hegel, g.w.f. - the jena lectures on the philosophy of spirit (18o5-6).pdf

Upload: segismundo-schcolnik

Post on 06-Feb-2018

227 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/21/2019 Hegel, G.W.F. - The Jena Lectures on the Philosophy of Spirit (18O5-6).pdf

    1/96

    H E G E L

    and the

    H U M A N

    SPIRIT

    A translation of

    the lena Lectures

    on the Philosophy

    of Spirit (18O5-6)wi th commentary

    by

    LEO RAUCH

    Wayne State University Press Detroit 1983

  • 7/21/2019 Hegel, G.W.F. - The Jena Lectures on the Philosophy of Spirit (18O5-6).pdf

    2/96

    Copyright 1983 by Wayne State University Press,

    Detroit, Michigan 48202. All rights are reserved.

    No part of this book may be reproduced

    without formal permission.

    The translation of the text is from G. W. F. Hegel,

    Gesammelte Werke,

    Volume 8:

    fenaer Systementwurfe

    III

    (Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag, 1976), edited by

    Rolf-P. Horstmann with Johann Heinrich Trede.

    By permission of the copyright holder,

    the Rheinisch-Westfahsche Akademie der

    Wissenschaften in Diisseldorf.

    Libraryof Congress Cataloging in Publ ica t ion Data

    Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, 1770-1831.

    Hegel and the human spirit.

    Translation of the text is from G.W.F. Hegel,

    Gesammelte Werke, Volume 8: Jenaer Systementwurfe III

    (Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag, 1976) T.p. verso.

    Bibliography: p.

    1.

    PhilosophyAddresses, essays, lectures.

    I. Rauch, Leo. II. Title.

    B2908 1983 193 83-12509

    ISBN: 0-8143-1739-1

    To Gil a

    .

    . .whose ideait

    / \

    M

    b

    *i

  • 7/21/2019 Hegel, G.W.F. - The Jena Lectures on the Philosophy of Spirit (18O5-6).pdf

    3/96

    CONTENTS

    Preface 9

    Introduction: On Hegel's Concept of Spirit

    15

    G. W. F. Hegel:

    The Philosophy of Spirit

    (1805-6) 83

    P A R T I .

    Spi r i t Accord ing to I t s Concept

    85

    A. Intelligence

    85

    B.

    Will

    99

    P A R T I I .

    Actual Sp i r i t

    11 9

    A.

    Recognition

    12 0

    i. Immediate Recognition

    12 0

    ii.

    Contract

    12 4

    i i i. Crime and P unishment

    12 8

    B.

    The Coercive Law

    13 2

    i. [Law and Marriage]

    13 4

    ii. [Law and Property]

    13 8

    iii.

    [Judicial Force]

    14 1

    iv. [Law, Life, and Death]

    14 5

    P A R T I I I .

    C o n s t i t u t i o n

    15 1

    A. Classes: The Nature of Self-Ordering Spirit

    16 2

    i. The Lower Classes and Their Outlooks

    16 3

    ii .

    The Universal Class

    16 7

    B.

    Government: The Self-Certain Spirit of Nature

    17 1

    C. Art, Religion, and Science

    17 3

  • 7/21/2019 Hegel, G.W.F. - The Jena Lectures on the Philosophy of Spirit (18O5-6).pdf

    4/96

    PREFACE

    On October 13, 1806, Jena fell to Napoleon's

    army. Hegel saw the great manhimself, history focused to a

    single point, "t his w orld-soul . . . on horseback." Just a few

    days before, Hegel had sent the first half of his

    Phenomenol-

    ogy f Spirit

    to his friend Niethammer in Bamberg, who was

    to relay the manuscript to the publisher. Despite Hegel's en-

    thusiasm for Napoleon, there was considerable danger. A few

    days later, Hegel fled his house and the city, carrying the last

    pages of the

    Phenomenology

    with him. Tradition has it that

    he finished them amidst the sounds of the battle.

