introduction; cognitive linguistic approaches to humor

Upload: uuseernaamee

Post on 26-Feb-2018

228 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/25/2019 Introduction; Cognitive Linguistic Approaches to Humor

    1/27

    Introduction Cognitive iinguistic approaches

    to humor

    GEERTBRONE ^KURT

    FEYAERTS ^

    and TONY VEALE^

    Ever since the publication of Victor Raskin's seminal work on the

    Seman

    tic Mechanisms of Humor

    (1985), l inguistic humor research has had a de-

    cidedly cognitive orientation. The cognitive psychological roots of the Se-

    mantic Script Theory of Humor (SSTH) presented in the aforementioned

    book, have been adopted in a large number of studies that have appeared

    since. In this respect, Attardo, in a recent discussion on the cognitive tum

    in literary studies, points out th at linguists w ho study hu m or may well

    be pleased to find out that they were doing cognitive stylistics all along

    (2002: 231). Indeed, the two most influential linguistic humor theories of

    the last two decades, the SSTH and the General Theory of Verbal Humor

    (GT VH , Attard o and Rask in 1991; A ttard o 1994, 1997, 2001a), along

    with a num ber of other theoretical studies (Gio ra 1991; Ko tthoff 1998;

    Yus 2003) share some significant features with the broad Hnguistic frame-

    work that is the methodological angle of the present thematic issue, viz.

    Cognitive Linguistics (CL).

    What is Cognitive Linguistics? Although introducing a highly diversi-

    fied research endeavor like CL is a book project in itself (see e.g. Taylor

    2002; Croft and Cruse 2004; Geeraerts and Cuyckens 2006), we necessar-

    ily limit ourselves to the pinpoint motto of the

    Cognitive Linguistics Series

    (Mouton de Gruyter) :

    Cognitive Linguistics subsumes a variety ofconcernsand broadly compatible the-

    oretical approaches that have a common basic outlook; that language is an inte-

    gral facet of cognition which reflects the interaction of social, cultural, psycho-

    logical, communicative and functional considerations, and which can only be

  • 7/25/2019 Introduction; Cognitive Linguistic Approaches to Humor

    2/27

    204

    G Brone et al

    The brief

    mission st tement

    above can be interpreted as a reaction on two

    levels against the formalist, Chomskyan tradition. First, rather than hy-

    pothesizing that language is a separate cognitive module in the mind,

    with its own principles, CL approaches language as part and parcel of

    cognition, guided by general cognitive principles that are not restricted

    to linguistic organization. In consequence, one of the major objectives of

    cognitive linguists is the study of the reflection of general conceptual

    mechanisms in language and linguistic structure. Second, the phrase a

    realistic view of acquisition, cognitive development and mental process-

    ing can be interpreted as a reaction against the generative-linguistic hy-

    pothesis that grammar is essentially innate ( Universal Grammar ), and

    exposure to language in use only plays a secondary role in language de-

    velopment. CL argues, in contrast, that an individual's knowledge of a

    language is based in knowledge of actual usage and of generalizations

    made over usage events (Taylor 2002: 27). In other words, grammar is

    considered to beusage-based grounded in experience (and hence not as

    schematic as the generative gramm ar). This claim has important method-

    ological consequences relevant to the present issue. If language acquisi-

    tion is a bottom-up process of generalization over usage events, then lin-

    guistic analysis should equally be bottom-up and data-driven, starting

    from actual language in use and making generalizations/schemas on the

    basis of patterns in the usage (rather than working the other way around,

    formulating transformations of abstract principles so as to fit the surface

    appearance of language). The further methodological implications of this

    general CL claim of a usage-based grammar are elaborated in the next

    section ( humor theoretical interest in cognitive linguistics ).

    Given this somewhat simplifying description of CL, it should be noted

    that the SSTH and GTVH both share with cognitive linguistics the funda-

    mental interest in the interrelationship between language and cognition in

    language use. In general, most recent linguistic humor research makes the

    same basic assumption with respect to humor that cognitive linguistics

    does with respect to linguistic structure in general, viz. that (humorous)

    language is not to be treated as an isolated, autonomous cognitive phe-

    nomenon. On the face of it, this observation may appear trivial, since

    there seems to be general agreement that understanding verbal (as well

  • 7/25/2019 Introduction; Cognitive Linguistic Approaches to Humor

    3/27

    ntrodu tion 205

    artificially drawn boundaries between syntax, semantics, and pragmatics

    that have been proposed in formalist theories of language. This question-

    ing of traditional boundaries in linguistic structure is one of the comer-

    stones of cognitive linguistics, since it aims at uncovering the role of do-

    main general conceptualization principles at all levels of linguistic

    structure.

    This overlap in the basic philosophy of both traditions opens up re-

    search perspectives for both cognitive linguists and humor researchers.

    Thus ,

    the aim of the present issue, dedicated to studies that analyze vari-

    ous semantic aspects of verbal humor from the perspective of cognitive

    linguistics, is essentially twofold. First, by embedding the linguistic study

    of humor within a larger terminological-conceptual framework that

    claims a cognitive-functional perspective, like cognitive linguistics, htim or

    researchers are urged to treat htmiorous language in relation (and in con-

    trast) to general patterns of hnguistic and cognitive structure rather than

    in isolation. In o ther w ords, ad op ting the too ls developed in cognitive lin-

    guistics can shed new light on the specific semantic construal of humorous

    texts an d the m ar k ed chara cter tha t these texts are generally considered

    to have (Giora 1991,

    2003;

    Kotthoff 1998). Second, from the perspective

    of cognitive linguistics, a linguistic framework that claims a focus on the

    cross-cognitive and conceptual aspects of language use should be able to

    natura lly cover cases of linguistic expressivity tha t are mo tivated thro ug h

    the marked, non-prototypical use of the everyday cognitive mechanisms

    described in that paradigm. After all , humor is interpreted on the fly in

    everyday discourse, just hke the other cases of figurative lan gu ag e cog-

    nitive linguistics has given center stage to, l ike metaphor, metonymy and

    conceptual integration. And just l ike these other cases, the study of hu-

    mor can yield interesting insights into some of the specifics of cognitive

    processing, insights that extend beyond the perspective of linguistic hu-

    mor theories alone. In the following paragraphs, both the htimor theoret-

    ical interest in cognitive linguistics and the cognitive linguistic importance

    of studying humor is discussed in more detail, in order to give an overall

    picture of this mutual interest.

  • 7/25/2019 Introduction; Cognitive Linguistic Approaches to Humor

    4/27

    206

    G. roneet al

    which promotes the exchange of insights in two directions. The true chal-

    lenge for both traditions is to explore some of the waste land tha t can

    be covered through this cooperative effort (for an argument in favor of a

    take-what-you-need strategy, see Ritchie 2004). In this section, we focus

    somewhat more on the two cornerstones of the cognitive linguistics para-

    digm introduced above, and the interesting implications these assump-

    tions have for humor theories.

    The first pillar of cognitive linguistics, the one that most clearly sepa-

    rates CL from truth-conditional and generative approaches to language,

    is the hypothesis thatmeaning isessentially conceptualization (Langack

    1987). This view runs counter to the classic formalist belief th at there is a

    one-to-one mapping between extemal world and linguistic-conceptual

    structure. Rather, dynamic semantic theories like CL argue that situa-

    tions can be construed in different ways [. ..

    and different ways of en-

    coding a situation constitute different conceptualizations (Lee 2001: 2).

