is there such a thing as personal identity?

Upload: dr-rene-mario-micallef-sj-std

Post on 04-Apr-2018

217 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/29/2019 Is There Such a Thing as Personal Identity?

    1/15

    Gene ral Phi l osophy Tuto r ial

    IS TH E R E S U C H A TH I N G A S P E R -S O N A L ID E N T I T Y ?

    R E N M A R I O M I C A L L E F

  • 7/29/2019 Is There Such a Thing as Personal Identity?

    2/15

    I S T H E R E S U C H A T H I N G A S P E R S O N A L I D E N T I T Y ?

    Ren M ar io Mica l l efHeythrop College, University of London

    1. INTRODUCTION

    D. Wiggins in his 1967 book Identity and Spa-

    tio-temporal continuity speaks about personal du-

    plication using a brain-splitting technique (as yet not

    surgically feasible, though possibly feasible in the

    not-too-distant future). Since the human brain is

    composed of two hemispheres that are very similar,

    such that one hemisphere can take up the functions

    of the other (in certain cases of injury etc.) the ques-

    tion is what happens to a person should one or

    both of the hemispheres be transplanted into an-

    other persons cranium (removing the recipients

    brain in the process), or into the empty crania of

    two different recipients. Bernard Williams in his

    1973 book Problems of the self has provided a

    psychological version of this situation using a sci-

    ence-fiction machine that scans the contents of the

    brain and stores all the information therein (memo-

    ries, intentions, desires) and transfers all this in-

    formation to another persons brain (or more than

    one person).

    Consider two cases:

    (C1) John is the original person; Alf is the recip-

    ient (he receives half Johns brain in Wig-

    gins case , or Johns brain contents using

    Williams machine);

    (C2) Jane is the original person, Frieda and

    Claire are the recipients (each receive half of

    Janes brain in the Wiggins case, or a copy of

    Janes brain contents in the Williams case (while

    the original brain is erased)).

    Given that personal identity is one-to-one, in

    (1) John-after-the-process is John-before-the-

    process and Alf is supposedly another person, in (2)

    it is not so clear whether (a) Frieda is Jane; or (a)

    Claire is Jane; or (b) neither Frieda nor Claire is

    Jane; but clearly one has to exclude the possibility

    that (c) Frieda and Claire are both Jane (though one

    may claim that (d) both Frieda and Claire were in

    Jane, they were occupying her).

    The problems illustrated in the above examples

    are typical problems of personal identity. Neverthe-

    less, before we delve any further into the issues, letus consider the metaphysical issue of identity.

    2. IDENTITY AND ITS PROBLEMS

    The kind of identity that concerns us in the first

    place is diachronic identity, persistence through

    time; in some cases, we are also concerned with

    synchronic identity, identity at a time. Pre-philosophically, we consider John to be the same

    person he was 10 minutes ago yesterday 5

    years ago. Yet, pre-philosophically, we also consider

    that John has changed, he has not remained identi-

    cal to the person we knew 5 years ago (he may be

    taller, think differently, and possibly have a new job

    in a different city; he may have undergone religious

    1

  • 7/29/2019 Is There Such a Thing as Personal Identity?

    3/15

    conversion, and now he would vote for a different

    party he also may have had plastic surgery). He

    is different from that John. We need to delve philo-

    sophically into the question to understand what liesbehind these seemingly conflicting intuitions, re-

    garding persistence throughtime. Questions regarding

    persistence atatimealso arise when considering the-

    ses such as Multiple occupancy, which suggests that

    Frieda and Clare were two persons living in the

    same place at the same time: within Jane.

    A. PERDURANTISM

    The first thing to say about persistence through

    time is that there are two ways of dealing with time

    that provide two radically different ways of ap-

    proaching the problem. Perdurantists consider time

    to be just another dimension of spacetime, and time

    is treated as we normally treat space. Usually, per-

    durantism comes with eternalism about time, i.e., all

    things exist in an equal degree: John of 5 years ago

    exists and is as real and as present in the universe

    as John of now and as John of 5 years from now

    into the future. John is a four-dimensional worm:

    just as Johns finger isnt John but simply part of

    John, so John at time t is not John, but just a tem-

    poral slice of the whole John, who is a temporally

    extended entity. Hence, for perdurantists, the ques-

    tion whether John-at-t1 is the same person as John-

    at-t2 becomes one concerning whether the trans-

    temporal John has temporal slices on the time axis

    at t1 and t2.

    This is probably the most elegant way of ap-

    proaching problems of persistence through time,

    but it is very far away from our common-sense no-

    tions of persistence through time, and is committed

    to a rigid determinism, since the future already ex-

    ists: statements of modality are most consistently

    understood in Lewis sense of modal individuals(that are conceptual aggregates of different individ-

    uals living in close possible worlds). Assuming de-

    terminism when searching for criteria of personal

    identity, while heuristically acceptable from a meta-

    physical standpoint, would make one wonder what

    use could such a criterion serve, given that one of

    the major uses of a criterion of personal identity is

    in the field of ethics, and determinism makes non-sense of ethical discourse.

    B. ENDURANTISM

    The other position, held by endurantists, who

    normally hold a presentist (tensed) conception of

    time (this thingis, here and now; in the past it was

    but it is not(now) what is wasin the past; in the fu-

    ture it will be but it isnt(as yet, now) what it will

    be: John was a child, is a law student, will be a barris-

    ter; he is not, now, a barrister, nor is he a child) claims

    that John, now, is fully John (not a temporal slice of

    a trans-temporal John), that John 5 years ago was

    also wholly and completely John, and that the John

    of now is the same concrete particular as the John

    of 5 years ago.

