

    It

    emerged

    as an

    offspring

    of

    the

    Moscow

    Religio-Philo

    sophical Society

    founded

    in

    1905

    by Margarita

    Morozova

    (1873

    1958),

    Prince

    Evgenii

    Trubetskoi

    (1863-1920),

    Sergei

    Bulgakov

    (1871-1944),

    Nikolai

    Berdiaev

    (1874-1948),

    Pavel

    Florenskii

    (1882-1937),

    and Vladimir

    Ern

    (1882-1917),

    to

    name

    its

    most

    active board members and

    participants. Margarita

    Morozova,

    a

    widow

    of

    Mikhail

    Morozov,

    a

    prominent

    Moscow

    industrialist

    and

    art

    supporter,

    managed

    the Puf

    publishing

    house with the

    help

    of

    Trubetskoi,

    Bulgakov

    and

    Berdiaev,

    the

    leaders

    of

    its editorial board.

    The

    board defined

    Puf

    goal

    as

    the

    philosophical

    rediscovery

    of

    East

    ern

    Orthodoxy

    and

    of its

    applicability

    in

    the

    contemporary

    world.1

    The

    journal

    Logos,

    published

    in

    German

    in

    T?bingen,

    and in

    Russian

    in

    Moscow,

    was

    founded

    with the

    help

    of Heinrich

    Rickert

    (1863-1936).2

    Its editorial board consisted of

    two

    groups

    of

    young

    neo-Kantians

    of

    Wilhelm

    Windelband's

    (1848-1915)

    school: the

    Russians Feodor Stepun (1884-1965), Nikolai Bubnov, and Sergei

    Gessen,

    and

    the Germans

    Richard Kroner

    and

    Georg

    Mehlis. The

    emergence

    of

    the

    journal

    in

    1910

    reflected

    Russians'

    growing

    interest

    in

    contemporary

    academic

    philosophy.

    The

    sophisticated

    philosoph

    ic

    technique

    of

    neo-Kantianism,

    as

    well

    as

    its claim

    to

    provide

    the

    system

    of

    logical

    foundation for

    both

    natural

    sciences

    and

    humani

    tarian

    culture,

    attracted

    many

    Russian

    students.

    Both Puf

    and

    Logos

    were

    financially

    supported

    by

    Morozova.

    She housed

    both

    Puf and

    Solov'ev's

    Religio-Philosophical Society,

    thus

    providing

    nascent

    Russian

    religious

    philosophy

    with its

    unique

    forum,

    and

    also

    helped funding

    Musaget,

    a

    Symbolist publishing

    house under

    the editorial

    leadership

    of

    Emil

    Metner

    (1872-1936),

    which

    published

    Logos.3

    A

    philosophical

    tournament

    between

    Logos

    This content downloaded from 194.27.240.181 on Thu, 9 Oct 2014 09:24:05 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Meerson_Put' against Logos_The Critique of Kant and Neo-Kantianism by Russian Religious Philosophers in the Beginning of the Twentieth Century_Weber

    4/20

    PUT

    AGAINST

    LOGOS

    227

    and

    Puf

    went

    on

    at

    the

    gatherings

    of

    the

    Solov'?v

    Society

    -

    which

    became the Platonic

    Academy

    of

    Moscow

    -

    provoking

    and

    sustain

    ing

    endless

    dialogues

    on

    ultimate

    issues.

    Both

    Logos

    and Puf

    could

    claim

    the

    legacy

    of Vekhi

    [Landmarks],

    the

    famous

    collection

    of arti

    cles

    on

    Russian

    intelligentsia;

    they

    can

    be

    viewed

    as

    the

    two

    branches

    resulting

    from

    the

    philosophical

    bifurcation

    of the

    Vekhi

    movement.

    While

    Berdiaev,

    Bulgakov

    and

    Gershenzon

    wrote

    for

    Puf

    ?

    Frank,

    Struve and

    Kistiakovskii,

    three

    other Vekhfs

    contributors,

    published

    in

    Logos.5

    Puf

    's

    authors

    argued

    that

    philosophical

    and

    theological

    revival should be achieved through the integration ofmodern philos

    ophy

    into

    the

    tradition

    of

    Christian

    Platonism

    and

    neo-Platonism,

    an

    integration

    started

    by

    Vladimir

    Solov'?v.

    Logos

    set

    the

    double

    goal

    of

    the

    philosophical

    education

    of the

    Russian

    public

    in

    the

    latest

    achievements

    of

    Western

    philosophy

    and the

    integration

    of

    Russian

    thought

    with

    the

    mainline

    of

    European

    philosophical

    development,

    chiefly

    neo-Kantian.

    I

    shall

    concentrate on

    Puf's

    polemics,

    and

    shall

    discuss

    four

    Puf authors, Ern, Berdiaev, Bulgakov, and Trubetskoi. All of them

    addressed

    the

    issue of

    neo-Kantianism

    and

    created the

    general

    image

    of

    Russian

    thought's

    unified

    front

    against

    the

    Germanophile

    Logos.

    In

    summing

    up

    Puf's

    argument,

    Stepun

    points

    out

    some

    affinity

    in

    the criticism

    of

    neo-Kantianism made

    respectively

    by

    American

    pragmatists

    and

    by

    Russian

    religious

    thinkers.

    Both

    opposed

    pure

    epistemology

    with

    a

    living

    and

    practical

    holistic

    philosophy.

    Stepun,

    however,

    simplifies

    the

    Russian

    reaction

    to

    neo-Kantianism

    by

    say

    ing

    that Russian

    philosophy generally

    shared

    Berdiaev's

    opinion

    that

    the interest

    in

    epistemological

    issues

    develops

    where the

    access

    to

    existence

    is

    lost. 6

    Berdiaev's

    existential

    protest

    that

    impressed

    Stepun

    the

    most

    was

    only

    one

    of

    the

    aspects

    of

    Puf

    's

    criticism.

    Along

    with

    several

    common

    features of this

    criticism,

    each thinker

    presented

    his

    critique

    with

    his

    own

    particular

    slant.

    ERN'S

    MILITANT

    NEO-SLAVOPHILISM

    It

    was

    Vladimir

    Ern,

    the

    most

    zealous

    advocate

    of

    the

    'Russian

    idea,'

    who

    gave

    a

    militant flavor

    to

    the

    otherwise

    harmless

    debate

    with his

    book

    The

    Battle

    for

    Logos.

    Ern

    launched

    the

    polemics

    with

    his

    article

    'Something

    on

    Logos,

    Russian

    philosophy

    and

    scientism,'

    written

    This content downloaded from 194.27.240.181 on Thu, 9 Oct 2014 09:24:05 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Meerson_Put' against Logos_The Critique of Kant and Neo-Kantianism by Russian Religious Philosophers in the Beginning of the Twentieth Century_Weber

    5/20

    228

    MICHAEL

    A.

    MEERSON

    in response to the first issue of Logos. The article was first published

    in

    Trubetskoi's

    'Moscow

    Weekly,'

    and

    was

    subsequently

    included

    in

    Bor'ba

    za

    Logos.

    Ern

    opposed

    the Russian

    philosophical style,

    which he

    defined

    as

    logism, ontologism

    and

    thorough

    personalism,

    to

    modern Western

    philosophy

    which,

    according

    to

    Ern,

    had

    come

    to

    the blind

    alley

    of rationalism

    ...

    and

    impersonalismo'7

    He

    stipu

    lated that

    his

    critique

    aimed

    at

    the

    dominant

    trend

    of

    this

    philosophy,

    rather

    than

    at

    Western

    thought

    as a

    whole.

    He

    singled

    out

    some

    Italian

    philosophers

    as

    'faithful

    to

    Logos,' especially

    Gioberti

    ( 1801-1852),

    whose

    'ontologism'

    he traced

    to

    Plato and

    Bonaventura8

    Ern

    defined

    the task and

    character

    of

    Russian

    thought

    as one

    that

    grew

    on

    the

    foundations of

    Western

    philosophy,

    but

    preserved

    its

    own

    tendency

    -

    toward

    religious

    and

    mystical

    holism,

    in

    the

    spirit

    of Christian

    neo-Platonism.

    He

    blamed

    Logos9s

    editors

    mainly

    for

    usurping

    the

    ancient

    trademark

    of

    holistic

    philosophy

    in

    order

    to

    label their

    prod

    uct

    which,

    in

    fact,

    had been

    made

    in

    Germany. 9

    He

    presented

    the

    innocent

    philosophical polemic

    as a

    contest

    of

    universal

    historical

    proportion

    between theRussian and the

    German

    spirit.

