lenls2006 tokyo sumiyo nishiguchi: covert emotive modality is a monster 1 covert emotive modality is...

67
LENLS2006 Tokyo LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive M Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive M odality is a Monster odality is a Monster 1 Covert Emotive Covert Emotive Modality Is a Modality Is a Monster Monster Sumiyo Nishiguchi Sumiyo Nishiguchi Stony Brook University Stony Brook University Osaka University Osaka University [email protected] [email protected] Logic and Engineering of Natural Language Semantic s 2006 Tower Hall Funabori, Tokyo, June 5-6, 2006

Upload: ethan-fields

Post on 02-Jan-2016

215 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

LENLS2006 TokyoLENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a MSumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monsteronster

11

Covert Emotive Modality Is Covert Emotive Modality Is aa

MonsterMonsterSumiyo NishiguchiSumiyo NishiguchiStony Brook UniversityStony Brook University

Osaka UniversityOsaka [email protected]@ic.sunysb.edu

Logic and Engineering of Natural Language Semantics 2006

Tower Hall Funabori, Tokyo, June 5-6, 2006

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

2

Abstract

It has been argued that attitude reports shift reference of indexicals in the embedded clauses in some languages (Schlenker 1999, 2003; Anand and Nevins 2004).

I argue that implicit speaker attitudes on factive propositions are a context shifting operator which changes context parameters.

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

3

I base my argument on the following three mono-clausal constructions:

i) fake past

ii) fake present

iii) out-of-the-blue wide-scope taking also/too

N.B. I adapt the term `fake' from Iatridou (2000).

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

4

1. Fake past:

Surprise licenses non-past interpretations of the past tense (Teramura 1984) with negative presuppositions.

(1) Oh, it was here (all along).

(2) A, koko-ni {at-ta/#a-ru} (Japanese)Oh here-LOC be-PAST/be-PRES

`Oh, it was/is here'

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

5

2. Fake present: Tense in narratives alternates between past and presen

t (Klein 1994; Teramura 1984, among others). Alternation between past and present directs reade

rs to re-experience narratives (Soga 1983).

(3) Picchaa nage-ta. Ut-ta. Ichiro hashi-ru. Pitcher throw-PAST hit-PAST   Ichiro run-PRES

Oshii. Auto. sorry out

`The pitcher threw a ball. (Ichiro) hit it. Ichiro runs. Oh,  no. He is out.‘   (Japanese)

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

6

3. Wide-scope taking discourse initial too/mo

Speaker's sentiments license wide-scope focus particle mo ‘also/even’and too without explicit antecedents.

(4) It's nice here, too.

(5) Yo-mo huke-ta. (Japanese)

night-also pass-PAST

`It’s become late'

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

7

What is a Monster?

Monster =Def an operator on character which is a function from context to content/intension

Kaplan (1977): there is no monster

The indexicals, e.g., I, you, it; that, this; here, now, tomorrow, do not change the references

Schlenker (1999,2003) All attitude predicates are monsters

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

8

Monster supporters:

Schlenker (1999,2003): Attitude verbs quantify over contexts of thought or of speech. Attitude predicates are monsters that shift the references of indexicals.As evidence,

-Amharic first person pronoun shifts its reference into third person under attitude verbs (Schlenker 1999, 2003).

Anand and Nevins (2004)-In Zazaki, the verb vano (say) shifts indexicalsI, you, here and yesterday in its scope.

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

9

Limited evidence for a monster

All supporting arguments for monsters have been based on the indexical shift in embedded context under attitude predicates.

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

10

Mono-clausal factive sentences

The three constructions discussed in this paper are factive simple sentences, not embedded under attitude predicates, but temporal and world parameters shift.

I argue that speaker's emotive/bouletic (in view of what I want) and epistemic speculative modality (in view of what I know, Kratzer 1991) is a context shiftable operator.