    The problem, here, concerns change. One may

    appeal to the distinction between qualitative sameness

    that comes in degrees, up to the point where two

    (or more) qualitatively identical things are indiscern-

    ible (in this sense we speak of identical twins)

    and numerical samenesswhereby two different names

    or labels are discovered (or known) to designate the

    2

  • 7/29/2019 Is There Such a Thing as Personal Identity?

    4/15

    same thing (the planet nearest to the Sun is Mer-

    cury). If I take a red brick and paint it white, it is

    still numerically the same brick though not qualita-

    tively the same brick (the brick survives a change inproperties). Similarly, if I chip off one of the bricks

    corners, it still is numerically the same brick (it sur-

    vives a change in parts). This seemingly obvious dis-

    tinction is nonetheless problematic: how may of

    these little alterations can I do to the brick in order

    that it remain numerically identical to the original

    red brick? In fact, though change in properties can

    be dealt with by building an essential-accidental dis-tinction into ones concept of concrete particulars,

    most endurantists deny that a concrete particular

    can survive a change in parts (since this cannot but

    concern the essence), (Loux, 2002:241).

    In other words, if one seeks to avoid invoking

    an essential-accidental distinction in ones account

    of concrete particulars, one cannot maintain that a

    concrete particular can survive a change in proper-

    ties (let alone in parts). For a bundle theorist (claim-

    ing that there is no more to the brick that the sum

    of its attributes: redness, shape, hardness, weight,

    density), changing an attribute does affect the

    structure of the concrete particular. If, on the other

    hand, the endurantist invokes some kind of essen-

    tial-accidental distinction in ones account of con-

    crete particulars, she may claim that change in prop-

    erties does not affect the core of the particular

    (and allows numerical identity to be conserved), but

    how will she deal with the problem of change in

    parts? A bare substratum theorist must tell us some-

    thing about the bare substratum: can a complex

    particular (a hill, a field) have a substratum? Can a

    living being have a substratum (that is over and

    above the substratum of the physical complex con-

    stituting it)? Do persons have bare substrata? The

    problem, here, is that if we start saying what the

    bare substratum is and what it isnt, and by whichthings (encountered in ordinary language) can it be

    possessed and by which things it cannot, our sub-

    stratum starts becoming essentially characterised

    it is no longer bare of any attributes.

    One may try to avoid these problems by being

    Aristotelian, and applying substance theory to con-

    crete particulars. Aristotle did not however consider

    a substance every thing that ordinary language treats

    as a thing: tables, chairs, marble blocks, rivers

    Substances were, for Aristotle, living things and

    basic blocks of his physical paradigm (the four ele-

    ments). Hence, even if we adopt some form of sub-

    stance theory, we would still need to go down to the

    elements of our physical paradigm (say muons, glu-

    ons, quarks, assumed to be physical simples) to

    speak of substances. Being indivisible, these physical

    simples cannot undergo change in parts and hence

    can endure in time; hence Aristotelian endurantists

    may deny that something persists through a change

    in parts while claiming that the basic blocks of our

    universe do not undergo change in parts and hence

    endurance is possible. Yet the question whether

    living beings, and persons in particular, can be treat-

    ed as substances still remains from Aristotle, and

    raises a plethora of problems, especially in the pre-

    dominant physicalist view of the world. Is there

    something indivisible that constitutes the person,

    allowing a person to endure in time?

    Roderick Chisholm (cit. in Loux, 2002) suggests

    that a person could be something microscopic, lo-

    3

  • 7/29/2019 Is There Such a Thing as Personal Identity?

    5/15

    cated somewhere in the brain. Whatever this might

    be, the important thing about it, according to the

    above reasoning, is that it be a simple substance.

    But if we have to postulate simple substances be-sides those invoked in explaining our physical para-

    digm, if there other simples in the universe besides

    quarks, muons and gluons, we are back into some

    form of dualism1, precisely what Chisholm is trying

    to avoid. If on the other hand we want to maintain

    the claim that the person is ultimately a group of

    cells (some part of the brain) or else a series of

    memories, intentions and other psychological datastored in the states in which such cells are, then,

    claiming that the person survives a change in parts

    (e.g. permanent loss of some memories, death of

    some brain cells involved in consciousness)

    would have to be coupled with abandoning the use

    of the strict and philosophical reading of numerical

    identity when speaking of persons. The upshot of

    this is that it seems that unless one is a dualist or aperdurantist, one cannot render the intuitive I am

    the same person I was 10 years ago with the philo-

    sophical notion of numerical identity understood to

    apply in an all-or-none and one-to-one way. In oth-

    er terms, a physicalist endurantist cannot speak of

    the persistence of persons through time as she

    speaks of the endurance of quarks. A person, it

    seems, may loose parts, and hence persistence ofpersons through time becomes a matter of degree

    (I am 80% the same person I was 10 years ago)

    and holds between more than one person (Frieda

    1 Understood as the theory claiming that there exists in theuniverse something else beyond what is known empirically.

    and Clare are both Jane; they both derive from parts

    of the person Jane).

