how semanticists derive narrow scope. 2 chierchia not come children children didn’t come. e...

37
How semanticists derive narrow scope

Upload: gerald-eastling

Post on 31-Mar-2015

215 views

Category:

Documents


1 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: How semanticists derive narrow scope. 2 Chierchia Not come Children Children didn’t come. e x[-come(x)] children k x[-come(x)] Children k (after the kind

How semanticists derive narrow scope

Page 2: How semanticists derive narrow scope. 2 Chierchia Not come Children Children didn’t come. e x[-come(x)] children k x[-come(x)] Children k (after the kind

2

Chierchia

Not comeChildren

Children didn’t come.

e

x[-come(x)]childrenk

x[-come(x)]Childrenk (after the kind type-shift that is obligatory to acquire argument status)

<e,t>

-come(childrenk)

=-(come(childrenk))=-(Qx[R(x,childrenk)&Q(x)] x[come(x)] )=-(Qx[R(x,childrenk)&Q (x)] x[come(x)])x[come(x)]come(x)

Page 3: How semanticists derive narrow scope. 2 Chierchia Not come Children Children didn’t come. e x[-come(x)] children k x[-come(x)] Children k (after the kind

3

Krifka (simplified)

ComeChildren

Children didn’t come.

<e,t>

x[-come(x)]x[children(x)]

x[-come(x)]x[children(x)]

<e,t>

x[-come(x)] x[children(x)]

= -come(x[children(x)])

= -(come(x[children(x)]))not allowed in standard Montague grammar!!!

=-(Qx[children(x)&Q(x)] x[come(x)] )=-(Qx[children(x)&Q (x)] x[come(x)])x[come(x)]come(x)

Page 4: How semanticists derive narrow scope. 2 Chierchia Not come Children Children didn’t come. e x[-come(x)] children k x[-come(x)] Children k (after the kind

4

Conclusion

> Narrow scope is always accounted for by local type-shifting and doesn’t presuppose that bare nominals always refer to kinds.

Carlson builds type-shifting into predicates.

Krifka applies local type-shifting to nouns.

Chierchia applies local type-shifting to nouns with a small detour via kinds.

> General constraint on covert type-shifting: apply it as locally as possible.

Page 5: How semanticists derive narrow scope. 2 Chierchia Not come Children Children didn’t come. e x[-come(x)] children k x[-come(x)] Children k (after the kind

The empirical validity of a locality constraint on type-

shifting

Page 6: How semanticists derive narrow scope. 2 Chierchia Not come Children Children didn’t come. e x[-come(x)] children k x[-come(x)] Children k (after the kind

6

Do bare nouns take wide scope?

YES!NO!

Min QueThe rest of the world (or close to it…)

If they do, there is no reason to assume a locality constraint on type-shifting...

The answer...

English (Carlson), Spanish (Espinal and McNally 2010 and references therein), Hungarian (Farkas and de Swart 2003), Russian (Geist 2010), Albanian (Kalluli 2001), Hebrew (Doron 2003), Hindi (Dayal 2003, 2004), Mandarin Chinese (Yang 2001, Rullmann & You 2006), Indonesian (Chung 2000, Sato 2008), Javanese (Sato 2008), Turkish (Bliss 2003), Brazilian Portuguese (Schmitt & Munn 1999)

Page 7: How semanticists derive narrow scope. 2 Chierchia Not come Children Children didn’t come. e x[-come(x)] children k x[-come(x)] Children k (after the kind

7

How to go about testing scope?

> A first attempt

Every boy read a book.

a. There is a book that every boy read.

b. Every boy is such that he read a book.

Why is this not a good format for test items?

wide

narrow

Because every situation that makes a. true will also make b. true.

Page 8: How semanticists derive narrow scope. 2 Chierchia Not come Children Children didn’t come. e x[-come(x)] children k x[-come(x)] Children k (after the kind

8

How to go about testing scope?

> A better attempt

John didn’t read a (single) book.

a. There is a book that John didn’t read.

b. John read no book.

Why is this a better format for test items?

wide

narrow

Because a. can be true in situations in which b. is not true.

