kant's philosophy of hope

Upload: xue-tian

Post on 07-Aug-2018

223 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/20/2019 Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    1/205

    Kant s Philosophy of H ope

  • 8/20/2019 Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    2/205

    American University Studies

    Series V

    Philosophy

    Vol. 103

    PETER LANG

    New York · San Francisco · Bern · Baltimore

    Frankfurt am Main · Berlin · Wien · Paris

  • 8/20/2019 Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    3/205

    Curtis H. Peters

    Kant s Philosophy of Hope

    PETER LANG

    New York · San Francisco · Bern · Baltimore

    Frankfurt am Main · Berlin · Wien · Paris

  • 8/20/2019 Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    4/205

    Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data

    Peters, Curtis H.

    Kant s philosophy of hope/ C urtis H. Peters.

    p.

      cm. — (American university studies. Series V, Philosophy; vol.

    103)

    Includes bibliographical references.

    Includes indexes.

    1.

      Hope. 2. Kant, Immanuel, 1724-18 04— Contributions in philosophy

    of hope . I. Title. II. Series.

    B2799 .H67P47 1993 193—dc20 90-35439

    ISBN 0-8204-1386-0 CIP

    ISSN 0739-6392

    The paper in this book meets the guidelines for permanence and durability of

    the Committee on Production Guidelines for Book Longevity of the

    Council on Library Resources.

    © Peter Lang Publishing, Inc., New York 1993

    All rights reserved.

    Reprint or reproduction, even partially, in all forms such as microfilm,

    xerography, microfiche, microcard, offset strictly prohibited.

    Printed in the United States of America.

  • 8/20/2019 Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    5/205

    TO THE MEMORY

    of

    ALBERT WILLIAM LEVI

    a friend who personified the very best in wisdom and virtue, whose

    death deprives this book of its most valued reader.

  • 8/20/2019 Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    6/205

  • 8/20/2019 Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    7/205

    ACKNOWLEDGMENTS

    The primary inspiration and assistance for this study were offered by a dis

    tinguished philosopher, Albert W illiam Levi. He is deserving of special credit for

    his insightfulness and for his helpful critique of my work . Steven S chwarzschild

    and Carl Wellman also provided generous and invaluable assistance in improving

    the analysis and argum entation. Unfortunately, the world has now lost the further

    contributions of Drs. Levi and Schwarzschild, and their presence will be sorely

    missed.

    Several librarians of Indiana University and of Indiana University Southeast

    were helpful in enabling me to obtain books and articles.

    I wish to thank Juli Crecelius for her very able work in preparing the manu

    script, John Finnegan and Wayne Brown for their assistance on computer matters,

    and the editors at Peter Lang for their general assistance in improving this work.

    Noel Hutchings, a student assistant, helped with some time-consuming details.

    Finally, I express my great gratitude to my wife, Pam Peters, for her patient

    encouragement as well as for her very capable typing of earlier drafts and for her

    work on the index.

    The shortcomings of this work would have been far greater without the kind

    assistance of all these people.

  • 8/20/2019 Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    8/205

    Copyright permissions:

    Excerpts reprinted with the permission of Macmillan Publishing Company from ON

    HISTORY by Imm anuel Kant and edited by Lewis White Beck. Copyright ©1963 by Macmillan

    Publishing Company.

    Excerpts from Immanuel Kant, ANTHROPOLOGY FROM A PRAGMATIC POINT OF

    VIEW,  The  Hague: Martinus Nijhoff,1974. Reprinted by permission of Kluwer Academic

    Publishers.

      All

      rights reserved.

    Excerpts from RELIGIONS W ITHIN THE LIMITS O F REASON A LONE by Immanuel

    Kant. Copyright 1934 by Open Court Publishing Company. Copyright © 1960 by Harper and

    Brothers. Reprinted by permission of HarperCollins Publishers.

  • 8/20/2019 Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    9/205

    TABLE OF CONTENTS

    NOTE ON REFERENCES

      xiii

    PREFACE xv

    CHAPTER 1 INTROD UCTION 1

    Ho pe in the W estern Philosop hical and Theo logical Traditions 1

    Hope in the Traditions through the E ighteenth

    Century  1

    Hope in the Traditions of the Nineteenth and Twentieth

    Centuries  6

    Issues to be Treated in a Theo ry of Ho pe 12

    Preliminary Com ments on Ka nt's Theory of Hope 14

    Purp ose of this Study 16

    Notes 17

    CHAPTER 2 MO RALITY AS THE BASIS FOR HOPE

      27

    Morality and Hope in the  Critique of Pure Reason  27

    Hope and Happiness

      27

    Virtue as the Sufficient and Necessary Condition

    for the Hope for Happ iness  28

    Retributive Justice as the Basis for the Hope

    for Happiness

      32

    The Idea of a Moral World  33

    M orality and Hop e in the Ethical W ritings 40

    Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals

      40

  • 8/20/2019 Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    10/205

    Critique of Practical Reason

      43

    Metaphysics of Morals

      46

    Conclusion 47

    Kant's Three Arguments on the Hope for Happiness  47

    Commentary  53

    Remaining Difficulties  59

    Notes 63

    CHAPTER 3 HO PE AND RELIGION  75

    Hope and the Natu re of K ant's Philosophy of Religion 75

    Hope and the First Attempts at Critical Philosophy

    of Religion: The

      Critique of Pure Reason

      and the

      Critique

    of Practical Reason

      78

    Hope and the Developed Philosophy of Religion:

    Religion within the Limits of Reason Alone  79

    Hope and the Highest Good Reaffirmed: the

    'Preface' to the First Edition

      81

    Hope and a Person's Quest for Virtue: Book I

      82

    The Ideal of Moral Perfection: Book II

      87

    The Ideal of an Ethical Comm onwealth: Books III and TV . . . .  92

    The

      Opus Postumum

      97

    Conclusion 99

    The Argum ents for the Ideals of Mo ral Perfection

    and an Ethical Commonwealth

      99

    Commentary and Remaining Difficulties  103

    Notes 107

    CHAPTER 4 HOPE AND HISTORY: WHAT MAY MANKIND

    HOPE?

      115

    Th e Concept of Man kind 116

    Hope and the Philoso phy of History 117

    The Ideal Polity 125

  • 8/20/2019 Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    11/205

    Conclusion 127

    Kant's Position: Philosophy of History as an Analogue

    to Individual Hope

      127

    Commentary and Criticism

      130

    Notes 136

    CHAPTER 5 CONCLUSION  141

    A General Description of K ant's Views on Hop e 141

    An Evaluation of K an t's Position on Hope 148

    Notes 166

    SELECTED BIBLIOGRAPHY  171

    INDEX  185

  • 8/20/2019 Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    12/205

  • 8/20/2019 Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    13/205

    NOTE ON REFEREN ES

    Quotations are from published English translations of Kant's works unless

    none are available. I do not always agree with the translations and in those cases

    point this out. Interpretations are based upon the German text. In the footnotes the

    page reference to the Akademie  edition are given in parentheses following the p age

    number of the English translation.

    The following abbreviated forms are used in footnotes:

    CPR

    Immanuel Kant,

      Critique of Pure Reason,

      trans. Norman

    Kemp Smith (New York: St. Martin's Press, 1965).

    CPrR

    Immanuel Kant,

      Critique of Practical Reason,

      trans.

    Lewis White Beck (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1956).

    Foundations

    Immanuel Kant,  Foundations of the Metaphysics of

    Morals,

      trans. Lewis White Beck (Indianapolis:

    Bobbs-Merrill, 1959).

    KGS Immanuel Kant,  Kant s Gesam melte S chriften,  Akademie

    Au sgabe , 28 vols. (Berlin: W alter de Gruyter, 1902- ).

    Religion Immanuel Kant,  Religion within the Limits of Reason

    Alone,

      trans. Th. Greene and H. G. Hudson (New York:

    Harper Row , 1960).

  • 8/20/2019 Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    14/205

  • 8/20/2019 Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    15/205

    PREF CE

    A person might legitimately wonder whether Kant really did offer a phi-

    losophy of

     hope.

    One of the purposes of this study is to show that it was Kant's

    intent to develop such a theory and that his writings do present a completed theory.

    His interest in hope and his desire to answer the question, 'What may I hope?' are

    relatively easy to document. Our argument that he did complete a philosophy of

    hope takes the form first of outlining the issues that a complete theory would have

    to address. This is done in chapter 1. Then, in chapters 2 through 5, we show

    how Kant's theory speaks to each of these issues in careful and extensive terms

    consistent with his critical philosophy as a whole. Indeed, his theory of hope can

    be seen as an integral part of his general critical philosophy.

    Chapter 1 also introduces the general argument by reviewing some of the

    major philosophical and theological perspectives on hope in the Western tradition

    to the present. This review is not, however, necessary to the argument of this

    book, and the reader could understand K ant's theory without examining this review.

    Because Kant developed portions of his philosophy of hope in various parts

    of his written works, we have first addressed the features of his theory of hope

    which appear in his writings on moral philosophy (chapter 2), then those features

    developed in his writings on philosophy of religion (chapter 3) and finally those

    presented in his works on political philosophy and philosophy of history (chapter

    4).

    Chapter  summarizes the features and claims of Kant's philosophy of hope.

    It also includes a critical assessment of this philosophy as well as responses to

    several of his critics.

  • 8/20/2019 Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    16/205

  • 8/20/2019 Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    17/205

    Chapter 1

    INTRODUCTION

    Hope has been a topic of theoretical interest for several prominent Western

    philosophers and theologians, and this interest has continued up to the present day.