    Hegel liked to see contemporary events, and philosophy

    itself,

    in global terms; for it is by reference to the cosmic, the

    universal, that the particular gets its meaning. Hegel saw Na-

    poleon, the "world-soul on horseback" (which phrase the

    French eventually mistranslated asla raison a cheval),as the

    unwitting instrument for the cosmic emergence of historical

    self-consciousness. Hegel's teaching and writing had well pre-

    pared him for this sort of perspective, this way of seeing

    everything in the broadest possible context. Indeed, in the

    preface to the Phenomenology written only after the main

    text had been completed, and possibly with the Napoleonic

    army already in view, Hegel says: "The true is the totality."

    Any partial "truth" would run afoul of its opposite and be

    contradicted by it. Only the entirety, Hegel believed, can be

    trusted to give the parts their proper meaning. Only a com-

  • 7/21/2019 Hegel, G.W.F. - The Jena Lectures on the Philosophy of Spirit (18O5-6).pdf

    5/96

    Preface

    plete world-system can enable us to understand the details

    whethe r it be a "deta il" such as the battle of Jena, or a philo-

    sophical "truth/

    7

    When Hegel came to Jena, in 1801, it was the center of

    philosophy in Germany. At the University, twelve men had

    been teaching philosophy, among them Schiller, Fichte (until

    1799), the Schlegels, and Schelling. Early in 1801, Hegel left

    Frankfurt and accepted Schelling's invitation to come and stay

    with him. Soon thereafter, Hegel wrote a book entitled

    Th e

    Difference Between Fichte's and Schelling's Systems of Phi-

    losophy. The time must have been an exciting and crowded

    one for him. A t the end of the sum mer semester, he submitted

    a postdoctoral dissertation (on planetary orbits) as a way of

    applying for a teaching post at the University. He took the

    qualifying examina tion and was awarded the right to lecture. It

    was his thirty-first birthday. He began as aPrivatdozentin the

    winter term of 1801-2. Two years later, he announced that he

    would present his entire philosophy as a unified w orld-system.

    The lecture series of 1803-4 and 1805-6 constitute two ver-

    sions of that system, and a part of the latter series makes up the

    subject of this book. In February, 1805, he was promoted to

    associate professor, and shortly thereafter decided to publish

    th e Phenomenology,on which he had been working.

    The Phenomenology of Spirit is Hegel's greatest work and

    and probably one of the ten most profound works in all phi-

    losophy. It has continued to fascinate, for its symphonic com-

    plexity as for its gothic mysteries. Many of the ideas dis-

    cussed in the

    Phenomenology

    were first aired in Hegel's Jena

    lectures of 1803 to 1806. This feverish period saw Hegel's first

    approaches to themes such as praxis, recognition, alienation,

    and the life and death of cultures. These ideas, beyond their

    value in and for themselves, have taken their place in the

    body of world tho ught, and have had an enormous impact on,

    for exam ple, Marxism, existentialism, and the social sciences.

    But it was here that they were given their first formulation.

    It was the Phenomenology, however, that had the lasting

    impact, and these lectures were forgotten. Not until a century

    after Hegel's death were the Jena lectures published. In 1931,

    10

    Preface

    the 1805-6 lectures were published by Johannes Hoffmeister

    as Jenenser Realphilosophie II. In the next year, the 1803-4

    lectures were published asJenenserRealphilosophie I. hi 1976,

    a critical edition of the 1805-6 lectures was issued by the

    Rhine-W estphalian A cademy of Sciences, as part of a new and

    comprehensive edition of Hegel's writings. The translation,

    publication, and discussion of this Jena material h as lagged far

    behind its interest and effect. No English translation has yet

    been done of the 1 805-6 series of lectures on the philosophyof

    Nature and on the philosophy of Spirit; nor has any book been

    devoted in its entirety to them, even though the lectures on the

    philosophy of Spirit have been discussed extensively in the

    works of Lukacs, Marcuse, Habermas, and Avineri, among

    others, and have excited considerable curiosity. (As for the

    1805-6 lectures on the philosophy of Nature, no doubt some-

    one will be coming forward with a translation of them before

    long.)