    In other words, situations can be framed in diflferent ways and these dif-

    ferent framings result in a different semantic structure. Bearing in mind

    this cognitive linguistic view on language as a recipe for constructing

    meaning, a recipe which relies on a lot of independent cognitive activity

    (Saeed 1996: 319), the notion of conceptualization processes is of central

    importance. Or as Croft and Cruse (2004: 42) put it, in cognitive linguis-

    tics conceptualization is the fundamental semantic phenomenon; whether

    altemative construals give rise to differences in truth conditions or not is a

    derivative semantic fact. So one ofth e tasks cognitive linguists set out to

    do is to uncover the conceptualization processes that are used in everyday

    language use. Over the last two decades, a whole range ofconstrual

    oper

    ations

    or conceptualization mechanisms have been uncovered (Langacker

    1987;Talmy 2000; Taylor 2002; Croft and Cruse 2004). These operations

    are considered to be cognitive in nature in that they are active on all levels

    of linguistic and conceptual organization, and are instances of more gen-

    eral cognitive processes as described in cognitive psychology (Croft and

    Cruse 2004: 45). Croft and Cruse present an overview of the vast litera-

    ture on construal and propose an altemative, more encompassing (in

    comparison to Talmy and Langacker) typology of construal operations,

    including the general categories of attention and salience, comparison,

  • 7/25/2019 Introduction; Cognitive Linguistic Approaches to Humor

    5/27

    Introduction

    207

    humor. And indeed, linguistic humor researchers have focussed on the

    functionality of some of these operations in the semantics of jokes and

    other humorous texts. For example, one of the fundamental construal

    mechanisms that underlie various semantic phenomena, is

    comparison

    which has been developed in phenomenology and cognitive psychology.

    And the most powerful reflection of this basic cognitive faculty is the hu-

    man need for categorization or

    framing

    i.e. viewing a linguistic expres-

    sion against the background of a frame of reference or prior experience.

    The hypothesis

    that frames

    (or scripts) as structured categories grounded

    in experience (Fillmore 1982) play an essential role in producing and

    comprehending linguistic utterances has not only been extremely influen-

    tial in the development of the semantic theory of cognitive hnguistics, but

    is also the foundation ofthe SSTH and GTVH . The SSTH (Raskin 1985)

    basically argues that jokes revolve around the opposition, overlap and

    switch between two (or more) scripts or frames. Jokes, on this view, are

    partly or fully compatible with two diflerent, (con)textually opposed

    scripts, only one of which is saliently activated in the flrst part of the

    text. The punch line of

    th

    joke turns out to be incompatible with the flrst

    script interpretation incongruity), but there is a lexical cue in the text

    (script-switch trigger) that enables the switch or shift from the first inter-

    pretation to the second, backgrounded script

    resolution).

    Coulson (2000)

    and Coulson et al. (this issue) elaborate on this idea with a discussion of

    frame shifting within a larger cognitive linguistic framework of language

    comprehension, labeled thespace structuringmodel. It is argued that this

    model better accounts for the influence of context in meaning construc-

    tion and the flexib le mechanisms that are involved in that process than

    the SSTH and GTV H. The psychological reahty of frame-shifting is sub-

    sequently tested in a num ber of psycho- and neurolinguistic experiments.

    The minimalist description above of the basic semantic idea of the

    SSTH and Coulson s approach touches upon a second principle of con-

    strual that has gained increasing interest in both cognitive linguistics and

    humor research, viz.

    salience.

    Jokes, it is argued, typically have a first,

    contextually salient interpretation that is discarded at the punch line in

    favor of a more marked reading (Giora

    1991:

    470). But as Giora has ex-

    tensively argued, salience, defined as the coded meanings that are fore-

    grounded in our mind, plays a central role not only in humor, but in a

  • 7/25/2019 Introduction; Cognitive Linguistic Approaches to Humor

    6/27

    208

    G. Brone et al.

    general (Giora 2002, 2003). According to Giora'sgr ded s lience hypoth-

    esis salient information is always accessed before any other, less salient

    information, and this very general organizational principle is exploited

    in many types of expressive language use, like novel metaphor, pun-

    ning, irony, and humor.

    Apart from the function of salience and framing, other general concep-

    tualization mechanisms have been treated, directly or indirectly, at vari-

    ous places in the humor literature, likefigure groundconstellations (Hof-

    stadter and Gabora 1989: 422; Attardo and Raskin 1991: 303; Attardo

    2001a: 19; borrowed from Talmy 1978), metaphor (Pollio 1996, based

    on Lakoif's conceptual metaphor theory), and conceptual mappings in

    general (Attardo et al. 2002). But since it is not our intention to give a

    full review of all of these points of contact in the domain of semantic

    principles, we will not further explore these issues here (for a more de-

    tailed overview, see Brone and Feyaerts 2003). The basic intention of this

    rough sketch is to illustrate some of the commonalities in the semantic

    construal of different types of language use and open up new perspectives

    for research exploring exactly this question of how everyday cognitive

    mechanisms are exploited in various ways for humorous, stylistic, or

    other purposes.

    Despite this obvious movement towards cognitively motivated seman-

    tic humor analysis, the tension between marked and unmarked semantic

    construal, which can be plotted using the meaning construction mecha-

    nisms of CL, and which accounts for the effect of unexpectedness or in-

    congruity (Kotthoff 1998: 50), has not been explored to its fullest in

    most of the linguistic humor research. The contributions to the present

    issue are intended to open this debate. As mentioned above, the implica-

    tions of these studies are not relevant to humor research alone, in that

    they illustrate one of the central claims of CL, viz. that the human con-

    ceptual system is prototypically structured and highly flexible (see also

    the section on cognitive linguistic interest in humor ). The contributions

    by Veale et al. and Kotthoff especially draw attention to the heuristic im-

    portance of prototypicality for describing humor in terms of ubiquitous

    cognitive categories of construal and communication.

    One central aspect of construal that has been widely discussed in CL,

  • 7/25/2019 Introduction; Cognitive Linguistic Approaches to Humor

    7/27

    Introduction

    209

    defined as the conceptualization of one domain (target) in terms of an-

    other domain (source), can be considered as a construal operation, since

    the choice of a particular domain for conceptualizing a target inherently

    onstrues

    the target in a specific fashion (cf. Croft and Cruse 2004: 194).

    Although it has been repeatedly pointed out that there is a theoretically

    interesting (vague) conceptual boundary between humor and metaphor/

    analogy (Koestler 1964; Hofstadter and Gabora 1989), humor theorists

    have, until recently, only focused on the potentially humorous ambiguity

    of a literal vs.figur tivereading of a metaphorical expression (Alexander

    1997; Attardo 1994). Pollio (1996) explores the boundaries in humor and

    metaphor, using insights from the interaction theory of metaphor (Black

    1962) and the Lakovian approach (Lakoff and Johnson 1980; Lakoff

    1987). It is argued tha t humorous bisociation (to use Koestler s 1964

    term) differs from metaphorical conceptualization in the profiling of do-

    main boundaries. Whereas metaphors essentially fuse the source and tar-

    get to form a single entity (Gestalt), suppressing the obvious domain

    boundaries, hum orous stimuli (un)intentionally emphasize the dissimilar-

    ities between domains. Veale et al. (this issue) follow a similar argument,

    in that they illustrate that in many cases of interactional humor, utter-

    ances with an underlying metaphorical (and/or metonymical) structure

    are used as a cue for a

    trumping strategy

    This strategy consists of a

    speaker B subverting a speaker A s utterance, e.g. by distorting the

    source/target structure of the initial metaphorical utterance.