    Most recently, some theologians have developed what is referred to as the theology

    of

     hope,

    and their work

     h s

     aroused widespread interest.

    1

    One of the most extensive and profound positions

     on

     hope that has ever been

    developed was created by Immanuel Kant in an age of widespread hopefulness.

    Although it has not been generally recognized that Kant had a theory of hope or a

    philosophy of hope, this is a shortcoming which the present study is designed to

    rectify.

    Kant's position on this important topic cut across his moral philosophy, his

    philosophy of religion, and his philosophy of history in a way that also provided a

    special unity to these diverse areas.

    2

      In this introductory chapter historical

    background is provided through a survey of some of the work which other philos-

    ophers and theologians have contributed on the theme of hope. This chapter also

    includes a description of the issues which a fully developed theory of hope would

    have to address as well as some preliminary remarks on Kant's theory

     itself

    Hope in the Western Philosophical and Theological Traditions

    3

    Hope in the Traditions through the ighteenth Century*

    Even a brief sampling of representative thinkers reveals that hope has been

    described in a wide variety of ways. Some have considered it to be an emotion and

    others a rational activity. Some have judged it a virtue but others a weakness or

  • 8/20/2019 Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    18/205

    2   Kant s Philosophy of Hope

    hand icap in mankind. Som e have thought it to be a natural pheno men on and others

    a special gift from God.

    In the Old and New Testaments hope was understood primarily as reliance

    and trust in God to com plete Go d's plan for humanity. Old Testament w riters used

    words associated with that concept to mean searching for refuge in God, trusting

    confidently in God to fulfill promises of blessing, and waiting patiently on God to

    accomplish this.

    5

      People can and should hope, because God is faithful to the promises

    God has made.

    The Apostle Paul meant by έ λ π ί ς (hope) waiting patiently, confidently, and

    joyfully for the resurrectio n of all believers and for the full adven t of the Kingdom of

    God.

    6

      He emphasized the primary evidence for the Christian's hop e-v iz., Jesus'

    resurrection; Go d's activity is itself the source and ground for hope.

    7

     Luke and Peter

    used the term to refer to their expectation of a new life in this world and of

    imm ortality in a future realm.

    8

    Neither Plato nor Aristotle, by contrast, associated έ λ π ί ς with religion, and both

    thought that hope could be detrimental. Plato understood it simply to be the

    expectation of a future p leasu re. He though t, in fact, that the experience of hop e itself

    carries with it a certain d egree of pleasure.

    9

      But he was chary of hu m ani ty's tendency

    to hope. He thought one often ho pes for what will not occur;

    10

      one of a human's

    foolish counselors, he com men ted, is hope easily led astray.

    11

      In several dialogues

    he wrote approvingly, however, of the hope for life after death.

    12

    Similarly, by

      ε λ ιά ς

      Aristotle meant the expectation or anticipation of an

    appealing future ex perience. He indicated that the human ability to hop e parallels the

    capacity to remem ber.

    13

      He suggested that people are led psychologically to think that

    what they hope for is particularly near at hand whereas what they fear is distant or

    nonexistent.

    14

      Aristotle, too, therefore, thought hope can mislead a person.

    Philo, Augustine, Aquinas, and Luther all laid great emphasis upon the value

    of hope . P eop le's capacity to hope is one of the most important things that distinguish

    them from other creatures, according to Philo. On the basis of the Septuagint version

    of Genesis

     4:26,

     he typified Enos (VJ1 ] 8 , a Hebrew word meaning man or human )

    as the representative of hope.

    15

      According to Philo, Eno s received this name because

    he placed his hope in God, and he alone is a true man who expects good things and

    rests firmly on comfortable [i.e., 'beneficial'] hopes.

    16

     Philo called ho pe  the nearest

  • 8/20/2019 Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    19/205

    Introduction  3

    and dearest possession of the human soul"

    17

     and the first thing "the creator sowed in

    the rich soil of the rational soul."'

    8

      He characterized hope as a longing for good things

    and as that which impels a person to important and worthy deeds; hope, he wrote, is

    "the fountainhead of the lives which w e lead."

    19

      Although hope directed toward such

    things as gain, glory, prizes, and happiness was valuable in his eyes since it leads

    people to accomplish good things, he maintained that the highest hope is that

    exemplified by Eno s~" a hop e and expectation of obtaining good things from the only

    bountiful God."

    20

      "No one," Philo wrote, "should be thought a man at all w ho does

    not set his hope on God."

    21

    Au gustine, too, exalted hope that is directed toward G od. He did not define a

    hum an in term s of hop e, but he did think hope is one of the three essential dim ensions

    in a godly life—the others being faith and love.

    22

      He held that Christian hope is

    directed toward full bliss in the next life-bliss that will attend being in the presence

    of God.

    23

      It is this hope that enable s a person to endure the sufferings of this life.

    24

    Since its object is the happiness of a future world, it is unaffected by any ind ication

    that life in this world is getting either better or worse.

    25

    Thom as Aquinas placed a similar importance on religious hope. He called it

    a "theological virtue" since it is central to the Christian life and since God is both its

    efficient cause and its object.

    26

      In his view all hope is directed toward happiness, but

    religiou s hope is aimed at a supernatu ral happ iness. The ultimate object of religious

    hope is the joy of union with God.

    27

      He distinguished hope from certain related

    phenomena on the grounds that its object is good (in contrast to fear), future (as

    distinct from joy), difficult (as opposed to desire), and possible (in contrast to

    despair).

    28

      Ho pe itself he characterized as the confident pu rsuit of such an object. He

    thought that it can be either appetitive (even animals can have simple hopes) or

    cognitive.

    29

      H op e-re ligi ou s h ope in particular—can lead a person to act in accordance

    with virtue and godliness.

    30

    Luther, too, thought that spiritual hope is of the highest value, but he

    emphasized its importance for helping a person to endure patiently the persecution

    and tribulation of this life. "To those who believe and have G od 's prom ise," he wrote,

    "this life is a wan dering in which they are sustained by the hope of a future and better

    life."

    31

      He defined hop e, in fact, as "spiritual courage."

    32

      He understood Christian

    hope to be directed not simply tow ard heavenly b liss in the sense of pleasu re but more

  • 8/20/2019 Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    20/205

    4

      Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    toward the full experience of righteousness and forgiveness in eternity.

    33

      Hope, he

    insisted, is prod uced by God ; it is a gift of mercy.

    34

    In marked contrast to these religious interpretations of hope, several phi

    losophers of the early m odern period, such as Hobbes, Locke, and Hu me, understood

    ho pe in more limited, psych ological terms . Hob bes thought that hop e is simply the

    com bination of an appetite for a particular object w ith the opinion that the object can

    be attained.

    35

      Lo cke associated hope with a particular kind of pleas ure:

    Hope is that pleasure in the mind, which everyone finds in

    himself,

      upon the thought of a probably future enjoyment of a thing

    which is apt to delight him.

    36

    And Hume described it as one of the passions which arises directly from the expe

    rience of pain or pleasure.

    37

      As the explanation for this emotion, he proposed the

    following:

    The mind by an  original  instinct tends to unite itself with the

    good, and to avoid the evil, tho' they be conceiv'd merely in idea, and

    be consider'd as to exist in any future time.

    38

    He described hope as the feeling which arises when a person thinks about any pro

    spective event that appea rs pleasureful and that is uncertain but not im possible.

    39

    Desca rtes and Spino za also described hop e in naturalistic, psychological term s,

    but Spinoza viewed it as a mo re comp lex phenom enon. Desca rtes held that hope is

    aroused when a desire for either the acquisition of

     a

     good or the remo val of

     an

     evil is

    accompanied by the probability that this can be accomplished.

    40

      "Hop e," Spinoza

    wrote, "is nothing but unsteady joy  [i.e., joy mixed with sorrow] arising from the

    image of a future or past thing about whose issues we are in doubt."

    41

      It is always

    mixed to som e extent w ith fear—fear that w hat is hoped for will not com e to

     pass.

      But

    since "all things hav e their necessary cause s, and m ust necessarily happ en as they do

    happen,"

    42

     hope is a sign of ignorance and wrong opinion.

    43

      The person wh o lives by

    reason eschews h ope bec ause he or she seeks to live by knowledge and will abide no

    doubt.

    Althoug h L eibniz devo ted virtually no attention specifically to the concept of

    hop e and nev er attempted to define it, he did in one dialogue ind icate its impo rtance,

    and he associated it closely with theodicy. He depicted Polidore, a learned man, as

  • 8/20/2019 Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    21/205

    Introduction

      5

    indifferent about life because he could see the imperfection in people and the falsity

    of the hope for immortality. But Theophile successfully convinced him that this

    world, its apparent evil and shortcomings notwithstanding, must be the best of all

    wo rlds. As a result Polidore wa s freed from his indifference and despair and becam e

    eager to engag e in purposeful activities.

    44

      Through this dialogue Leibniz suggested

    that a perso n w ho desp airs over the evil in this world loses hope as well as the will to

    engage in meaningful p ursuits. Without the confidence that everything in this world

    is properly ordered by a benev olent G od, there is no reason for a person to wo rk for

    good things now or to expect th em in a future life.

    In the eighteenth century there were a number of thinkers who, although they

    did not offer analyses of the nature of hope, did present elaborate descriptions of the

    goals and foundations for the hope for man kin d's developm ent in this world. The

    Abbe de Saint Pierre, Anne Robert Turgot, Gotthold Lessing, and Antoine-Nicolas

    de Condorcet all proposed optimistic views of humanity's future.