    Ern's

    continuing

    argument

    peaked

    in

    his

    paper

    From

    Kant

    to

    Krupp,

    delivered

    in

    the

    fall of 1914

    to

    the

    Solov'?v

    Society,

    at

    the

    height

    of anti-German

    feeling

    in

    Russia.

    Therein he

    depicted

    German

    militarism

    as

    a natural

    offspring

    of Kant's

    phenomenalism.

    More

    over,

    he maintained that Kant's critical

    revolution

    in

    philosophy

    meant

    for

    German

    patriotic

    awareness

    what the

    French

    Revolution

    of 1789

    meant

    for the French. Kant

    was

    the real

    father of the

    anthro

    pocentric world view that did away with old religious metaphysics. It

    was

    not

    Nietzsche

    but Kant who

    guillotined

    the old

    living

    God

    in

    the

    labyrinths

    of

    the Transcendental

    Analytic.

    Kant's

    phenomenalism,

    along

    with half

    a

    century

    of the neo-Kantians'

    collective

    labors,

    sev

    ered the

    channels of the

    intellectual communication

    between

    man

    and

    God,

    and locked the human

    mind

    in

    the realm

    of

    earthly,

    limited

    goals, thereby preparing

    the

    ground

    for

    the fast advance of

    German

    technology.

    The

    latter,

    aiming

    at

    the

    war

    for German

    domination,

    found its ultimate

    expression

    in

    Krupp's military industry,

    his

    can

    nons,

    which

    Ern

    called the

    most

    perfect

    and

    sophisticated

    tools of

    destruction.

    Thus,

    Krupp

    's

    arms

    represent,

    in

    Ern's

    words,

    the

    purest

    form of Kant's

    Sein

    fur

    sich

    organized

    scientifically

    and techno

    logically.

    With his

    philosophy,

    Kant

    dialectically posits

    Krupp,

    This content downloaded from 194.27.240.181 on Thu, 9 Oct 2014 09:24:05 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Meerson_Put' against Logos_The Critique of Kant and Neo-Kantianism by Russian Religious Philosophers in the Beginning of the Twentieth Century_Weber

    6/20

    PUT

    AGAINST

    LOGOS

    229

    claims

    Ern,

    and

    Krupp,

    in

    his

    most

    perfect

    products,

    gives

    the

    mate

    rial

    expression

    for

    the

    phenomenalist

    premises

    of Kant's

    thought.

    Ern

    concludes

    his

    lecture

    with

    an

    appeal

    to

    the

    Russian

    army

    to

    use

    their

    spiritual

    might

    to

    overthrow the

    armored

    German

    legions. 10

    Many

    Russian

    critics,

    including

    some

    of

    his

    colleagues

    in

    Put\

    were

    bewildered and

    even

    appalled by

    Ern's

    bizarre

    conclusions.

    Ern

    responded

    to

    these critics

    in

    another

    public

    lecture,

    'The

    Essence

    of German

    Phenomenalism,'

    delivered

    in

    Petrograd

    in

    November,

    1914,

    and

    in

    Moscow

    in

    January,

    1915.

    He

    supported

    his

    argumen

    tation,

    developed along

    the same lines with a new vivid illustration:

    two

    weeks after he

    had

    delivered his lecture

    'From Kant

    to

    Krupp,'

    the Bonn

    University

    Department

    of

    Philosophy

    granted

    doctorates

    honoris

    causa

    to

    both

    Krupp

    and

    Ausenberg,

    the

    manager

    of

    Krupp

    's

    industrial

    complex.11

    BERDIAEV'S

    CRITIQUE

    Polemics

    with both Kant and neo-Kantians made

    one

    of the

    key

    theses and served

    as

    the

    departing

    point

    in

    Berdiaev's

    first

    philo

    sophical

    book,

    The

    Philosophy

    of

    Freedom.

    Having developed

    his

    philosophical

    style

    under Nietzsche's

    influence,

    Berdiaev insisted

    on

    the

    right

    of

    a

    philosopher

    to

    speak directly

    out

    of his

    own

    existential

    experience.

    Berdiaev attacked

    neo-Kantianism

    as

    the

    very

    epitome

    of

    modern

    scholasticism hostile

    to

    life

    and

    to

    the

    spontaneous

    search

    for truth.

    He

    appreciated,

    of

    course,

    the

    positive

    contribution of

    crit

    ical

    epistemology:

    it

    occupied

    the central

    position

    in

    the intellectual

    life of his

    age,

    and

    it

    represented

    the

    finest

    product

    of

    intellec

    tual culture. Neo-Kantianism had also

    provoked

    a

    philosophical

    revival and advanced the

    technique

    of

    philosophizing.

    Berdiaev

    maintained, however,

    that the

    movement

    lacked the

    philosophical

    eros

    that enlivened the

    great

    systems

    of

    German idealism such

    as

    Hegel's.

    Uninspiring

    and

    purely

    technical,

    neo-Kantianism

    symp

    tomatized the loss of

    integrity

    by

    the

    contemporary

    mind,

    and its

    indecisiveness, Hamletism in philosophy. For Berdiaev, Kant's

    genius

    indicated

    a

    serious disease

    of

    Western civilization: Kant for

    mulated the fatal

    rupture

    of

    philosophical

    mind from

    the

    sources

    of

    being.

    After

    Kant,

    neo-Kantians

    merely deepened

    this

    fatal

    rupture

    by

    completing

    the

    substitution of

    abstract

    cognition

    for

    the

    real,

    This content downloaded from 194.27.240.181 on Thu, 9 Oct 2014 09:24:05 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Meerson_Put' against Logos_The Critique of Kant and Neo-Kantianism by Russian Religious Philosophers in the Beginning of the Twentieth Century_Weber

    7/20

    230

    MICHAEL

    A.

    MEERSON

    living

    attitude

    of

    subject

    to

    object.

    Their

    critical

    epistemology

    radi

    cally

    denies

    the

    primary

    goal

    of

    knowledge

    -

    the

    uniting

    of

    knowing

    subject

    with

    being.12

    Divorced

    from

    life,

    neo-Kantian

    criticism

    could

    produce only

    illusionistic

    and

    solipsistic

    doctrines.

    Its

    claim

    to

    construe

    a

    philo

    sophical

    method

    free from

    the

    psychological

    and

    ontological

    premises

    was

    ridiculous,

    because it is

    the

    human

    being

    who

    philos

    ophizes,

    and human

    knowledge

    takes

    place

    in

    the

    anthropological

    milieu.

    For

    Berdiaev,

    critical

    epistemology

    addressed

    only

    a

    limited

    form of

    knowledge,

    which he calls

    fictional,

    since a

    cognizing

    sub

    ject

    taken outside

    of existence is

    purely

    fictional. Neo-Kantians

    articulated

    the

    concept

    of

    experience

    arbitrarily

    and

    limited it

    by

    rationalistic

    boundaries

    as

    they

    pleased.

    According

    to

    Berdiaev,

    the

    opposition

    between

    thinking

    and

    existence

    was

    caused

    by

    a

    philosophic

    malnutrition

    of

    sorts;

    philosophy

    must

    be

    nourished

    by

    two

    kinds

    of

    experience,

    scientific

    and

    mystical.

    Berdiaev

    grounded

    this

    argument

    in

    the

    philosophy

    of

    Nikolai

    Losskii,

    a

    Russian

    who

    defended mystical empiricism and extended the realm of possible

    experience

    far

    beyond

    rational

    limits,

    as

    well

    as

    in

    William

    James'

    pragmatism

    and

    Bergson

    's

    philosophy

    of

    life:

    the

    latter

    two

    looked

    for

    the existential

    justification

    of

    knowledge.

    Berdiaev

    emphasized

    that

    James,

    like

    Losskii,

    recognized experience

    beyond

    the limits of

    the

    rational,

    such

    as

    the

    perfectly

    valid

    experiences

    of saints and

    mystics. Calling

    Kant's

    ratio

    'small

    reason,'

    Berdiaev

    opposed

    to

    it

    Logos,

    the

    'big

    reason' of

    the

    mystical philosophy

    of

    Augustine,

    Eriugena,

    Eckhart, Boehme,

    and

    other

    mystics,

    who

    were

    nourished

    by

    the

    Catholic,

    or

    worldwide,

    soborny

    experience

    of

    the Eastern and

    Western

    churches.

    Extending

    this tradition of

    mystical

    philosophy

    to

    the

    Russian

    thought

    of

    the

    Slavophiles,

    Solov'?v

    and

    Dostoevskii,

    Berdiaev

    argued

    that

    for this Russian

    tradition

    neo-Kantianism

    could

    have

    only

    a

    very

    limited,

    technical

    value.13

    KANTIANISM

    AND

    BULGAKOV'S

    TRANSCENDENTAL

    BASE FOR

    ECONOMY

    Bulgakov

    also

    partly

    owed the

    main thesis of

    his first

    philosophic

    book,

    The

    Philosophy

    of

    Economy,

    to

    his

    polemics

    with

    Kant and

    neo-Kantianism.