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

11

Surprise, empathy and sentimentality affect temporal interpretations and satisfy presuppositions.

(6) MODAL(||φ||<<tc, wc, ac>, <ti, wi>>)

=|| (||φ||<<ti, wc, ac>, <ti, wi>>

(t: time, w: world, a: speaker, c: context, i: index)

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

12

Generalized quantifier

Covert modal functions as a determiner taking negative presupposition in the restrictor and overt predicate in the nuclear scope (Kratzer 1991; Berman 1991; von Fintel 1994; Ippolito 2003).

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

13

Organization of the paper

Sections 3 and 4 examine mono-clausal fake past and fake present sentences and show that modality distorts temporal interpretation.

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

14

Section 5 shows that emotive modality accommodates the presupposition of too, wide-scope taking mo/to/ye `also/too’ used out of the blue in Japanese, Korean and Chinese.

I argue that speaker‘s sentiments shift contexts so that presuppositions are satisfied.

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

15

1. Fake Past

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

16

The past tense marker can receive non-past interpretation when associated with discovery, fulfillment of expectation, recalling of a plan (Teramura 1984, among others) often as exclamatives.

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

17

Fake Past and Aktionsarten:Fake Past of Discovery

English:

Stative predicates

(7) Oh, it was here (all along).

* Eventive predicates

(8) Oh, the bus {#came/is coming}.

(NB: The terminology `fake' is taken from Iatridou (2000).)

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

18

Japanese/Korean:Stative predicates(9) A, koko-ni at-ta/#a-ru. (Japanese) Oh here-LOC be-PAST/be-PRES

`Oh, it was here‘(10)Chek-i yogi iss-ot-ne. (Korean)

book-NOM here be-PAST-EXC

`Oh, the was here'

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

19

Eventive predicates:

(11) Basu-ga ki-ta. (Japanese)

bus-NOM come-PAST

`The bus is coming‘

(12) Ya ush-la. (Russian)

I go-PAST

`I am leaving‘

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

20

The past tense refers to present, not simple past

(13)# Oh, the book was here. But it is not here anymore.

(14) # A, shinbun-ga koko-ni at-ta. Oh newspaper-Nom here-Loc be-Past

Demo ima-wa mo nai.but now-Top already Neg

`Oh, the newspaper was here. But it's not here anymore'

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

21

Fake past of remembrance

(15) What was your name? (Teramura 1982)

(16) Where did you live?

(17) Onamae-wa nan-deshi-ta-ka. Name-TOP what-HON-PAST-Q

`What was your name ?’

(18) Osumai-wa dochira-deshi-ta-ka-ne. residence-TOP where-HON-PAST-Q-PAR

`Where did you live?’

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

22

Mismatched temporal adverbials

Japanese:(19) Asu-wa Maria-no tanjobi-dat-ta.

tomorrow-Top Maria-GEN birthday-be-PAST`Tomorrow is Maria's birthday‘

Mandarin:

(20) Mintian you-le wanyan. tomorrow have-PERF party`I had a party tomorrow'

English:(21) There was a party tomorrow.

Antecedent of counterfactuals can (Ippolito 2003)(22) If it rained tomorrow, I would go shopping.

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

23

Then,

Tense is a shiftable indexical. What shifts tense?

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

24

Implicit attitude is a monsterous function that changes a context parameter

(23) fake(|| past φ||<tc, wc, ac, hc>, <ti,wi>)

=||past φ||<ti, wc, sc, hc>,<ti,wi>

(t=time, w=world, a=speaker, h=hearer, c=context, i=index, ti < tc, c=<wc, tc, ac>, i=<wi, ti>)

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

25

In the framework of the double index system (Lewis 1980), the ordinary past tense morphology shifts the temporal index into the prior time:

||present φ|| ||<tc, wc, sc, hc>, <tc,wc>

||past φ||<tc, wc, sc, hc>, <ti,wi>

||past φ||=1 iff there is time ti prior to the utterance time tc

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

26

Fake tense operator:

(24) Where c=<wc, tc, ac>, i=<wi, ti>,

ti is prior to tc, c: Dc=Ds×De, s: Ds=Dw×Dt

Fake: ((c×s)→t) →((c×s)→t)

Fake (||φ||<c, i>)=1 iff ||φ||<c[ti/tc], i>=1

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

27

Necessary condition for fake past interpretation: surprise

Speaker's surprise due to negative presupposition causes fake past interpretation in simple sentences.