    Each series of the Jena lectures was offered as a world-

    system: both a philosophy of nature and a philosophy of the

    human spirit. The problem facing any commentator on them,

    however, is that they are lecture notes, not finished texts.

    Many points are left cryptic, perhaps meant to be expanded in

    class discussion. Thoughts are often left unconnected, and

    connecting sentences must be interpolated. There are exten-

    sive marginal notes, some of great interest, but it is not al-

    ways clear what point in the text they are meant to illumi-

    nate. In this respect, the 1976 Academy edition sometimes

    differs radically from the 1931 edition, appending a note to a

    different place in the text and thus giving it a different con-

    text of meaning. (A look at the actual manuscript shows how

    tenuous all this is.) Some statements merely hint at what

    they mean, and the commentator is on thin ice in trying to

    interpret them. Of course, one can turn to other writings of

    Hegel in support of one interpretation or another, but this

    also has its dangers and difficulties.

    On one hand, Hegel's thinking is all of a piece: his ideas, in

    1805,

    are continuous with those of 1821 and after. It is as

    though he knew, from the very beginning of his mature think-

    11

  • 7/21/2019 Hegel, G.W.F. - The Jena Lectures on the Philosophy of Spirit (18O5-6).pdf

    6/96

    P r e f a c e

    ing, exactly what his philosophy was and where it would take

    him, and he sim ply set about expounding it. For this reason it

    would seem perfectly legitimate to rely on a passage, say, in his

    Encyclopaedia(1817) to illumin ate some dark point in the Jena

    lectures of 1805. The trouble with that approach, however, is

    that the consistency we see is established inductively: itfol-

    lows from the texts, but cannot dictate their course. Accord-

    ingly, no reference to a later work can serve to establish con-

    clusively anything about the earlier work and therefore many

    of the dark points must remain dark. We must remember that

    what we have here are lecture notes, to which Hegel made

    numerous marginal additions which are merely

    keys,

    not open

    doors to his full intentionsand these keys are often keys for

    him alone. Sometim es Hegel jots down a word or phrase, and

    its connection to the context is clear; sometim es it is not. The

    manuscripts themselves resemble the scores of Beethoven

    more than Mozart, with numerous changes and additions, de-

    letions and ins ertions. Hegel will sometimes let himselfgoin a

    marginal passage which runs on for pages and seems to depart

    from the context which inspired it. T he scholars of the Acad-

    emy have done an outstanding job in putting the manuscripts

    together, even if, in some instances, you can see them guess-

    ing. The reader of the translation presented here will have to

    keep this in mind, and read the footnotes not as the clarifying

    additions that footnotes are usually intended to

    be,

    but as after-

    thoughts , hints at emerging lines of thinking which Hegel may

    have intended to follow up in the presentation of his lectures,

    but did not do so in the lectures as written out.

    In most of the editorial decisions, I have followed the lead

    of the 1976 edition, especially in regard to specific points of

    phrasing and the placing of the marginal notes. The editors of

    the new edition have obviously been far more scrupulous in

    their reading tha n Hoffm eister was in 1931. I have followed

    neither edition slavishly, however, and have broken up para-

    graphs and changed punctuation in what I felt were the inter-

    ests of clarity. In some cases I have taken the liberty of "at-

    taching" a marginal note to a point a few words prior to or

    after the place assigned to it in the 1976 edition, on the

    12

    Preface

    grounds that my placement seems to make better sense. But

    in no cases are these editorial liberties of a controversial na-

    ture, and whenever an explanatory woisd-or phrase has been

    added by me, this has been indicated by square brackets.

    (Where a marginal note of Hegel's is a word or phrase ap-

    pended to a sentence in the text, I have put the phrase in a

    footnote without capitalizing the initial letter, to indicate

    that it is a continuation of the sentence. Where a marginal

    note comprises a whole sentence or sentences, I have natural-

    ly capitalized th e first word.)

    The difficulties for the Hegel translator are further com-

    pounded in a work such as this which was never intended for

    publication. As a text, these 1805-6 lectures are incomplete:

    only in being read by Professor Hegel, in the lecture hall,

    would its jotted hints become voiced thoughts. Thus, even

    with bracketed additions and introductory essays, this incom-

    pleteness is a problem which the translator can at best only

    partially overcome.