    Kant

    attempted

    to

    answer

    the

    question

    of

    how

    This content downloaded from 194.27.240.181 on Thu, 9 Oct 2014 09:24:05 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Meerson_Put' against Logos_The Critique of Kant and Neo-Kantianism by Russian Religious Philosophers in the Beginning of the Twentieth Century_Weber

    8/20

    PUT

    AGAINST

    LOGOS

    231

    knowledge, especially

    scientific

    knowledge,

    is

    possible. Recogniz

    ing

    the

    validity

    of

    this

    problem,

    Bulgakov

    added

    to

    it another

    ques

    tion

    that

    constituted

    the

    central

    topic

    of

    his

    study:

    how

    production,

    or

    economic

    activity,

    is

    possible,

    i.e.

    what

    are

    the

    a

    priori

    conditions

    for

    an

    objective

    industrial

    action.

    He

    considered

    his

    task

    regarding

    economy

    to

    be

    fully

    analogous

    to

    Kant's task

    regarding knowledge

    set

    out in

    the

    Critique

    of

    Pure

    Reason.14

    According

    to

    Bulgakov,

    knowledge

    and

    economic

    activity

    merge

    in

    technology. Basing

    his

    assertion

    on

    Leo

    Lopatin's

    study, Bulgakov

    maintained

    that

    scien

    tific

    knowledge

    is

    practical,

    i.e. it is technical.

    Technology,

    whether

    primitive

    or

    highly

    sophisticated,

    is

    a

    necessary

    part

    of

    any

    industry.

    In

    terms

    of

    epistemology, technology

    is

    a

    leap

    from

    knowledge

    to

    action.

    In

    Bulgakov's

    aphoristic

    language,

    technology

    is

    logical,

    and

    logic

    is

    technological:

    one

    builds

    a

    bridge

    across

    a

    river

    through

    calculus. 15

    Therefore

    all

    aspects

    of human

    activity,

    including

    cog

    nition,

    ultimately

    can

    be reduced

    to

    economic

    goals,

    and all kinds

    of

    knowledge,

    even

    the

    most

    abstract,

    are

    productive.

    Bulgakov

    rejected Kant's idea that knowledge is passive, andmaintained that

    it

    is

    a

    volitional

    activity

    that

    requires

    an

    effort.

    While

    economy

    acts

    upon

    the material

    world

    and

    claims

    ever

    new

    terrains

    for

    its

    own

    advance,

    cognition

    acts

    laboriously

    upon

    the ideal

    world,

    opening

    ever

    new

    fields for

    human

    knowledge.16

    Kant

    postulated

    the unsurmountable

    opposition

    between

    subject

    and

    object.

    Bulgakov

    viewed

    this

    postulate

    as

    merely

    hypothetical,

    a

    postulate

    needed

    by

    Kant for

    methodological

    reasons.

    Knowl

    edge,

    like

    production,

    involves

    labor,

    a

    feature

    overlooked

    by

    Kant.

    Having imported

    the

    notion of labor

    from

    political

    economy

    to

    epis

    temology, Bulgakov

    defined

    labor

    in

    epistemological

    terms

    as

    a

    living

    energy

    that

    welds

    together

    subject

    and

    object.

    In

    economic

    labor,

    the

    subject

    imprints

    his/herself

    on

    the

    object

    of

    production.

    The

    subject's

    action

    presupposes

    objective

    reality.

    As

    a

    form of

    pro

    duction,

    knowledge

    also

    involves

    the

    subject's stepping

    out

    into

    non-self

    (more

    precisely

    not-yet-self),

    the

    actualization

    of the

    pri

    mordial

    identity

    of

    self

    md

    non-self,

    of

    subject

    and

    object

    in

    every

    act

    of

    cognition.

    Since

    the

    opposition

    of

    subject

    and

    object

    isovercome

    through

    labor

    in

    both

    economy

    and

    cognition,

    both

    activities

    have

    the

    same

    metaphysical

    ground,

    namely

    the

    identity

    of

    subject

    and

    This content downloaded from 194.27.240.181 on Thu, 9 Oct 2014 09:24:05 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Meerson_Put' against Logos_The Critique of Kant and Neo-Kantianism by Russian Religious Philosophers in the Beginning of the Twentieth Century_Weber

    9/20

    232

    MICHAEL

    A.

    MEERSON

    object. For Bulgakov, life is the ceaseless process of the discovery

    and actualization

    of this

    identity. 17

    Kant's

    methodological

    abstraction

    stems out

    of his

    sundering

    of

    human

    mind into

    two

    types

    of

    reason,

    theoretical

    and

    practical.

    Bulgakov

    considered this division which

    constitutes the

    very

    core

    of Kant's

    philosophy,

    to

    be

    a

    groundless

    abstraction,

    since

    practical

    and

    theoretical

    'reasons' do

    not

    exist

    in

    separation.

    Neo-Kantianism

    retains

    this

    arbitrary

    division,

    and deals

    with

    the

    same

    Kantian

    sub

    ject reduced

    to

    passive

    reason

    alone. Bulgakov called this subject

    idle and

    impersonalistic,

    and

    considered this

    desubjectification

    of

    the

    subject

    to

    be

    the

    cause

    of

    the

    fatal

    determinism

    of Kan

    tianism.

    Being

    'idle' and

    passive,

    Kant's

    subject

    lacks

    the sound

    self-consciousness of its

    own

    subjectivity,

    it is

    deprived

    of the

    reality

    of

    self.

    In

    Bulgakov's

    opinion,

    Kant

    compensates

    for the lack

    of this selfhood

    by

    replacing

    it with the

    unity

    of

    transcendental

    apperception. 18

    Because

    technology

    and

    production require

    an

    active,

    labor

    ing,

    and,

    for this

    reason,

    personalistic

    subject, technology

    finds

    no

    place

    or

    explanation

    in

    Kant's

    theory. Bulgakov

    consistently empha

    sized

    that

    in

    its

    both

    forms

    -

    cognitional

    and

    productive

    -

    labor

    presupposes

    person.

    Since Kant's

    critique

    lacked

    this

    personalistic

    perspective,

    it

    had

    destroyed

    much

    more

    than Kant intended

    to.

    With his

    subject turning

    into

    an

    epistemological

    abstraction,

    Kant's

    anthropocentric

    revolution had

    failed.

    Upon

    this

    nail

    hammered

    into the

    air,

    ruled

    Bulgakov,

    one

    cannot

    hang

    even a

    bit of

    fluff,

    let alone the universe which the 'Copernican' Kant wished to fasten

    toit. 19

    Following

    Losskii,

    Bulgakov

    pointed

    to

    epistemological

    indi

    vidualism

    as an

    Achilles' heel of

    both

    Kant and

    neo-Kantianism.

    According

    to

    Kant's

    theory,

    the

    subject

    exists alone and there is

    no

    provision

    for its interaction with

    others.

    Following

    the

    same

    path,

    Cohen and his school defined

    epistemological

    individualism

    as

    a

    method,

    while,

    according

    to

    Bulgakov

    it is

    merely

    a

    methodological

    fiction. 20

    Not

    only

    does

    Kant's subjectivism fail

    to

    lead

    to

    person

    alism,

    but

    it

    also undermines his central

    thesis

    -

    the

    transcendental

    method

    itself.

    Bulgakov

    rescued this method with the

    help

    of

    the

    metaphysical

    notion

    of

    humanity

    as

    a

    whole.

    It is

    the

    human

    race

    throughout

    its

    history

    that

    is the

    transcendental

    subject

    of

    both

    This content downloaded from 194.27.240.181 on Thu, 9 Oct 2014 09:24:05 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Meerson_Put' against Logos_The Critique of Kant and Neo-Kantianism by Russian Religious Philosophers in the Beginning of the Twentieth Century_Weber

    10/20

    PUT

    AGAINST

    LOGOS

    233

    knowledge

    and

    economy.

    The

    presupposition

    of

    humanity,

    rather

    than

    of

    an

    individual

    or

    individuals,

    as

    the

    'transcendental

    subject'

    is

    essential

    for both

    knowledge

    and

    economy.

    Kant's

    transcenden

    talism

    presupposed

    the

    agglomeration

    of the

    cognitive

    labor of

    all

    historic

    humanity.

