intellectual property and pharmaceutical drugs...

12
Intellectual Property and Pharmaceutical Drugs: An Ethical Analysis Richard T. De George recompense if the result they achieve is useful and beneficial to others who are willing to pay for it. It would be unfair or unjust for others to take that result, market it as their own, and profit from it without having expended comparable time or money in development, before the orig- inal developer has a chance to recoup his in- vestment and possibly make a profit. Intellectual property protection gives innovators this chance. The second part of the argument is based on consequences. It states that unless developers are allowed a period during which to recoup their investment and make a profit, the incen- tive to produce new products beneficial to so- ciety will be greatly reduced. Society benefits from new products, both initially and after they are no longer protected and fall into the public domain. Hence, the greatest benefit to the com- mon good or to society is achieved by offering inventors and developers of new products a pe- riod during which they can make their profits without the competition of free riders. Both ar- guments together lead to the conclusion that protection of intellectual property for a limited period of time is just and produces more good for society than an absence of such protection. I shall call the two arguments together the Standard Argument (SA). For the sake of ar- gument, let us accept SA as a valid moral justi- fication for intellectual property. It is general in form, and applies to pharmaceutical products as well as to inventions, machines, and other types of intellectual property. There have been many studies by economists to support the second part of the Standard Argument. The pharmaceutical The notion of intellectual property (IP) is con- tentious. Nonetheless there is justification for granting exclusive rights to some original use- ful products or processes if the result benefits the common good. This is recognized in Arti- cle 1, Section 8 of the U.S. Constitution, which establishes the power of Congress "to promote the progress of science and useful arts, by se- curing for limited times to authors and inven- tors the exclusive right to their respective writings and discoveries." The length of time is somewhat arbitrary, has varied over the past century, and is vastly different for copyright than for patents, the latter offering much stronger protection for a shorter period of time. THE MORAL JUSTIFICATION OF INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY Because intellectual property is significandy dif- ferent from other kinds of property, 1 the ethical defenses of intellectual property differ from the defenses—such as the Lockean—of other kinds of property, and traditions in different parts of the world treat intellectual property differently. Nonetheless, there is a two-part argument in de- fense of the ethical legitimacy of limited intel- lectual property rights that is intuitively attractive, widely held, and, I believe, sound. The first part is a fairness, or justice, argu- ment that says that, within the economic system of free enterprise, those who spend time and/ or money in developing a product or the ex- pression of an idea deserve a chance to receive © 2005. Business Ethics Quarterly 15, no. 4.

Upload: others

Post on 22-Apr-2020

4 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Intellectual Property and Pharmaceutical Drugs ...learn.uncg.edu/courses/phi361/readings/DeGeorge...Ethical Issues Regarding Emerging Technologies 465 PHARMACEUTICAL PATENTS Intellectual

Ethical Issues Regarding Emerging Technologies 465

PHARMACEUTICAL PATENTS

Intellectual Property and Pharmaceutical Drugs: An Ethical Analysis

Richard T. De George

recompense if the result they achieve is useful and beneficial to others who are willing to pay for it. It would be unfair or unjust for others to take that result, market it as their own, and profit from it without having expended comparable time or money in development, before the orig­inal developer has a chance to recoup his in­vestment and possibly make a profit. Intellectual property protection gives innovators this chance.

The second part of the argument is based on consequences. It states that unless developers are allowed a period during which to recoup their investment and make a profit, the incen­tive to produce new products beneficial to so­ciety will be greatly reduced. Society benefits from new products, both initially and after they are no longer protected and fall into the public domain. Hence, the greatest benefit to the com­mon good or to society is achieved by offering inventors and developers of new products a pe­riod during which they can make their profits without the competition of free riders. Both ar­guments together lead to the conclusion that protection of intellectual property for a limited period of time is just and produces more good for society than an absence of such protection.

I shall call the two arguments together the Standard Argument (SA). For the sake of ar­gument, let us accept SA as a valid moral justi­fication for intellectual property. It is general in form, and applies to pharmaceutical products as well as to inventions, machines, and other types of intellectual property. There have been many studies by economists to support the second part of the Standard Argument. The pharmaceutical

The notion of intellectual property (IP) is con­tentious. Nonetheless there is justification for granting exclusive rights to some original use­ful products or processes if the result benefits the common good. This is recognized in Arti­cle 1, Section 8 of the U.S. Constitution, which establishes the power of Congress "to promote the progress of science and useful arts, by se­curing for limited times to authors and inven­tors the exclusive r ight to their respective writings and discoveries." The length of time is somewhat arbitrary, has varied over the past century, and is vastly different for copyright than for patents , the latter offering m u c h stronger protection for a shorter period of time.

THE MORAL JUSTIFICATION OF INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY

Because intellectual property is significandy dif­ferent from other kinds of property,1 the ethical defenses of intellectual property differ from the defenses—such as the Lockean—of other kinds of property, and traditions in different parts of the world treat intellectual property differently. Nonetheless, there is a two-part argument in de­fense of the ethical legitimacy of limited intel­lectual property rights that is intuitively attractive, widely held, and, I believe, sound.

The first part is a fairness, or justice, argu­ment that says that, within the economic system of free enterprise, those who spend time a n d / or money in developing a product or the ex­pression of an idea deserve a chance to receive

© 2005. Business Ethics Quarterly 15, n o . 4.