    A further problem stems from the difference between Ger-

    man and English as philosophical languages: the tendency, in

    German, is to let one word mean as many things as possible,

    while the tendency in English is (ideally) to use words which

    have no more than one meaning or which will stand for no

    more than one meaning throughout a given context. Thus

    the German tendency is to be explosively connotative, and

    this has unquestionably conditioned German philosophical

    thinking up to the present day. This cultural difference

    makes philosophy originally expressed in German often ap-

    pear ambiguous in Englishunless, that is, the translator

    adopts and indicates different meanings for the same word,

    as the context dictates. But even this endeavor can prove

    frustrating to the translator, who must try to fix a meaning

    for a word which Hegel uses loosely.

    The three most notorious instances of this ambiguity in

    language are, in my opinion, Geist, Entdusserung, and Auf-

    hebung. The first of these is used not only in the context of

    individual "mind/

    7

    but also in that of the political and cul-

    tural self-awareness on the part of a community, as well as

    13

  • 7/21/2019 Hegel, G.W.F. - The Jena Lectures on the Philosophy of Spirit (18O5-6).pdf

    7/96

    f t s f

    the very mysterious "spirit" which moves world history.

    Since Hegel uses the one word Geist, for these three very

    different meanings, what we as readers must do is both to

    isolate these meanings from each other and find a common

    meaning for all three which would enable us to use the one

    term. (This, it seems to me, is the key to understanding He-

    gel.) In the same way, Entdusserungmeans, for Hegel, "exter-

    nalization" and "alienation/' each with a positive as well as

    negative connotation. In order to convey the meanings of that

    term, I have used one word or the other, sometimes both in

    tandem. It is obvious that Hegel is in many places exploiting

    the ambiguity of these words.Aufhebung, too, has positive as

    well as negative connotations, and quite often Hegel intends

    both in the one word. Thus it means (at the minimum) "tran-

    scendence," "overcoming," "elevation," and "retention," as

    well as "cancellation," "negation," "annulment," "dissolu-

    tion," "abrogation," "termination," "suspension," "suppres-

    sion," "sublation," "removal," and "repeal." Here, too, I have

    chosen the word (or two) which I believe best conveys the

    meaning. Another somewhat less problematic term is

    A n-

    schauung. Despite its variegated meanings, the standard En-

    glish rendering is "intuition." I have stayed with that where

    possible, but have not hesitated to use other renderings where

    the context would have made "intuition" awkward. (After all,

    Weltanschauung is "world view," not "world intuition.") In

    the questionable cases, I have added the German term in pa-

    rentheses in order to alert the reader.

    I could go on, to complain (as a translator) of other words

    Hegel used, and of the way he used thembut that would be

    unmannerly on my part, when the host is so gracious and the

    feast so rich.

    14

    INTRODUCTION

    On Hegel 's Concept

    of Spirit

    The Jena lectures are an attemp t at presenting a

    comprehensive world-system. Any such system m ust include

    (and reconcile) two seemingly opposed aspects: the world of

    physical nature and the world of mind. One is extended in

    space, the other in time. One is determined by physical forces

    and laws, the other is supposedly free. There are numerous

    ways of distinguishing between the two sorts of things which

    make up the cosmic inventory. And the more sharply we

    draw the distinction, the more pointedly the question may be

    asked: how can one universe include both sorts of things?

    It is easy enough to polarize the distinctionsalmost any-

    one can be a dualist. The deeper challenge, however, is to

    emphasize the distinctions and then to resolve them, to start

    as a dualist and then to arrive at a monistic and all-inclusive

    view of the world without, however, blurring the differences.

    On the other hand, it is equally easy to be a monist, to say

    that everything in the world is only one kind of entity (mate-

    rial particles, say, or sense impressions). This, however, leads

    to simplification and reduction: spatial entities such as tables

    and chairs are undeniably different from mental entities such

    as thoughts and desires. How, then, are we to conceive of a

    world that can include them both, with their differences?