    Without this

    presupposition, Bulgakov argued,

    all individual

    acts

    of

    cognition

    or

    production

    would

    collapse,

    having

    nothing

    to

    hold

    them

    together.21

    Bulgakov

    advocated the

    personalistic approach

    developed by

    Russian

    philosophy:

    personality

    emerges

    within

    a

    community,

    personhood

    and sobornos f are correlative. The

    concept

    of transcen

    dentalism

    as

    sobornosf

    takes

    us,

    however,

    outside

    of

    Bulgakov's

    study

    and leads

    to

    the

    philosophy

    of

    prince Sergei

    Trubetskoi,

    who

    developed

    the

    notion of

    the conciliar

    consciousness

    [sobornoe

    soz

    nanie]

    of

    humanity,

    and

    to

    prince Evgenii

    Trubetskoi,

    his

    younger

    brother.

    Evgenii

    in

    his

    study

    of

    Kant and

    neo-Kantianism,

    applied

    the

    transcendental

    method

    itself

    as an

    immanent

    criterion

    for

    evaluation

    of their

    theories

    of

    knowledge.22

    TRUBETSKOI:TOWARDS

    THE TRUE

    GROUNDING

    OF

    TRANSCENDENTALISM

    Of all Puf 's

    critics of

    neo-Kantianism,

    Trubetskoi

    presented

    the

    most

    complete philosophical picture

    with his

    own

    epistemological

    vision,

    developed

    on

    the basis of

    his

    minute

    study

    of the

    Kantian

    theory

    of

    knowledge.

    The main thesis of Trubetskoi's

    study

    is that

    one

    cannot

    build

    philosophy

    on

    epistemology

    alone,

    because

    any

    theory

    of

    knowledge

    collapses

    without

    being

    rooted

    in

    ontology.

    Metaphysical presuppositions expelled

    by

    the

    philosopher's

    con

    scious

    mind

    sneak

    through

    the back door

    of

    the

    unconscious. Accord

    ing

    to

    Trubetskoi,

    this had

    happened

    to

    Kant

    and

    the

    neo-Kantians.

    They

    claimed

    to

    have

    produced

    a

    pure

    critical

    epistemology

    which

    was

    founded

    on

    a

    priori

    premises

    and

    which

    had

    transcendental

    validity. In the process, they uncritically adopted some metaphys

    ical

    presuppositions

    which rendered their theories

    self-contradictory

    and

    incomplete.23

    Trubetskoi

    set

    himself

    the

    task of

    laying

    these

    hidden

    premises

    bare,

    pointing

    out

    these

    contradictions,

    and

    thereby

    supplementing

    the

    Kantian

    transcendental method.

    This content downloaded from 194.27.240.181 on Thu, 9 Oct 2014 09:24:05 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Meerson_Put' against Logos_The Critique of Kant and Neo-Kantianism by Russian Religious Philosophers in the Beginning of the Twentieth Century_Weber

    11/20

    234

    MICHAEL

    A.

    MEERSON

    Trubetskoi pointed out three basic flaws inKant's epistemolog

    ical

    enterprise.

    First,

    by

    confusing

    the

    psychological

    and

    the

    logical

    in

    his

    premises,

    Kant

    undermined the foundation

    of

    his

    apriorism.

    Second,

    he

    automatically

    allowed

    for

    metaphysical presuppositions

    without

    taking

    into

    account

    their

    metaphysical

    nature.

    Third,

    having

    neglected

    the transition from

    the

    individual

    to

    the

    universal,

    he

    failed

    to

    provide

    his transcendental method

    -

    the

    most

    original

    contribution

    of

    his

    system

    -

    with

    secure

    axiomatic

    grounds.

    The confusion of the psychological and the logical had already

    occurred

    in

    the

    key

    part

    of Kant's

    system,

    where

    he

    postulated

    that

    space

    and

    time

    are a

    priori

    and

    purely

    subjective

    intuitions.

    Kant

    sought

    unconditional,

    pure

    knowledge,

    rather than

    a

    knowledge

    tainted

    by

    sense

    perception.

    According

    to

    Trubetskoi,

    Kant failed

    to

    find this

    knowledge

    precisely

    because it does

    not

    exist

    outside of

    our

    psychological

    experience.

    Our

    knowledge

    of human

    psychology,

    upon

    which Kant

    relied,

    is also

    empirical.

    As

    such,

    this

    knowledge

    is

    conditioned

    and mediated

    by

    the

    very

    forms of

    thought

    and

    per

    ception

    that

    Kant wanted

    to

    found

    upon

    it.

    For

    Trubetskoi,

    Kant

    ungroundedly

    turns

    the

    psychological

    limitation

    of

    our

    perception

    into

    the

    logical

    necessity

    for

    thought.

    Thus,

    Kant's

    assertion

    that

    space

    and time

    are a

    priori

    necessary

    conditions

    of

    sense-experience

    is

    based

    on

    psychological

    data

    on

    the

    organization

    of

    the human

    mind.

    From

    this

    postulate,

    Kant

    inferred the transcendental

    validity

    of

    space

    and time for all humans.

    According

    to

    Trubetskoi,

    this

    alone

    suffices

    to

    destroy

    Kant's

    proof

    of

    the

    a

    priori

    nature

    of

    our

    judgement concerning space and time. Furthermore, the limiting of

    the

    universal

    validity

    [obshcheznachimosf]

    of

    spatial

    and

    temporal

    forms

    to

    humans alone

    undermines

    the whole foundation

    for

    the

    a

    priori

    nature

    of

    mathematical

    judgements.24

    The

    metaphysical

    presuppositions

    of

    Kant's

    epistemology

    become

    especially

    apparent

    in

    his

    teaching

    on

    the

    thing-in-itself

    [Ding-an-sich].

    Following

    Vladimir Solov'ev's criticism

    of

    Kant,

    Trubetskoi

    finds Kant's

    sundering

    of

    reality

    into

    things-in-them

    selves and phenomena, on the one hand, and Kant's claim that we

    cannot

    know

    a

    thing-in-itself

    as

    both

    highly metaphysical

    and

    contra

    dictory.

    If

    we

    admit

    that

    a

    thing-in-itself

    exists,

    then

    we

    already

    know

    something

    about

    it.And Kant

    himself,

    according

    to

    Trubetskoi,

    knew

    a

    lot

    about

    it,

    if

    he

    postulated

    its

    unknowability.

    This

    unknowability

    This content downloaded from 194.27.240.181 on Thu, 9 Oct 2014 09:24:05 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Meerson_Put' against Logos_The Critique of Kant and Neo-Kantianism by Russian Religious Philosophers in the Beginning of the Twentieth Century_Weber

    12/20

    PUT

    AGAINST

    LOGOS

    235

    of the thing-in-itself presupposes its reality: for if the thing-in-itself

    were

    merely

    a

    product

    of

    human

    thought

    or

    imagination

    it would

    be

    totally

    knowable. Kant

    often

    depicted

    the

    thing-in-itself

    as

    being

    correlative

    to

    phenomenon,

    and

    presented

    both

    as

    the

    two

    sides of

    one

    reality.

    Without

    noticing

    the obvious contradictio

    in

    adjecto,

    he

    even

    called the

    thing-in-itself

    'the

    appearing

    unknown.'25

    These contradictions

    stem

    from

    the

    disguised metaphysics

    of

    the

    Ding-an-sich

    concept

    itself. As

    Trubetskoi

    pointed

    out,

    for

    Kant

    the

    thing-in-itself

    is

    a

    concept

    on

    the border between the

    physical

    and

    the

    metaphysical,

    what

    he

    called

    a

    'frontier

    concept'

    of human

    rea

    son.

    Trubetskoi

    argued

    that the

    very

    affirmation of

    such

    a

    'frontier'

    implies

    a

    realm

    beyond

    it,

    the

    possibility

    of

    rising

    above the

    human

    view

    point

    and

    of

    judging

    it from the

    higher,

    absolute

    view

    point. 26

    In

    other

    words,

    in

    order

    to

    describe

    the

    physical

    world

    with

    any

    meta-language,

    one

    inevitably

    has

    to

    assume

    a

    metaphysical point

    of view. Kant's

    meta-language

    concept

    of

    the

    thing-in-itself

    is

    no

    exception.

    Trubetskoi also maintained that an

    epistemology

    that denies the

    possibility

    of

    knowing anything

    beyond

    phenomena

    is

    contradictory,

    because

    knowledge

    by

    its

    nature

    transcends

    the realm

    of

    phenomena:

    the

    cognition

    of

    phenomena

    reveals the

    truth

    that is

    super-phenom

    enal and

    super-psychological.

    This is

    true

    especially

    in

    the

    case

    of

    scientific

    knowledge,

    with which Kant and the neo-Kantians

    were

    particularly

    concerned.