    One may claim at this point that such a notion

    of person is counter-intuitive; but this is a conten-

    tious claim, since we have, in everyday language,

    different notions of person. Clearly, in a normative

    context (law, ethics), and in a religious context,

    common language avoids indeterminate notions of

    the person, and does not easily admit that a person

    can be duplicated or divided, or that two person

    could be united into one. But certainly, there are

    also in common language less rigid notions of per-

    son that we may invoke in metaphysics2.

    3. PERSONAL PERSITENCE

    Let us, at this point, take a moment to define

    our terminology. In the case of perdurantism, given

    that temporal slices of a person are numerically dis-tinct, one can hardly speak of personal identity.

    Hence, a more general term, I suggest, would be

    personal persistence, that would cover bothpersonal

    perdurance and personal endurance (according to the

    different interpretation of persistence through time).

    Within personal endurance, I distinguish between

    personal identityand personal contiguity, the former be-

    2 It is not so obvious, as some authors seem to suggest, thatrigid notions of personal identity mirror our pre-philosophicnotions. We often speak experiences of change (e.g. growth of achild, maturation of teenagers, adult conversion, repentance,radical transformation, moral corruption) using diversitylanguage applied to persons: John is not the same person anymore, Margaret is not the same person she was 8 years ago. Infact, ordinary language assumes personal identity in certaincontexts and personal alteration in other, and assumes these tocome in varying degrees. Hence, before claiming that ordinarylanguage suggests a rigid notion of personal identity, one mustaccount for these uses of diversity language.

    4

  • 7/29/2019 Is There Such a Thing as Personal Identity?

    6/15

    ing a relation that is one-to-one and all-or-none, the

    latter being a relation of degree that can hold be-

    tween more than two observed entities. Using a

    different way of subdividing personal persistence,one may say that personal identity is a type of rigid

    personal persistence, personal contiguity a type of non-

    rigid personal persistence. The notion of rigidity ap-

    plied to perdurance becomes a question of whether

    the perdurantist allows overlap when cutting up

    spacetime or not. The 4-dimensional ontology of

    perdurance allows ample gerrymandering when cut-

    ting up spacetime, no particular way of cutting upspacetime is metaphysically privileged. Hence, we

    can define Alf II as the section of spacetime com-

    posed of John-before-the-procedure (and adjacent

    temporal slices extending backward in time) and Alf

    (and adjacent temporal slices extending forward in

    time), and define John II as the section spacetime

    occupied by John-after-the-procedure and adjacent

    temporal slices extending forward in time (with re-spect to the procedure). This is a non-overlapping

    way of cutting spacetime, that allows us to speak of

    rigid personal persistence (even though its rigidity

    may be very counter-intuitive, as shown by the ex-

    ample itself: to the common person in the street,

    the definitions of Alf II and John II state that John-

    before-the-procedure perdures as Alf, and that

    John-after-the-procedure is not the same person asJohn-before-the-procedure.) One may, nevertheless

    allow overlap, by defining, say, John III as John-

    before-the-procedure (and preceding slices) plus

    John-after-the-procedure (and successive slices) and

    defining Alf III as John-before-the-procedure (and

    preceding slices) plus Alf (and successive slices).

    Since John III and Alf III share sections of

    spacetime, we may say that they are similar to a cer-

    tain degree (according to the volume of spacetime

    they share): here we have a case of non-rigid per-

    sonal persistence in the case of perdurance; notethat the idea that a person may be a persistence in

    time of a contemporary person, or a even of a fu-

    ture person, is unproblematic in an eternalist con-

    ception of time.

    3. SIMPLE AND COMPLEX VIEWS.

    One may nevertheless contest the fact that eve-ryday language supports metaphysical notions of

    rigid and non-rigid personal persistence, and one

    may want to stick to rigid personal persistence, in-

    sisting that any notion of personal persistence that

    comes in degrees and that is not a one-to-one rela-

    tion is counter-intuitive. In this case, the most rea-

    sonable alternatives are perdurantism and some

    form of dualism. Let us consider a number of met-aphysical universes to explore these possibilities3.

    A) In group A of universes, there are things(tables, chairs, atoms, human bodies) and,

    separately, persons. Personhood and its per-

    sistence through time is an ultimate unana-

    lysable fact; the observable persistence of

    body, brains, experiences, intentions, etc.,

    does not ontologically constitute personal

    identity, but serves only as fallible evidence

    3 The enumeration does not have the pretence of being exhaus-tive: I have in mind to represent the most popular positions andthink that my arguments can be extended to more nuancedconstructions.

    5

  • 7/29/2019 Is There Such a Thing as Personal Identity?

    7/15

    in the evaluation of whether the person has

    persisted in the time span being considered.

    a. In universe Aa, unity of consciousnessis not a sufficient criterion of personal

    persistence, though some degree of

    unity of consciousness is necessary for

    personal persistence. Two persons can

    therefore feel, consider themselves or

    be conscious of being the same person.