    The profound achievement of Hegel is that he is neither a

    dualist nor a monist; he regards both these outlooks as merely

    partial truths, and, therefore, as partial falsehoods as well.

    Whenever Hegel considers one of the traditional dichot-

    15

  • 7/21/2019 Hegel, G.W.F. - The Jena Lectures on the Philosophy of Spirit (18O5-6).pdf

    8/96

    Hegel

    and the

    Human Spirit

    omiesmind/body, subject/object, being/becoming, univer-

    sal/particular, infinite/finitehe regards it not as offering a

    choice between alternative viewpoints,

    but

    rather

    as a

    polar-

    ity which must

    be

    resolved.

    The

    truth

    in its

    totality does

    not

    restat the levelofdivision,and such division must therefore

    be overcomein favorof thehigher, comprehensive truth.The

    clue

    to

    resolving

    the

    various divisions, Hegel believes, lies

    in

    the human effort

    to

    arrive

    at

    such comprehensive truth,

    or,

    more precisely, lies

    in our

    awareness

    of

    that effort.

    The hu-

    man consciousness, becauseit"includes"alldichotomies,ab-

    sorbs them intoitself, isthustheultimate unityof all differ-

    ences. Indeed,

    it is the

    very essence

    of

    consciousness,

    as

    Hegel

    sees

    it, to be the

    absolute unity

    of

    opposites.

    (The

    more funda-

    mental duality,

    the

    choice between dualisms

    as

    against

    mo-

    nisms,is as old as philosophy itself.)

    The Jena lectures of 1805-6 comprise an internal duality

    themselves, since there

    is a

    section

    on the

    philosophy

    of Na-

    ture

    and

    another

    on the

    philosophy

    of

    Spirit.

    The

    former

    in-

    cludes topics such

    as

    mechanics, chemistry,

    and

    physics,

    which arediscussedin a waythat is rather abstruseand the

    entire sectionis by now well out-of-date.Thesectionon the

    philosophy

    of

    Spirit,

    on the

    other hand,

    has

    much

    to say to us

    today,

    and

    offers discussions

    on the

    topics

    of

    intellect, will,

    recognition, alienation, property,law,crimeandpunishment,

    social classes,and thetheoryof culture.

    In

    his

    Encyclopaedia

    of the

    Philosophical Sciences(1817),

    Hegel divides

    the

    philosophy

    of

    Spirit into three sections:

    Subjective Spirit (which concerns

    the

    psychological aspect),

    Objective Spirit (concerning

    the

    political

    and

    social),

    and Ab-

    solute Spirit (art, religion, philosophy). This arrangement is

    approximated

    in the

    Jena lectures,

    the

    difference being

    in the

    main headings

    and how

    they subdivide; also,

    the

    area

    of ob-

    jective spiritishere given greater weight thantheothertwo.

    What Hegel wants

    to

    show

    is the

    continuity

    of the

    human

    spirit, from

    the

    level

    of the

    individual psyche

    to

    that

    of the

    transcultural. From

    the

    level

    of the

    individual intellect

    to

    that

    of culture and beyond, there is one Geist which breathes

    throughall.

    16

    Introduction

    P A R T I. Spirit According tcrlts Concept

    A .

    Intelligence.

    In

    undertaking

    to

    discuss-*the areas

    of

    intel-

    lect

    and

    will,

    as two

    components

    of the

    subjective human

    spirit, Hegel

    is

    addressing himself

    to

    another

    of the

    well-

    known dichotomies

    in the

    tradition

    of

    philosophy. Intellect

    and will have traditionally been seen

    as two

    functions

    op-

    posed

    to one

    another,-

    and if any

    dichotomy ever needed

    re-

    solving, this

    one

    does. Indeed

    it is

    along these lines that

    the

    psyche itself

    is

    divided against

    itself.

    Yet intellect

    and

    will have certain aspects

    in

    common,

    as

    functions of the psyche. First, there is their indeterminacy,

    since

    no

    external force

    can

    dictate what their content will

    be.