    Astronomy,

    or

    physics

    study

    phenomena

    like

    galaxies

    or

    atomic

    particles

    which

    simply

    cannot

    appear

    to

    man

    and

    cannot become the objects of human experience.27

    Trubetskoi

    pointed

    out

    that

    metaphysical

    presuppositions

    become

    even more

    apparent

    in

    Kant's

    transcendental

    method.

    According

    to

    Kant,

    experience begins

    when

    /

    link in

    judgment

    my

    empirical

    con

    sciousness

    with 'consciousness

    in

    general'

    [Bewusstsein

    ?berhaupt].

    Trubetskoi

    insisted

    that

    'consciousness

    in

    general'

    is

    a

    metaphysical

    assumption

    which

    has

    no

    ground

    in

    Kant's

    theory,

    but

    without

    which

    Kant

    cannot

    make his

    system

    work. Kant

    uncritically

    assumed

    that

    all human

    beings

    have

    the

    same

    forms of

    thought

    and

    representa

    tion. He

    applied

    'my' categories

    to

    phenomena

    on

    the

    ground

    that

    the

    phenomena

    are

    'my'

    representations.

    But if

    phenomena

    are

    only

    'my' representations,

    T

    cannot

    presuppose

    that

    other

    people

    per

    ceive

    the

    same

    phenomena

    in

    the

    same

    way.

    Trubetskoi

    pointed

    out

    This content downloaded from 194.27.240.181 on Thu, 9 Oct 2014 09:24:05 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Meerson_Put' against Logos_The Critique of Kant and Neo-Kantianism by Russian Religious Philosophers in the Beginning of the Twentieth Century_Weber

    13/20

    236

    MICHAEL

    A.

    MEERSON

    that although Kant repeated 'we', and 'our' ?fur uns] unceasingly, his

    system

    provided

    no

    ground

    for the crucial transition

    from T

    to

    'we.

    '

    According

    to

    Trubetskoi,

    this is

    a

    major

    contradiction

    in

    Kant's

    key

    theory

    of

    'transcendental

    apperception.'28

    Trubetskoi

    maintains

    that

    Kant

    in

    his

    teaching

    on

    transcendental

    apperception

    actually

    arrived

    at

    absolute

    consciousness,

    but could

    not

    admit

    it

    because of his stand

    on

    metaphysics.

    Therefore

    his

    'I

    am' becomes the ultimate

    condi

    tion of

    our

    knowledge,

    and

    replaces

    the

    absolute,

    banished from his

    theory.

    The

    expelled

    absolute

    nevertheless

    comes

    back in dis

    guised

    form

    as

    human

    reason,

    held

    by

    Kant

    to

    be

    the

    lawgiver

    of

    nature. 29

    Trubetskoi

    saw

    the

    main

    tendencies of

    the neo-Kantian

    movement

    in

    the extension

    of Kant's

    struggle

    on

    two

    fronts,

    against psycholo

    gism

    and

    against

    metaphysics.

    He

    found

    both tendencies

    developed

    in

    the

    work

    of

    Hermann

    Cohen. Cohen narrowed Kant's

    goal

    to

    the

    epistemological

    task of

    explaining

    how

    knowledge

    is

    possible

    for

    science

    rather than

    for

    a

    psychological subject.

    Critical

    of

    Kant's

    continual confusion

    of

    the

    logical

    and the

    psychological,

    Cohen

    drove the

    theory

    of

    knowledge

    away

    from

    psychological premises

    to

    purely logical

    ground.

    If

    for Kant

    knowledge

    came

    from both

    sen

    sibility

    and

    reason,

    for Cohen

    thought

    did

    not

    depend

    on

    anything

    external

    to

    it,

    senses

    included.

    Pure

    thought

    contains

    the

    first

    prin

    ciple

    [Ursprung]

    of all

    knowledge.

    If

    Kant maintained that

    only

    the

    form of

    knowledge

    is

    a

    priori

    and that

    knowledge

    is

    the

    application

    of

    categories

    of

    thought

    to

    the

    data of

    senses,

    Cohen

    insisted that

    thought produces out of itself the givenness of data which is a part

    of the

    cognitive

    process.

    As

    a

    result,

    he

    arrived

    at

    a

    total

    rejection

    of

    sensibility

    as an

    independent

    source

    of

    knowledge.30

    Cohen's

    ideal

    that

    pure

    thought

    itself

    produces

    the

    object

    of

    its

    knowledge

    may

    give

    the

    wrong

    impression

    that

    he shares

    Hegelian

    pan-logicism.

    But

    resolutely

    rejecting

    all

    metaphysics,

    including

    Hegelian,

    Cohen

    turned his

    rational

    grounding

    of

    cognition

    into

    methodological

    concepts.

    In

    this

    system,

    which Trubetskoi

    called

    pan-methodism,

    Cohen

    recast

    all

    reality

    into method.

    Knowledge,

    which

    means

    for

    Cohen

    first

    of

    all

    scientific

    knowledge,

    does

    not

    intend

    to

    express

    any

    knowledge

    of

    reality

    ;

    it

    has

    exclusively

    method

    ical

    validity.

    With science

    deprived

    of

    empirical

    contact

    with

    reality,

    and

    its

    object

    transformed

    into science's

    own

    methodology,

    Cohen's

    This content downloaded from 194.27.240.181 on Thu, 9 Oct 2014 09:24:05 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Meerson_Put' against Logos_The Critique of Kant and Neo-Kantianism by Russian Religious Philosophers in the Beginning of the Twentieth Century_Weber

    14/20

    PUT

    AGAINST LOGOS

    237

    scientism

    destroys

    the

    very

    foundation

    of

    science.31

    Nevertheless,

    in

    reducing

    a

    posteriori

    to

    a

    priori

    elements,

    Cohen

    regressed

    from Kant

    and

    in

    fact

    destroyed

    the

    very

    a

    priori premises

    of

    his

    epistemology.

    As

    Trubetskoi

    demonstrated,

    Kant

    displayed

    the

    stable

    system

    of

    categories

    that condition

    as

    such and thus

    was

    independent

    of

    empir

    ical facts.

    For

    Cohen,

    categories

    themselves

    depended

    on

    any

    given

    science, and,

    consequently,

    on

    particular

    and

    changeable

    data. The

    a

    priori

    elements of

    thought

    are

    reduced

    to

    the

    hermeneutics of

    human

    hypothesis,

    which is

    necessarily

    empirically

    conditioned.

    The whole

    enterprise

    of transcendentalism comes to

    naught.32

    According

    to

    Trubetskoi,

    Heinrich

    Rickert,

    the

    head of the

    Freiburg

    School,

    understood

    better than

    Cohen

    the

    main

    difficulty

    of

    the

    epistemological

    issue:

    how

    to

    sail

    between the

    Scylla

    of

    psychologism

    and

    the

    Charybdis

    of

    metaphysics.

    Rickert admitted

    that

    the

    object

    of

    knowledge

    is

    independent

    of

    and

    even

    transcen

    dent

    to

    thought.

    Therefore

    in

    the

    act

    of

    knowing,

    cognizing

    thought

    reaches

    out

    for

    the

    transcendent.

    In

    order

    to

    do

    so,

    our

    thought

    has

    to

    conform with the transcendent object. The problem, inTrubetskoi's

    view,

    started

    at

    this

    point.

    Whereas

    Cohen,

    fleeing

    the

    'danger'

    of

    metaphysics, replaced

    being

    with

    methodology,

    Rickert,

    out

    of the

    same

    fear,

    replaced

    it

    with value. He

    maintained

    that

    the

    transcen

    dent

    of

    knowledge

    is

    not

    being,

    but rather

    the

    notion

    of

    transcendent

    value

    or

    transcendent

    norm-setting. 33

    Trubetskoi

    observed that

    Rickert invests this

    'transcendent value'

    with all the features of the

    absolute. The

    transcendent

    value,

    though

    a

    non-being,

    constitutes the

    logical

    and

    metaphysical ground

    of all

    being.

    Its

    metaphysical

    connotation

    is

    suggested by

    the

    epigraph

    from Plato's

    Republic

    that

    Rickert used for

    his

    main

    epistemological

    study.

    Plato's

    text

    says

    that the

    supreme

    good

    is that which itself

    is

    not

    essence,

    but which abides

    beyond

    essence,

    excelling

    it

    by

    importance

    and

    might,

    and

    that it

    supplies

    objects

    with

    their

    knowa

    bility.

    Trubetskoi

    maintained

    thatRickert's

    'transcendent

    value,'

    like

    Plato's

    idea of

    good,

    is

    super-subsistent;

    it

    abides

    beyond

    being,

    and

    grounds

    both

    being

    and

    knowledge.34

    For

    Rickert,

    any

    knowledge necessarily

    presupposes

    a

    super

    individual

    consciousness that

    transcends the limitations of

    any

    particular

    individual.