Page 2: Intellectual Property and Pharmaceutical Drugs ...learn.uncg.edu/courses/phi361/readings/DeGeorge...Ethical Issues Regarding Emerging Technologies 465 PHARMACEUTICAL PATENTS Intellectual

466 Ethical Issues Regarding Emerging Technologies

industry and some economist have persuasively argued that m o r e new drugs are developed when pharmaceutical companies make suffi­cient profits to invest in research and develop­ment, and the pharmaceutical industry argues that the large profits for which the industry is known are necessary to underwri te bo th the high cost of developing a new drug and the large number of initial attempts that never turn into successful, marketable drugs.

The industry then builds on the Standard A r g u m e n t to develop what I shall call the Status Quo Approach (SQA), which is a legal-economic approach, to reply to critics of their policies who a d o p t n o t an economic b u t a moral approach to pharmaceuticals. The Sta­tus Quo Approach takes existing intellectual property law, especially pa tent law, as setting the appropr ia te parameters within which to view and answer all challenges to the practices of pharmaceutical companies. Taking this ap­proach leads to concentration on using the law to help these companies protect and increase their profits so that they can develop new drugs. Thus they defend their techniques to extend the time before which generic drugs can be in­troduced, to extend patent protection on an international level th rough the World Trade Organization (WTO), to produce me-too drugs or drugs that are only marginally different from existing drugs ra ther than concentra t ing on breakthrough drugs, and so on. Morally based attacks that make a link between patents and the availability of drugs for the p o o r are re­jected as misconceived. Nonetheless, there is an at tempt to diffuse the latter attacks by giving away some drugs in some circumstances. These giveaway programs are p resen ted as the in­dustry's or a particular company's living u p to its social responsibility. Social responsibility is the surrogate for moral responsibility, is part of the Status Quo Approach, and is seen by the industry as answering morally based criticism.

The SQA is an approach that pharmaceuti­cal companies are comfortable with, as well as

one that is widely accepted. It has the benefits of tradition, of requiring no change in current practices or law, and of having produced ben­eficial results in the past. Hence, one can argue, it is more likely than untried alternative schemes of intellectual property protection to produce beneficial results in the future. The approach thus entrenches and sanctifies the status quo.

Both the Standard Argument and the Sta­tus Quo Approach, however, are coming under increased strain and attack, and in this paper I shall a t t empt to examine the di rect ion of those strains and the validity of these attacks. Only if we fully appreciate the Standard Ar­g u m e n t and the Status Q u o Approach , a n d their shortcomings, can we make sense of the continuing charges made by critics and the re­sponses made by the pharmaceutical industry. My aim is to br ing some order to a very con­fused and confusing public discussion on the actions of pha rmaceu t i ca l companies , the obligat ions a t t r ibu ted to them, and the c la imed r ight of the publ ic with respec t to needed drugs. Although clarifying the discus­sion is my main pu rpose , I shall also make some suggestions for improving the situation.

THE LIMITS OF THE STANDARD ARGUMENT

Patents, I have argued, can be justified from an ethical point of view. But that justification is l imited. Despite the const i tut ional ly stated basis for patents, ne i ther common good (nor utilitarian) considerations form part of what is requi red for a patent . Nor have ethical con­siderations been a dominan t consideration in changes that have been m a d e in pa t en t law. Hence the details of how pa ten t pro tec t ion has developed do not follow from the ethical justification. It is no t tha t the way in which patent law has developed is unethical, but that it is only one of many sets of ethicallyjustifiable ways of protect ing pharmaceuticals.

Page 3: Intellectual Property and Pharmaceutical Drugs ...learn.uncg.edu/courses/phi361/readings/DeGeorge...Ethical Issues Regarding Emerging Technologies 465 PHARMACEUTICAL PATENTS Intellectual

Ethical Issues Regarding Emerging Technologies 467

Discussions of intellectual property are very complex and involve knowledge of convoluted laws, legal decisions, and economic and busi­ness analyses. Typically, at any negotiation in­volving intellectual property prior to the drafting of legislation, the parties are govern­ment officials, lawyers, and corporate repre­sentatives. Thus the best defense of those policies is given not in ethical but in legal and economic terms. This is why the SQA uses these. Critics, however, fail to be convinced by such considerations. It is not clear to them who, if anyone, represents the general public in the general process. It is difficult for any government to represent both the consumer and the industry, and the public's trust in gov­ernment as representing the public's interest is lessened when the industry present in the negotiations is the pharmaceutical industry, which is known for being one of the most suc­cessful lobbying groups and for being among the top spenders of lobbying money.

The complaint about the Standard Argu­ment is not that it is wrong, but that it is taken to prove too much and to respond to all ob­jections. The mantra that is repeated by in­dustry representatives in every context and in reply to every criticism with respect to intel­lectual property protection, pricing, and access is that unless the pharmaceutical companies are profitable enough to have the funds to do so and can expect future profits from their products, they will not engage in R&D and will not develop new drugs, which, of course, ben­efit society as a whole. When critics point to the fact that the industry has the highest rate of profit of any industry year after year, this is the primary answer. When critics complain about the high cost of drugs and the fact that the price of drugs increases much faster than the inflation rate, this is their answer. When the critics claim that the developed nations are forcing the less-developed ones to adopt stan­dards of intellectual protection that go against their traditions and may not be in their best

interests, this is their answer. When critics say that the reason for intellectual property pro­tection is not private profit but the common good, this is the answer. And all this makes some sense because there is ample evidence that, without profits, there are few new drugs developed. Yet the answer covers over a good deal, as I shall try to show. . . .