    45

      Saint-Pierre

    proposed several specific plans for reform in government, economics, finance, and

    education (the most important being his suggestion that a union of states be formed

    in which war would no longer be used to settle disputes), but underlying those

    proposals was his view that humanity is making progress in knowledge and govern

    ment. He held that the development of mankind pa rallels that of the individual and

    that hum anity is only now beginn ing to move beyond its infancy in the use of reason.

    In his view the biggest obstacles to progress are wars, superstition, and jealousy

    among the leaders of nations.

    46

    Turgot supported his optimism with an analysis of mankind's peculiar talents.

    He held that hum an ability to learn from new experience s coupled w ith the capacity

    to transmit knowledge to succeeding generations through language virtually insure

    future progress.

    47

    Less ing proclaimed that hum anity will assuredly progress. M ankind will ad

    vance particularly in virtue to the point where people will do what is right merely

    becau se it is right. Lessing thou ght that a per son 's reason, educability, and potential

    autonomy make this a certainty.

    48

      He wrote, "N o It will com e it will assuredly

    com e the time of perfecting, when m en .. .will do what is right becau se it

     is

     right."

    49

    De Condorcet's most important work,

      Sketch for a Historical Picture of the

    Progress of the Human Mind,  appeared in 1794~just one year after Kant's  Religion

  • 8/20/2019 Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    22/205

    6

      Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    within the Limits of Reason Alone

      (the central work for his views on hope) was

    published. De Cond orcet indicated what his particular "hopes" were for human

    development:

    Our hopes for the future condition of the human race can be

    subsumed under three important heads: the abolition of inequality

    between nations , the progress of equality within each nation, and the true

    perfection of mankind.

    50

    D e Condo rcet did not think of these goals as mere dreams or wishes; he fully expected

    that people would attain them since history reveals how far we have already pro

    gressed and since hum an rationality m akes further advancem ent a virtual certainty.

    51

    D e Condorcet tho ught of ho pe as a confident, rational expectation that is based upon

    our experience of the past and our understanding of humanity and the world. It looks

    forward to goals which mankind will attain within history.

    Hope in the Traditions of the Nineteenth and Twentieth Centuries

    "Hope" has received attention in the works of many figures o ver the past two

    cen turies. Th e selection of peop le wh o are referred to in this section constitutes only

    a sam pling, but it does includ e key figures and diverse view points.

    Neither Hegel nor Marx described his system in terms of hope, and both crit

    icized C hristian ho pe, but they did themselves attempt to show how various forms of

    developm ent will occur. Their systems embodied a degree of optimism . According

    to Hegel, the dynamic of dialectic allows the contradictions and inadequacies found

    in any particular "moment" or stage in the development of consciousness to be

    overcome (aufgehoben) through negation thereby making a new , more comprehensive

    stage possible. Dialectic enables developmen t and progress to occur. Bu t although

    there is a strain of hopefulness which runs throughout h is system, Heg el did severely

    criticize one particular type of ho pe -v iz., Christian hope. He considered it to be one

    of the forms of the "unhappy consciousn ess." This particular "mom ent" in the

    developm ent of consciousness is deeply bifurcated. Although it is a part of the

    changeab le, contingent world, yet it focuses upon a supposedly imm utable realm, and

    consequently it is divided w ithin itself.  This bifurcation can never be overcom e, so

    the one wh o hopes cannot find satisfaction. The consciousness remains opposed to

    itself and is, therefore, unhappy.

    52

  • 8/20/2019 Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    23/205

    Introduction

      7

    Marx proposed that dialectical interactions in the economic sphere together

    with consequent social conflicts move mankind toward new economic/social

    systems—and eventually to a society without class distinctions. An a dequate

    understan ding of the dynam ics of history could support this hop e for the future. But,

    like Hege l, he endeavored to make his system rigorous and scientific—with no p lace

    for dreams of fanciful projections. Thus he, too, was critical of religious hope. Such

    hope reveals peo ple's real distress and seeks

     to

     relieve it, but it presents m ere illusions

    about another world. A realistic, scientific approach to human prob lem s, he though t,

    require s that the false hope of religion be destroyed: "The abolition of religion a s the

    illusory  happin ess of the peo ple is required for their real happiness."

    53

    Several thinkers have grounded hop e in the advances of modern science. Julian

    Huxley h as argued that through evolution the biological world has progressed to the

    point that one of its products, humanity, can now consciously study and direct this

    evolutionary pro cess. "Our destiny," he claimed enthusiastically, "is to be the agent

    of the evolutionary process on this planet, the instrument for realizing new pos

    sibilities for its future."

    54

      H e even called for a new religion based on science and

    hum anism to bring hum anity to the full realization of its role as evolutionary agent.

    55

    He view ed the possibilities for further evolutionary p rogress to be virtually unlimited

    and therefore looked to the future witfi great hop e.

    Peirce argued that hope is actually a necessary prerequisite for the development

    of science. Rational inquiry, he thought, requires the prior assumption that the hum an

    com mu nity w ill m ove toward success in its intellectual pursuits.

    56

      He referred t o this

    postulation as the "hope in the unlimited continuance of intellectual activity" and

    described it as one of the three "sentiments" which are "indispensable requirements

    of logic."

    57

      In calling hop e a "sentiment," he m eant that it is a desire or expectation

    that does not have the rational support to be either belief or knowledge.

    58

      Bu t the

    hope for intellectual develo pm ent, although not based upon rational evidence , is the

    prerequisite for the use of reason in a scientific com m unity. Th is hope is as m uch die

    foundation for knowledge and science as religious hope might be for faith and

    religion.

    Like P eirce, Mill though t that hope could be beneficial, but he emp hasized its

    value for helping the individual to improve himself or herself.  He associated hope

    with the imagin ation, and he thoug ht that me only way to ju dg e the merit of ideas

  • 8/20/2019 Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    24/205

     

    Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    which a person develops in his or her imagination (for example, thoughts about an

    afterlife) is by their utility.

    59

      Although in one essay he wrote that he thought a person

    could live the richest and b est of lives without hope,

    60

     in a later writing h e argued tha t

    "the beneficial effect of such hope is far from trifling."

    61

      It allays the despondence

    that sets in when one sees,

    .. .the exertions and sacrifices of life culminating in the formation of a

    wise and noble mind, only to disappear from the world when the time

    has just arrived at which the world seems about to begin reaping the

    benefit of it. . . .The gain obtained in the increased inducement to

    cultivate the improvement of character up to the end of life is obvious

    without being specified.

    62

    Although their view s differ in important respects, Kierkegaard, Heidegger, and

    M arcel have described ho pe as an important dimension of being

     human.

      In two works

    which Kierkegaard published under pseudonyms  (Either/Or,  "edited by Victor Ere-

    mita," and

     Repe tition

      "by Constantine Con stantius"), he seemed to hold a low opinion

    of hope . The young aesthete of

      Either/Or,

      Part I, decried hope as a "faithless

    shipmaster" because it dissipates one's attention and thereby keeps a person from

    inventiveness and the artistic life-both of which are said to require disciplined

    attention.

    63

      Similarly, in

      Repetition

      hope is labeled "a charming maid that slips

    through the fingers" and "an alluring fruit."

    64

      It is much better to live fully in the

    present than to waste on e's life on daydream s. But Kierkegaard distinguished genuine

    religious (Christian) hope from this idle dreaming . The truly religious person does

    not simply live in or toward the future. In fact, this pe rso n's ho pe can only arise after

    all expectations and dreams for a better future are completely dashed and discarded.

    Christian hop e is "hope against hope."

    65

      It is hope in the eternal and develops only

    after a person realizes fully that he or she is finite and will die; it grows out of the

    deep anxiety that Kierkegaard described so fully.

    66

      In hope one relates expectantly

    to the possibility of the good—but in the eternal rather than the future, the infinite

    rather than the finite.

    67

    Heidegger emphasized that what is important w ith respect to hope is not to be

    found in its object. It is, rather, in what happen s to a person in the act of hoping :

    [Hope's] character as a mood lies primarily in hoping as

     hoping

    for something for oneself (Fiir-sich-erhoffen).  He who hopes takes

  • 8/20/2019 Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    25/205

    Introduction

    9

    himself w ith him into his hop e, as it were, and brings himself up against

    what he hopes for.

    68

    Hope is one of the existential dimensions of human life which reveals our basic

    temporality.

    M arcel laid stress on the great value of hop e. He distinguished h ope from

    particular wishes, desires, or dream s. He understood it to be , rather, a fundamental

    metaphysical perspective:

    Hope consists in asserting that there is at the heart of being,

    beyond all data, beyond all inventories and calculations, a mysterious

    principle which is in connivance with me, which cannot but will that

    wh ich I will, if wh at I will deserv es to be willed and is , in fact, w illed by

    the whole of my being.

    69

    M arcel thought m at hope is a basic openn ess to "being" and to its good future. It is

    not directed toward particular finite objects or goals, and it is not a shallow

    optimism.

    70

      It is, we m ight say, a basic faith throu gh w hich a person rejects the

    temp tation to despair and hold s to the conviction that reality is good.

    71

    From m, too, described ho pe as one of

     the

     intrinsic elem ents of the structure of

    life (the others being faith an d fortitude). W ithout hope a person begins to die.

    72

    Ho pe, he wrote, stands between passive w aiting and un realistic activism:

    It is like the crouched tiger, which will jump only when the

    mo me nt for jum ping has com e. Neither tired reformism nor

    pseud o-radical adven turism is an expression of ho pe . T o hope means to

    be ready at every moment for mat which is not yet born, and yet not

    bec om e desp erate if there is no birth in our lifetime.