    The scenario allows the possibility of

    two separate persons (say Johann and

    Frederick) living in two different, but

    subjectively indistinguishable worlds, to

    have the same consciousness at time t0,

    which time marks the separation of

    their life histories. An intuitive render-

    ing of this scenario is the situation re-

    sulting after a case of branch-line tele-

    transportation whereby Johann is tele-

    transported to the subjectively indistin-

    guishable world4, Twin-earth (hence in-

    stantiating Frederick) while the original

    body (and person: Johann) is not de-

    stroyed (and remains on Earth). After

    the procedure, both Johann and Fred-

    4

    Subjectively indistinguishable means that all that is known byhumans on both Earth and Twin-Earth is identical; but possi-bly, further investigations (e.g. in the nature of sub-atomic par-ticles) would reveal in the future (after t0) that the two worldsare objectively different. For instance, emeralds have alwaysbeen green on both Earth and Twin-Earth, but at tx (1 hr aftert0), the emeralds on Twin-Earth become blue, while those onearth stay green. This is eventually traced to a difference in thenature of quarks: on Earth they are eternally stable, on twin-earth, twin-quarks are such that they shift to a different config-uration once every n years (n > (tx-tg); where tg marks the timewhen Twin-Earth came into being).The point, here, is to allowJohann and Frederick to have different histories after t0, whicha rigid determinist might not otherwise allow.

    erick feel that they are the same person

    as Johann-before-the-procedure, just

    woken up to continue with his life.

    (Furthermore, one may assume that

    the teletransporter and its operator are

    undetectable by the scientific instru-

    ments on both Earth and Twin-Earth,

    and that its operation does not leave

    any noticeable signs in either world:

    there is already Twin-Johann on Twin-

    Earth, and the matter composing him

    is simply shaped into Frederick without

    affecting any other matter on Twin-

    Earth. Neither Johann nor Frederick

    know anything about the teletranspor-

    tation).

    b. In universe Ab, consciousness is both anecessary and a sufficient condition for

    personhood: two persons cannot be

    conscious of being the same person. If

    at time t0, Frederick is conscious of be-

    ing Johann for times before t0, they

    must be the same person; if they are

    separate persons, Frederick cannot ever

    be conscious of being Johann.

    B)

    In group B of universes, persons are notseparate from the physical and mental states

    that indicate their presence to the senses;

    personhood does not transcend the observ-

    able. Furthermore, it is assumed that the

    mental rests on the physical, at least in the

    sense that if physical matter were to be re-

    6

  • 7/29/2019 Is There Such a Thing as Personal Identity?

    8/15

    moved from these universes, nothing would

    remain.

    a. Ba is an endurantist universe in which aperson endures: he exists wholly and

    completely at each of several different

    times.

    b. Bb is a perdurantist universe wherein aperson perdures: she has temporally

    different parts; Jane-of-8-years-ago and

    Jane-of-two-minutes-ago are temporal

    slices of Jane, just like Janes right hand

    and Janes external ear are spatial slices

    of Jane.

    The groupings A and B represent two different

    positions in matters of personal identity (or contigu-

    ity). Group A represents the so-called simple viewof

    personal persistence: beyond the observable or em-

    pirical person, there is what I will call a transcendentalperson5; empirically determined persistence in time is

    only fallible evidence for persistence on the tran-

    scendental level. In Group B of universes, one as-

    sumes the complex view, whereby there exists a

    criterion of personal persistence that a third party

    can observe. There is something (else) that personal

    persistence consists in: it is an analysable fact given

    that persons are not (to be considered as) separatelyexisting entities; they are dependent on mental

    and/or physical entities6.

    5 In the Kantian sense of non (fully) empirically accessible in adirect manner.

    6 Pace Noonan (1989:121-122)s claim (sustained by hardy anyargumentation) that the complex view does not entail a meta-physical reductionism (or rather reductivism) but only a

    I will argue that Aa and Bb are interesting ways

    of dealing with personal persistence, though not

    very useful in dealing with the real issues we are

    concerned with in the personal identity literature.Ab and Ba seem untenable, though endurantism

    may support a less rigid notion of personal persis-

    tence than personal identity.

    I will proceed here by arguing against Ab. The

    arguments apply also to versions of Bb (perduran-

    tism plus complex view) that identify the person

    with consciousness.

    A. PERSONS AND CONSCIOUSNESS

    Many people holding the simple view tend to

    limit the transcendental person to consciousness,

    following a more general trend to identify person-

    hood with consciousness, or at least to claim that

    persistence of self-consciousness is a necessary and

    sufficient condition to persistence of personhood. A

    logical reductionism as characterized by Dummett. Accordingto Noonan, the complex view only entails that there exist rela-tions satisfying [a kind membership characterization] whosespecification informatively constrains the class of possible per-sonal histories. As I understand it, to specify informativelysuch relations is to give an empirically verifiable criterion, oth-erwise creation by creator-demon and not destruction by de-stroyer-demon could be a criterion that satisfies Noonansdefinition (provided we explain in a logically consistent way ifand how these demons intervene, say, in a case of reduplica-tion). Hence, if we claim that such empirically verifiable criteria

    (say having the same experiences, or possessing the same brain)are to be ontologically and conceptually dependent on persons(121) and not on independent as in the case of Parfits bundlesof experiences, we need a theory of concrete particulars where-in what is ontologically and conceptually dependent on per-sons cannot be reduced to being ontologically and conceptuallydependent on something simpler than a person. Though defini-tionally distinct, it seems that the complex view, some form ofreductionism, and (I would add) perdurantism go together (giv-en the above discussion). If one maintains that the informativecriteria sought by the complex view must be empirical, or ob-servationally accessible, one can hardly also maintain that suchcriteria belong to persons, understood, say, as observationallyinaccessible simple substances.

    7

    (footnote continued)

  • 7/29/2019 Is There Such a Thing as Personal Identity?