    As

    Trubetskoi

    maintained,

    this

    idea

    of Rickert's

    expresses

    the

    necessary ontological premises

    of

    knowledge,

    which

    This content downloaded from 194.27.240.181 on Thu, 9 Oct 2014 09:24:05 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Meerson_Put' against Logos_The Critique of Kant and Neo-Kantianism by Russian Religious Philosophers in the Beginning of the Twentieth Century_Weber

    15/20

    238

    MICHAEL

    A. MEERSON

    he nevertheless failed to develop. Out of fear ofmetaphysics, Rickert

    interpreted

    the

    super-individual

    consciousness

    as

    a

    methodological

    concept.

    This

    half-way

    acknowledgement

    of universal conscious

    ness

    aborts the

    transcendental

    method,

    thus

    rendering

    Rickert unable

    to

    complete

    his

    theory

    of

    knowledge. According

    to

    Trubetskoi,

    Rick

    ert

    postulated

    the

    unity

    of the immanent and

    the

    transcendent

    in

    knowledge,

    but

    admitted his

    inability

    to

    find

    for it

    an

    adequate

    philosophical

    expression,

    and

    stated

    that

    the

    unity

    of

    immanent

    and transcendent

    in

    knowledge

    is

    a

    miracle

    that

    one can

    ascertain

    but

    cannot

    explain. 35

    Having pointed

    out

    the flaws

    and

    limitations

    of

    the

    Kantian

    tran

    scendental

    method,

    Trubetskoi

    attempted

    to

    complete

    it

    and free

    it

    from

    inner

    contradictions.

    He

    appropriated

    as a

    lasting philo

    sophical

    discovery

    Rickert's

    thesis

    that

    there

    is

    no

    being

    without

    consciousness,

    and Cohen's thesis

    that all

    knowledge

    has

    a

    rational

    first

    principle

    as

    its

    foundation.36

    But

    he drew different

    conclusions,

    maintaining

    that

    the transcendental

    method

    implies

    the

    infinity

    of

    knowledge.

    He insists that our

    knowledge,

    limited as it

    is,

    can cover

    all

    ages

    because

    it is

    based

    on

    the

    super-temporal

    truth.

    Either

    every

    temporal

    event

    is

    immortalized

    in

    absolute

    consciousness,

    argued

    Trubetskoi,

    or

    our

    human

    knowledge

    of

    temporal

    events

    is

    deprived

    of

    any

    objective

    foundation.

    The

    absolute

    consciousness

    grounds

    the

    certainty

    of human

    knowledge,

    since

    only through

    the

    absolute

    can

    we

    recognize

    the universal and the transcendental

    common

    to

    all

    mankind.

    Trubetskoi

    emphasized

    that without

    it

    we

    cannot

    find

    any,

    even phenomenal knowledge, since the latter is knowledge as long

    as

    it

    has,

    according

    to

    Kant,

    the formal characteristic of absolute

    necessity

    and

    certainty. 31

    Trubetskoi

    explained

    the

    mechanism of

    human

    cognition

    in

    rela

    tionship

    with

    the

    absolute consciousness

    in

    his

    analysis

    of

    judgment

    which

    he

    pursued

    on

    the

    basis of

    Kant's and

    Rickert's

    investigations.

    He

    relies

    upon

    Rickert's

    discovery

    that

    in

    the

    act

    of

    judgment

    the

    truth

    binds

    as

    imperative

    a

    knowing subject.

    Trubetskoi

    gives

    back

    the

    ontological

    status to

    the

    binding

    truth

    that

    Rickert

    interprets

    in

    a

    methodological

    sense.

    According

    to

    Trubetskoi,

    the

    cognizing

    human

    subject

    must

    come

    to

    the

    consciousness

    of

    his otherness

    in

    relation

    to

    the

    absolute,

    because

    the

    essential

    law

    and

    form of

    our

    thought,

    its

    a

    priori,

    is

    that

    any

    judgment

    necessarily posits

    the

    abso

    This content downloaded from 194.27.240.181 on Thu, 9 Oct 2014 09:24:05 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Meerson_Put' against Logos_The Critique of Kant and Neo-Kantianism by Russian Religious Philosophers in the Beginning of the Twentieth Century_Weber

    16/20

    PUT AGAINST

    LOGOS

    239

    lute.

    In

    Trubetskoi's

    analysis, judgment

    is

    a

    triune

    act

    that consists

    of:

    1)

    the

    presupposition

    of

    the

    absolute,

    2)

    the

    positing

    of

    my

    self,

    'I,'

    as

    other,

    and

    3)

    the

    linking

    of these

    two

    together.

    Thus in

    every

    act

    of

    its

    consciousness,

    the

    self

    both

    affirms

    itself

    and

    goes

    out

    beyond

    itself. This

    means

    that

    every

    act

    of

    judgment

    presupposes

    also

    self-consciousness,

    not

    the

    self-consciousness

    of the

    absolute

    in

    the

    Hegelian

    sense,

    but the

    self-consciousness of

    a

    cognizing subject

    vis-?-vis the absolute.

    In

    other

    words,

    Trubetskoi

    affirmed the

    per

    sonalistic

    nature

    of

    every

    act

    of

    judgment,

    or

    cognition,

    the

    aspect

    which Kant had missed.

    My

    /

    think,

    contrary

    to

    Kant,

    is not

    only

    my

    representation,

    argued

    Trubetskoi,

    it

    also has

    my

    knowledge

    of myself

    which,

    as

    such,

    goes

    beyond

    subjective

    representation

    to

    the

    trans-subjective

    realm,

    since this

    act

    posits

    my

    self

    as a

    subsis

    tent

    subject, independent

    of

    any

    particular

    representations.

    Finally,

    it

    presupposes

    the

    linking

    of

    self's

    individual

    judgment

    with

    the

    transcendental

    validity,

    or

    with the

    absolute.

    In

    this

    way,

    Trubet

    skoi

    completes

    the

    transcendental

    method,

    discovered

    by

    Kant,

    and

    developed by neo-Kantians.38

    Conclusion

    Logos'

    activity,

    which

    provided

    the

    philosophical

    challenge

    of

    neo

    Kantianism,

    was a

    real

    blessing

    for Puf

    's authors. It

    required

    from

    them

    greater

    terminological precision,

    and

    confronted them with the

    contemporary

    philosophical

    issues. The

    polemics

    with

    Logos

    helped

    Puf

    to

    coin what

    eventually

    has

    become known

    as

    the

    specific

    legacy

    of

    Russian

    philosophy.

    Puf 's

    philosophical enterprise,

    aborted

    by

    the

    Bolshevik

    revolution,

    was

    carried

    out

    in

    emigration, mainly

    in

    Berdiaev's Paris

    journal

    also entitled

    Puf,

    and

    in

    the Paris

    'YMCA

    Press,'

    with

    Berdiaev

    as

    its director. Vasilii

    Zenkovskii

    (1881-1962)

    and

    Nikolai Losskii

    (1870-1965),

    each

    writing

    in

    emigration

    a

    history

    of

    Russian

    philosophy,

    contributed

    to

    Puf

    in

    Russia.39

    Puf 's

    polemics

    with neo-Kantians had

    an

    enduring

    influence

    on

    Russian

    thought.

    If

    Ern,

    who

    died

    in

    1917,

    and

    Evgenii

    Trubetskoi,

    who died in 1920,

    completed

    their

    dialogues

    with the neo-Kantians

    during

    their

    Puf

    years,

    Bulgakov

    carried it

    on

    in

    greater

    detail

    in

    his

    book

    The

    Tragedy

    of

    Philosophy,

    written in

    1920-21,

    and

    published

    in

    Russian

    only

    in

    1993.40

    In

    this

    book,

    he

    further

    developed

    Trubet

    skoi 's thesis

    on

    the

    absolute foundation of

    transcendentalism

    and

    his

    This content downloaded from 194.27.240.181 on Thu, 9 Oct 2014 09:24:05 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Meerson_Put' against Logos_The Critique of Kant and Neo-Kantianism by Russian Religious Philosophers in the Beginning of the Twentieth Century_Weber

    17/20

    240

    MICHAEL A. MEERSON

    analysis of the tripartite structure of the act of judgment. Berdiaev

    incorporated

    many

    of his

    findings

    from

    the

    polemical

    period

    into

    the

    subsequent

    development

    of

    his

    personalism.

    Both

    Berdiaev

    and

    Bulgakov adopted

    the

    key

    thesis of neo-Kantian

    philosophy,

    namely

    that there

    is

    no

    existence

    without

    consciousness,

    and

    transformed it

    into

    a

    cornerstone

    of

    personalism:

    since

    consciousness is

    personal,

    there is

    no

    impersonal

    being; being always

    has

    personhood

    as

    its

    ground.