    73

    He distinguished hope from optimism on the grounds that the optimist is not really

    engaged in the issues mat face mank ind. But the one who hopes has "faith in m an 's

    capacity to extricate himself from what seems the fatal w eb of circum stances that he

    has created."

    74

      The one who hop es takes the critical problem s that confront hum anity

    with utmost seriousness and works zealously, rationally, and realistically for their

    solution within history.

    75

      Ho pe is a state of being open and com mitted to life and

    growth.

    76

    On e might expect that other psychologists w ould hav e offered analyses of hope ,

  • 8/20/2019 Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    26/205

    10

    Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    but they have genera lly given it little attention. Freud, Jung , and Skinne r have

    disregarded the phenom enon almost entirely. How ever, one figure, Ezra Stotland, has

    attempted to develop a comp lete psychological theory governing ho pe. His proposal

    differs markedly from F rom m 's humanistic position. Stotland defined hope rather

    rigidly as "expectation of attaining a goal" and then, using a behavioristic model, he

    considered its nature and effectiveness as a motive.

    77

      On the basis of his analysis of

    a considerable amou nt of psychological research, he determined that increased impor

    tance of the goal and increased expectation of goal attainmen t leads to greate r though t

    and activity with regard to attaining the goal.

    78

      It is important to note that Sto tland's

    methods allow one to ascribe hope to many animals other than humans.

    Hermann C ohen and Martin Buber are among those who w rote of hope in terms

    of m ank ind's developm ent toward a better future. Both built upon concepts and ideals

    from th e Old Testam ent. According to Cohen, a Kant scholar who se views were very

    much influenced by K an t's w ritings, hope has reached its highest developm ent in the

    monotheism and advanced ethic of Judaism, for this hope is neither egoistic nor

    hedo nistic. It is, rather, a com mitm ent to the Messianic ideal of fulfillment and

    salvation for all mankind within history.

    79

      Messianic hope is directed toward a

    thoroughly ethical, human itarian ideal:

    The Messianic idea offers man the consolation, confidence, and

    guarantee that not m erely the chosen p eople but all nations w ill, at some

    future time, exist in harmo ny, as nature does today.

    80

    This hop e is grounded upon the "idea" of God

    81

     (as a practical postula te in the Kantian

    sense).

      Coh en adm itted that there is a place in religion for a "hope" for life beyon d

    death, but he considered it to be of secondary im portance, and he rejected traditional

    notions of imm ortality. Life beyond death is really one of the "secrets of God," he

    thought, and not at all central to faith the way messianic hope   is .

    82

    Buber looked to the Old Testament prophets as the great advocates of hope . He

    described their hop e as two-d imen sional: hope for the introduction of full jus tice in

    human relationships and hop e for G od 's establishment of the full Kingd om of God on

    earth. On these two dimensions, Buber wrote:

    I believe in both in one. Only in the building of the foundation of

    the former I myself take a hand, but the latter may already be there in all

  • 8/20/2019 Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    27/205

    Introduction

    11

    stillness when I awake some morning, or its storm may tear me from

    sleep. And bo th belong together, the "turning" and the "salvation," both

    belong together, God kn ow s how, I do not need to know it. That I call

    hope.

    83

    Bub er defined hope as "an outlook for a better hour" and thought that it develops in

    its most potent forms in those periods of special stress when "the personal need of

    each [individual] reveals the great need of m an."

    84

      Bub er though t that the Naz i era

    and the years w hen the "cold

     war

    was at its height were such periods.

    85

      Bu ber 's hope

    for mankind was in a completely just community in which people would live in full

    cooperation and mutual respect. He pointed to the "Kvuza" or "Village Com mu ne"

    of modern Israel as the place wh ere this is best exemplified at present. There wishful

    thinking has been destroyed by h arsh realities, but the openness of people to strive for

    an ever mo re improved and responsive socialism creates "in its stead a greater hope

    which is no longer emotionalism but sheer works."

    86

      In order to help hum anity as a

    wh ole to work toward full com mu nity, he urged the powerful peop les of the world to

    move away from ideology to its very opposite'-to a "Civilization of Dialogue" of

    which openness, cooperation, and respect would be the marks.

    87

    Ernst Bloch, a Marxist, was also primarily interested in the development of

    ma nkind. In his view it is hope itself which leads a person to strive to overcom e

    alienation and to create a better future. A hum an is a being w ith a Utopian in stinc t~a

    tendency to dream d reams, and therefore a person can reach beyond him self or herself

    to create that which is som ehow better. In his major wo rk,  Das Prinzip Hoffnung,

    Bloch analyzed several forms of consc iousness which em body hopefulness—from

    seemingly trivial "little daydream s" to profound ultimate ideals, and he showed how

    all of them illustrate the huma n drive to create the new and to attain fulfillment.

    88

    Hop e is not in vain, he argued, for the future is truly open. Everything is becom ing

    and includes its future possibilities.

    89

      He was concerned that the mo dern human

    underv alues hope and thereby stifles the primary impetus for progress. Bloch has,

    therefore, issued a call to people to live in hope. "The imp ortant thing is to learn the

    art of hoping," he announced at the outset of D a i

      Prinzip Hoffnung.

    90

      Through hope

    one can realize his or her potentiality and create a better world.

    91

    Jürgen M oltman n, wh o has been an impo rtant figure in the "theology of hope "

    m ovem ent, has offered a reinterpretation of Christian e schatology in the light of som e

  • 8/20/2019 Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    28/205

    12

      Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    of Ernst Bloc h's view s. M oltmann contended that primitive Christianity was thor

    oughly apocalyptic and eschatalogical, and he sought to help the Church today to

    reclaim a sense of urgency and hope. Christian hope yearns for the fullness of

    Chris t's resurrection—for the time when the decisively new will break into the present.

    It is not unrealistic, he argued, for it provides the only way to take seriously the

    possibilities of the present.

    92

      Th e future is included in the reality of God , and the

    Christ-event

     is

     an anticipa tion of the full expe rience of God that awa its the Christian.

    93

    M oltmann pro posed that the world be viewed as pregnant with possibility for whole

    ness and full life. Accord ingly , he has been an advo cate of political and social

    chang e, but he has not reduced hope to the striving for such changes in this w orld.

    94

    Issues to be Treated in a Theory of ope

    Th e preceding sketch reveals a num ber of questions which are associated with

    the concept of hop e. Th e various interpretations of the range of phenom ena w hich

    have been referred to under the word "hope" deal with one or more of the following

    questions: (1) W hat is the basic nature of hope? (2) W hat are the preconditions for

    hope ? (3) W hat justifies hop e? (4) W hat is the content or object of hop e? (5) What

    is the function or purpose of hope? (6) W hat is the identity of the one who hop es?

    These emerge as the questions which it is important for a developed theory of hope

    to answer.

    1.

      'What is the basic nature of

     hope?'  The re has been an obviou s divergence

    of opinion on hop e's gen eral character. It has been described, for exam ple, as a

    feeling, as a rational expectation, as a supernatural virtue, and as a form of

    imagination. The interpretations differ so widely that this question em erges as one

    of the most im portant to be addressed in a tiieory of hope.

    One of the most im portant aspects of this question concerns die degre e to which

    hope is rational. Plato, Aristotle, de Con dorcet, and Peirce, for examp le, associated

    hope far mo re closely with reason than did such thinkers as Hume, Spino za, Mill, or

    Kierkegaard. Th e degree to which hope is or is not rational affects the answers to

    other questions regarding hope--e.g., 'What justifies hope?'

    2.

      '

     Wh at are the preconditions for hopeT

      The type of hope of which Luther

  • 8/20/2019 Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    29/205

    Introduction

    13

    among others wrote required faith as a prerequisite. For Hobbes hope can only arise

    if

     a

     person feels an attraction for something. Leibniz implied that hope presupposes

    the adoption of a theodicy.  There is an important distinction which is relevant to the

    question of hope's preconditions—

    viz.,

     between the capability to hope and the right

    to the same. Some conditions might have to be fulfilled before a person is able to

    hope. For

     example,

     a

     person might

     be

     incapable of holding religious hope without a

    prior experience of faith. But preconditions might also be required before a person

    is entitled to hope. Thus it might be suggested that a person must show love before

    he or she has the right to hope for eternal

     bliss.

      A theory of hope should show what,

    if any, preconditions there are for hope.

    3.  'What justifies hopeT

      The question must first be asked whether hope can

    ever be justified. If hope is associated with error, as Spinoza, for example, claimed,

    or if it raises a person's expectations unrealistically, then hope might be something

    to guard against.

    If hope is at least partly rational, then the adequacy of specific reasons and

    evidence would be relevant to its possible justification in particular cases. This raises

    further questions about what would constitute adequate reasons and evidence as well

    as whether a person must be satisfied with slender rational support and consequent

    low probability in his or her hope. Special difficulties are raised by the use of

    revelation to justify some types of hope. It must then be asked whether revelation is

    a type of evidence which must be judged and evaluated on the same bases as other

    evidence or whether it

     is

     somehow above questioning—and

     perhaps

     even above reason

    so that it calls upon a person for a direct response of commitment.

    4.