    9/15

    person, according to Locke, is a thinking intelligent

    being with reason and reflection that can consider

    itself as itself, the same thinking being, in different

    times and places (Locke, cit. in Noonan, 1989:10).From this definition, one may deduce that the nec-

    essary and sufficient conditions for personhood are

    reason, reflection and consciousness; since reason-

    ing and reflection are actions limited in time and

    their contents may change, it seems that only con-

    sciousness seems relevant to the issue of personal

    persistence. It is debatable whether we can use crite-

    ria for personal persistence that do not belong toour definition of the person, since if we claim, say,

    that mammals have episodic memory, continuity of

    episodic memory (or quasi-memory) may entail that

    a person is the same mammal as another person,

    but not necessarily the same person (if we want to

    maintain that there is something special about per-

    sons, and that issues of personal persistence are not

    reducible to ones of mammal persistence). HoweverI shall side-step this issue, and return to the issue of

    consciousness, that has a considerable importance

    in the literature, given the widespread assumption of

    Lockes definition of person.

    I think that it difficult to argue for Universe Ab

    without postulating some more metaphysically sta-

    ble substrate for consciousness. Seemingly, Ab

    overcomes the quietism of Aa by suggesting that

    though there is nothing observable which could tell

    us if Frederick is Johann or not, if Frederick is Jo-

    hann then he must be conscious of being the same

    person as Johann, if not, he must be conscious of

    being someone else. Since there is something it is like

    being Johann to which one has no access if one

    does not know what it is like to be Johann and if

    one has never been Johann we cannot, on this

    sole basis, tell if Frederick is Johann or not, except

    by asking him whether he feels he is Johann or not.

    This causes epistemological problems that make usfall into the metaphysical quietism of Aa (Frederick

    may or may not be Johann, we cannot really tell

    there is no way by which we can verify criteria of

    personal identity or personal persistence any logi-

    cally coherent criterion is plausible and hence we

    have no one criterion to which we can appeal for

    fecund analysis of the problems of personal persis-

    tence)7.

    But what is problematic with asking Frederick if

    he is conscious of being the same person as Johann

    or not? Imagine that Frederick finds out about the

    teletransportation, and has internally warranted be-

    lief that Twin-Earth came into existence at t0, and

    that Earth had been destroyed in the teletransporta-

    tion process: one expects him to be conscious of

    being Johann, even though his belief might not

    track the truth. Or imagine that Frederick and Jo-

    hann both become astronauts, and after being lost

    in space, find a planet which they think is their

    planet: Frederick lands on Earth, Johann on Twin-

    Earth. Each would be convinced that he his the

    same person that left that planet on the spaceship a

    few years back: that the friendships he had, the

    places he visited, the quarks he is made of are those

    present in the world where he landed. Hence, the

    fact that Frederick feels he is Johann does not guar-

    antee that there is personal identity between the

    two.

    7 We shall return to this below.

    8

  • 7/29/2019 Is There Such a Thing as Personal Identity?

    10/15

    B. A BROADER VERSION OF THE SIMPLE VIEW

    Let us now consider universe Aa. I think we

    cannot summarily dismiss Aa, if anything because

    most of our moral intuitions and laws belong to a

    linguistic and conceptual paradigm of religious

    origin, where such a conception of personhood is

    predominant8. The problem with it is its quietism: if

    we cannot definitely determine if p1 at t1 is the

    same person as p2 at t2 through experience, we

    could find all sorts of criteria for determining

    whether p2, after a certain mind- or brain-involving

    process, possesses the same soul, cogito, psyche etc.

    as p1 that existed before the process, so long as the

    metaphysical structure is logically coherent. Such

    transcendental persons can be mortal or immortal,

    divisible or indivisible, created or eternal, etc. This

    pluralism, I feel, is not problematic from the meta-

    physical point of view (unless one holds the dogma

    that all but what is posited by the simplest and neat-

    est theory is inexistent): we could have all sorts of

    internally coherent metaphysical notions of the per-

    son and criteria of personal persistence. The point,

    however, is that what has given rise to the personal

    identity literature is not simply a quest for endless

    8 Personal identity debates are not new to Philosophy; theyhave an old tradition. Ever since the Latin term persona (from

    gr.prosopon, a theatrical term for mask or character, e.g. perso-nae dramatis) was applied to the Christian God, people havewondered how one could reconcile the idea of three personswith one substance (triune consubstantiality). More recent dis-cussions in Theological Philosophy focus on the problematicfusion of the concept-experience of Christian Love (personalGod) with the Greek idea of Unmoved mover, e.g. after PierreAubenques definition of the Aristotelian God as the unlovinglover. These issues show how in Philosophy, the person hasbeen linked to some non-corporeal metaphysical foundation,and how the discussion of personal identity issues has, in thetradition, presupposed such a notion of person. One wonders,at this point, whether such discussion can still make sense witha more physicalist notion of the person.

    metaphysical speculation, neither simply a taste for

    science-fiction thought experiments and even less a

    desire to justify metaphysically the various religious

    understandings of the person: we are rather con-cerned with having answers useful and relevant to

    normative philosophy, say, bioethics, we want to

    know what founds a persons rights and responsibil-

    ities. On this account, the complex view seems

    more interesting, since it claims to provide criteria

    that are empirically accessible.