Page 9: How semanticists derive narrow scope. 2 Chierchia Not come Children Children didn’t come. e x[-come(x)] children k x[-come(x)] Children k (after the kind

9

A small classroom experimentDeze diagnose heeft ons doen inzien waarom hij sommige dwangideeën heeft, zoals altijd de eerste willen zijn (op de trap, in bad, aan tafel...) of woedebuien (omdat hij dingen niet begrijpt) of irrationele angsten (zoals steeds denken dat er bijen rond zoemen, terwijl het soms maar een grasmaaier is). Hoe ouder hij wordt, hij is nu bijna acht jaar, hoe duidelijker het autisme wordt.

Ik vind het absoluut niet leuk dat hij moet huilen vanwege mij. En dat is wel een aantal keren op een dag, omdat hij dingen niet mag of dat hij juist iets moet (naar bed gaan bijvoorbeeld). Ik weet dat het er bij hoort, maar leuk is anders. Nu kan ik er weer even tegen.

omdat hij dingen niet begrijpt

because he things not understand

omdat hij dingen niet mag

because he things not may

Does this necessarily mean that he doesn’t understand anything?

Does this necessarily mean that he’s not allowed to do anything?

Page 10: How semanticists derive narrow scope. 2 Chierchia Not come Children Children didn’t come. e x[-come(x)] children k x[-come(x)] Children k (after the kind

The set-up of the English experiment

Page 11: How semanticists derive narrow scope. 2 Chierchia Not come Children Children didn’t come. e x[-come(x)] children k x[-come(x)] Children k (after the kind

11

Setting-up the bare nominal test items

A.B.

A.B.

This last sentence is truth-conditionally only compatible with a wide scope reading of colleagues.

Task: judge the naturalness of the last utterance with respect to the rest of the dialogue on a scale from 0 to 5.

Rationale: subjects should not accept a continuation in which Flynn contradicts himself.

Page 12: How semanticists derive narrow scope. 2 Chierchia Not come Children Children didn’t come. e x[-come(x)] children k x[-come(x)] Children k (after the kind

12

Further design of the experiment

An experiment that would only look at the acceptability of bare nominal items would be meaningless.

Why?Because we wouldn’t know what the numbers meant.

Our baseline

Given that we were testing whether bare nominals could scope above negation, we needed an item that could not.

> Negative Polarity Items

Page 13: How semanticists derive narrow scope. 2 Chierchia Not come Children Children didn’t come. e x[-come(x)] children k x[-come(x)] Children k (after the kind

13

An example of an NPI test item

Page 14: How semanticists derive narrow scope. 2 Chierchia Not come Children Children didn’t come. e x[-come(x)] children k x[-come(x)] Children k (after the kind

14

Further design of the experiment

Experiments also need control items and fillers.

Why?

Control items are used to check whether people are actually sensitive to the phenomenon one is testing.

Our control items > Singular indefinites

Filler items are used to try to distract subjects in such a way that they don’t discover what the experiment is really about.

Our fillers > See example

Page 15: How semanticists derive narrow scope. 2 Chierchia Not come Children Children didn’t come. e x[-come(x)] children k x[-come(x)] Children k (after the kind

15

An example of a singular indefinite

Page 16: How semanticists derive narrow scope. 2 Chierchia Not come Children Children didn’t come. e x[-come(x)] children k x[-come(x)] Children k (after the kind

16

Examples of filler items

Page 17: How semanticists derive narrow scope. 2 Chierchia Not come Children Children didn’t come. e x[-come(x)] children k x[-come(x)] Children k (after the kind

17

Further design of the experiment

> Overview of the number of items:

2 NPI items2 Singular indefinite items3 Bare plural items5 Fillers

> Participants and procedure:

Questionnaire was put online. Included a number of questions that would allow us to weed out non-native speakers. Total number of relevant questionnaires: 63.