THE RIGHT-TO-HEALTH-CARE ARGUMENT

Just as the Standard Argument is often as­sumed by the pharmaceutical industry, the de­fense of the right to health care is often assumed by its critics. The critics do not deny the overall validity of the SA and the SQA, but at its limits the critics challenge the applica­tion of the argument and the defenses of their practices given by representatives of the phar­maceutical industry. The central claim is that although the Standard Argument justifies the right to intellectual property, the right is only a prima facie and not an absolute right. In many cases the right holds sway and trumps other considerations. But in the case of phar­maceuticals it comes up against other prima facie rights, namely the right to life, the right to adequate health care, and the right to access essential lifesaving drugs; it comes up against the obligation to aid those in need; and it comes up against competing claims made in the name of the common good. The right to life, the right to adequate health care, the right to access to essential lifesaving drugs, and the obligation to aid those in need, critics note, must be given at least as much consideration as intellectual property rights. Not only do IP rights not necessarily trump those other rights, but they are in fact often trumped by them. The pharma industry tends to argue that in­tellectual property rights are always sacrosanct, when they are not. Although critics sometimes give too little weight to the actual strength of

Page 4: Intellectual Property and Pharmaceutical Drugs ...learn.uncg.edu/courses/phi361/readings/DeGeorge...Ethical Issues Regarding Emerging Technologies 465 PHARMACEUTICAL PATENTS Intellectual

468 Ethical Issues Regarding Emerging Technologies

IP rights, the rights to health and to health care raise serious issues in certain circumstances about the pharma industry's claims. Hence the discussion does no t end with simply asserting the Standard Argument and the SQA.

What then are the arguments in support of the r ight to hea l th and heal th care and the right to access, and how can they be weighed against the right to intellectual property?

There is considerable confusion in the liter­ature, and although the basic ethical claims are usually fairly clear, how they are justified is not.

We can start by distinguishing two different rights that are often confused. They are related but are not identical. One is the right to health; the o ther is the right to heal th care. The UN Declaration of H u m a n Rights, Article 25, states

(1) Everyone has the right to a standard of liv­ing adequate for the health and well-being of himself and of his family, including food, cloth­ing, housing, and medical care and necessary social services, and the right to security in the event of unemployment, sickness, disability, wid­owhood, old age, or other lack of livelihood in circumstances beyond his control.

Al though there are a n u m b e r of different rights included in this sentence, for our pur­poses two are centra l . O n e is t h e r ight to heal th ; the o the r is the r ight to medica l or hea l th care. It is general ly agreed tha t the rights stated in the Declaration are primarily rights that members of a state enjoy vis-a-vis their governments. Thus, the primary obliga­tion that is correlative to the right to heal th falls o n the state. T h e r igh t to hea l th has perhaps received so little at tent ion in devel­o p e d na t ions because in its most plausible sense these nations face no problem with re­spect to it. Most plausibly the right to health is analogous to the right to life. T h e state can­not give anyone health. Its obligation, rather, is to ensure that the conditions necessary for maintaining good heal th are provided and to prevent any party from damaging the health of

another. Unders tood in this way, the state has the obligation to provide those conditions that p romote the heal th of its citizens, such as en­suring clean water and air, providing sewers and sanitation, and taking o the r basic mea­sures necessary to p r o m o t e and pro tec t the health of its members. But although states may have that general obligation, their obligation does not exhaust the obligation of others. The rights impose obligations on business, indi­viduals, and others as well. It is a violation of the h u m a n r ight to heal th , for instance, for manufacturers to d u m p toxic waste that will infiltrate a community's water supply and cause people to fall ill. The obligation no t to cause harm to people 's health and thus no t to act in this way is a negative obligation. Positively, com­panies are b o u n d to provide safe and healthy working conditions for their employees. Pro­viding these condi t ions is an obligation im­posed on them by their employees ' r ight to health, whether or no t it is also requi red by law. And positively, the government has the obligation to pass and enforce such laws.

If one reads the right to heal th care in the same way, then it is an obligation of states or governments to see that medical care is avail­able to their people, whether or no t the gov­ernments actually provide it. Although states are generally held responsible for protect ing the heal th of their citizens by providing the c o m m o n goods of clean dr inking water and sewers and other general sanitation facilities, they are no t usually held responsible for pro­viding health care in the same way. The reason is that the principle of subsidiarity comes into play. The principle of subsidiarity states that one does not call on a h igher level to do a job that can be done at a lower level. With respect to heal th care, it is usually applied intuitively, even by those who do no t use that term. Thus, when children get sick, for instance, it is typi­cal for their parents to care for them, and fam­ily members usually are the primary caregivers, ra ther than the state. When a family is unable

Page 5: Intellectual Property and Pharmaceutical Drugs ...learn.uncg.edu/courses/phi361/readings/DeGeorge...Ethical Issues Regarding Emerging Technologies 465 PHARMACEUTICAL PATENTS Intellectual

Ethical Issues Regarding Emerging Technologies 469

to adequately care for someone who needs medical care, they might first go to the circle of friends, or to the larger community. When the community cannot handle the need, they go to the city or the state or federal level. Al­though in a developed society the structures are in place to handle the needs of people at the appropriate level, they are considerably different in a country that has a socialized med­icine program than in a country that does not. If a government is unable to handle the need or needs it faces, it might appeal to the inter­national community. Also assumed by this process is that individuals have not only the right to health and health care, but they also have the obligation to do what they can to pre­serve their health and to care for themselves to the extent they are able to do so. Thus the rights to health and to health care impose cor­relative obligations on many parties. So far the obligations of pharmaceutical companies are no different from the obligations of other com­panies. But this is only part of the story.