    Second, thereis the characteristicway the intellectand the

    will point beyond themselves

    to a

    specific conte nt.

    And

    third,

    they haveadimensionof universality, whereby their content

    is broadened into

    the

    "types" which

    the

    intellect uses

    in its

    thinking, and in the caseof the will, into the "ideals"and

    "ends" which

    the

    will sets

    for itself.

    Yet

    the

    differences b etween t hem

    are

    just

    as

    great. First,

    the

    standards involved

    in the use of

    the intellect (e.g., consistency)

    arenot thoseof thewill (e.g., assertiveness). Second,theintel-

    lect's affirmation doesnotnecessarily leadto action,asdoes

    the affirmation

    on the

    part

    of the

    will. Third,

    we

    usually

    de-

    ploy

    the two

    functions

    in

    opposite directionsthe theoretical

    against

    the

    practical,

    the

    vita contemplativa against

    the

    vita

    activa. This listof similaritiesanddifferencescanbe extended

    at length.

    As

    was

    said earlier,

    for

    Hegel

    it is the

    essence

    of

    conscious-

    nessto be theunity ofopposites. This unity requires eachof

    two opposed elements

    to be

    identical

    to the

    totality.

    Yet

    this

    seems self-contradictory,

    for how can two

    opposed things

    be

    identical to the same thing? In regard to intellect and will,

    however,

    the

    contradiction

    is

    only

    a

    seeming

    one,

    since

    it is

    altogether transcendedin theunifying consciousness.

    We

    can now see,

    more generally,

    one of the

    ways

    by

    which

    Hegel arrives at the unification of dualities, whatever they

    might

    be. He

    will take

    one

    term, such

    as

    G^ist"conscious-

    17

  • 7/21/2019 Hegel, G.W.F. - The Jena Lectures on the Philosophy of Spirit (18O5-6).pdf

    9/96

    Hegel

    and the

    Human Spirit

    ness,"

    "mind," "spirit"and apply

    it to

    both sides

    of an

    oppo-

    sition.

    The

    opposed e ntities the n become mere aspects

    of

    that

    unifying termand since that term

    is of

    broader scope than

    either

    of the

    polar terms,

    we

    would

    be

    wrong (methodologi-

    cally)

    to

    ascribe

    an

    independent reality

    to

    either

    of the

    poles.

    They

    are

    therefore annulled , transcendedaufgehobenpre-

    served within

    the

    unifying term

    and at the

    same time negated

    by

    it.

    One problematic feature (among many)

    in

    this approach

    is

    that

    the

    unifying term Hegel uses will most likely already

    exist in ordinary language, and thus will carryits connota-

    tions with it intoitsphilosophicaluse. Thetermisextended

    beyond its ordinary connotations by being givena technical

    (i.e., philosophical) meaningand thenwe mayexpecta se-

    ries of clashes between the various meanings. Althoughthe

    German word Geist mayadmitof such technical extension,

    the English words "consciousness," "mind,"

    and

    "spirit"

    do

    so only with difficultyso that, inordinary English,we gen-

    erally speakof a cultural "spirit"or acollective "mind" only

    with inverted commas added.

    Yet

    one

    reason

    why we

    cannot rest satisfied with ordinary

    language

    is

    that

    it is

    much

    too

    restricted

    by

    finitude

    and par-

    ticularity. What marks intelligence,

    on the

    other hand,

    is its

    element

    of

    universality. Thus intelligence steps back from

    the

    particularity

    of a

    thing

    to see it in its

    generic,

    or

    universal,

    light

    (the way the

    thing conforms

    to a

    type,

    and soon).Yet in

    ordinary perception,

    and in the

    language associated with

    it,

    we

    are

    immersed

    in the

    particularity

    of

    objects.