(25) (Nai-to omotte-i-ta-ra,) at-ta.NEG-COMP think-be-PAST-then be-PAST

`It was here (surprisingly).'

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

28

Without surprise, the fake past interpretation cannot be obtained.

(1)-(22) would only refer to the past state or events.

(26) Hon-ga at-ta.

book-NOM be-PAST

`The book was (=used to be) here’

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

29

Or, the speaker’s expectation is realized

(27) (Kuru-to omotte-i-ta basu-ga yappari) ki-ta. come-COMP think be-PAST bus-NOM as I expected come-PAST

`The bus is coming (as expected)’ The speaker doubted or has not been sure if p. The common ground contains both p worlds and

non-p worlds Fake past assertions disambiguates the actual w

orld (cf. Stalnaker 2004)

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

30

The data set is incomplete before the utterance (Veltman 1981)

The speaker does not know enough data but expects that ``the book is not here’’ ``the bus is coming’’ ``tomorrow is not Mary’s birthday’’

The data set becomes complete by seeing the facts or remembering the facts

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

31

Exp: Expectation function based on the available data

(28) Expa(wi)(ti)||φ||wi,tiΛExpa(wc)(tc)||φ||wc,tc

ΛKnowa (wc)(tc)||φ||wc,tc

(29) Expa(wi)(ti)||~φ||wi,tiΛExpa(wc)(tc)||φ||wc,tc ΛKnowa(wc)(tc)||φ||wc,tc

(ti<tc, tc: utterance time, wc: actual world)

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

32

Unaccusativity: Verb Classes of Fake Past

Fake past predicates are mostly limited to unaccusative verbs such as be, exist, and come (cf. Kusumoto 2001; Ogihara 2004 for relative clauses).

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

33

Unaccusativity test

VP internal numerals associate with the surface subject (Miyagawa 2004):

(30)Honi-ga [VPtsukue-no ue-ni ti ni-satsu at]-ta.

book-NOM desk-GEN up-LOC 2-CL be-PAST

`There were two books on the desk’

(31)Basu-ga [VP ekimae-ni ti ni-dai ki]-ta.

bus-NOM station-front-LOC 2-CL come-PAST

`Two buses came in front of the station’

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

34

(32) A, warat-ta.

oh smile-Past

`Oh, (the baby) is smiling’

(32)’ A, [gakuseii-ga butai-de ti san-nin warat]-ta. oh student-NOM stage-LOC 3-CL smile-PAST

`Oh, the three students laughed on the stage’

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

35

(33) Shimat-t-a.

close-PAST-be

`Oh, no‘

(33)’ *Gakuseii-ga mae-de ti san-nin shimat-ta. st

udent-NOM front-LOC 3-CL close-PAST

`The three students made a mistake in front’

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

36

Adjectives (Individual-Level)

(34) Yo-kat-ta.

good-be-PAST

`Thanks goodness' (when a lost wallet was returned with money)

(35) (While I expected it to be blue) Kiiro-kat-ta.

yellow-be-PAST

`It is yellow'

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

37

Conversational Backgrounds:

1. Speculative epistemic necessity/possibility:

must/probably/might ¬φ

2. Stereotypical conversational background (in view of the normal course of events)

For all w, w’ W, for any A⊆P(W): w≤∊ Aw’iff {p:p A ∊ and w’ p} ⊆{p:p A and w p} ∊ ∊ ∊ (Kratzer1991)