Another argument comes into play here that develops the obligation to help others in serious need to the extent that one can do so. There are two versions of this. One is a weak version which says that one has the obligation to help others in serious need to the extent that one can do so with little or moderate cost to oneself. A stronger version says that one must do so even at great expense to oneself, although one does not have to make oneself worse off than the person or persons one is helping. The obligation to aid others in serious need can be justified by either a rule-utilitarian approach, which argues that more good is achieved overall if this rule is followed than if it is not; or by a deontological approach, which bases it on the respect due others as persons and beings worthy of respect. The obligation is one that is widely acknowledged. Intuitively, if one sees a child drowning and one can save the child's life by extending a hand, one has the obligation to do so. Not to do so would be

characterized by most people as inhuman or barbaric. The obligation holds even if one will be late to an appointment, or if one will get one's shoes wet in the process of saving the child. The obligation becomes less clear as the cost to oneself increases, and most would agree that one is not obliged to save the child at the risk of one's drowning oneself.

The application of this principle with re­spect to an individual vis-a-vis a drowning child is straightforward. It becomes more and more problematic as the case becomes more com­plex. What if the child is drowning in the water of a crowded beach, with a thousand people on it? Is it the obligation of each of the thou­sand to save the child? Is the obligation greater for those closer? Is it exculpatory for someone who is dressed to say that the obligation falls on those in bathing suits? Would all be equally blameworthy if no one did anything and the child drowned? Now increase the number of children drowning, say from an overturned boat, to twenty. Each person on the beach can save at most one of the children. Is it the oblig­ation of every person on the beach to save all the children, or to save only one, and, if the lat­ter, which one? When we then move to mil­lions of people in danger of death from the lack of medical care in the world and ask what is the obligation of developed countries, of those living in developed countries, of NGOs, and of pharmaceutical companies with respect to the needy, the arguments tend to get more and more tenuous. This is not to say that there is no obligation to help based on the right of the people to health or medical care. But the complexity of the situation suggests the need for action by many parties on many levels.

If one accepts the obligation of aid, then it is not difficult to argue that those in the best po­sition to help have the greatest obligation to do so. Nowjoin that with the fact that those in the health professions have special obligations with respect to health and health care. They have these special obligations because of the field

Page 6: Intellectual Property and Pharmaceutical Drugs ...learn.uncg.edu/courses/phi361/readings/DeGeorge...Ethical Issues Regarding Emerging Technologies 465 PHARMACEUTICAL PATENTS Intellectual

470 Ethical Issues Regarding Emerging Technologies

they have freely chosen, because they are related to health care in a way others are not, because they have the expertise that others lack, and be­cause they make their living or profit from health-related activities. A doctor, for instance, has a greater obligation to help an accident vic­tim if other aid is not available, than does some­one without medical training. A hospital has a greater obligation to help an accident victim brought through its doors than does a bank or a department store, and people naturally would bring such victims to a hospital rather than to some other kind of enterprise. . . .

With this background we can develop the right to access to needed medicines. But the ar­gument works differently with respect to life-saving medicines, to those which are necessary for heal th but which treat non-life-threaten­ing illnesses, and to those that are nei ther and are simply life-enhancing.

T h e s t rongest case can be m a d e for the right to access to those drugs that are essential for the preservation of life. If one has the right to life, then one has the right to that which is necessary to sustain one 's life—be it food and shelter, or medicines and medical care. Med­icines, obviously, are included in medical care. The right of access to available lifesaving med­icine has both a negative and a positive aspect. Negatively, all have the obligation no t to pre­vent anyone from having access to what they need to sustain their lives. The positive oblig­ation to ensure that access is available, as in the earl ier case, falls on a variety of part ies (applying the principle of subsidiarity) and is practically limited by the goods and resources available in a given situation. . . .

I shall call the set of a rgumen t s I have sketched out above the Moral Argument .

People typically invoke something like the above general arguments with respect to the drug industry and drug companies. The vari­ous claims are that the industry as a whole and the individual companies that make it u p have special obligations; that these are related to

what they p roduce , namely pharmaceut ica l drugs; that they are in a special posit ion to help and that therefore they have the special obl igat ion to d o so; a n d tha t those in d i re need, because of their right to health care, im­pose obligat ions on those able to he lp , in­cluding the pharmaceutical industry.

We can apply this claimed right to access both on the international and on the national level in the United States and see how we can weigh it against the right to intellectual property.

We should note that approaching ethical issues relating to the pharmaceutical industry from the perspective of the Moral Right to Ac­cess dramatically changes the issues that rise to the surface as opposed to those that arise when taking the Standard Argument and the Status Quo Approach. To see how, we can start with the pha rmaceu t i ca l compan ie s ' use of the term "social responsibility."

THE MORAL RESPONSIBILITY OF PHARMACEUTICAL COMPANIES

With this background, we can now ask: What are the obligations, from an ethical point of view, of the pharmaceutical industry as a whole and of individual pharmaceutical companies? T h e above discussion forms the background that is generally unde r s tood by critics, even though they do no t often articulate their ar­guments very clearly. Can we come u p with general obligations that stem from the rights of those in need of medical care? Clearly, phar­maceutical companies are not the only health­care providers and the entire obligation to fulfill the rights in question does not fall on them. And clearly if they have special obligations, that does not mean that governments, individ­uals, families, NGOs, and so on do not also have obligations. Since governments have the pri­mary responsibility to provide for the health care of their citizens, they bear the primary oblig­ation. They may ei ther mee t this obligation

Page 7: Intellectual Property and Pharmaceutical Drugs ...learn.uncg.edu/courses/phi361/readings/DeGeorge...Ethical Issues Regarding Emerging Technologies 465 PHARMACEUTICAL PATENTS Intellectual

Ethical Issues Regarding Emerging Technologies 471

directly or indirectly by ensuring the needs of the public are met in some other way.