    In

    stepping

    back from that particularity,

    we

    step into

    an

    awareness

    of

    ourselves,

    and in so

    doing

    the

    intelligence becomes pure

    sub-

    ject, entirely

    for

    itself"in contrast

    to the

    object, which

    is

    "in

    itself. For

    Hegel, then,

    air

    knowledge

    is

    problematic,

    since

    it

    involves contrasting elementse.g.,

    the

    subjective

    and the objective, the universal and the particularwhich

    must clash, at least implicitly. When the clash is madeex-

    plicit,as aconflict orevenacontradiction,it can beresolved

    (aswas said earlier)by themindin its awarenessof its own

    activity in positing these elements. Accordingly, all knowl-

    18

    Introduction

    edge leads implicitly

    to

    self-kntfwledge. That implicit trajec-

    tory, made explicit, becomes

    the

    dialectic

    of

    knowledge.

    Now that

    we

    have seen

    how

    consciousness

    is

    beset

    by in-

    ner oppositions,

    and

    even contradictions (which

    it is

    supposed

    to reconcile),

    we can

    well expect

    the

    concept

    of

    sei/-knowl-

    edge

    (as

    consciousness

    of

    consciousness)

    to be

    even more

    self-

    contradictory. Indeed,

    the

    concept

    of

    self-knowledge

    is one of

    the most problematic

    and

    important ones

    in

    Hegel's philoso-

    phy. Usually, when

    I

    know something,

    I

    objectify

    it as

    there,

    as "other" thanmyself. How,then,can"knowing"beapplied

    to the self, when the knowing subject is the object known?

    Hegel'sway out of this difficulty, here,is tosay'that what^the

    intelligence graspsis notitselfbut its act.

    Above all, in this unity of subject and object in self-

    knowlege, intelligence is in and for itself. In thisway the

    dichotomy between knowerandknownisovercome. WhenI

    am immersed

    in

    experiencing

    the

    ordinary world

    of

    objects,

    the selfis anobject in itself as all other objectsare. But in

    knowing itself, the self is both in itself and for itself

    self-enclosed

    andyet

    open

    to itself.

    Here, then,

    we

    have

    a

    concrete example

    of how

    Hegel uses

    the

    concept

    of

    human

    consciousness

    to

    overcome

    one of the

    traditional dichoto-

    mies .In my

    self-consciousness,

    I

    have

    my own in itself as

    my object:

    I am

    separated from

    it, and yet I am at one

    with

    it.

    In this

    we see the

    autonomy

    of

    consciousness,

    its

    freedom

    from

    all

    external determination

    in the

    power

    to

    relate

    to, or

    negate,

    any and

    every thing th at

    is the

    object

    of

    consciousness.

    Hegel speaks

    of the

    self

    and

    consciousness

    as an All-

    Encompassing Night,

    in

    which anything, everything,

    or

    noth-

    ing

    can

    occur. Thus

    the

    self is negativity, a frightening vacuity,

    for

    it is

    totally arbitrary

    in its

    freedom, free

    to

    call forth im ages

    or

    to

    ignore them,

    to

    connect

    or to

    dismember them.

    To

    "mean" (meinen)

    is to

    "make mine"

    {mein).

    In

    being reminded

    of something,Igiveit themeaningofbeing-for-me.hiremind-

    ing myself [eiinnein],I re-internalize [innere],and I thereby

    re-entermyself.

    Inall this, Hegel revealsthe roleof theselfand the im-

    plicit awareness

    of

    oneself:in

    all

    awareness

    as

    such. Knowl-

    19

  • 7/21/2019 Hegel, G.W.F. - The Jena Lectures on the Philosophy of Spirit (18O5-6).pdf

    10/96

    Hegeland the Human Spirit

    edge already involves

    a

    synthesis

    of

    content

    and

    selfwhich

    is

    why

    sei/-knowledge

    is

    always

    in the

    wings

    and

    ready

    to

    make its appearance. Thus a thing is never simply there;

    rather, with the constant proximity of selfhood, with our

    awarenessof the selfin irscreationof the thing,we seethat

    the thing

    is not

    what

    it is ( das

    Ding

    ist

    nicht

    was es

    i st

    ;/

    ),

    since instead

    of

    simply being there,

    it is

    being-for-me.

    The

    thing's being

    is

    bound

    up

    with

    the self, its

    beingis

    the

    self

    ("sein Sein

    ist Ich

    selbst

    ;;

    ):

    the

    object

    is

    subject.