    etonymyin a cognitive hnguistic approach, is generally viewed as a

    cognitive mechanism enabling the selection of a salient reference point in

    a frame to refer to a different concept in the same frame or to the frame

    as a whole (Langacker

    1993;

    Panther and Radden 1999). This conceptual

    approach to metonymy covers phenomena that were previously treated in

    pragmatics as inferences or conversational implicatures (Gibbs 1999; Pan-

    ther and Thomburg 2003). Given the general agreement that humor in-

    terpretation involves complex inferential activity, metonymy can be ar-

    gued to play a substantial role in this process. Barcelona (2003) argues

    that the inferential work in joke interpretation is facilitated by pre-

    existing metonymic connections in a cognitive frame. Metonymic con-

    nections, on his account, are the driving force behind the script switching

    process (Raskin 1985) that yields the resolution. Brone and Feyaerts

  • 7/25/2019 Introduction; Cognitive Linguistic Approaches to Humor

    8/27

    210

    G

    Brone

    etal.

    de automatization

    results in a balanced processing difficulty, which is ar-

    gued to contribute to the humorous effect (see also Giora 1991, 2003).

    Another construal operation that has only very recently received scru-

    tiny in humor research is

    viewpoint

    If meaning, as advocated in the CL

    framework, is essentially construed from a specific perspective, then

    adopting a different viewpoint automatically entails a different conceptu-

    alization. Of particular interest for humor researchers is the treatment of

    viewpoint in mental

    spaces

    theory(Fauconnier 1994 [1985], 1997). The

    theory of mental spaces was introduced to linguistics and cognitive science

    to coherently deal with a wide range of problematic semantic phenomena,

    such as indirect reference, pragmatic functions (Nunberg 1979), referen-

    tial opacity, (counterfactual) conditionals, compositionality, etc. Mental

    spaces, on Fauconnier's account, are small conceptual structures that

    proliferate when we think and talk, allowing a fine-grained partitioning

    of our discourse and knowledge structures (Fauconnier 1997: 11). On

    this account, viewpoint is dealt with in terms of different mental spaces:

    the viewpoint space is the structure from which others are accessed.

    Humor research has only very recently touched upon the relevance of

    mental spaces. Ritchie (this issue) argues that the accepted dichotomy be-

    tween referential and linguistic jokes is not satisfying, since both create

    an event which is open to alternative interpretations, albeit by different

    means. By the same token, the generally accepted view that a reader/

    hearer of a joke is forced into a reinterpretation from an incorrect to a

    correct interpretation of a lexical element or grammatical construction,

    thus performing a frame-shifting operation , does not account for all (or

    even the majority) of verbal jokes. Ritchie explores a number of jokes

    that revolve around a misinterpretation by a story character, and proposes

    an account of viewpoint shifts/reinterpretations in terms of mental spaces

    (see also Brone forthcoming for a systematic account). Attardo (2001b)

    uses a mental space account of

    ironical

    mode adoption.Mode factive

    utterances (i.e. utterances allowing mode adoption), such as irony, meta-

    phorical utterances, fiction, etc., trigger the construction of a new mental

    space (next to the base/reality space) so as to allow the hearer to avoid

    having to reject the utterance as ill-formed. In accordance with dLa-

    conmtr s

    presupposition

    float

    principle

    (1994 [1985]: 61), it is argued tha

  • 7/25/2019 Introduction; Cognitive Linguistic Approaches to Humor

    9/27

    Introduction

    211

    indeed provides some articulate tools that have not been fully explored

    in linguistic humor theories. Uncovering patterns in the semantics of hu-

    morous texts, using these mechanisms, can provide useful insights into

    the essentially marked character of these texts. The tension between

    normal and marked use (or between prototypical and peripheral use) of

    semantic-pragmatic devices seems to play an essential role in the humor

    game. One of the general conclusions that can be drawn from the papers

    in the present issue is that a prototypical model is needed for the use of

    conceptualization operations, differing core cases in conventionalized lan-

    guage use from more marked uses. Analogously, from a more pragmatic

    point of

    view,

    the contribution by Kotthoff advocates a highly flexible de-

    scription of communication principles in terms of prototypical categories.

    The second cornerstone of the cognitive linguistic philosophy of lan-

    guage is that linguistic structure is

    usage based.

    Usage-based models of

    language essentially state that a speaker's linguistic system is grounded

    in usage events, and hence is experientially driven (Langacker 1987,

    1988; Barlow and Kemmer 2000). Langacker (1988: 131) notes concisely

    tha t [i]n describing cognitive gra m m ar as a 'usage -base d' m odel of lan-

    guage structure, I have in mind the 'maximalist ' , 'non-reductive', and

    'bottom-up' character of the general approach (as compared to the mini-

    m alist, reductive an d top-dow n spirit of the generative tra dit ion ). If the

    linguistic system is indeed inherently tied to usage ( bottom-up ), then

    the primary source of information is the actual use of language

    in context.

    In contrast to most formal approaches to language, CL argues that lin-

    guistic and non-linguistic context both play an essential role in the pro-

    duction and processing of language. There is no strict boundary between

    linguistic and contextual information, in that features of contextual (and

    pragmatic) information can, through conventionalization, become part of

    the linguistic system as such. The linguistic uttera nce as such merely func-

    tions as a cue the processor uses as a starting point in the meaning con-

    struction process (supra).

    Uncovering the tight interaction between contextual and linguistic un-

    derstanding is the main research goal of the steadily growing field of cog-

    nitive discourse analysis (La nga cke r 20 01; V an H oe k et al. 1999). One of

    the adv anta ges of such a perspective is tha t it can provide a va luable

  • 7/25/2019 Introduction; Cognitive Linguistic Approaches to Humor

    10/27

    212 G. Brone et al.

    obvious interest to hiiinor researchers studying the interpersonal and in-

    ferential nature of

    humor.

    On the level of interpersonal dynamics, it needs

    to he ohserved that many cases of humor directly or indirectly draw on

    collaborative Kotthoff, this issue) and adversarial (Veale et al., this

    issue) strategies in interaction. Speakers in running (humorous) discourse

    often huild on previously introduced strands or themes (Davies 1984),

    and thus either proceed on a humorous topic in collaboration with other

    participants, or counter another participant's utterance hy means of ad-

    versarial humor strategies (cf. Davies 1984 on the thematic principles of

    contradiction and elaboration). The semantics of multi-agent forms of

    hum or has been poorly analyzed in hum or research, especially in compar-

    ison to the hulk of literature on (canned) jokes, which often does not refer

    to the context these jokes are delivered in. Cognitive linguistics explicitly

    states that language is grounded in discourse and social interaction (Lan-

    gacker 2001: 143), which means that the context of speech and shared

    knowledge all play a central role in semantics, and they cannot he sepa-

    rated from the core meaning of an utterance. Langacker's notion of a

    current discourse

    space

    defined as a mental space com prising those ele

    ments and relations construed as being shared hy the speaker and hearer

    as a hasis for com munication at a given moment in the flow of discourse

    (2001: 144), illustrates this unified treatment of semantics. On this view,

    meaning arises in discourse through a range of

    cues,

    rather than by sim-

    ply processing stored semantic information (see also the papers by Kotth-

    off and Coulson et al., this issue).

    Apart from the general theoretical importance, positing a usage-based

    model of language and conceptualization has major

    methodologic l

    impli-

    cations

    as well. Usage-based theories hypothesizing a tight relationship

    between linguistic structures and real usage necessarily need to base their

    claims on the observation of actual data, rather than on constructed ex-

    amples. This has led to a renewed attention to the empirical support of

    theoretical claims, both on the level of production and processing.