      '

     What is the content or ob ject of hopeT

      Another

     issue

     of crucial importance

    concerns hope's content or object. For Plato and Hume hope was always aimed

    toward pleasure and for Aquinas toward happiness, but Luther specifically mentioned

    righteousness as hope's end and de Condorcet equality. Mill emphasized the hope for

    personal life after death. Cohen, Buber, and Bloch were among those who wrote of

    hope as directed toward a better life in this world for all people. For Marcel hope has

    no object at all but is simply openness toward the future.  The nature of hope's content

    or object is an important issue to be addressed in a theory of hope.

  • 8/20/2019 Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    30/205

    14

      Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    5. 'What is the function or purpose of hopeV

      Does hope serve a vital purpose

    for peop le that is not accomplished by anything else? Ho bbes, Lo cke , and Spinoza

    were am ong those wh o did not think it to be particularly important. Bu t Au gustine

    and Luther exalted hope on the grounds that it helps a person to endure suffering.

    Philo, Fromm , and Bloch were among those wh o thought that hope arouses a person

    to perform worthy

     deeds.

      For A ristotle hope w as the counterpart to memory—it opens

    the future for hum anity. And Heideg ger wrote that hope brings out an aspect of

    human temporality by transporting people into the future. Some thinkers,

     e.g.

      Mill,

    have attempted to justify hope on the basis of the purpose it can fulfill for m ankind.

    The question of hope's purpose or function is related to fundamental issues

    regarding the nature of hum anity. If a hum an is more than a com plex org anism, if a

    person is, for example, a creature whose ultimate end is oneness with God or whose

    future is open to his or her own shaping and molding, then perhaps hope can be the

    key to hum an fulfillment. If, by contrast, a perso n is a creatu re whose projections and

    desires are as likely to bring failure and grief as success, then hope has little or no

    purpose.

    6.

      'What is the identity of the one who hopesT

      In many cases the writers

    mentioned above seem ed to think of the individual as the subject of hope. A person ,

    they thought, hopes for his or her own eternal bliss, his or her own pleasureful

    experienc es, and the like. But som e of the writers,

     e.g.

     de Co ndorcet, Peirce, Cohen,

    Bub er, and Bloch, were more concerned about the developm ent of man kind. For

    them the subject of hop e is the hum an race. In several Old Testam ent passages on

    hop e, the subject is not so much an individual as it is Go d's peop le.

    A fully developed theory of hope should deal with all of these issues-with

    ho pe 's basic n ature, its preconditions, its justifications, its content, its function or

    purpose, and its subject. In Ch apter 5, we shall see that Kant offered a full theo ry of

    hop e in which he specified positions on each of these points.

    Preliminary Com ments on Kant s Theory of Hop e

    It is seldom realized just how important Kant considered the topic of hope to

    be.  He referred to its significance several times throug h a long portion of his

  • 8/20/2019 Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    31/205

    Introduction 15

    philosophical career, and he treated it and related themes repeatedly.

    In a famous passage from the

     Critique of Pure Reason

      (1781) he revealed his

    interest in the topic:

    All of the interests of m y reason, speculative as well as practical,

    com bine in the following questions:

    1.

      What can I know?

    2.

      W hat ought I do?

    3.  W hat may I hope?

    95

    In that work he included a brief answer to the third question.

    96

    In the years which follow ed, Kant gave attention to various aspects of the topic

    in "Idea for a Universal History from a Cosmopolitan P oint of View " (1784), "What

    is Enlightenment?" (1784),

     Critique ofPractical Reason  (1788), Critique of Judgment

    (1790),

     and "On the Failure of All Attempted Theo dicies" (1791).

    97

    His most important work on hope was  Religion within the Limits of Reason

    Alone

      (179 3). In a letter to C. F. Stäudlin, which accom panied a copy of the then

    newly published work, he indicated the close relationship which he saw between the

    book and the topic of hope:

    The plan I prescribed for myself a long time ago calls for an

    examination of the field of pure philosophy with a view to solving three

    problem s: (1) W hat can I know ? (metaphysics). (2) What ought I to do?

    (moral philosoph y). (3) W hat may I hope? (philosophy of religion). A

    fourth question ough t to follow, finally: Wh at is man? (anthropology, a

    subject on which I have lectured for over twenty years). W ith the

    enclosed work, Religion within the Limits [ofReason Alone], I have tried

    to comp lete the third part of my plan.

    98

    Th is book did not mark the end of Kan t's treatment of the topic. He dealt with

    aspects of it again in "Perpetual Peace" (1795), Metaphysics of Morals  (1797), and

    The Strife of Faculties

      (1798).

    99

    The re are certain aspects of Ka nt's philosophy as a whole which had an impor

    tant impact upon his theory of hope.  For exam ple, in his critical system Kant did not

    treat religion in any traditional sense. The results of the

     Critique of Pure Reason

      led

    him to speak of God as an

     a priori

      "Idea" of practical reason rather than as objective

    reality that can be known by theoretical reason. The primacy of ethics over religion

  • 8/20/2019 Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    32/205

    16  Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    required that piety be defined in terms of morality rather than of worship or of some

    other spiritual activity. As we shall see, Kant developed his theory of hope in ways

    that were consistent with these views.

    A second example of how Kant's general philosophy impacted his theory of

    hope can be seen in the effect that his general a priori methodology had upon his

    theory of hope. Kant relied on pure reason, rather than on either revelation or

    empirical evidence, for example, as the basis for many general truths. He also

    presented hope's objects or ideals as  a priori  "Ideas." As a consequence, his

    justification of hope is quite unlike any of those found in the views previously

    mentioned.

    A third example is brought out in Kant's philosophical anthropology. He

    distinguished strongly between the human as an individual and as a species ( Gat-

    tung ).

    m

      This distinction recurs frequently in Kant's writings and is crucial for his

    philosophy of religion and philosophy of history.

    101

      As an individual or person, a

    human is both a physiological creature driven by desires and a rational being who is

    responsible for developing his or her own knowledge and virtue. But human physio

    logical and rational traits are such that certain of one's objectives can be attained only

    by the species. Kant's theory of hope is largely individualistic in nature, but in

    Chapter 4 we shall see that in his philosophy of history he presented a social analogue

    to that

     theory.

      There it is mankind rather than the individual that is the subject.

    urpose of this Study

    The purpose of this study is twofold:  1) to offer an analysis and interpretation

    of Kant's views on hope and 2) to provide a critical evaluation of the same.

    A careful examination of the full range of Kant's views on hope is lacking in

    the literature. There is no work specifically devoted to the study of that theme in his

    philosophy. The topic is hardly touched upon in the journals. Although Kant

    associated hope closely with religion, such standard works on his philosophy of

    religion as those by W ebb and England leave it virtually unmentioned.

    102

     Much has

    been written, of course, about the  summum bonum, and several writers have exam

    ined Kant's views on the prospects of humanity's further historical development, but,

  • 8/20/2019 Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    33/205

    Introduction   17

    although the writings on these topics have often been very beneficial, they have

    generally provided interpretations that have not taken into consideration Kant's

    broader views on hope.

      Goldmann has offered a more extensive interpretation, but,

    although his views are interesting, he has distorted Kant's position.

    103

     A more helpful

    discussion of the topic is in a work by Despland, but his primary concern was not in

    the topic of hope.

    104

    We shall attempt to show that Kant's philosophy of hope is an interesting and

    well-developed theory.

     And it

     is

     noteworthy that

     his

     views

     are

     not merely

     a

     variation

    of "Enlightenment optimism." Although he wrote of reason, science, human potential,

    and history in ways that are reminiscent of Turgot, de Condorcet, Lessing, or Voltaire,

    the differences from these and other 18th-century thinkers are remarkable and put his

    views into the new form of a "critical theory." His philosophy of hope is unique and

    must be judged on its own merits.

    NOTES

    'The m ost prominent of the contemporary theologians dealing with hope have been Jürgen

    Moltmann, Wolfhart Pannenberg, and Johannes B. Metz.

    The "theology of hope" has evoked widespread interest. Theological symposia on the topic

    have been held at Chicago, Santa Barbara, and New York.

    Dialogue

     entitled its entire volume VII (1968)  The Fu ture of Mankind" and included several

    articles on the theology of hope in it.  The Lutheran Quarterly, vol. XXI, no. 1 (Feb., 1969) and

    Cross Currents, vol. XVIII, no. 3 (summ er, 1968) were completely devoted to the topic. The

     Cross

    Currents issue has been published in book form under the title, The Future of Hope, ed. Walter H .

    Capps (Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1970). For an introduction to the theology of hope movement,

    c/. Walter H. Capps, "Mapping the Hope Movement,"  The Future of Hope, pp . 1-49. Capps has

    further developed his overview in W alter H. Capps,

     Tim e Invades the Cathedral;  Tensions in the

    School of Hope (Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1972).

    ^To be sure, Kant did consider hope in works which are not normally associated with the

    three areas of his philosophy listed. For exam ple, he dealt with the topic rather extensively in the

    Critique

     of Pure Reason.

      But since this treatment was included in a section on moral philosophy,

    it will be considered in Chapter

     2.

      A portion of the Critique of Judgment deals with philosophy of

    history, so it is considered in Chapter 4.

    3

    In this section the views of only a sample of significant philosophers and theologians are

    presented. Special attention is paid to those figures whose importance for the history of thought is

    most widely acknowledged and who m ade significant contributions on the topic of hope. The

  • 8/20/2019 Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    34/205

    18

    Kant s Philosophy of Ho pe

    sample does reveal the diversity of the views that have been developed as well as the primary

    themes and problems that arise in connection with hope.

    The traditions are divided at the end of the eighteenth century because Kant developed his

    theory near the close of that century.