3. Bouletic modality (in view of what I want):

φworlds are ranked higher than ¬ φ worlds

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

38

Modal base f: in view of the what I know:

(c×s)→((c×s)→ t )→ t) Ordering source g: in view of normal course of event

s

(c×s)→((c×s)→ t )→ t) Ordering source h: in view of what I want:

(c×s)→((c×s)→t )→t)

Where Ds=Dw×Dt, Dc=Ds×De

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

39

(36) φ

h: ordering source-bouletic

g: ordering source - stereotypical

MODAL f: modal base – speculative modal

(cf. Kratzer 1991; von Fintel and Iatridou 2005)

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

40

(37) ||fake (past)|| (wc)(f)(g)(h)(||φ||)

1 if wcmaxg(wi)(f (wi) ) Λwcmaxh(wi)(f (wi) ) : ||φ||(wc)=1,

||past||(wc)(f)(g)(||φ||), otherwise.

Where for a given strict partial order <p on worlds, define the selection function maxp that selects the set of <p -best worlds from any set X of worlds:

X W: maxp(X)={wX: ¬ w'X: w'<p w}

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

41

Restrictive quantification

Modal scopes over due to its quantificational force (Lewis 1968, 1973; Kripke 1972). Modal takes the presupposition as its restrictor, and the assertion in its nuclear scope (Berman 1991; von Fintel 1994; Heim 1982; Diesing 1992).

(38) MODAL [λi. [|¬φ|]i] [λi.[|φ|]i] determiner restrictor nuclear scope

[surprisingly] [while expecting ¬φ ] [φ is true]

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

42

Negative presupposition as cataphora

(39)

MODAL P 1

MODAL not it2 MODAL P1 VP2

<MODAL> <not it2> bus come

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

43

2. Fake Present

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

44

Narrative Present Narratives would freely alternate tense betw

een past and present when storytelling as in (40) (Klein 1994; Mikami 1953; Nara 2001, among others).

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

45

(40) Kocho-wa usuhige-no aru iro-no kuroi me-no okina principal-TOP mustache-GEN be color-GEN black eye-GEN big tanuki-no-yona otoko-de a-ru. Yani mottaibet-te-i-ta.badger-GEN-like man-be-PRES Terribly pompous-be-PAST`The principal was a dark complexioned man, with a whistery mustache and large eyes like a badger. He was pompous.'

(Soseki Natsume, Bocchan, quoted from Nara (2001), glossed by the author)

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

46

Fake present tense invites readers into a depicted world so that thereader experiences the story as if present (Soga 1983).

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

47

NARRATOR SAYSfunction and empathy The proposition is embedded under NARRATOR SA

YS function which shifts the context.

It is the empathy of both writer and reader which shifts the context parameter:

(41) NARRATOR SAYS(([|φ|]<tc, wc, sc, hc>, <ti, wi, si, hi>)=[|φ|] <ti, wi, si, hi> ,<ti, wi, si, hi>

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

48

3. Discourse Initial too/mo

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

49

Discourse Initial Too with Surprise

(42) He is nice. He is a linguist, too.

(43) It’s nice here, too.

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

50

Wide-scope Mo `also/even’ in Japanese Mo `also/too’, a focus marker or a quantifier-li

ke element (Kuroda 1969) in Japanese, can associate with the whole proposition (Numata 1986, 2000).

This mo takes wide scope over unaccusative predicates out of the blue without explicit antecedent that satisfies the presupposition. For example, (44) is usable without particular antecedent.

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

51

(44) Yo-mo huke-ta.night-also pass-Past

`It grew late‘

Semantically, mo takes wide scope.

LF: mo [ yo-<mo> huke-ta]also night pass-Past

`It grew late'

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

52

About mo

A particle attached to noun phrases in Japanese.