    Pro-

    duction

    data

    can be drawn from corpora collecting usage material. This

    way, corpus analysis can chart linguistic variation at all possible levels,

    including sociolectic, dialectic, idiolectic, but also expressive variation.

    As a central instance of linguistic variation, expressivity and creativity

  • 7/25/2019 Introduction; Cognitive Linguistic Approaches to Humor

    11/27

    Introduction

    213

    Data on the

    processing

    of linguistic input can be drawn from simula-

    tion experiments like reading times, priming tests, ERP-analyses, etc.

    Vaid et al. 2003) provide an overview of the various accoun ts that hav e

    been prop ose d of the different stages of m ean ing ac tivation in jok e com -

    prehension. In order to test empirically the conflicting hypotheses in the

    literature, the authors used a lexical decision semantic priming experi-

    ment to measure the time course of meaning activation. Coulson et al.

    this issue) report on a number of studies that test the psychological real-

    ity

    of frame shifting

    supra) in joke com prehens ion. Self-paced reading

    times for one-line jok es see also Co ulson a nd K uta s 1998) show th at

    jokes that require frame-shifting take longer to process than straight end-

    ings.

    These da ta suggest th at frame-shifting requires an extra processing

    cost. A com plem entary ER P-exp erime nt event-related brain potentials)

    was conducted to get a more fine-grained view of the cognitive process

    involved in frame-shifting see also Co ulson a nd K ut as 2001). It is argu ed

    that a sustained negativity 500-900 ms is the ERP effect that indexes the

    frame-shifting needed for joke comprehension. In a third experiment,

    Coulson et al. measure eye movements to examine whether the reinterpre-

    tatio n process of frame-shifting involves an increased am ou nt of regres-

    sions leftward eye mo vem ents) in com parison to non-joke endings. The

    eye tracking data show that total viewing duration is longer for jokes

    than for non-joke controls, and that participants make more regressive

    eye movements when frame-shifting is required for the interpretation. In

    general, these empirical studies show a renewed awareness of the need for

    experimental backup of theoretical hypotheses, a need that has been ex-

    pressed, am on g others , by Atta rd o 2001a: 208). Nevertheless, this field

    is still in its infancy pa rtly beca use it is no torio us ly difficult to design

    methodologically sound tests), and needs a fair amount of basic data.

    In sum, in this first section we have connected some of the basic con-

    cepts of the Cognitive Linguistics framework to the specific linguistics

    of humor in an at tempt to uncover common ground and new perspectives

    for both cognitive linguists and humor researchers. As a stepping stone,

    we used two of the key ideas in CL. First, the broad, dynamic view on

    meaning as comprehensive conceptualization leads to a focus on the re-

    flection of higher-level construal mechanisms or conceptualization opera-

  • 7/25/2019 Introduction; Cognitive Linguistic Approaches to Humor

    12/27

    214

    G. Brone et al.

    including these general cognitive mechanisms may contribute to the de-

    velopment of a genuinely cognitive account of verbal (as well as non-

    verbal) humor. A second trigger in the discussion is the cognitive hnguis-

    tic view on linguistic structure as usage-based. The implications of this

    basic claim for the scope of semantic analysis and for the methodologies

    that are used, are not trivial. From the perspective of production, a cog-

    nitive semantic analysis needs to take into account the rich conceptual

    landscape in which meaning emerges, including semantic, pragmatic, con-

    textual, cultural, and even (inter)personal information. This multidimen-

    sional perspective may contribute to a better understanding of the way

    in which different cu es join tly trigg er a hu m or ou s effect. O n the level of

    processing, a cognitive linguistic account generates direct hypotheses that

    can be tested in a simulation setting. This may provide a new impetus

    for the much-needed interaction between descriptive-theoretical work and

    empirical testing in linguistic humor research.

    This general account of the potential contribution of a cognitive lin-

    guistic perspective on humor does not, as such, motivate why cognitive

    linguists interested in linguistic structure in general may find the study

    of humor compelling and worthwhile. In the next section, we pursue the

    question why cognitive hnguists should (occasionally) deviate from the

    accepted path of conventional language use to study more creative cases.

    To a large extent, this interest arises from looking at the arguments pro-

    posed in this section from a different angle.

    2

    Cognitive linguistic interest in humor

    There are several levels on which a cognitive linguistic theory of meaning,

    defined in a broad sense, might benefit from the inclusion of humor and

    creative language as an object of research. Not claiming any exhaustive-

    ness in this regard, we will restrict our observation to those matters which

    appear most relevant to the aim and set-up of this issue.

    Vis-a-vis its characterization as a

    usage-based

    dynamic theory of

    meaning as conceptualization, treating language on a par with other cog-

    nitive abilities. Cognitive Linguistics is urged to take creativity into ac-

  • 7/25/2019 Introduction; Cognitive Linguistic Approaches to Humor

    13/27

    Introduction

    215

    this m ost hu m an of cognitive behaviors d o we do justice to our theories of

    language. Artificially restricting language data to that which is considered

    core or central can only serve to keep our models of language blind to the

    realities of human language knowledge, and thus hobbled with respect to

    the scientific method." Generally, the analysis of creative language use

    used as a cover term including all kinds of verbal humor and witallows

    a more accurate picture to be drawn of the way in which our experience is

    structured by cognitive construal mechanisms such as metaphor, meton-

    ym y, figure/ground-arrangement, frames, etc. In the following, the im-

    pact of this observation will be discussed in more detail both with respect

    to descriptive semantic theory as well as regarding psycholinguistic ex-

    periments on the processing of language.

    From the perspective of semantic theory, we draw attention to four di-

    mensions of semantic structure, in which the functionality of analyzing

    non-conventionalized, creative language use for CL theory becomes ap-

    parent. A first aspect pertains to the basic CL claim concerning the non-

    restrictive,

    encyclopedic

    nature of the meaning of an utterance. In many

    hu m oro us con texts like joke s, collaborative o r adversarial interaction ,

    wordplay etc. (see

    Kotthoff

    Veale et al., this issue), the successful pro-

    cessing of the intended meaning heavily depends on the activation of

    experiential (cultural, social, embodied .. .) knowledge shared by both

    speaker and hearer in the current discourse space (Langacker 2001). The

    witty effect in an exchange like (1), for instance, hinges only partially on

    the exploitation ofthe linguistic structure ofthe verb

    to aim for.

    Crucial is

    the activation of encyclopedic knowledge concerning Von Braun's early

    career as a scientist at the service of Nazi-Germany (see Veale et al., this

    issue).

    (1) Vo n Bra un (S): I aim for the stars

    title of coffee-table book)

    Boo k critic (H ): I aim for the stars, but I keep hitting Lo nd on .

    title of book review)

    A

    second aspect of meaning construal which is inherent to any semantic

    structure, but frequently exploited in creative language use, concems the

    varying degrees of s lience displayed by different meanings of a single

    word with respect to its usage in a given context or frame. Salience of a

    word or utterance is defined in Giora (1997: 185) as "a function of its

  • 7/25/2019 Introduction; Cognitive Linguistic Approaches to Humor

    14/27

    216 G

    roneet al.

    scripts against the background of which meanings are being profiled. In

    humorous utterances like (1), it is apparent that at any moment in unfold-

    ing discourse, interlocutors may decide to realize the cognitively salient

    meaning by altering the conceptual background.