Given present structures, the pharmaceuti­cal industry, as part of the health-care system, ar­guably has two basic ethical obligations. I shall call the first the Production Obligation and the second the Access Obligation. The obligations of the industry with respect to health care are broader and more general than the obligations of any particular pharmaceutical company. The industry's obligations can only be met to the extent that individual companies take the ap­propriate action. Yet the two levels—industry and company—should be kept distinct, even though many critics conflate the two.

The Production Obligation

The Production Obligation consists in the obligation to develop and produce beneficial drugs. This is the area of the industry's ex­pertise and it is that which the companies in the industry can do that others cannot. More­over, in this regard one can argue that the pharmaceutical industry as well as individual companies have the obligation to pursue needed new lifesaving drugs more than to pur­sue alternatives to drugs that already exist and are effective, namely, so-called me-too drugs. Benefit to the patient, and hence to the pub­lic and the common good, should play a greater role in the case of health care than in other industries, just as safety is paramount in the engineering industries, whether it be in airplane or building and bridge safety. This first obligation is not an unjust imposition by society, but simply reflects part of the role of pharmaceutical companies in society. The obligation is one that is arguably shared by governments also. The United States Govern­ment funds billions of dollars worth of medical research, and it is appropriate that it does so because of its obligation to fulfill the rights of its citizens to health and to health care. In a free enterprise system governments do not

engage directly in production, although they can encourage and promote production through their system of intellectual property protection and their tax system, among oth­ers. To the extent that the pharmaceutical in­dustry fails to produce needed drugs, it is up to governments to ensure that they are produced.

Many pharma companies and the industry in general, as well as government-sponsored pro­grams, are engaged in the search for cures or remedies for cancer, various kinds of heart dis­ease, new and improved antibiotics to fight in­fections, and so on. The industry as a whole, therefore, not only is actively engaged in fulfill­ing this obligation, but individual pharmaceu­tical companies have an economic interest in pursuing breakthrough and essential new drugs. The market for such drugs, if they treat diseases suffered by large numbers of people in the de­veloped countries, is potentially lucrative.

Nonetheless the market incentive fails with respect to orphan drugs. Diseases which are lifethreatening but in which the market is ei­ther small or the potential recipients poor, re­quire a different approach.

In the United States the Orphan Drug Act has proven to be a successful marriage of government and pharmaceutical companies. The government provides tax incentives and guarantees 7 years of exclusivity (after FDA ap­proval) to encourage drug makers to develop drugs that affect fewer than 200,000 people and are generally unprofitable. The result has been, on the whole, positive, despite abuses. . . .

The market similarly fails with respect to the development of drugs for diseases restricted to those living in tropical countries. Although the governments in such countries have the re­sponsibility for providing for the health of their people, they have insufficient funds to promote research and in addition they lack the facili­ties and the expertise needed. With minimal budgets for health care, they have difficulty pro­viding the bare essentials of clean water and sanitation and developing an adequate delivery

Page 8: Intellectual Property and Pharmaceutical Drugs ...learn.uncg.edu/courses/phi361/readings/DeGeorge...Ethical Issues Regarding Emerging Technologies 465 PHARMACEUTICAL PATENTS Intellectual

472 Ethical Issues Regarding Emerging Technologies

system for health care, regardless of the cost of drugs. Under these conditions the obligation of aid comes to the surface. In this case the ap­propriate aid is the development of drugs for the diseases in question. The obligation does not clearly fall on any particular pharmaceuti­cal company, and how it is to be apport ioned among countries and the pharmaceutical in­dustry worldwide is a topic that urgently needs addressing. The first step in any solution, how­ever, is to recognize the obligation. Perhaps something comparable to an international or­p h a n d rug act can be agreed upon ; perhaps governments can subsidize special research in these areas; perhaps companies can agree to fund jo in t research for drugs that would not be covered by patents and would be produced and distr ibuted at cost. T h e actual action taken should be the result of negotiations among all the interested and affected parties. The phar­maceutical industry clearly has an impor tan t role to play in any such negotiations. But ap­proaching the problem from the point of view of the Moral Argument brings to the fore oblig­ations in this regard that the Standard Argu­men t and the Status Quo Approach do not.

Al though I have indicated the financial in­centive that d rug companies have to pursue impor tan t new drugs, critics of the pharma­ceutical indust ry have concen t r a t ed on whether the drug industry is actually doing ei­ther all it can and should do, or all it claims to be doing with respect to the development of new drugs. The issue arises in par t because of the industry's use of the Standard Argument and the Status Q u o Approach. The many tac­tics used by pharmaceutical companies to pro­duce profits are justif ied, the SA a n d SQA claim, because these profits are necessary to fund the research that has led to and will lead to the deve lopmen t of new essential drugs . The industry thus implicitly acknowledges that the product ion of such drugs is its goal, even if it does no t acknowledge that it is also its obligation.