    'Severa l Hebrew words we associated with hope —the most important of which are iTD 3 ,

    Π Ο Γ Ο Γ Ρ , Π   1p , and~n\u . I n the Septuagint these and a few other words were occasionally translated

    by έ λ π ί ς and έ λ π ί ζ ε ι ν , but none was translated exclusively that way. riLO emphasizes trust or

    reliance, and it often connotes a condition in which a person feels at ease or secure. Cf. Psalms 22:5,

    26:1,

     37:3, Jeremiah 17:7, and Isaiah 32:9-10. Π Ό Π means searching for refuge or yearning for

    security.

      Cf.

     Psalms 2:12, 25:20, 71:1,141 :8, and Isaiah

     30:2.

      The primary meaning of ^Π   >  with

    3  is to wait expectantly for something or someone. Cf. Isaiah 42:4, Ezekiel 13:6, Psalms 33 :18 ,22 ,

    and 119:43, 74. Likewise,  Π   If

    7

      means to wait or look eagerly for something or someone.  Cf.

    Ge nesis 49 :18,Isa iah5 9:ll,and Jerem iah8 :15,1 3:16 ,6:19 . ~)3\U sometimes means to wait or yearn

    for.  Cf. Psalms 119:166, 10 4:27,145 :15, and 146:5.

    6

    C/.Galatians 5:5, Romans 5:2ff.,8:24f., 12:12,15:4,Ephesians 1:18,2:12, Philippians 1:20,

    and Titus 1:2, 2:13, 3:7.

    7

    I Corinthians 15:20-23, and Romans 4:17-21, 15:12-13.

    8

    In the book of

     Acts,

     Luke emphasized the central place that hope occupies in the Christian

    life. Jes us ' resurrection, he argued, has vindicated the hope that a Messiah would com e and that a

    life of glory is in store for all believers.   Cf. Acts 2:26, 23:6, 24:15, 26:6f., 28:20. In I Peter hope

    is the expectation of glory in this life and in the next.

      Cf

      I Peter 1:3,

     2 1;

     3:15.

    For a fuller treatment of hope in the Old and New Testaments, cf  Rudolf Bultmann and

    Karl

     H.

     Rengstorf, ' Ε λ ιά ς ,  έ λ π ί ζ π ,

    Theological Dictionary of the New Testament, 1964, Π ,

     517-

    35 ,

     and P. S. Minear, Hope,

    The Interpreter s D ictionary of the Bible,

     1962, Π , 640-43.

    'Plato,

     Philebus,

     36a-b.

     Cf.

     also

     Laches,

     198b. Plato 's most extensive treatment of hope and

    expectation is to be found in Philebus, esp . 36-40.

    m

    Ibid., 40a-b . It is worth noting that Plato thought the gods provided the virtuous person

    with correct expectations and the evil individual with incorrect ones.

    Plato,

     Timaeus,

     69d.

    On the question w hether hope is beneficial, there is an old Greek fable according to which

    Zeus gave hum anity a jar of good things, but the hu man's curiosity led to taking off the cover, and

    all the things escaped except hope. The fable concludes, And so it is that hope alone abides with

    men, promising to give us each of the other blessings that escaped.

    Babrius,

     #58. The translation

    is by Ben Edw in Perry in the Loeb Library edition (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press,

    1965), p. 75.

    n

    Cf  Plato, Phaedo, 63c, 64a, 67a-68b; Apology, 41c ; and Republic 331a.

    Aristotle,  Rhetoric,  Π , 12, 1389a 20f.; Π , 13, 1390a, 5ff.; and  De Memoria et

    Reminiscentia,

     1, 449b, 27f.

  • 8/20/2019 Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    35/205

    Introduction

    19

    Aristotle,

     Rhetoric,

     Π , 5,1383a  16ff.

    15

    The translated Septuagint version is:  To Seth a son was born, and he called his name

    Enos;

     he hoped to call on the name of the Lord God. In Quod Detenus Potion Insidiari Soleat,

    XXXVin,  138, Philo rendered the last part of this verse,

      He

     first hoped

     to

     call

     on

     the name

     of

     the

    Lord God. The Hebrew text in the Kittel edition may be translated, To Seth a son was born, and

    he called his name Enos; then man began to call on the name of the Lord.

    Just  as in  Philo's system Enos typified hope,  so  Enoch represented repentance  and

    improvement, and Noah symbolized justice. Philo, De Abrahamo HI, 17, and VI , 33.

    I6

    Philo, De Abrahamo, Π , 8. The translation is by F. H. Colson in the Loeb Library edition

    (Cam bridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1950), VI, 9. The phrase Colson translated as

    comfortable hopes is  έ λ π ίσ ι χ ρ η σ τ α ΐ ς .

    Ibid.

    18

    Philo,

     De

     Praemiis

     et Poenis,

     Π , 10. The translation is by F. H. Colson in the Loeb Library

    edition,

     Vin, 319.

    l9

    Ibid., Π , 11. The translation is by Colson in the Loeb Library edition, VHJ, 319.

    ^ h i l o ,

      Quod Detenus P otion Insidiari

     Soleat, XXXV HI, 138. The translation is by F. H.

    Colson and G. H. Whitaker in the Loeb Library edition, Π , 295.

    2l

    Philo,

     De

     Praemiis

     et

     Poenis,

     Π , 14. The

     translation

     is by

     Colson

     in the

     Loeb Library

    edition, VJU, 321.

    22

     Augustine,

     On

     Christian Doctrine, 1,37-40; E nchiridion, 1,3, andU, 8. The subtitle of the

    Enchiridion is On Faith, Hope, and Love. Augustine based his list of characteristics on I Cor.

    13:13.

    23

     Augu stine,

     Confessions,

     Book Thirteen, XIV, 15; City of God , XIX, 20.

    Augustine, C ity of God, XIX, 4:

     Confessions,

     Book Ten, XXVffl-XXIX, 39-40.

    R .  A.  Markus,  Saeculum: History  and  Society  in the  Theology  of St.  Augustine.

    (Cambridge: University Press, 1970), p.  166.

    ^Thom as Aquinas,

     Summa

     Theologica, Part Π  of Second Part, Q 17 , Arts. 1,5,6; Part I of

    Second Part, Q 62, Art. 3; De Virtutibus in  communi, 12. The other theological virtues are faith and

    love.

      Thom as also designated hope as one of the  four principal passions of the soul—the others

    being sadness, joy,

     and

     fear. Thom as Aquinas, De Veritate,

     Q

     26 ,

     Art. 5.

    ^Thom as A quinas, Summa Theologica, Part Π of Second

     Part,

     Q1 7, Arts. 2-4; De Virtutibus

    in communi, 12.

    28

    Thomas Aquinas, De

     Spe,

     1,

     ad 1.

    29

    Thomas A quinas,

     Summa Theologica,

     Part

     I of

     Second Part,

     Q 40,

     Arts.

     1-3;

     Part

     Π of

  • 8/20/2019 Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    36/205

    2

    Kant s Philosophy

      of

      Hope

    Second Part,

     Q

     18, Arts.

     1 and 4.

    ' When hope

      is

     given

     up, men

     rush headlong into

     sin, and are

      drawn away from good

    works. (Thomas Aquinas,  Summa Theologica, Part  Π of  Second Part,  Q 20, Art. 3.) The

    translation is

     by

     the Fathers of the Eng lish Dom inican Province

     in

     the Great Books of the W estern

    World edition (Chicago: Encyclopaedia Britannica, 1952), XX , 477.

    31

    Martin Luther,

      Lectures

     on

     Genesis, Chapters 45-50,

      trans. Paul

      D.

      Pahl,

     Vol. Vm,

    Luther s Works

     (St.

     Louis: Concordia Publishing House, 1966),

     p. 115.

      Cf. also

     a

     remark which

    Veit Dietrich attributed

     to

     Luther:

    Faith teaches that there

     is a

     resurrection of the dead

     on the

     Last Day. Then

    hope adds: Well, if that is really true, then let us stake all we have on it; and let us

    suffer whatever

     we

     must,

     if

      thereafter

      we

     shall become such great lords. (Martin

    Luther, What Luther Says, ed. Ewald Μ . Plass, Π (St. Louis: Concordia Publishing

    House, 1959), p.

     669.)

    32

    Luther, What Luther

     Says,

     Π , 6 68 .

    33

    Martin Luther, Lectures on Galatians,

     1535,

     trans. Jaroslav Pelikan, Vol. XXVII, Luther s

    Works (St. Louis: Concordia Publishing House, 1964), pp. 26ff.

    ^Luther, What Luther Says,

     Π ,

      668-669.

    Calvin gave hope somewhat less prominence that Luther,

     but he did

     think

     it an

     important

    aspect of the Christian life. Hope ,

     he

     thought, is

     an

     unshakable confidence that one will experience

    glory. Doubt can never be consistent with hope ; hope is virtual knowledge that blessing awaits one

    beyond

     death.

     Cf. John Calvin, Treatises in Defense of  the Reformed Faith, trans. Henry Beveridge

    (Grand Rapids: Wm . B. Eerdmans, 1958), Γ Π ,

     137f.

    35

    Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, Part I, Chapter VI (New York: E. P. Dutton, 1950), p. 43.

    ' 'John Locke, An

     Essay

     Concerning

     Human Understanding,

      Π , XX,

     9.

    David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, ΙΠ ,

     Π , DC

     (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1958), p.

    438.

      The other direct passions he listed are desire, aversion, grief, joy, fear, and volition.

    Ibid.

    Ibid,  p.

     439.