    This later

    development

    of

    their

    thought

    takes

    us,

    however,

    outside

    the

    historical

    frame of Puf

    activity.

    The

    polemic

    with

    Logos

    which

    sought

    to

    integrate

    Russian

    thought

    into

    the

    international

    philosophical

    process

    contributed

    to

    this

    integration

    in

    a

    particular

    way.

    Thus

    Berdiaev

    and

    Bulgakov

    in

    the

    course

    of

    this

    polemic

    arrived

    at

    a

    criticism of

    neo-Kantianism similar

    to

    Bergson

    's

    philos

    ophy

    of life

    and

    to

    American

    pragmatism.

    However,

    Russian

    criti

    cism

    was

    highly

    original

    and

    was

    carried

    out

    within

    the

    framework

    of

    religious-philosophy

    which

    strove to

    achieve

    a

    new

    synthesis

    of

    the Eastern

    Orthodox

    religious

    tradition

    with the

    most

    sophisticated

    achievements of

    contemporary

    philosophy.

    While the Puf authors'

    immediate

    influence

    on

    the

    neo-Kantians

    was

    rather limited

    -

    they

    probably

    influenced

    Stepun

    alone

    -

    they

    articulated

    some

    of the inner

    logic

    of

    neo-Kantianism,

    and,

    in

    a

    way,

    predicted

    its

    consequent

    evolution toward

    ontology,

    even

    of

    a

    neo-Platonic

    leaning. According

    to

    Stepun,

    most

    of

    the

    Logos

    editors

    eventually

    abandoned the

    course

    of

    pure

    epistemology

    for

    metaphysics. Stepun

    and

    Hessen

    came

    to

    collaborate with

    Bulgakov,

    Berdiaev and other Russian Christian thinkers in Fedotov's Novyi

    Grad

    [New

    City]

    in

    Paris

    during

    the 1930s.

    Mehlis embraced

    romantic

    and

    mystical

    philosophy

    close

    to

    neo-Platonism.41 Richard

    Kroner,

    one

    of

    the

    most

    productive

    of

    Logos's

    editors,

    during

    his

    long

    philosophical

    career

    passed

    through

    almost all of the

    philosophical

    positions

    opposed

    to

    pure

    epistemology.

    He

    first

    judged

    theory

    of

    knowledge

    from the

    stand-point

    of

    a

    philosophy

    of life close

    to

    that

    of

    Bergson.

    Then he

    moved

    to

    neo-Hegelianism,

    reinterpreting

    Kant

    in

    the

    light

    of

    mystical ontology.

    After he left Nazi

    Germany

    for

    the

    United

    States,

    Kroner

    developed

    his

    philosophy

    of

    revelation,

    and

    in

    the

    last,

    American

    period,

    occupied

    himself

    mainly

    with

    religious

    philosophy.42

    Thus

    in

    the

    ironic

    recollection of

    Stepun,

    the

    warning

    of

    Windelband

    to

    his

    students,

    who had

    called their

    journal Logos

    This content downloaded from 194.27.240.181 on Thu, 9 Oct 2014 09:24:05 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Meerson_Put' against Logos_The Critique of Kant and Neo-Kantianism by Russian Religious Philosophers in the Beginning of the Twentieth Century_Weber

    18/20

    PUT

    AGAINST

    LOGOS

    241

    and its

    first

    issue

    Messiah,

    that

    if

    they

    continued the

    same

    path they

    would

    land

    with

    monks,

    rang

    true.43

    In

    his article

    on

    Ernst

    Cassirer,

    written

    in

    the late

    1920's,

    Alexei

    Losev

    (1893-1988)

    observed the

    unpredictable

    development

    of

    neo

    Kantianism

    toward

    ontology

    and

    metaphysics.

    Losev

    mentioned

    Hartmann,

    Natorp,

    and Cohn.

    In

    the second edition of

    his famous

    book

    on

    Plato,

    Natorp,

    one

    of the

    leading

    neo-Kantians,

    renounced

    his

    own

    Kantian rendition

    of

    Plato,

    and

    came

    to

    interpret

    him

    in

    the

    spirit

    of neo-Platonism.

    According

    to

    Losev,

    Natorp

    in

    his

    last work

    completely revises his epistemology in the light of neo-Platonic

    ontology.44

    Cohn moved toward

    Hegel.45

    For

    Losev

    these devel

    opments,

    as

    well

    as

    the

    philosophy

    of

    symbolic

    forms

    of

    Cassirer,

    signify

    the

    definite

    spilling

    over

    of neo-Kantianism

    beyond

    its

    own

    epistemological

    limits

    toward

    metaphysics

    and

    ontology.46

    Puf's

    authors

    anticipated,

    however,

    this

    development,

    in

    their

    polemics

    with

    Logos.

    NOTES

    1

    Cf.

    Sbornikpervyio

    Vladimire Solov'eve

    (Symposium

    I:On Vladimir

    Solov'?v),

    Moscow:

    Puf, 1911,

    Ot

    izdatel'stva,

    p.

    IL

    2

    Fedor

    Stepun:

    Byvshee

    i

    nesbyvsheesia,

    (The

    Fulfilled and

    Unfulfilled),

    Second

    Edition,

    Overseas Publications

    Interchange

    Ltd.,

    London,

    1990,

    Vol.

    I,

    pp.

    130

    1.

    The German

    edition of

    Logos

    was

    luckier than the Russian

    one.

    It

    survived

    World War

    I and lasted

    another

    decade until Nazis'

    coming

    to

    power.

    Cf.

    Logos

    (Internationale

    Zeitschrift

    f?r

    Philosophie

    der

    Kultur),

    Vol.

    1-22, Mohr,

    T?bingen,

    1910-1933.3

    Pis'ma S.

    N.

    Bulgakova

    k M. K.

    Morozovoi,

    Published

    by

    N.

    A.

    Struve,

    Vestnik

    Russkogo Khristianskogo

    Dvizheniia

    (Herald

    of the

    Russian Christian

    Movement).

    #144,1985,

    Vyp.I-II,

    p.

    123.

    4

    One

    can

    compare

    their VekhVs articles

    with

    Puf

    editorial

    manifesto,

    compiled

    by

    Berdiaev

    and

    Bulgakov

    in

    Sbornikpervy:

    O

    Vladimire Solovieve

    (First

    Com

    pilation:

    On

    Vladimir

    Solov'?v),

    Puf, Moscow,

    1911,

    p.

    1.

    5

    See

    content

    of

    Logos

    in Mikhail V.

    Bezrodnyj,

    'Zur Geschichte des

    russis

    chen

    Neukantianismus.

    Die

    Zeitschrift

    Logos

    und ihre Redakteure.'

    Zeitschrift

    ?r

    Slawistik

    37

    (1992), pp.

    503-505.

    6

    Stepun,

    ByvsAee..,

    pp.

    150,148.

    7 Vladimir Ern: Skovoroda, Put', Moscow, 1912,

    pp.

    1,2,17,22.

    8

    Vladimir

    Ern:

    Sochineniia,

    [Works],

    Izd.

    Pravda, Moscow, 1991,

    p.

    405.

    Ern

    wrote

    his Master's thesis

    on

    Rosmini's

    theory

    of

    knowledge

    and his

    Doctorate

    on

    the

    philosophy

    of

    Gioberti,

    and

    published

    both

    studies

    in Puf.

    9

    Vladimir

    Ern:

    Bor'ba

    za

    Logos

    (The

    Struggle

    for

    Logos),

    Puf, Moscow,

    1911.

    pp.

    73-75,84,91.

    As

    Stepun

    sums

    up

    Ern's

    polemics,

    In

    all his

    critique against

    This content downloaded from 194.27.240.181 on Thu, 9 Oct 2014 09:24:05 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Meerson_Put' against Logos_The Critique of Kant and Neo-Kantianism by Russian Religious Philosophers in the Beginning of the Twentieth Century_Weber

    19/20

    242

    MICHAEL A.

    MEERSON

    us,

    Logosists,

    Ern

    persistently

    was

    making

    the

    point

    that

    as

    advocates of

    scientific

    philosophy

    cut off from the Greek and Christian

    tradition,

    we

    ought

    not to

    have

    invoked the

    term

    sanctified

    in

    the

    Gospel

    and

    meaningful

    for the

    Orthodox

    Chris

    tian.

    Stepun:

    Byvshee...,

    I,

    p.

    258.

    10

    'Ot

    Kanta

    k

    Kruppu'

    (From

    Kant

    to

    Krupp),

    Sochineniia,

    pp.