NP+mo1 `also’

(45) Ken-mo ki-ta. Ken-also come-Past

`Ken came, too'} }

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

53

Mo2 obtains the meaning of `even' when the NP is focused (Watanabe 2004).

(46) [Ken]F-mo ki-taKen-also come-Past`Ken came, too'

The `even' mo2 forms NPIs with indeterminates (wh-words) (Kuroda 1965; Watanabe 2004; cf. Lahiri 1998):

(47) Dare-mo ko-nai.who-mo & come-Neg`Nobody comes'} }

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

54

Mo3

(48)Haru-mo takenawa-ni nari-mashi-ta. spring-also peak-GOAL become-HON-PAST `T

he spring has reached its peak'

(Numata 2000: 172)

(49) Ko-no saifu-mo huruku-nat-ta.This-GEN wallet-also old-become-PAST

`This wallet has become old’

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

55

Mo evokes sentiments that a nominative case marker ga would not.

In (48), the speaker feels pleasant to find that spring has reached its peak.

In (49), the speaker feels touched to see her worn bag, remembering the past. Covert emotive, e.g., I’m glad that, happily, be touched with or I regret, is a monsterous function which satisfies the presupposition.

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

56

Korean to `also/even’

Korean to `also/even' has similar usage.

(50) Pom-to wat-ta.

spring-also come-PAST

`Spring came' (That's why I'm so sad)

To `also/even' demonstrates speaker's attitudes.

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

57

Sentence focus ye `also' in Mandarin(51) Qiutian ye lai-le.

fall also come-PERF

(In view of the foregoing events) `Fall came'

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

58

Numata (2000) claims that such mo (also/too) attenuates the strength of assertion by giving rise to fictitious presupposed events.

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

59

Speaker sentimental modality shifts the context Speaker’s sentimental modality

licenses too/mo3/to/ye shifts the context into a world in which the

presupposed events exist so that the presuppositions of too/mo3/to/ye are accommodated.

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

60

(50) MODALemotive(|| mo-φ||<tc, wc, sc, hc>, <ti, wi, si, hi>)

=|| mo-φ|| <ti, wi, sc, hc> ,<ti, wi, si, hi>

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

61

Unaccusativity

The predicates of this type of mo are either unaccusative verbs with ta `PAST’, or adjectives. E.g., huke-ta `have grown late’, owari-ni chikazu-i-ta `have neared the end’, takenawa-ni-naru `have reached the peak’, iro-ase-ta `have faded the color.’

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

62

Restrictive Quantification by Emotive Modality

Modality functions as a determiner which takes negative presupposition as the restrictor and the overt unaccusative VP in the nuclear scope (cf. Heim 1982; Berman 1991; von Fintel 1994).

The negative counterpart is a copy of the overt proposition, which is a sentential cataphora subordinated under negative modality (cf. Roberts 1996).

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

63

(51) TP

MODAL P VP

MODALbouletic presupposition

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

64

Modal also resembles psych-verbs such as surprise or affect in the argument structure. Emotive modal takes speaker as an experiencer and the event as the theme.

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

65

Speaker is an experiencer argument of psych-verbs (cf. Belletti and Rizzi 1988) (52) FocP

mo TP

DP T’

yo <mo> vP T

speaker v’ ta

v

VP e

NP V

huke Mo adjoins to TP via internal merge and reprojects into t

he head of FocP (cf. Hornstein and Uriagereka 2002).

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

66

Conclusion

The three constructions,fake pastnarrative presentdiscourse initial mo/too

discussed in this paper show that covert emotive modality interacting with bouletic, epistemic and circumstantial modality shifts context parameters in simple sentence.Surprise, empathy and sentimentality affect temporal interpretations and satisfy presuppositions.

LENLS2006 Tokyo Sumiyo Nishiguchi: Covert Emotive Modality is a Monster

67

Conclusion

Implicit speaker attitudes shift context parameters. Modality shifts temporal interpretations, and contexts in order to satisfy presuppositions of a focus particle.