    • Rene Descartes, Passions of the Soul, Part Π , Art. LVm.

    'Spinoza,

     Ethics,

     Γ Π , Prop. XVIII,

     n. 2.

    42

    Baruch Spinoza, Spinoza s Short Treatise on God,

     Man,

     an d His

     Well-Being,

     trans.

     A.

     Wolf

    (New York: Russell

     &

     Russell, 1963),

     p.

     92.

    Ibid.

  • 8/20/2019 Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    37/205

    Introduction

    2 1

    This dialogue, which is without title, appears in Gottfried W ilhelm

     Leibniz,

     Philosophical

    Papers and Letters, ed . Leroy E. Loemker (Chicago: U niversity of Chicago Press, 1956), 1,332-38.

    Leibniz developed elaborate theological and metaphysical argumentation to support his theodicy,

    the most complete collection of which is his work entitled simply, Theodicy. But neither this book

    nor his other writings related to the topic contain specific discussion of hope.

    45

    Less sanguine about mankind's further development were such figures as Voltaire and

    Rousseau, but even they held that under certain conditions humanity could make great advances

    beyond its present conditions. Voltaire proposed that mankind would be able to expand know ledge

    greatly and live a much richer life if it could free itself from wars, prejudices, superstitions, bigotry,

    and fanaticism.  Cf. especially

     Essai sur

     les moeurs

     et l'esprit des

     nations

     et sur lesprincipauxfaits

    de l'histoire depuis Charlemagne jusqu'a Louis

     XIII,

     ed. Rene Pomeau (Paris: Gam ier, 1963).

    Rousseau, of course, claimed that the development of civilization had led to human regress, but even

    he proposed that humanity could com e to a much better state if all economic, social, and political

    inequalities could be eradicated. His Social Contract was a proposal for such a cond ition.  Cf. Jean

    Jacques Rousseau,  The Social Contract and Discourses, trans. G. D. H. Cole (New York: E. P.

    Dutton and C o., 1913).

    The question of ust how prominent

      optimism

    really was in the eighteenth century has been

    the topic of an extremely lively debate. Carl Becker characterized the age as an era of faith in

    human ability to build the Heavenly City on this earth through the full use of man kind's rational

    capacity to comprehend all the laws of nature. Ernst Cassirer thought that the prevailing philosophy

    of that age was optimistic because people were confident that mankind can know and live according

    to natural physical and moral laws. Charles Frankel has contended that the century was m arked by

    a faith in reason and science (rather than revelation) as reliable guides to truth and insurers of

    progress.

    Henry Vyverberg and Peter Gay have been among the challengers to this prevailing view.

    They have argued that there was also a realization in that century of mankind's fanaticism,

    ignorance, and other defects and that there was a corresponding streak of pessimism that ran through

    the age.  Although their points have offered a valuable antidote to the interpretations of Becker and

    others, nevertheless it is true that several writers of that period were confident that human progress

    in many areas was assured.

    For the key arguments in this debate, cf. C arl L. Becker, The Heavenly City of the E ighteenth

    Century

     Philosophers

     (New Haven: Yale University P ress, 1932); Ernst Cassirer,

     The Philosophy

    of the Enlightenment, trans. F. A. C. Koelln and J. P. Pettegrove (Boston: Beacon Press, 1955);

    Charles Frankel,

      The Faith of Reason

      (New York: Octagon Books, 1969); Henry Vyverberg,

    Historical Pessimism in the French Enlightenment (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University P ress,

    1958);

     Peter Gay, The Party

     of Hum anity

     (New

     York:

     Alfred A. Knopf,

     1964),

     pp.

     188ff.

     and 270f.;

    and R. O. Rockwood

     (ed.),

     C arl Becker's Heavenly City Revisited (Ithaca, N.

     Y.:

     C ornell University

    Press, 1958).

    * C .

      I. Castel, abbe de Saint-Pierre, Scheme for a Lasting Peace,  trans. H. Hale Bellot

    (London: Peace Book Company, 1939).  Cf. also J. B. Bury,  The Idea of Progress  (New York:

    Dover, 1955), pp. 127-43.

    47

    Anne Robert Jacques Turgot,

     R eflections on the Form ation and Distribution of Riches

    (New York: Macmillan, 1898). Cf. also Anne Robert Turgot,  "Tableau philosophique des progres

    successifs de l'esprit humain," Oeuvres de

     Turgot, ed.

     G ustave Schelle (Paris: F. Valcan, 1913-23),

    vol.

     I.

  • 8/20/2019 Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    38/205

     

    Kant's Philosophy

      of

      Hope

    • Gotthold Lessing, The Education of the Human Race, Lessing's Theological Writings,

    trans.

     Henry Chadwick (Stanford: Stanford U niversity Press, 1957), pp. 82-98.

    *>Ibid., p. 96.

    ' Antoine-Nicolas

      de

     Condorcet, Sketch

     for a H istorical Picture of  The Progress of the

    Human

     Mind,  trans. June Barraclough (London: Weidenfeld

     and

     Nicolson, 1955), p.

     173.

    5l

    In

     a key

     passage

     de

     Condorcet wrote:

    We shall find in the experience of the past,

     in

     the observation of the progress

    that the sciences

     and

     civilization have already made,

     in

     the analysis

     of

     the progress

    of the human m ind and of the development of its faculties, the strongest reasons for

    believing that nature

     has set no

     limit

     to

     the realization

     of

     our

     hopes.

     (Ibid.,

     p .

     175.)

    52

    G. W. F. Hegel, The Phenomenology of Mind, trans. J. B. Baillie (2d ed.; New York:

    Macm illan, 1949), pp. 251-67, esp. 254f.

    M

    Karl Marx, Contribution to the Critique of Hegel's Philosophy of Right, Karl Marx and

    Friedrich Engels,

     O n Religion (New

     York: Schocken Books, 1964),

     p. 42. The

     paragraph which

    precedes the sentence quoted reads:

    Religious distress is at the same tim e the expression of real distress and the

    protest against real distress. Religion is the sigh of the oppressed creature, the heart

    of a heartless world, just as

     it is the

     spirit

     of

     a spiritless situation.

      It is the

     opium

     of

    the people.

      (Ibid.)

    Julian Huxley, New

     Bottles for New Wine

     (New York: Harper & B rothers, 1957), p. 289.

    55

    Cf. Julian Huxley, Religion without Revelation (New York: New American Library, 1958),

    esp.

     pp. 181-212.

    56

    Charles Sanders Peirce,

     Collected Papers

     (Cambridge, Mass.: Belknap Press, 1965-66),

    5.357. He also referred to this hope as the  assumption that man or the comm unity (which may be

    wider than  man)  shall ever arrive  at a  state  of  information greater than some definite finite

    information.

    (Ibid.)

    Ibid., 2.655.

    The other two sentiments he mentioned are interest in an indefinite community —which he

    likened

     to charity, and  recognition of the possibility of this interest being made supreme —which

    he called faith.  Cf. ibid.

    5>

    Ibid., 2.654f.

    59

    John Stuart Mill,

     Theism (New

     York:

     The

     Liberal Arts Press, 1957), pp .

     55 and

     78-82.

    ' This

     is the

     essay , Utility

     of

     Religion, which

     he

     wrote between

      1850 and 1858.

      John

    Stuart Mill,

     "Nature " and

      Utility

     ofReligion "

     (New York:

     The

     Liberal Arts

     Press, 1958), pp.

     79-80.

    61

    Mill, Theism, p. 81. This essay was written between 1868 and 1870.

  • 8/20/2019 Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    39/205

    Introduction

      23

    62

    Ibid.,

     p p.

     81f. In the

     same essay

     he

     wrote,

    When the reason is strongly cultivated, the imagination may safely follow its

    own end and do its best to make life pleasant and lovely inside the castle, in reliance

    on the  fortification raised  and  maintained  by  reason round  the  outward bounds.

    (ÄW.,p.81.)

    63

    S0ren Kierkegaard, Either/Or,

     trans.

     David F. and Lillian M . Swenson (Garden City, New

    York: Doubleday, 1959), I, 288-89.

    64

    S0ren Kierkegaard,

     Repetition,

     trans. Walter Lowrie (New York: Harper  Row, 1964),

    p.

     34.

    65

    S0ren Kierkegaard,

     For

     Self-Examination,  Judge for  Yourselves

    and

     Three Discourses,

    1851, trans. Walter Lowrie (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1944), p. 102.

    A s, for example,

     in

     The Sickness unto

     Death.

     Cf S0ren Kierkegaard, F ear and Trembling,

    and

     The

     Sickness unto Death,

      trans. Walter Lowrie (Garden City, New  York: Doubleday and

    Company, 1954), pp. 141-262.

    67

    S0ren Kierkegaard, Works

     of Love, trans.

     Howard and Edna Hong (New York: Harper and

    Brothers, 1962), pp. 234ff.

    ^Martin Heidegger, Being

     and

     Time, trans. John Macquarrie

     and

     Edward Robinson

     (New

    York: Harper & Row, 1962), p.

     396.

    ^Ga briel Marcel,

     The

     Philosophy

     of

     Existentialism, trans. M anya Harari (New York: Citadel

    Press, 1970), p. 28.

    ' Gabriel Marcel, Homo Viator, Introduction

     to a Metaphysic of

     Hope, trans. Emm a Craufurd

    (Chicago: Henry Regnery, 1951), pp . 32-36.

    n

    lbid.,

      p. 36, and

     Gabriel Marcel, Being and

     Having,

     trans. Katharine Farrer (New York:

    Harper

     

    Row, 1965), p.