    A third aspect, in which the analysis of humorous material might add

    to a more comprehensive view on conceptualization concerns the inclu-

    sion ofdiscourse as a relevant dimension for an adequate determination

    of semantic structure. With regard to a discursive-cognitive analysis of

    jokes,

    Giora (1991: 469) formulates the

    marked

    informativeness require

    ment

    according to which jokes and point-stories are markedly infor-

    mative. Their final informative messages are marked in that they are too

    distant, in terms ofth number of similar features, from the messages pre-

    ceding them . As such, they provide a cognitive link to the preceding

    text, but at the same time they violate the expected, conventional pattern

    of gradual increase in informativeness (see also Coulson

    2000:33ff;

    Coul-

    son and Kutas 2001). In her pragmatically oriented contribution, Kotth-

    off (this issue) emphasizes the impact of discursive elements on the gener-

    ation of a humorous meaning in collaborative conversation. In CL, this

    observation parallels a broadening ofth analytical scope, integrating dis-

    course elements into the paradigm of Cognitive Grammar as apparent in

    the Current Discourse Space model, as proposed by Langacker (2001).

    Finally, the analysis of creative language use (humor) highlights proto

    typicality

    as a major structural characteristic of semantic-conceptual or-

    ganization. Although since the very beginning, CL has embraced prototy-

    picality as a basic feature of categorization, which integrates fiexibility

    with structural stability (see, among others, Geeraerts 1989, 1997), most

    studies in the field have related this notion to the structure of lexical-

    semantic categories. Linguistic studies of creative language demonstrate

    that humorous effects tend to be generated through the exploitation of

    prototypical categories throughout the current discourse space. Interest-

    ingly, these categories are not restricted to the level of lexical semantics

    (Veale et al., this issue), as they are also identified on the pragmatic plane

    Kotthoff,

    this

    issue).

    In their survey of different kinds of verbal as well as

    non-verbal humor, Brone and Feyaerts (2003) demonstrate that even on a

    meta-linguistic level, construal mechanisms appear as prototypically or-

  • 7/25/2019 Introduction; Cognitive Linguistic Approaches to Humor

    15/27

    ntroduction 217

    well-chosen metonymic expression lets us mention one entity that is sa-

    lient and easily coded, and thereby evoke essentially au tom atic ally a

    targe t tha t is either of lesser interest or har der to nam e (L an gac ke r 1993:

    30).

    Such manipulations may rely on, for instance, the profiling of non-

    essential side elements in a visual setting or an event structure as reference

    points, or also the non-profiling of highly salient elements ( profile gap ,

    Brone and Feyaerts

    2003:

    3Iff). The analysis of these phenomena in

    terms of non-prototypical cases of metonymic construal, rather than

    humor-specific logical mechanisms, strongly invites an integrated, non-

    modular CL account of humor. At the same time, however, it calls upon

    CL to further refine its heuristic tools in order to live up to its name as the

    framework most suitable for the analysis of dynamic meaning construc-

    tion. More specifically, as instances of creative language use show, con-

    strual mechanisms seem to require a more elastic definition in terms of

    prototypical characteristics in order to bring evenfull creativity (Bergen

    and Binsted 2003) within reach of basic cognitive construal mechanisms.

    By adopting a construal approach to incongruity resolution, the linguistic

    interest in humor interpretation might stretch beyond the purely humor

    theoretical perspective. Instead of focusing on the uniqueness of the hu-

    mor phenomenon (e.g. in logical mechanisms), a CL account may reveal

    the way in which day-to-day cognitive capacities are explored and pushed

    to the limit for humorous purposes.

    Besides its relevance for descriptive sem antic theo ry, the analysis of cre-

    ative language use (humor) also promises new insights to psycholinguistic

    studies on the processing of language. In the context of this issue, we

    briefiy refer to two observations whose relevance extends beyond the se-

    mantic structure of humorous utterances alone. A first benefit of tackling

    humorous material through the application of experimental methods con-

    cems the psychological reality of frames, more specifically, the process of

    frame shifting. In their observation of regressive eye movements, Coulson

    et al. (this issue) confirm earlier reading time findings by Coulson and

    K utas (1998, 2001) as they note that peop le were m ore likely to m ake

    regressive eye movements when they read the joke than the straight end-

    ings,

    as if they wanted to re-examine earlier parts of the sentence for clues

    to which altem ative frames should be retriev ed (Cou lson et al., this

    issue).

    A second, related observation pertains to the multifold interaction

  • 7/25/2019 Introduction; Cognitive Linguistic Approaches to Humor

    16/27

    218

    G

    rone

    etal

    psycholinguistics. Whereas the traditional psycholinguistic approach to

    meaning construction focuses on the way in which context determines

    the processing of lexical items (rather than how these items may have

    any impact on the representation of the broader discourse event (context,

    frame, message ...), Coulson et al. (this issue) use frame-shifting jokes to

    demonstrate the need for a model of message-level processing prom pted

    by language .

    3 Outline of the issue

    In the opening paper of the issue Seana Coulson, Thomas Urbach and

    Marta Kutas present thespace structuringmodel a cognitive linguistics

    inspired model of linguistic comprehension that focuses on the interaction

    between sentence processing and text processing. Using insights from that

    model, the authors report on a number of experiments that test the psy-

    chological reality

    oi

    frame-shifting the semantic and pragmatic reanalysis

    that is necessary for the interpretation of the punchline of a joke. In the

    case of frame-shifting, the lexical processing of the punchline triggers the

    construction of cognitive models in working memory. Previous self-paced

    reading and ERP (event-related brain potentials) experiments both sug-

    gest tha t frame-shifting involves an additional processing cost in com par-

    ison to non-joke controls. The eye-tracking study presented in this issue

    confirms the results of previous studies under the more natural reading

    conditions this methodology provides. In addition to the other studies,

    the eye movement data show that the extra cognitive cost is not simply a

    question of word recognition, since the length of the readers' initial gaze

    duration of a word did not differ significantly for jokes and controls.

    Rather, the cost is related to higher-level processing, as indexed by the

    longer total viewing duration of words in jokes. The fact that jokes elicit

    more regressive eye movements upon encountering the punch word than

    straight controls provides additional evidence for the psychological reality

    of a reanalysis process like frame-shifting.

    Graeme Ritchie starts from the widely accepted idea in humor theories

    that many jokes consist of a set-up phase, which has a salient interpreta-

  • 7/25/2019 Introduction; Cognitive Linguistic Approaches to Humor

    17/27

    ntrodu tion 219

    the reader/hearer or a character in the joke. In order to capture this strat-

    ification, Ritchie presents an account in terms of viewpoints or belief sets,

    formalized by means of

    ment l sp ces

    (Fauconnier 1994 [1985]). It is ar-

    gued that the reinterpretation process does not necessarily have to be di-

    rectly in the mental space of the audience, but rather, it suffices that it

    happens in a viewpoint that is accessible to the audience (nested view-

    point).

    An in-depth analysis shows that the change of interpretation can

    occur in the hearer's viewpoint, in the narrative viewpoint or in the view-

    point of a story character, hence widening the canonical view that the

    reinterpretation process involves a hearer making a revision from a previ-

    ously false to a correct interpretation. What is more, the higher-level, for-

    mal treatment of forced reinterpretation provides a generalization that

    can not be captured by some other taxonomies (like e.g. the widely ac-

    cepted verbal-referential distinction). In using a mental space account to

    capture this generalization, Ritchie seems to corroborate one of the basic

    claims of cognitive hnguistics, viz. that it is possible to account for a wide

    range of phenomena, verbal as well as non-verbal, using a restricted set of

    basic conceptual mechanisms.