Page 18: How semanticists derive narrow scope. 2 Chierchia Not come Children Children didn’t come. e x[-come(x)] children k x[-come(x)] Children k (after the kind

Results of the English experiment

Page 19: How semanticists derive narrow scope. 2 Chierchia Not come Children Children didn’t come. e x[-come(x)] children k x[-come(x)] Children k (after the kind

19

Results: Means and SD

Page 20: How semanticists derive narrow scope. 2 Chierchia Not come Children Children didn’t come. e x[-come(x)] children k x[-come(x)] Children k (after the kind

20

Results: Means and SD

Page 21: How semanticists derive narrow scope. 2 Chierchia Not come Children Children didn’t come. e x[-come(x)] children k x[-come(x)] Children k (after the kind

21

Results: statistics

There’s a (significant) difference between the NPI items and the BP items.

There’s a (significant) difference between the BP items and the SI items.

There’s a (significant) difference between BP1 and BP2. /

Paired t-tests

Page 22: How semanticists derive narrow scope. 2 Chierchia Not come Children Children didn’t come. e x[-come(x)] children k x[-come(x)] Children k (after the kind

Conclusion of the English experiment

Page 23: How semanticists derive narrow scope. 2 Chierchia Not come Children Children didn’t come. e x[-come(x)] children k x[-come(x)] Children k (after the kind

23

Do bare nouns take wide scope?

There is ground to assume that bare nouns can take wide scope.

> This means that the general narrow scope behaviour cannot be derived solely by forcing covert type-shifting to apply locally.

> Covert type-shifting turns out to be less constrained than might seem at first sight.

Page 24: How semanticists derive narrow scope. 2 Chierchia Not come Children Children didn’t come. e x[-come(x)] children k x[-come(x)] Children k (after the kind

Questions/discussion

Page 25: How semanticists derive narrow scope. 2 Chierchia Not come Children Children didn’t come. e x[-come(x)] children k x[-come(x)] Children k (after the kind

25

Modification

Page 26: How semanticists derive narrow scope. 2 Chierchia Not come Children Children didn’t come. e x[-come(x)] children k x[-come(x)] Children k (after the kind

26

Modification

Page 27: How semanticists derive narrow scope. 2 Chierchia Not come Children Children didn’t come. e x[-come(x)] children k x[-come(x)] Children k (after the kind

27

Syntax

Page 28: How semanticists derive narrow scope. 2 Chierchia Not come Children Children didn’t come. e x[-come(x)] children k x[-come(x)] Children k (after the kind

28

The preference for narrow scope

Page 29: How semanticists derive narrow scope. 2 Chierchia Not come Children Children didn’t come. e x[-come(x)] children k x[-come(x)] Children k (after the kind

29

The preference for narrow scope

Page 30: How semanticists derive narrow scope. 2 Chierchia Not come Children Children didn’t come. e x[-come(x)] children k x[-come(x)] Children k (after the kind

30

The preference for narrow scope

Page 31: How semanticists derive narrow scope. 2 Chierchia Not come Children Children didn’t come. e x[-come(x)] children k x[-come(x)] Children k (after the kind

31

Participant comments

Page 32: How semanticists derive narrow scope. 2 Chierchia Not come Children Children didn’t come. e x[-come(x)] children k x[-come(x)] Children k (after the kind

32

Participant comments

Page 33: How semanticists derive narrow scope. 2 Chierchia Not come Children Children didn’t come. e x[-come(x)] children k x[-come(x)] Children k (after the kind

33

Differences between test items

Page 34: How semanticists derive narrow scope. 2 Chierchia Not come Children Children didn’t come. e x[-come(x)] children k x[-come(x)] Children k (after the kind

34

Differences between test items

Page 35: How semanticists derive narrow scope. 2 Chierchia Not come Children Children didn’t come. e x[-come(x)] children k x[-come(x)] Children k (after the kind

35

Differences between test items

Page 36: How semanticists derive narrow scope. 2 Chierchia Not come Children Children didn’t come. e x[-come(x)] children k x[-come(x)] Children k (after the kind

36

Participants

Page 37: How semanticists derive narrow scope. 2 Chierchia Not come Children Children didn’t come. e x[-come(x)] children k x[-come(x)] Children k (after the kind

37

Mistakes