I t is in this context that some critics claim that the amoun t that the industry spends on R&D is less than the amoun t that it spends on marketing (including advertising, free samples to doctors, etc.), that the a m o u n t may even be less than the amount it spends on lobbying gov­e r n m e n t officials; that most of the profits it makes are not in fact plowed back into research bu t distributed as dividends to shareholders; and that most of the research that leads to new drugs comes from government - funded re­search, the results of which are appropriated for private gain. All of this may be appropri­ate. But it is no t self-evidently so, and this is what most concerns the critics. The industry in its blanket claims fails to be convincing.

According to a 2002 study of the National Insti tute for Hea l th Care Managemen t Re­search and Educational Foundation for the pe­riod 1989-2000, only 35 percent of new drug applications contained new active ingredients (of which only 15 percent were considered to provide "significant improvement over existing drugs") , while 54 pe rcen t were incrementa l modifications of existing drugs (and u n d e r Hatch-Waxman get u p to 3 years of market ex­clusivity) and 11 percent were identical to ex­isting drugs.2 Although these facts by themselves prove nothing with respect to the obligation to provide new drugs, they are used by critics to off­set the image that the pharmaceutical industry suggests by its use of the SA to justify its ap­proach to the development of new drugs.

To be convincing the industry must first ac­knowledge its obligations; but even more im­portant it must be willing to show why the above activities are necessary to produce new drugs. Simply pointing to new drugs as proof is an in­stance of a logical fallacy. Simply because new drugs have been produced and the industry has been profitable using its advertising, lobbying, and other techniques, does not show that these techniques are necessary to produce new drugs.

If one takes the obligation to p roduce new lifesaving drugs seriously, t h e n o n e migh t

Page 9: Intellectual Property and Pharmaceutical Drugs ...learn.uncg.edu/courses/phi361/readings/DeGeorge...Ethical Issues Regarding Emerging Technologies 465 PHARMACEUTICAL PATENTS Intellectual

Ethical Issues Regarding Emerging Technologies 473

consider changes in the status quo with re­spect to IP. Essential, lifesaving drugs can and arguably should be distinguished from other drugs for a variety of purposes. Me-too drugs and incremental changes, as well as cosmetic changes, do no t clearly deserve the same pro­tection or the same encouragemen t and in­ducemen t on the par t of government . . . .

The Access Obligation

The second obligation, the Access Obligation, is the obligation to make the drugs the indus­try or a company develops available to those who n e e d t h e m . Simply developing t h e m would no t serve any purpose otherwise. Ful­filling this obligation may be compatible with the existing structures relating to existing prac­tices concerning intellectual property, pricing, government regulation, charity, and so on. Yet critics claim that bo th the industry and the market fail to some extent with regard to this obligation, and they claim that if and when cu r ren t practices i m p e d e the fulfillment of this obligation, then the r ight to access and the concomitant obligation to provide access take precedence over IP and other rights.

The argument as we have developed it so far imposes a stronger obligation on governments to ensure access than it does o n the pharma­ceutical industry. As we have developed the ar­gument to aid, it comes into play most clearly in times of dire need. This would apply most clearly with respect to essential lifesaving drugs. The obligation to help those in need in less dire circumstances is proport ionately weaker. But the obligation of governments is no t to ensure access only for lifesaving drugs, but for all drugs needed for health. Governments are obliged to ensure their people have access, whether by actually buying and supplying the drugs or by other means—such as making sure the price of drugs makes them accessible. The right to access puts a strain on any strong claim to in­tellectual property rights in drugs, if what stands

in the way of people receiving lifesaving drugs is maximizing corporate profit.

(a) Let us look at the poor countries first. The question of access to many medicines is a press­ing need. Although governments have the re­sponsibility to enable or provide access, it is beyond the ability of many of them to do so. Hence the obligation falls on others able to do so. Included in that number are pharmaceu­tical companies, especially those that manu­facture the needed drugs. The issue was brought to global attention by the AIDS epi­demic. The drugs in question are very expen­sive and only a few are on the current WHO list of essential drugs because of that. The most widely used such drug in poor countries is a combination of three generic drugs produced by the Indian pharmaceutical company Cipla. Nonetheless, it is clear from the Moral Argu­ment that when millions of people are dying and can benefit substantially from available medicines, they have a right to access with re­spect to them. A consensus is emerging that many parties are ethically responsible for ac­cess—the patient, the local government, other governments that can help, NGOs, interna­tional organizations, and the drug companies. The problem is clearly not only the result of practices of pharmaceutical companies. Even if the drugs were given away free, access by many of the needy would still be a problem. And a number of pharmaceutical companies have instituted plans to give away antiretroviral drugs, to sell them at cost, or to license them for production by generic manufacturers in less developed countries under certain condi­tions. Arguably they are at least to some extent meeting their obligation to be part of the so­lution. (We have already seen the arguments of critics to the industry's approach that it is being socially responsible by its programs.)

Both nations and companies seem to ac­knowledge in principle the obligation to re­spond in case of dire need. Thus, for instance, a provision of the TRIPS agreement states that mandatory licensing of necessary medicines is justifiable in times of extreme national emer­gencies (such as epidemics) as decided by the country in question. Yet despite the Agreement the right to access is not being met and the phar­maceutical industry bears part of the blame. The TRIPS Agreement, despite its recognition of the obligation to aid, has in practice had little

Page 10: Intellectual Property and Pharmaceutical Drugs ...learn.uncg.edu/courses/phi361/readings/DeGeorge...Ethical Issues Regarding Emerging Technologies 465 PHARMACEUTICAL PATENTS Intellectual

474 Ethical Issues Regarding Emerging Technologies

effect and has been faulted for a number of rea­sons. In 2001 PhRMA and a group of pharma­ceutical companies charged South Africa with violating the WTO's rules on patents by pro­ducing the drugs needed by their people and 40 companies filed suit. After much adverse pub­licity, the charges and the suit were withdrawn. But neither the industry nor the companies in­volved ever acknowledged the right of the South African government to provide access to the needed life saving drugs in accord with the spirit of TRIPS, if not with its letter.