    The

    transi-

    tion is easy, then, from thisto the self-knowledge in which

    the subject isobject.

    Yet Hegel cannot remain withtheIdealism w hich says that

    the thingis notwhatit is, but israther madeup of oursense

    perceptions. This view

    is

    only

    the

    first step toward truth,

    a

    step

    we

    must

    go

    beyond.

    The

    next step

    is to

    turn further

    inward

    to the self, to an

    understanding

    of its

    activity,

    and

    then from there

    to

    turn

    to the

    outer world again. This move-

    mentis areturntobeingbut only afterwehave fully under-

    stood the human faculty bywhich wegive namesto things

    thatare there.

    The free self givesaname to ameaning,and assigns that

    name

    to the

    thingas

    the

    essence

    of the

    thingeven though

    the thing itself

    is

    altogether different from

    the

    noun. This

    name-giving

    is

    therefore

    a

    negative function.

    Yet by

    means of

    that function

    the

    thing

    is

    objectified,

    is

    seen

    as

    being outside

    th eego.Hegel poin tsout that thisis themost basic creativity

    exercisedby themind, and this creativityis in a wayrecog-

    nized in Genesis, where Adam's assigned task is to give

    names

    to

    things.

    To

    name

    is the

    sovereign right

    of

    spirit,

    Hegel says,

    our way of

    creating

    all

    nature, possessing

    it as our

    own, stamping

    it

    with

    our

    spirit.

    The

    lion becomes

    a

    thing

    that

    is

    named "lion." Nature

    is

    thereby made spiritual;

    the

    object's being

    is

    thereby

    our own.

    Hegel rejects the Empiricist philosophy which generally

    seesus as existing in apassive relationto theworld: things

    impinge on us (we are the

    tabula rasa)

    and thus we have

    images

    of

    them,

    or

    rather

    we

    experience

    our

    experience

    of

    them,

    but not the

    things themse lves. Hegel asserts that rather

    20

    Introduction

    than

    a

    realm

    of.

    images,

    the

    wttfld

    is a

    realm

    of

    names,

    of

    meanings bestowed. That subjective bestowal

    is

    externalized:

    the nameis not merelyone for me ;uather^it becomesthe

    thing

    as itis,

    this

    isa

    lion. Thus

    the

    puzzles raised

    by

    Empiri-

    cism (e.g.,thetreein theforestand theproblemofsolipsism)

    are spurious because they emanate from this false picture

    of

    our passivity.

    Our

    real relation

    to the

    world

    is

    entirely active.

    In naming,

    we

    overcome

    the

    particularity

    of

    experience.

    Thus in addition to man's name-giving capacity, he has a

    capacity

    to

    rise above particularity, above

    the

    immediate,

    to

    universalityandthought.Theproper name becomesageneric

    name,

    and we see the

    object

    in a new

    light.

    In

    rising

    to

    that

    level, however, we alsosee ourselvesin a new light, as as-

    signers

    of

    names

    and

    meaningsas

    ego.

    Hegel

    is

    well aware

    of

    the

    difference betw een

    the

    volatile

    ego and the

    determinate

    world to which the ego relates.How can that fluid entity

    (within)

    be the

    basis

    of all

    that

    is out

    there

    and

    fixed?

    The

    answer is that the ego comes to its own fixity in its self-

    awarenessthe awareness

    of

    itself

    as

    activity,

    as

    "labor":

    it

    sees

    itself, at

    this point,

    in its

    expressions

    and

    creationsin

    artifacts, language, social relationsbut above all it sees

    itself.

    The constitution of the ego itself is this very processof

    self-relation, self-mediation. "Labor"

    (in the

    .broad sense

    noted above)

    is the

    externalization

    of the

    ego

    in an

    object.

    But

    th e

    ego

    also returns

    to itself, as we saw. And it is

    precisely

    this return whichis the basisof its transcendent properties

    ancTcapacities,its universalityand necessity.

    As name-giver,

    the ego

    preserves every thing

    in its

    "night,"

    and

    in