    Although Helga Kotthoff's analysis of conversational humor formally

    figures as a pragmatic approach, this contribution also provides valuable

    input to the recent discussion in Cognitive Linguistics to pursue the con-

    cept of 'usage-based hnguistics' to the full (see, among others, Geeraerts

    2003).

    Specifically, three key notions of CL-theory may be identified, mo-

    tivating the relevance of this paper for the theoretical orientation of the

    present issue. First, and most importantly, Kotthoff highlights flexibihty

    as a crucial characteristic of semantic/pragmatic categories such as com-

    munication principles. By doing so, she adopts an ecological view on (lin-

    guistic) categorization, which basically boils down to the adaptation

    of prototype theory to linguistic analysis. This theory still represents one

    of

    th

    methodological cornerstones of CL, providing a structural explana-

    tion for the differentiation between, among others, preferred (salient) and

    non-preferred (less-sahent) meaning structures. Although she does not

    explicitly argue in terms of 'prototypicahty,' a major point of Kotthoff's

    paper concerns the flexible extension of communicative principles, thus

    rejecting an explosion of maxim s in favor of maxim exploitation

  • 7/25/2019 Introduction; Cognitive Linguistic Approaches to Humor

    18/27

    220 G Brone et al

    be an exclusive characteristic of CL, it does represent an essential facet of

    its characterising semantic structure in terms of conceptual structure.

    Third, Kotthoff's approachalthough mainly articulated in terms of a

    pragmatic modeladheres to Langacker's description (2001) of the

    viewing frame (or: immediate scope of predication ) being built up

    through different channels of conceptualization which, next to the objec-

    tive content, also contain features such as gesture, intonation, sequencing,

    etc.As Kotthoff puts it: In order to describe the production of meaning

    in concrete sequences, other sorts of knowledge must be referred to (e.g.

    knowledge of sequencing, stylistic expectations, discursive genres and

    contextualization procedures) which constitute a collateral system of

    communication. To put it the other way around: in recent years, Lan-

    gacker (CDS-model) and CL have themselves embraced a more discur-

    sive approach of meaning description, thus complementing the traditional

    CL-focus on lexical-semantic and grammatical constructs.

    It is clear that on the basis of each of these three notions alone, a lin-

    guistic analysis cannot be claimed to be part of the Cognitive Linguistic

    paradigm, especially since the two latter may be characteristic for other

    approaches as well. Yet, it is the combined application of these three

    features that renders this contribution particularly relevant for a CL-

    approach of humor.

    Tony Veale, Kurt Feyaerts and Geert Brone pursue a similar argument

    for the case of adversarial hum or in conversation, using the cognitive lin-

    guistic notion of construal operations. A specific adversarial humor strat-

    egy is singled out, which revolves around the subversion of the linguistic

    forms of exchange. Based on a technical definition of this phenomenon

    they label trum ping , the authors illustrate how agents in a conversa-

    tional setting can reflect and dis tor t the linguistic-conceptual con-

    strual set up in a prior tum in conversation. A typology of trumping

    mechanisms is presented, based on the different levels of linguistic organi-

    zation on which the reflection or parallelism in the trumping game can be

    situated. More specifically, the use of insights from cognitive linguistics

    reveals that adversarial agents exploit the various conceptual mechanisms

    underlying an opponent's utterances in order to tum the tables in the hu-

    mor game. In doing so, an agent can trump an adversary by demonstrat-

  • 7/25/2019 Introduction; Cognitive Linguistic Approaches to Humor

    19/27

    ntroduction 221

    up in the previous utterance s) Langacker 2001). On the basis of the

    analysis, the au thors conclude that a cognitive semantic account in terms

    of general principles of conceptual organization provides an adequate ac-

    count of the tension between markedness and transparency in humor and

    exhibits an ecological validity that is lacking in most linguistic humor re-

    search. The issue finishes with a thought-provoking epilogue article by

    Salvatore Attardo, who, from the point of

    vi w

    of the GT VH , points out

    a number of potential strengths and weaknesses of the cognitive linguistic

    endeavor.

    4 Perspectives for future research

    If cognitive linguistics is to live up to its reputation as a framework of dy-

    namic meaning construction, it should be demonstrably capable of han-

    dling the most dynamic aspects of humorous meaning. The papers in

    this special issue, we believe, go some way toward providing such a dem-

    onstration. However, many key questions remain either unanswered, or

    worse, unasked, and cognitive linguistics must prove its value on these

    questions also. For instance, how does humor relate to other cognitive

    and social phenomena that appear to have a strong family resemblance?

    Such phenom ena include:gossip jokes, like scandalous stories of

    th

    mis-

    behavior of others, are amongst the most contagious memes that human

    society has evolved; what makes these forms such compelling vehicles

    for dynamic meaning, and what meaning-construction and meaning-

    grounding mechanisms do they share?); insults not always humorous,

    but the most valued are always creative; why does society prize indirect

    and ambiguous assaults on character as clever over more direct and un-

    ambiguous attacks?); underst tement surely some mechanism of under-

    specification is shared with humor?); overst tement like metaphors, hu-

    mor often exploits literal mistruth); and so on. Since cognitive linguistics

    refuses to box language and meaning into strict modular compartments

    of mind, we should expect the cognitive ecology it fosters to have direct

    application to all of these questions.

    In line with this cognitive ecology, according to which humor figu res

    among other cognitive phenomena requiring a holistic, integrated ap-

  • 7/25/2019 Introduction; Cognitive Linguistic Approaches to Humor

    20/27

    222 G. Brone et al.

    the awareness of prototypicality as an inherent property of conceptual

    and linguistic categories is of crucial importance. To what extent and in

    what ways a fiexible category structure may be stretched for humorous

    purposes represents a complex research topic. Ultimately, pursuing this

    approach must lead to the conclusion that humor is a marked {deautom-

    atized

    yet structurally not irregular kind of language use. In terms of

    specific research questions further elaborating this general hypothesis,

    several topics of interest may be discerned. Finishing off, we therefore

    offer a survey of four such topics, located on a theoretical/descriptive as

    well as an empirical/methodological plane. Each of these topics com-

    prises an indicative, yet non-exhaustive list of concrete research questions.

    4 .1 . The relationship between creativity and hum or

    Circumscribing the boundaries of humorous language is not a straight-

    forward task. Although the mechanisms of humor on the one hand, and

    those of metaphor, irony and linguistic creativity on the other are not

    identical, neither are they are clearly demarcated categories of cognition.

    To what extent does humor exploit different kinds of figurative and idi-

    omatic language use? Is there a real difference between literal and figura-

    tive humorous language use, or is the difference as elusive, and in some

    ways ideological, as it is in the study of metaphor? Just as all metaphors

    are neither literally ano m alo us no r false, neithe r should a jo ke rely on the

    perception of an incongruity to force a humorous interpretation. Cer-

    tainly, metaphors can be stretched so far as to cross the line from persua-

    sive analogy into humorous juxtaposition, but metaphors can be perceived

    as humorous without negating their truth-theoretic content. Humor, like

    othe r forms of playful creativity, rely to som e exten t on the lu d ic spirit

    of participants. Further research is required to elucidate precisely which

    mechanisms of mind are shared by creative language and humorous lan-

    guage, and which, if any, predates the other.

    4.2.