The TRIPS Agreement requires that poor countries adopt the type of IP protection found in the developed countries. They must do so whether or not it impedes the government of the country in question from meeting its oblig­ation to provide access to needed drugs for its people. In this way it fails to consider the com­mon good of the people of the country in ques­tion. For instance, while strong defenses of intellectual property with respect to pharma­ceuticals may produce the best results overall for developed countries, they do not seem to do so for poor and developing countries, such as India. If, as drug companies claim, new drugs cost $800,000,000 to develop, then developing countries are probably not able to develop any. They are better served by developing generic drugs or by requiring compulsory licensing of drugs or by some other strategy. Compulsory licensing and parallel importing policies—with measures adopted to prevent the development of a gray market—would arguably benefit poor countries more than present arrangements. The Moral Argument puts these as well as other suggestions on the table for consideration, while the Standard Argument and the Status Quo Approach—used in negotiating TRIPS— in effect prevent their being raised. . . .

(b) As opposed to poor countries that cannot af­ford drugs, the United States can afford to pay for drugs. In fact the United Stated both pays more for drugs and contributes more to the profit of the pharmaceutical companies than any other nation. So the aspect of the right to access that has received the greatest attention is the barrier of high prices to access, even though access and price are not the same thing. Even if drugs were free, access requires that the drugs be transported, distributed, and administered to patients. At issue is accessibil­ity, especially of the newer drugs for which no competitive generic drug is available. Although

the lack of accessibility for the poor and el­derly on restricted incomes gets most publicity, more and more people are complaining that the high cost of drugs is limiting accessibility by putting the cost of insurance out of their reach. As insurance prices rise, employers are less and less willing to pay the escalating costs and are forcing employees to bear a larger and larger portion of the cost. The complaints against the pharmaceutical industry focus especially on two issues that are seen as limiting access. One is the high and ever increasing price of new drugs covered by patents. Not only the poor and elderly, but even middle-class families find that the "co-pay" portion of medicines is in­creasing at a rate so much faster than inflation that they are having a harder time keeping up. The second is what is seen as illegitimate at­tempts by drug companies to "extend" their patents and to prevent generic drugs from en­tering the market, thereby keeping prices high and restricting access for those who can afford only the lower cost of the generics.

The Status Quo Approach simply applies market economics, assuming the force of law in protecting intellectual property rights with respect to patents, and adding that the over­all result is not only fair but produces the most good for society. A rights approach to health care yields a different focus. If the right to access to needed drugs is more important than the right to property, then the status quo is up for evaluation and becomes a candidate for change, rather than for passive acceptance. The issue then is not what does market eco­nomics prescribe, but how should the status quo be changed to do justice to the right to access to needed drugs. This means once again that intellectual property rights with respect to pharmaceutical drugs should be carefully scrutinized and perhaps changed. . . .

i. Access and the Cost of Drugs. My earlier ar­g u m e n t dis t inguished between those drugs that are necessary for life and those that are impor tant for illnesses that are not life-threat­ening. In the United States critics of pharma­ceutical industry pricing are critical of both, and for the most part insurance plans do not distin­guish clearly between the two kinds of drugs. The assumption—and as we have seen a dubious assumption—of most Americans is that they are

Page 11: Intellectual Property and Pharmaceutical Drugs ...learn.uncg.edu/courses/phi361/readings/DeGeorge...Ethical Issues Regarding Emerging Technologies 465 PHARMACEUTICAL PATENTS Intellectual

Ethical Issues Regarding Emerging Technologies 475

entitled or have a right to the best drugs available for their condition. The relation between the cost of health insurance and the price of medi­cines and between the cost of health care and the price of medicines is complicated. But the cost of medicines has increased much faster than the cost of health care generally, and the justi­fication for the increase in not obvious, except if one invokes market economics and produces the not-surprising result that the market has been willing to pay the higher prices.

The right to access argument in the U.S. is jo ined to a fairness argument. That argument says that fairness involves all parties paying their fair share for medicines, including paying suffi­cient amounts so that drug companies have a continuing incentive to produce more benefi­cial drugs. The complaint is not that American consumers are subsidizing drugs for the poor countries, or even that they are subsidizing the pharmaceutical companies' compassionate pro­grams. That would be acceptable, and the better off—such as Americans in general—may well have the obligation to bear this cost. But under the Status Quo Approach, in effect, Americans are subsidizing not only poor countries but also seem to bear a disproport ionate load. Japan, Canada, and the countries of Europe all nego­tiate much lower prices than are available in the United States. Americans are increasingly find­ing it not only ironic but unfair that U.S. drugs cost more in the United States than in other de­veloped countries. This leads to such anomalies as the U.S. government presently prohibit ing the importation of U.S.-made drugs from Canada for personal use. while various state governments attempt to find ways of making it legal for senior U.S. citizens to buy U.S.-made drugs from Canada, where the government helps keep the price lower than it is in the United States. . . .