    313-8.

    11

    'Sushchnosf

    nemetskogo fenomenalizma

    (The

    Essence

    of

    German

    Phenome

    nalism),

    Sochineniia,

    p.

    320.

    12

    Berdiaev,

    Filosofiia svobody, Smysl

    tvorchestva

    (The

    Philosophy

    of

    Freedom,

    The Sense

    of

    Creativity),

    Moscow:

    Pravda,

    1989,

    pp.

    15-8, 32,68-9.

    13

    Ibid.,

    pp.

    19,

    29,35-37,47,54,68-73.

    14

    Bulgakov,

    Filosofiia

    khoziastva

    (Philosophy

    of

    the

    Economy),

    Puf,

    Moscow,

    1912, p. 52.

    15

    Leo

    Lopatin,

    PolozhiteVnyie

    zadachi

    filosofii

    (The

    Positive Tasks

    of

    Philos

    ophy)

    Part.

    II,

    p.

    231.

    Bulgakov, Filosofiia...,

    pp.

    184-5.

    l?

    Ibid.,

    pp.

    101-2.

    17

    Ibid.,

    pp.

    99,102-3.

    18

    Ibid.,

    pp.

    95-6,100.

    19

    Ibid.,

    pp.

    53,116.

    20

    Nikolai

    Losskii,

    Vvedenie

    vfilosofiiu

    [Part I]

    Vvedenie

    v

    teoriiu

    znaniia

    [An

    introduction

    to

    Philosophy.

    Part I.

    An Introduction

    into the

    theory

    of

    knowledge].

    St.

    Petersburg,

    1911,

    pp.

    164,198-9, Ibid.,

    p.

    116.

    21

    Ibid.,

    pp.

    114-5,119-20.

    22 Prince

    Evgenii

    Trubetskoi,

    Metafizicheskie

    predpolozhenia poznania

    [The

    Metaphysical Presuppositions

    of

    Knowledge],

    Puf,

    Moscow,

    1917,

    p.

    4.

    23

    Ibid.,

    pp.

    i-ii.

    24

    Ibid.,

    pp.

    7,11,43-4. Cf.,

    Frederick

    Copleston,

    S. J.:

    A

    History

    of

    Philosophy,

    Image

    Books,

    New

    York, 1985,

    vol.

    VI,

    pp.

    238-9.

    25

    Trubetskoi refers

    to

    the

    first edition of Kritik

    der reinen

    Vernunft,

    Hartknoch,

    Riga,

    1781,

    pp.

    358,

    344;

    Metafizicheskie...,

    pp.

    118-23.

    26

    Ibid.,

    p.

    130.

    27

    Ibid.,

    pp.

    290,135.

    28

    Ibid.,

    pp.

    7,10,74,77,80,82.

    29

    Ibid., pp. 88, 76,74,131.30

    Trubetskoi refers

    to

    Cohen's

    Kants Theorie

    der

    Erfahrung,

    F.

    Dummlers

    Ver

    lagsbuchhandlung,

    Hartwitz und

    Gossmann,

    Berlin,

    1885,

    pp.

    216-217,

    and

    Logik

    der

    reinen

    Erkenntniss,

    B.

    Cassirer,

    Berlin, 1902,

    pp.

    67,

    129,

    Metafizicheskie...,

    pp.

    247,210-1,217,219,234.

    31

    Trubetskoi refers

    to

    Cohen's

    work Ethik

    der reinen

    Willens,

    B.

    Cassirer,

    Berlin,

    1904,1907,

    pp.

    330-3;

    446-7;

    Metafizicheskie...,

    pp.

    222,210,223-5,227.

    32

    Ibid.,

    p.

    231.

    33

    Trubetskoi

    discusses Rickert's

    two

    fundamental

    works,

    Zwei

    Wege

    d. Erken

    ntnisstheorie,

    (Kantstudien,

    B.XIV,

    vols.

    2

    u

    3),

    and

    Die

    Grenzen

    der

    natur

    wissenschaftlischen

    Begriffsbildung,

    J.

    C. B.

    Mohr,

    T?bingen

    u.

    Leipzig,

    1902.

    Metafizicheskie...,

    pp. 250,273,249,276.

    34

    Ibid.,

    pp.

    276,279.

    35

    Ibid.,

    pp.

    266-7,283,280.

    36

    Ibid.,

    pp.

    236,241,275.

    37

    Ibid.,

    pp.

    33,

    41,45-46.

    38

    Trubetskoi maintains that

    Kant's

    teaching

    on

    transcendental

    apperception

    This content downloaded from 194.27.240.181 on Thu, 9 Oct 2014 09:24:05 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Meerson_Put' against Logos_The Critique of Kant and Neo-Kantianism by Russian Religious Philosophers in the Beginning of the Twentieth Century_Weber

    20/20

    PUT AGAINST

    LOGOS

    243

    implies

    the

    distinction

    between

    the

    individual

    consciousness,

    or

    my

    'self,'

    and the

    universal

    consciousness,

    or

    the absolute.

    Ibid.,

    pp.

    251, 83,

    85-7.

    39

    Nikolai Losskii:

    Intuitivnaia

    filosofiia

    Bergsona {Bergson's

    intuitive

    Philos

    ophy),

    Puf,

    Moscow,

    1913.

    Zenkovskii

    wrote

    a

    two-volume

    study

    on

    Nikolai

    Gogol's

    religious

    views,

    announced

    by

    Puf

    for

    publication.

    The

    book,

    shortened

    and

    rewritten,

    appeared

    only

    in

    Paris

    YMCA-Press,

    Puf 's

    emigr?

    successor.

    40

    S.

    N.

    Bulgakov:

    Sochineniia

    v

    dvukh

    tomakh,

    vol.

    I,

    Filosofiia

    khoziaistva,

    Tragediia

    filosofii,

    Nauka, Moscow,

    1993.

    Prior

    to

    this,

    the

    book

    was

    published

    only

    in

    German

    translation,

    as

    Die

    Trag?die

    der

    Philosophie,

    Otto

    Reichl

    Verlag,

    Darmstadt

    1927.

    41

    Cf.

    Georg

    Mehlis,

    Einf?hrung

    in

    ein

    System

    der

    Religionsphilosophie,

    J. C.

    B. Mohr, T?bingen, 1917. Eng. Trans. The Quest for God; an Introduction to the

    Philosophy of Religion,

    Tr.

    by

    Gertrude

    Baker,

    Williams and

    Norgate,

    London,

    1927;

    Die

    deutsche

    Romantik, Rosi,

    M?nchen, 1922;

    Plotin,

    F.

    Frommann,

    Stuttgart,

    1924;

    Die

    Mystik

    in

    der F?lle ihrer

    Erscheinungsformen

    in

    allen

    Zeiten

    und

    Kulturen,

    F.

    Bruckmann, M?nchen,

    1927.

    42

    Richard

    Kroner,

    Das

    Problem

    der historischen

    Biologie,

    Gebruder Born

    traeger,

    Berlin, 1919;

    Von Kant

    bis

    Hegel,

    Mohr,

    Tubingen,

    vols.

    1-2, 1921-24;

    The

    primacy of

    Faith,

    The Macmillan

    company,

    New

    York, 1943;

    How

    do

    we

    know

    God?

    An

    Introduction

    to

    the

    Philosophy

    of

    Religion,

    Harper

    &

    brothers,

    NY

    &

    London, 1943;

    Culture

    and

    Faith,

    1951

    ;

    Speculation

    and Revelation in

    Modern

    Philosophy,

    Westminster

    Press,

    Philadelphia,

    1961.

    43

    Stepun,

    Byvshee...,

    p.

    175-176.

    44

    Paul

    Natorp:

    Piatos

    Ideenlehre,

    1st

    ed.,

    D?rr,

    Leipzig,

    1903;

    2nd ed.

    F.

    Meiner,

    Leipzig,

    1921;

    Die deutsche

    Philosophie

    der

    Gegenwart

    in

    Selbstdarstellungen,

    R.

    Schmidt.,

    Leipzig,

    1921.

    45

    Jonas Cohn:

    Theorie

    der

    Dialektik,

    F.

    Meiner,

    Leipzig,

    1923.

    46

    Alexei Losev: 'Teoriia

    mificheskogo myshleniia

    u

    E.

    Kassirera'

    (E.

    Cassirer's

    Theory

    of

    Mythical Thinking),

    Simvol

    (Zhurnal

    khristianskoi

    kul'tury

    pri

    slavian

    skoi biblioteke

    v

    Parizhe),

    30

    (1993),

    pp.

    311-312.

    1847 47

    Place

    N.W.

    Washington,

    DC

    20007

    USA