    C. PERDURANTISM AND ENDURANTISMABOUT PERSONS

    Going over to Bb (after having discussed the

    problems with Ba above), I think that perdurantism

    does provide us with an attractive way of dealing

    with issues of personal persistence. Yet, it is not

    clear why a perdurantist should have any interest in

    issues of personal persistence at all. Since perduran-

    tism insists on allowing ample gerrymandering of

    spacetime, it does not seem capable of providing an

    account of why cutting up spacetime in such a way

    that we have areas corresponding to the common

    sense notion of person should be preferable to any

    other way of cutting up spacetime (e.g. one which

    puts together bits of dogs, cars, buildings, persons

    etc. that are spatio-temporally adjacent). If persons

    are ontologically equivalent to any other entities

    resulting from a whatsoever system of cutting up

    spacetime, issues ofpersonalpersistence has no par-

    ticularmetaphysical significance.

    I have already argued against Ba in Section 1 of

    this essay (claiming that one cannot consistently be

    a endurantist about persons and not be a dualist,

    9

  • 7/29/2019 Is There Such a Thing as Personal Identity?

    11/15

    unless one gives some plausible account of concrete

    particulars to sustain ones view) An endurantist

    may claim that quarks endure, but not that persons

    endure in the same way as quarks, i.e. by remainingnumerically identical to themselves through time.

    He may instead opt for personal contiguity, i.e. for a

    non-rigid understanding of personal persistence.

    4. WHAT IS THE POINT OF RIGID NO-

    TIONS OF PERSONAL PERSISTENCE?

    Though problematic and of limited use, a rigidnotion of personal persistence does seem to make

    sense in Aa. However, I feel that within the more

    physicalistic paradigms (Ba, Bb), personal identity

    (as a one to one relation that does not come in de-

    grees) is a fetish from the metaphysical point of

    view. Clearly, from the normative point of view, we

    need the concept of a determinate person (which is

    not the soul, as religiously understood), just as weneed the concepts of good and bad (which are not

    the religious concepts ofholyand evil), but this does

    not entail that we must postulate a corresponding

    metaphysical entity within a physicalist universe.

    Thomas Reid (cit. in Noonan 1989:20) notes:

    [Identity] has no fixed nature when applied to bodies, and

    very often questions about it are questions about words. But

    identity when applied to persons has no ambiguity and admits

    not of degrees of more or less. It is the foundation of all rights

    and obligations and of all accountableness, and the notion of it

    is fixed and precise.

    From such passages regarding the so-called de-

    terminacy thesis, it seems that what matters is the

    numerical identity of moral agents, not of meta-

    physical entities. Indeed, from a metaphysical point

    of view, rigid notions of personal persistence are of

    limited use, both in Ba and Bb. Keeping rigid no-

    tions of personal persistence within the limits of

    normative philosophy, I think that from the de-scriptive standpoint we should make do with non-

    rigid personal persistence.

    Physicalists often compare personal persistence

    with life as understood in contemporary Anglo-

    American philosophy9: life is constituted by certain

    structures (prokaryotic or eukaryotic cells, defined

    in by necessary and sufficient criteria) capable of

    performing certain (necessary and sufficient) func-

    tions (respiration, growth, reproduction, sensitivity

    to changes in the environment), rather than by

    the presence of some elan vital. Life goes on as

    long as these structures are not destroyed and they

    continue performing the specified functions. Such a

    characterisation is certainly a rigid notion of life:

    one cannot be 50% alive. One may seek to establish

    a similar characterization of what is necessary and

    sufficient for personhood, and persistence through

    time would then be a question of continuity in these

    structures and functions. For instance, Stewart

    (2001) argues that there are three Great Criteria of

    personal identity and these are corporeal: episodic

    memory is based in the neocortex, continuity in the

    brain, subjectivity (consciousness) in the thalamus.

    Such an approach, however whereby one is ei-

    ther alive or dead, either 100% the same person or

    another person decides borderline cases (viruses,

    coma states) by appealing to the definition. The def-

    inition is the final court of appeal to find out if x is

    9 David Papineau (cit. in Stewart 2001) compares consciousnessto life in this way.

    10

  • 7/29/2019 Is There Such a Thing as Personal Identity?

    12/15

    living or not. But such definitions in biology do not

    demarcate ontological differences or differences

    that correspond to clear natural difference; rather,

    since the borders are fuzzy, we need definitions tocut straight lines, to serve our convenience10. If so,

    the criteria are normative ones, and we must not use

    them to sustain metaphysical distinctions.

    Consider the initial cases of John and Jane. Cer-

    tainly, Alf and John-after-the-process are to some

    degree personally persistent with John-before-the-

    process, and Claire and Frieda are personally persis-

    tent to some extent with Jane. If after the process

    John and Jane were found guilty of a horrible mur-

    der, non-rigid personal persistence would suggest

    that John, Alf, Claire and Frieda need psychological

    help and a programme of rehabilitation, while rigid

    personal persistence would most probably let Alf

    loose, as well as Claire, or Frieda, or both.