    Construal mechanisms in humor

  • 7/25/2019 Introduction; Cognitive Linguistic Approaches to Humor

    21/27

    Introduction 223

    interpretation of different types of humorous texts involve cognitive

    mechanisms of construal? Do these mechanisms operate in the same, a

    similar or a different way compared to non-humorous language use? To

    what extent can conceptual mechanisms be characterized as essentially

    flexible, prototypically organized categories?

    4.3.

    Interplay of quan titative and qualitative variables

    Humorous utterances are extremely fragile linguistic and conceptual con-

    structs, the meaning of which depends vitally on a nexus of quantitative

    criteria such as the time of delivery, and the activation of key expecta-

    tions) and qua litative criteria such as social conte xt, cultur al tab oo s,

    shared world models, etc.). This fragility of humorous language makes it

    an ideal linguistic form in which to theorize about the relationship be-

    tween the quantitative and qualitative aspects of language and cognition.

    How can we objectively determine the complexity of a given stimulus or

    complexity of the intended cognitive resolution process? Should this be

    based on degree of conventionahty, contextual expectation, complexity

    of inferential wo rk, the cognitive m echa nism s th at are exploited e.g.

    frame-shifting), or maybe a combination of all of these parameters?

    4.4 . mpirical methods on the processing of humor

    Many of the notions introduced in support of conceptual models of

    hu m or are in serious need of experim ental i.e., psycholinguistic, neuro -

    hnguistic and corpus-linguistic) support if they are to hold theoretical

    water. Cognitive linguistics, in prescribing a usage-based model of lan-

    guage, explicitly aims to develop a conceptual apparatus that is both a

    beneficiary of insights from, and a source of testable hypothesizes for,

    psycholinguistics To m asello 1998, 2002; Barlow and Ke m m er 2000).

    With respect to this inherent symbiosis between theory and empiricism,

    the analysis of humor elicits a set of compelling issues that present a

    methodological and theoretical challenge to cognitive science. To what

    extent do the existing empirical methods meet the requirements of testing

  • 7/25/2019 Introduction; Cognitive Linguistic Approaches to Humor

    22/27

    224 G Brone et al

    models be useful in delineating hypotheses testable in an experimental

    environment?

    Many of the questions raised here are still largely unsolved, though

    they have an important catalyzing role to play in deciding the future

    direction of our discipline. Indeed, we expect that in the short-term a

    cognitive-linguistic approach to humor will raise as many questions as it

    helps to answer. With this inevitability in mind, we conclude this intro-

    duction with a question that is, for the most part, rhetorical, since we be-

    lieve we already have a partial answer that is worth sharing. If the remit

    of Cognitive Linguistics is considered in its broadest sense, as the Cogni-

    tive Science of

    language,

    then no account of humor will be complete with-

    out a computational dimension. This does not necessarily mean that re-

    searchers should implement computational realizations of their models,

    merely that the models are unambiguous to the extent that such realiza-

    tions are at least possible. The goal of course is to take subjectivity out

    of the loop and to somehow capture that aspect of a humorous meaning

    that humans themselves cannot always quantify w ithout recourse to it's

    funny because it makes me laug h. This is an immense challenge and one

    that we should at least aspire to. Our question then is: how should one

    engage of a computationally-viable program of humor research in a cog-

    nitive linguistics framework? One should, we suggest, select a humorous

    sub-phenomenon that is at once both small and easily circumscribed

    (light-bulb jokes, puns, hyperbolic insults, etc.) ndconceptually scalable.

    Scalability is the key issue here: having constructed a detailed model of a

    very specific humorous niche, one will of course want to build on this

    model to capture further aspects of the humor phenomenon, but one can

    only scale if an upgrade path exists between the initial niche and the

    broader picture. Note that scalability depends not only on the phenome-

    non

    itself

    but also on how the phenomenon is tackled and on the as-

    sumptions that are made in formalizing a model.

    For instance, we would submit that while punning has the potential to

    be a scalable phenomenon, the sub-phenomenon of w holly-homophonous

    punning

    is not

    scalable yet that the sub-phenomenon of polysemous-

    punning

    is

    scalable. We base this claim on the realization that polyse-

    mous punning requires a conceptual as well as a phonetic understanding

  • 7/25/2019 Introduction; Cognitive Linguistic Approaches to Humor

    23/27

    Introduction

    225

    a very limited model of deautomatized idioms, one can construct a

    computationally-viable model of trumping that subverts well-known

    idioms using just lexico-semantic inform ation. Th us, from this hum ble be-

    ginning, trum ps like he is the cream in m y coffee; yes, sour c ream can

    be understood and generated. From here it is a steep, but essentially

    climbable upg rade pa th to trump s like I am a great believer in the idiom

    'drown your sorrows', but I can never persuade my wife to go swimming

    with m e. A nd from here it is an even steeper climb to hu m oro us sub -

    version in gene ral, such as the w orld w ould ha ve a lot less litter if they

    gave pointed sticks to blind people .

    To this end, we believe that humor researchers should always have an

    upgrade path, no matter how ambitious, and that we should always ask

    the questions: ho w formalizable is this phe nom eno n, how scalable is

    this phenom enon, and where does its upgrad e pa th lead?

    ^University of Leuven

    ^University College Dublin

    ote

    Correspondence address; [email protected]

    eferences

    Alexander, Richard J.

    1997

    Aspects of Verbal Hum our in English.

    Tubingen: Gunter Narr Verlag.

    Attardo, Salvatore

    1994

    Linguistic Theories of Hum or.

    Ber l in /New York: Mouton de Gruyter .

    1996 Hu m or. In Verschueren, Jef, Jan-O la Os tma n, Jan Blom ma ert, and Chris

    Bulcaen (eds.). Handbook of Pragmatics. Amsterdam/Phi ladelphia: John

    Benjamins, 1-17.

    1997 Th e seman tic foundations of cognitive theories of hum or. Humor. Interna-

    tional Journal of Humor Research 10 (4) , 3 95 ^ 20 .

    2001a

    Hum orous Texts: A Semantic and Pragmatic Analysis.

    Ber l in /New York:

    Mouton de Gruyter .

    2001b H um or and irony in interaction: Fr om mo de ado ption to failure of detec-

    tion. In Anolli , Luigi, Rita Ciceri, and Giuseppe Riva (eds.).

    Say Not

    to Say: New Perspectives on Miscommunication. Am sterdam: IOS Press,

  • 7/25/2019 Introduction; Cognitive Linguistic Approaches to Humor

    24/27

    226

    G. Brone et al.

    Attardo, Salvatore, and Victor Raskin

    1991 Script theory revis it)ed: Jok e similarity and joke representation al mo del.

    Humor: International Journal of Humor Research 4 3), 293 -347 .

    Attardo, Salvatore, Christ ian F. Hempelmann, and Sara Di Maio

    2002 Script oppos itions and logical mech anisms: Mo deling incongruities and

    their resolutions. Humor. International Journal of Humor Research 15 1),

    3 -46 .

    Barcelona, Antonio

    2003 The case for a meto nym ic basis of prag ma tic inferencing: Evidence from

    jokes and funny anecdotes. In Panther, Klaus-Uwe and Linda Thomburg

    eds.). Metonymy and Pragma tic Inferencing.

    Amsterdam/Phi ladelphia :

    John Benjamins, 81-102.

    Barlow, Michael, and Sijzanne Kem mer eds.)

    2000

    Usage-based Models of Language.

    Stanford: CSLI Publications.

    Bergen, Benjamin, and Kim Binsted

    2003 The cognitive linguistics of scalar hum or. In Ac hard , Michel and Suzanne

    Kemmer eds.) .Language Culture andMind Stanford: CSLI Publications.