The standard reply to all questions about the high cost of drugs is to appeal to the SA and the SQA and claim that unless there are the profits brought about by high prices, there will be many fewer future drugs. The Status Quo Approach

tends to present a quest ionable dichotomy: either protect drugs and drug pricing to the maximum or face a future with fewer new in­novative drugs. The claim is made no matter what the percent of profit, no matter what the prices, no matter how much the industry spends on lobbying and advertising to consumers. The claims are blanket, the justification is blanket, and the public is asked to take the claims on faith. The consuming public must take it on faith that money spent on the recently devel­oped technique of advertising prescription drugs to the general public, for instance, is necessary to produce the profits that will lead to new drugs. They must take it on faith that money spent on researching minor changes in existing drugs is necessary to produce the profits that will lead to new drugs. They must take it on faith that the various tactics that seek loopholes in legisla­tion—whether with respect to the Orphan Drug Act to garner windfall profits or Hatch-Waxrnan or other legislation to keep competition at bay as long as possible—are necessary to produce the profits that will lead to new drugs.

Tha t faith has been shaken. Because there is very little transparency in d rug pricing eco­nomics, the claims have worn thin. That the in­dustry needs the highest rate of profit of any industry is no t obvious, even for the produc­tion of new p roduc t s / The lack of adequate transparency exacerbates the communicat ion gap and hinders fruitful dialogue. Abuses and attempts at gaming the system further erode trust. . . .

ii. Access and Patents. If there is a difference between different kinds of drugs, and if people have a greater right to access to the more es­sential drugs than to the less essential ones, then at least it becomes an open question what the best means of protecting the different kinds is. If one takes seriously the Moral Argument, then the assumption of the SQA that all drugs deserve the same length or s t rength of pro­tect ion a n d tha t they should be t rea ted the

Page 12: Intellectual Property and Pharmaceutical Drugs ...learn.uncg.edu/courses/phi361/readings/DeGeorge...Ethical Issues Regarding Emerging Technologies 465 PHARMACEUTICAL PATENTS Intellectual

476 Ethical Issues Regarding Emerging Technologies

same as all other patents in all other areas, is on the table for discussion. Al though the laws governing patents are uniform for all products and processes, the range of processes and prod­ucts is extensive, the differences among them considerable, and so the a rgument for a one-size-fits-all approach is questionable. Moreover, the pressure on pharmaceutical patents is dif­ferent from the pressure on patents in general. No one has a right to a better mouse trap, and the marke t may legitimately de te rmine who gets one ; bu t the r ight to access to essential medicines places an obligation on all those who can satisfy that right to come u p with an equitable means of doing so. . . .

Since access and price are related, attempts to extend the protected life of a drug by intro­ducing slight modifications to get new patents or to delay the entry of generic competitors— which would lower the price and increase ac­cessibility—are no t justified by the Standard Argument and are more appropriately seen as taking advantage of the system.. . .

T h e task with respect to pharmaceut ica l products is to balance claims to intellectual property rights against the rights to access to needed medicines, the common good, and the obligation to aid. The economic argument that unless companies can make a profit from their research in discovering, developing, and pro­ducing drugs, they will no t produce them, is only a partial defense of the existing patent sys­t em a n d one that focuses only on proper ty rights. It is only a partial defense because patent protection is not the only conceivable way of ei­ther protecting intellectual property or of guar­anteeing profits. It does no t show that o ther alternatives—public financing of research and development, cooperation instead of compe­tition on some drug development, government regulation of prices or guarantees of profits at a certain level for certain drugs, and so on, are no t viable alternatives. In particular, the SA and SQA do no t show that intellectual prop­erty rights, no mat ter how strong and justifi­able, t rump the right to basic health care and

the right of access to needed medicines or that the right to profits trumps these, the common good, or the obligation to aid. . . .

NOTES

1. Unlike other property, intellectual property is infinitely shareable. It can be stolen, borrowed, copied, and one still has it. Intellectual property refers to some products of the mind. But ar­guably the most important products—ideas— cannot be claimed as one's property. Only the expressions of ideas or their embodiment in some product or process can with any plausi­bility be said to constitute property in any sense. Even in these cases, no expression or invention is developed completely independendy. In the realm of knowledge one always builds on what has gone and has been developed before and is part of the public domain.

2. NIHCM, "Changing Patterns of Pharmaceuti­cal Innovation," p. 3 at http://www.nihem.org/ innovations.pdf.

3. According to the Fortune 500 Report, in 2001, the pharmaceutical industry was the most prof­itable industry again for several years running. In 2001 the profit of the top 10 drug makers increased 33 percent, and drug prices in­creased 10 percent, even though the rate of inflation was only 1.6 percent. The Public Citizen (April 18, 2002, "Pharmaceutical Industry Ranks as Most Profitable Industry—Again" at http://www.citizen.org/congress/refoirn/drug_ industry/profits) notes that "The drug industry maintains that it needs extraordinary profits to fuel risky R&D into new medicines. But com­panies plow far more into profits than into R&D. Fortune 500 drug companies channeled 18.5 percent of revenue into profits last year. Yet they spentjust 12.5 percent of revenue on R&D." It also reports that for 2002 the industry had re­turn on assets of 14.1 percent (compared with a median of 2.3 percent for Fortune 500 com­panies) ; that it spent 30.8 percent of its revenue on marketing and administration, but only 14.1 percent on R&D; and that its direct-to-consumer advertising increased from $800 million in 1996 to $2.7 billion in 2001. (Public Citizen, Congress Watch, June 2003, "2002 Drug Industry Profits: Hefty Pharmaceutical Company Margins Dwarf Other Industries," at http://www.citizen.org/ congress/reform/drug_industry/r_d/articles. cfm?ID=9923).