    Or consider that Williams machine is marginal-

    ly defective (or the surgeon in Wiggins case causes

    minimal damage to a nerve) such that the aggres-

    sive part of Johns brain that was responsible for

    the murder is destroyed, or altered in the (99.8%

    successful) duplication process, and John becomes a

    peaceful, law-abiding, loving person with a normal

    life: he has no memories of being abused by a vio-

    lent father, no desires of sadism, no criminalthoughts. On Alfs side, the duplication is 99.7%

    successful, however only some insignificant brain

    10 For instance, the distinction between animals and plants isthere to there to specify what should be studied by botanistsand what by zoologists; that between living and non-living or-ganisms specifies what organisms are to be studied by virolo-gists and what by bacteriologists and mycologists.

    cells (or brain data) were damaged; Alf follows in

    the steps of John-before-the-process and becomes a

    trigger-happy gangster. The police manage to find

    evidence only for the murder before the duplicationprocess, and both John and Alf stand trial. Rigid

    personal persistence would supposedly demand that

    Alf be acquitted and John be convicted. Non-rigid

    personal persistence, however, could allow that

    even if John-after-the-process is overall more physi-

    cally contiguous with John-before-the-process than

    Alf, for legal and moral purposes, Alf is more con-

    tiguous with John-before-the-process than John-after-the-process.

    Consider, furthermore, Jane writes a will leaving

    all her possessions to herself. After the procedure,

    a Claire and Freida go to court, each claiming that

    she is Jane and the other isnt. Of what use can a

    rigid notion of personal persistence be in such cas-

    es?

    All these cases, and the above discussion, sug-

    gest that we abandon rigid notions of personal per-

    sistence in metaphysics (in particular, all talk of per-

    sonal identity) and adopt a non-rigid language to

    describe and deal with the cases in the personal

    identity literature.

    3. PARFIT AND WHAT MATTERS IN SUR-

    VIVA L

    This position was proposed, in a famous paper

    by Derek Parfit (1971) who argued that the notion

    of personal identity (or rigidnotions of personal per-

    sistence) has little value in what we are philosophi-

    cally concerned with when we are dealing with cer-

    11

  • 7/29/2019 Is There Such a Thing as Personal Identity?

    13/15

    tain problems regarding the human self. He targets

    two dogmas of personal identity: a) that in [the]

    cases [where we have no idea how to answer a ques-

    tion about personal identity], the question aboutidentity must have an answer; b) that unless the

    question about identity has an answer, we cannot

    answer certain important questions (questions about

    such matters as survival, memory, responsibility)

    (3-4).

    One can immediately recognize (a) as the de-

    terminacy thesis (Is x identical to y, or not?), that

    motives the search for internally coherent rigid no-

    tions of personal persistence, and (b) as regarding

    the use we can make of our notions of personal

    persistence. In the above discussion, we argued that

    universes Ab and Ba could not provide answers

    since they are not tenable as such (they do not co-

    herently allow for a rigid notion of personal persis-

    tence), and that while universes Aa and Bb could

    logically allow the possibility of a rigid notion of

    personal persistence, such notion would not answer

    questions like those in (b) above and hence are of

    little use. In other words, criteria derived from such

    ontologies either would not help us when dealing

    with (a) or, if they do, they are of no use in tackling

    the issues of (b). The way out of this deadlock

    seems to be denying the truth of (a) and (b). In the

    paper, Parfit adopts a non-rigid notion of persis-

    tence, and proposes, as a criterion, psychological

    connectedness. He then show how such a non-rigid

    criterion can be used to solve problem cases, and

    how it is useful in dealing with the issues of (b).

    Unfortunately, some authors have reduced Par-

    fits original intuition to the thesis that contrary to

    what we are all naturally inclined to believe, we do

    not have a basic and non-derivative concern for our

    future existence and well-being (Noonan, 1989: 23-

    24) and summed up his position to the motto iden-tity is not what matters in survival. Parfit, however,

    uses the issue of survival only as an example

    (1971:4) to show that personal identity because of

    its rigidity is a concept of little use and should be

    replaced by notions that are not one-to-one and all-

    or-none. Hence, the main thesis in his paper is

    much wider that sub-thesis (identity is not what

    matters in survival) from which the paper gained itsfame. Parfit claims that when we use the language

    of personal identity, what matters (e.g. when we

    are considering a case of someone surviving a brain

    operation) isnt really personal identity as Locke

    understands it, but rather another sort of persis-

    tence of persons through time. Discussing survival,

    Parfit states:

    The relation of the original person to each of the resulting peo-

    ple contains all that interests us all that matters in

    any ordinary case of survival. [] Most of the relations which

    matter can be provisionally referred to under the heading psy-

    chological continuity. [] I said earlier that what matters in

    survival could be provisionally referred to as psychological

    continuity. I must now distinguish this relation from another,

    which I shall call psychological connectedness. [] Now

    that we have distinguished the general relations of psychologicalcontinuity and psychological connectedness, I suggest that con-

    nectedness is a more important element in survival.

    Parfit (1971:10-11.20-21)

    Hence, Parfits intuition is that we need a dif-

    ferent language, since the language of identity,

    [though its use] is convenient [] can lead us

    astray (p 11); judgements of personal identity have

    12

  • 7/29/2019 Is There Such a Thing as Personal Identity?

    14/15

    great importance [but] what gives them their im-

    portance is the fact that they imply psychological

    continuity [? i.e. connectedness ?]11 (p 12). This, I

    think, is quite different from the thesis regardingwhether my concernthat I survive wholly and com-

    pletely (in the problem cases of the personal identity

    literature) and not someone else, and not as two

    persons, and not as 49% of a person and 51% of

    another is originary or derived.