    Black, Max

    1962 Models and Metaphors. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Brone, Geert

    forth- Hype r- and misun derstanding in interactional hum or.

    Journal of

    coming

    Pragmatics.

    Brone, Geert and Kurt Feyaerts

    2003 The cognitive linguistics of incongruity resolution: M arke d reference-point

    structures in humor. University of Leuven, Department of Linguistics pre-

    print no. 205.

    Coulson, Seana

    2000

    Semantic Leaps: Frame-shifting and Conceptual Blending in Meaning Con-

    struction. New York/Cambridge: Cambridge Universi ty Press.

    Coulson, Seana, and Marta Kutas

    1998

    Frame-Shifting and Sentential Integration

    Cognitive Science Technical Re -

    port No. 98.02). La Jolla, CA: UCSD.

    2001 Getting it: Hu m an event-related brain response to jokes in good and poo r

    comprehenders.

    Neuroscience Letters

    316, 71-74.

    Croft, William, and Alan D. Cruse

    2004 Cog nitive Lingu istics Cam bridge Tex tboo ks in Linguistics). Cam bridge:

    Cambridge University Press.

    Davies, Catherine E .

    1984 Joint jokin g. Imp rovisational hu m oro us episodes in conve rsation. In Brug-

    m an, Claudia et al. eds.). Proceedings of the 10th Annual Meeting of the

    Berkeley Linguistics Society.Berkeley: University of Berkeley Press,360-371 .

    Fauconnier, Gilles

    1994 [1985]

    Mental Spaces.

    Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    1997

    Map pings in Thought and Language.

    Cambridge/New York: Cambridge

    University Press.

    Fillmore, Charles J.

  • 7/25/2019 Introduction; Cognitive Linguistic Approaches to Humor

    25/27

    Introduction

    227

    1997 Diachronic Prototype Semantics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    2003 Dec ontextualizing an d recontextualizing tendencies in 20th-century linguis-

    tics and literary theory. In Mengel, Ewald, Hans-Joerg Schmid, and Michael

    Steppat eds.), Anglistentag 2002 Bayreuth. Trier: Tr ier W issenschaftlicher

    Verlag, 369-379.

    Geeraerts, Dirk, and Hube rt Cuyckens eds.)

    2006

    Handbook of Cognitive Linguistics.

    Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Gibbs , Raymond W., J r .

    1999 Speaking and thinking with metonym y. In Panther, Klaus-Uw e and Gu nter

    Radden eds.) . Metonymy in Language and Thought. Amsterdam/Phi ladel -

    phia: John Benjamins, 61-76.

    Giora, Rachel

    1991 On the cognitive aspec ts of the jo ke . Journal of Pragmatics 16, 465 -485 .

    1997 Un dersta nding figurative an d literal language: Th e graded salience hypo the-

    sis. Cognitive Linguistics 8 3), 183-206.

    2001 Irony and its discontent. In Steen, Ge rard and Dick Schram eds.). The

    Psychology and Sociology of Literature. Amsterdam: John Benjamins, 165-

    184.

    2002 Op timal innov ation and pleasure. In Stock, Oliviero, Ca rlo Stra ppa rava ,

    and An ton Nijholt eds.). The April Fools Day Workshop on C omputational

    Hum our: Proceedings ofthe Twentieth Twente W orkshop on Language Tech-

    nology Series TW TL 20). Enschede: U T Service Centrum , 11-28.

    2003 On our

    Mind:

    Salience, Context and Figurative Language. New York: Ox-

    ford University Press.

    Giora, Rachel , and Ofer Fein

    1999a Irony: Co ntext and salience. Metaphor and Symbol 14, 241-2 57.

    1999b Irony com prehension: Th e graded salience hypothesis. Hum or: Intemational

    Journal of Humor Research 12 4), 425436.

    Hofstadter , Douglas, and Liane Gabora

    1989 Synopsis of the wo rksho p on hum or and cognition. Humor: International

    Journal of Humor Research 2 4), 417 -440.

    Koest ler , Arthur

    1964 The Act of Creation. London: Hutchinson.

    otthoff

    Helga

    1998 Spafi Verstehen. Zur Pragmatik von konversationellem Hum or. Tubingen:

    Niemeyer.

    Lakoff

    George

    1987

    Wom en, Fire and Dangerous Things. What Categories Reveal about the

    Mind

    Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Lakoff

    George, and Mark Johnson

    1980 Metaphors We Live By. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Langacker , Ronald W.

    1987 Foundations of Cognitive Gram mar, vol. 1. Stanford: Stanford University

    Press.

    1988 A usage-based mo del. In Rud zka-O styn, Brygida ed.). Topics in Cognitive

    Linguistics. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins,

    127161.

  • 7/25/2019 Introduction; Cognitive Linguistic Approaches to Humor

    26/27

    228

    G. Brone et al.

    Nunberg, Geoffrey D.

    1979 The non-un iqueness of seman tic solutions: Polysemy.

    Linguistics and Philos-

    ophy

    3, 143-184.

    Panther, Klaus-Uwe, and Gunter Radden (eds.)

    1999 Metonymy in Language and Thought. Amsterdam/Phi ladelphia : John

    Benjamins.

    Panther, Klaus-Uwe, and Linda Thomburg (eds.)

    2003 Metonym y and Pragm atic Inferencing (Pragmatics and Beyond 113).

    Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins.

    Poll io, Howard R.

    1996 Boun daries in hum or and me taph or. In M io, Jeffery Scott and Albert N .

    Katz (eds.), Metaphor: Implications and Applications. Mahwah, NJ: Law-

    rence Erlbaum, 231-253.

    Priego-Valverde, Beatrice

    2003 L humou r dans la conversation familiere: description et analyse linguistiques.

    Paris:

    L Harmat t an .

    Raskin, Victor

    1985

    Semantic Mechanisms of Humor.

    Dordrecht: D. Reidel .

    Ritchie, Graeme

    2004 The Linguistic Analysis of Jokes. London/New York: Rout ledge.

    Saeed, John

    1996

    Semantics.

    Oxford: Blackwell.

    Talmy, Leonard

    1978 Figure and grou nd in complex sentences. In Green berg, Joseph H., Charles

    A. Ferguson, and Edith Moravcsik (eds.), U niversats of Human Language.

    Stanford: Stanford University Press, 625-649.

    2000 Toward a Cognitive Seman tics, vols. 1 and 2. Cam bridge, M A: M IT Press.

    Taylor, John

    2002

    Cognitive Grammar.

    Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Tomasello, Michael (ed.)

    1998 The New Psychology. Cognitive and Functional Approach es to Language

    Structure,

    vol . 1. M ahw ah/L ond on: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    2002

    The New Psychology. Cognitive and Functional Approach es to Language

    Structure, vol . 2 . Mahwah/London: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Vaid, Jyotsna, Rachel Hull , Roberto Heredia, David Gerkens, and Francisco Martinez

    2003 Getting a jok e: The time course of mea ning activation in verbal hum or.

    Joumal of Pragmatics

    35, 1431-1449.

    Van Hoek, Karen, Andrej A. Kibrik, and Leo Noordman (eds.)

    1999 Discourse Studies in Cognitive Linguistics. Amsterdam/Phi ladelphia : John

    Benjamins.

    Yus, Francisco

    2003 H um or and the search for relevance.

    Joumal of Pragmatics

    35, 1295-1331.

  • 7/25/2019 Introduction; Cognitive Linguistic Approaches to Humor

    27/27