     74.

    72

    Erich Fromm ,

     The Revolution of Hope

     (New York: Harper & R ow, 1968), p. 13.

    n

    Ibid.,  p . 9.

    74

    Erich Fromm ,

      The Anatomy of Human Destructiveness

     (New York: Holt, Rinehart, and

    Winston, 1973), p. 438.

    75

    Fromm,  The  Revolution  of  Hope,

      pp. 17ff.

      Fromm even provided

      a

      this-worldly

    interpretation of resurrection:

    Resurrection

     in

     its new meaning—for which the Christian m eaning would be

    one of the possible sym bolic expressions—is not the creation of another reality after

    the reality of this life, but the transformation of this reality in the direction of greater

    aliveness.  Man and society are resurrected every mom ent in the act of faith and of

    hope  in the  here  and now;  every  act of  life,  of  awareness,  of  compassion  is

  • 8/20/2019 Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    40/205

      4

    Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    resurrection; every act of sloth, of

     greed,

     of selfishness is death.  Ibid., p. 17.)

    16

    Ibid.,

     p p.

      llff.

    Ez ra Stotland, The Psychology of Hope (San Francisco: Jossey-Bass, 1969), pp .

     7f.

    n

    Ibid.,  pp.  17ff.

    Hermann Cohen,  Reason and H ope: Selections from  the Jewish Writings of Hermann

    Cohen,

     trans. Eva Jospe (New York: W. W . Norton, 1971), pp. 122ff.

    m

    Ibid., p . 126.

    Cf

      ibid.,

     p .

      123.

    82

    Hermann Coh en,

     Religion der Vernunft aus den Quellen des

      udentums (2d

     ed.;

     Darmstadt:

    Joseph Melzer Verlag, 1966), pp. 363-64. Co hen 's view

     of

     life after death

     was

     simply that o ne's

    spirit would go  home to God; he did not understand it as personal, individual existence beyond

    death.  Cf. Cohen, Reason and Hope, p.

     139.

    ''Martin Buber, Replies

     to My

     C ritics, The P hilosophy of Martin Buber, ed. Paul Arthur

    Schilpp

     and

     Maurice Friedman

     (La

     Salle, Illinois: Open Court, 1967), p.

     715.

    ^M artin Buber, Hope

     for

     t is

     Hour, Pointing the W ay; Collected Essays of Martin

     Buber,

    ed. Maurice S. Friedman (New York: Harper  Row, 1963), p. 220.

    85

      Hope for this Hour was originally delivered as a speech in 1952 at the conclusion of a

    lecture tour Buber had conducted in the United States.

    ^Martin B uber, Paths in Utopia, trans. R. F. C. Hull (Boston: Beacon Press, 1958), p.  142.

    The word for the village comm une may also be transliterated, 'kvu tzah.'

    87

    Buber,

     Pointing the W ay,

     pp. 224-29. The ideal community can be understood, I think, as

    people living together in full I-Thou relationships as they are described in Martin Buber, /

     and

    Thou, trans. Ronald Gregor Smith (New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, 1937).

    88

    Ernst Bloch, Das Prinzip Hoffnung (Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp Verlag, 1959).  In each of

    the five main sections of the book Bloch treated a form of  this consciousness.  The sections are

    titled, Little Daydreams, The Anticipating Consciousness, Wish-Ideals in a Mirror, Sketches

    of a Better World, and  Wish-Ideals of the Fulfilled Mom ent.

    89

    Bloch expressed this point with the slogans, 'S is not yet P' and 'Incipit vita nova.'  Ernst

    Bloch, Man on His

     Own: Essays

     in the

     Philosophy of Religion,

     trans. Ε . Β . Ashton (New York:

    Herder & Herder, 1970), p.

     90.

    Bloch, Das

     Prinzip Hoffnung,

     p . 1.

    Bloch,

     M an

     on His

     Own,

     p. 91.

  • 8/20/2019 Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    41/205

    Introduction 2 5

    w

    Jurgen Moltmann, Theology of

     Hope,

     trans. James W . Leitch (New York: Harper & Row ,

    1967),

     p. 25.

    Jürg en Moltmann, The Theology of Hope, The Future of Hope, ed. Frederick Herzog

    (New York: Herder and Herder, 1970), pp. lOff.

    ^Moltmann's views have been expanded and altered by a number of other prominent

    theologians—e.g.  Pannenberg, Metz, SchauU, and Braaten. They have been strong advocates of

    living for an eschaton of freedom, justice, equality, and peace, and some have proposed that

    Christians should be revolutionaries—fighting to open up God 's future. SchauU has been the

    strongest advoca te of revolution, but Braaten has also written along those lines. Cf. Richard SchauU,

    Revolutionary Change in Theological Perspective, Christian Social Ethics in a Changing World:

    An Ecumenical Theological

     Inquiry,

     ed. John C. Bennett (New York: Association, 1966), pp . 23-43,

    and Carl

     E.

     Braaten, The Future of God: The Revolutionary Dynamics of Hope (New York: Harper

    and

     Row,

     1969),esp.pp. 141-166. ForPan nenb erg's views, c/Wolfhart Pannenberg, Tfteo/ogy and

    the Kingdom of G od (Philadelphia: The W estminster Press, 1969) and What is Man?, trans. Duane

    A. Priebe (Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1970). For the views of Metz,  cf.  Johannes B. Metz,

    Creative Hope, Cross

     Currents,

     XVII (1957), 171-79; The Responsibility of Hope, Philosophy

    Today, X (1966), 280-88; Poverty of the Spirit (New York: Newman P ress, 1969); and Theology of

    the World (New York: Herder and Herder, 1969).

    CP R, A804-805 = B832-833.

    Alles Interesse m einer Vernunft (das spekulative sowohl, als das praktische)

    vereinigt sich in folgenden drei Frage n:

    1.  Was kann ich wissen?

    . 2. Was soll ich thun?

    3.

      Was darf ich hoffen?

    This material is examined in Chapters 2 and 3.

    T he relevant material in these writings will be treated in Chapters 2 and 4.

    Imm anuel Kant, Philosophical Correspondence

     1759-99,

     ed. Arnulf Zweig (Chicago: T he

    University of Chicago Press, 1967),

     p.

     205.

     The brackets are the editor's.  Religionwithin the Limits

    of Reason Alone is very important for the purposes of this study, and in Chapter 3 it is treated in

    some detail.

    There is also an interesting passage in the Logic  which shows Kant's interest in hope.

    Although the w ork was first published in

     1800,

     it was a handbook Kant used for his lectures on logic

    and may have been written several years earlier. The passage reads:

    The field of philosophy in the cosmopolitan sense [i.e., in the sense in which

    it unites all men in the search for the ultimate end of human reason] may be

    summarized in the following questions:

    1. What can I know?

    2.  What should I do?

    3.

      What may I hope?

    4.  What is man?

    Metaphysics answers the first question, ethics the second, religion the third, and

  • 8/20/2019 Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    42/205

    2 6

    Kant's Philosophy of Hope

    anthropology the fourth. (Immanuel Kant, Logik, KGS , IX, 25.)

    Relevant parts of the

     M etaphysics of Morals

     will receive attention in Chapter 2. Portions

    of Perpetual Peace and The Strife of Faculties are treated in Chapter 4.

    l00

    Some translators,  e.g.  Beck (Immanuel Kant, Idea for a Universal History from a

    Cosmopolitan Point of View, On History (Indianapolis: Bobbs-M errill, 1963), p.  3 (VIE, 18) as

    well as Greene and Hudson (Kant, Religion within the Limits of Reason Alone (New York: Harper

    and Row, I960)), have rendered the term  Gattung as race in the sense of the human race, but

    Kant also wrote about various races ( Racen ) in such essays as  Von den verschiedenen Racen der

    Menschen.

    m

    Cf.  Chapter 4, section I. The distinction may be found in Kant, Idea for a Universal

    History, p. 13 (VIII, 18-19), and in Kant, Anthropology from a Pragm atic Point of

      View,

      trans.

    Mary J. Gregor (The Hague: Martinus

     Nijhoff,

      1974), pp. 151-52 (VII, 285-86), and pp. 182ff.  (VII,

    321ff.). In the latter work K ant also included sections on the character of the sexes, of nations, and

    of races, but those categories can be understood in terms of the nature of the species.

    l02

    Clement C. J. Webb, Kant's Philosophy of Religion (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1926); and

    F. E. E ngland, Kant's Concept of God (London: Allen and Unwin, 1929). In his study of K ant's

    philosophy of religion, Schweitzer focused on the tension between K an t's critical idealism and his

    moral emphasis and did not give attention to the topic of hope.  Cf.  Albert Schweitzer,  Die

    Religionsphilosophie Kants in der Kritik der reinen Vernunft bis zur Religion innerhalb der Grenzen

    der bloßen Vernunft (Freiburg: J. C. B. Mohr, 1899). Bohatec 's excellent study of the historical

    backgrounds to Religion within the L imits of Reason A lone treats the topic of ho pe only briefly.  Cf.

    Josef Bohatec, Die Religionsphilosophie Ka nts in der  Religion Innerhalb der Grenzen der bloßen

    Vernunft

    (Hildesheim: Georg Olms, 1966). Wood mentioned hope only in passing in the work in

    which he defended K an t's use of the moral postulates.

     Cf.

     Allen

     W.

     Wood,

     Kant's M oral Religion

    (Ithaca: Cornell University P ress, 1970).

    103

    Lucien Goldmann, Imm anuel Kant