    What is the purpose of the thesis regarding my

    concern about my survival in Parfits paper? At the

    onset of the paper, speaking about the first dogma

    Parfit (pp. 3-4) states: My targets are two beliefs [

    ; t]he first is that in these cases the question about

    identity must have an answer. [..] I cannot see how

    to disprove this first belief. I shall describe a prob-

    lem case. But this can only make it seem implausi-

    ble. Parfits example mirrors the John and Jane cas-

    es at the beginning of this essay, and illustrates the

    difficulties one encounters in attempting an answer.

    What I have tried to do in this essay is to show that

    the difficulty to providing such an answer is inher-

    ent in our ways of understanding time and concrete

    particulars. Rigid personal persistence claims that it

    respects the fact that, intuitively, Jane sees herself

    after the procedure only as dead, as Claire or as

    11 In the first part of the paper, Parfit uses the concept of psy-chological continuity as a first approximation before introduc-ing that of psychological connectedness. Hence my addition insquare brackets.

    Frieda, but not as somewhat both12. I contest this

    by saying that this is not true (she cansee herself as

    being somewhat both) and even if it were, this does

    not justify rigid personal persistence as a descriptivetheory unless one can argue for the internal coher-

    ence of rigid personal persistence; and demonstrate

    that Jane is not using a normative or religious idea

    of person to evaluate a hypothetical situation that

    nobody, as yet, has gone through. Parfit, on the

    other hand, introduces the aspect of concern for my

    future existence claiming that contrary to what cer-

    tain rigid theorist claim, such concern does notcause problems for the non-rigid notions of person-

    al persistence; it can be analysed in terms of the en-

    tities posited by such notions. Hence, Parfit analyses

    this concern in terms of the entities posited by his

    psychological connectedness criterion (that Noonan

    calls Parfitian survivors). However, if such an anal-

    ysis may appear not convincing to some, one should

    nonetheless point out that the idea of what we areconcerned with has limited use in deciding meta-

    physical issues13. Clearly, if we have two theories of

    logically equal standing, we may find one more in-

    teresting if it reflects what we are concerned with.

    But one can hardly claim that myconcerncan ground

    metaphysical entities and relations. Many people are

    concerned with surviving death in an afterlife, but

    12 Multiple occupancy seems to be an alternative, but it seemsto imply that every time we use Williams machine, we have topostulate another occupant in the original brain. This, I think, ismore counter-intuitive than the appeal to non-rigid personalpersistence, given that different notions of person and of same-ness are co-present in ordinary language, some of which dosupport non-rigid personal persistence.

    13 That is, one cannot reject a metaphysical notion, say, of per-sonal persistence simply because it does not account for whatwe are concerned with.

    13

  • 7/29/2019 Is There Such a Thing as Personal Identity?

    15/15

    this does not prove metaphysically that there is an

    afterlife and that these persons will be related to

    their counterparts in the afterlife in a one-to-one

    and all-or-none fashion. Unless there is a metaphys-ically coherent explanation of the entities I am con-

    cerned with, unless metaphysics can provide an on-

    tology wherein what I am concerned with exists and

    makes sense, one cannot invoke metaphysics to deal

    with such concerns, but should rather appeal to

    theology, psychology and other disciplines14.

    9. CONCLUSION

    In this essay, I have argued that the known

    metaphysical construals of personal identity, and of

    other rigid notions of personal persistence (those

    that insist that the relation be one-to-one and all-or-

    none) are either inconsistent or not useful in dealing

    with what we are concerned with in the issues of the

    personal identity literature, and that we should con-sider using non-rigid notions, such as personal con-

    tiguity. Furthermore, I have claimed that this is the

    main point underlying Parfits 1971 paper.

    14 Some rather vitriolic critics of Emmanuele Severino (Univ. ofVenice)s grotesque neo-parmenidean ontology claim that hebuilt his whole system in order to cope with the tragic death ofhis brother (who is reported to have committed suicide in frontof him when he was still a child). In Severinos metaphysics,things (that are) are neither created nor destroyed, they simplyappear and disappear as we move through time (compare withthe 4-d perdurantist ontology). Even if these critics were right,this does not mean that Severinos concern with the continuedexistence of his brother explains the plausibility and the fame ofhis ontology; rather one must admit that his theory has a valuein itself, and that to Severinoit could have an added value inthat it helps him deal with his childhood trauma.

    REFERENCES

    Honderich, T. (ed.). 1995. The Oxford companion

    to Philosophy. Oxford University Press. Oxford.

    xx+1009 pp.

    Loux, M. J. 20022.Metaphysics. A contemporary in-

    troduction. Routledge. London New York.

    xiv+303pp.

    Noonan, H. W. 1989. Personal Identity.

    Routledge. London New York. x+262pp.

    Parfit, D. 1971. Personal Identity. In The Philo-

    sophical Review80:3-27.

    Parfit, D. 1984. Reasons and Persons. Oxford Uni-

    versity Press. Oxford. xvi+543pp.

    Perry, J. (ed.). 1975. Personal Identity. University

    of California Press. Berkeley (CA) Los Angeles

    (CA) London. vi+248pp.

    Stewart, W. 2001. Personal Identity. On the www

    at site:http://mbdefault.org/8_identity/3.asp

    14

    http://mbdefault.org/8_identity/3.asphttp://mbdefault.org/8_identity/3.asphttp://mbdefault.org/8_identity/3.asphttp://mbdefault.org/8_identity/3.asp