facts and theories1

Upload: ayaz

Post on 03-Apr-2018

215 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/28/2019 Facts and Theories1

    1/23

    Facts and Theories Hahnemanns Balancing Act

    Concepts of Health and Disease in Hahnemann

    To the year 1 students (intake 2009) of the Centre for Homeopathic Education, London.

    After I had discovered the weakness and errors of my teachers and books, I

    sank into a state of sorrowful indignation, which had nearly altogether

    disgusted me with the study of medicine. (S.Hahnemann,Aesculapius in

    the Balance, p.410)

    Over the last 15 years it has been my experience that there is no better way

    to deepen ones understanding of homeopathic philosophy than to read and

    reread the writings of Samuel Hahnemann. This article is concerned with

    concepts of health and disease as formulated by Hahnemann in his Organon,

    Chronic Diseases and some of his pre-Organon writings. A focus of this

    article is the productive tension which exists between Hahnemanns theories

    (in particular the miasm theory and the concept of the Vital Force) and his

    phenomenological approach in practice. Having a good understanding of

    Hahnemanns homeopathy establishes a standard by which all other, later

    developments in homeopathy, can be measured against. Such an approach

    can help to avoid confusions surrounding the different so-called

    methodologies.

    Homeopathy as restorative art

    It has become a commonplace to speak of homeopathy as a science and an

    art. Hahnemann himself speaks of the healing art, by which he means more

    1

  • 7/28/2019 Facts and Theories1

    2/23

    than just homeopathy. Some have taken this to mean that homeopathy is not

    just a rigorous, rational discipline (the science part), but also a creative art

    where individual practitioners can freely add ideas to the already existing

    structure. The meaning of art as it appears in the Organon is different. In

    ORG VI, 1 and 2 Hahnemann says of the highest ideal of cure that it is to

    make the sick healthy and a rapid, gentle and permanent restoration of

    health. Hahnemann stresses homeopathy as a restorative, not a creative art.

    The goal of homeopathy is to restore the patient to a previous state of health,

    which is at the same time the baseline for homeopathic treatment. On the

    one hand, that seems a fairly conservative undertaking, as it does not include

    any improvement of the persons previous state of health, but simply a return

    to it. On the other hand, it introduces great clarity when it comes to the

    treatment goal, which is explicitly not to change or better the person to be

    treated, but simply to return that person, whatever their shortcomings, moral

    or otherwise might be, to a state of capacity, which allows them to continue

    their life unhindered by disease. From the following passage one can see that

    Hahnemann does not think it is the role of the homeopath to change a

    persons usual, healthy state of mind, whether that state of mind appeals to

    others or not:

    For example, one often encounters patients with the most painful, protracted

    diseases, who have a mild, gentle emotional mind such that the medical art-

    practitioner feels impelled to bestow attention and sympathy upon them. If the

    physician conquers the disease and restores the patient again (which is not a rare

    possibility with the homeopathic mode of treatment) the physician is often

    astonished and startled at the dreadful alteration of the patients emotional mind.

    The physician often meets with ingratitude, hard-heartedness, deliberate malice and

    the most degrading, the most revolting tempers of humanity qualities that were

    2

  • 7/28/2019 Facts and Theories1

    3/23

    precisely those possessed by the patient in former, healthy days. (ORG VI, 210,

    footnote).

    By calling the former days healthy despite ingratitude, hard-heartedness,

    deliberate malice, degrading and revolting tempers, it is clear thatHahnemann was neither judging nor treating his patients according to their

    moral imperfections.A bad temperper se was not necessarily pathological;

    it only became so if that had changed with the onset or duration of the

    disease. For Hahnemann, health was the absence of disease, and disease the

    deviation from a previous state of health. No more, no less.

    Knowledge of disease what does that mean?

    In ORG VI, 3 Hahnemann writes: To be a genuine practitioner of the

    medical art, a physician must: Clearly realise what is to be cured in diseases,

    that is in each single case of disease (knowledge of disease). Disease,

    according to Hahnemann, can only be recognised in each individual case of

    disease. There is no abstract disease, but only individual cases of disease.

    Still, Hahnemann does not advocate ignoring conventional pathology. He

    just makes important distinctions as to its importance. Pathology consists of

    two aspects:

    a) the disease label, e.g. arthritis, and b) of signs and symptoms, which in the

    case of pathology are called pathognomic symptoms, e.g. pain, redness,

    heat, swelling, nodules, etc. The disease label is an abstraction, an

    interpretation; it belongs into the meaning category. A series of individualsigns and symptoms add up, in the pathology books, to the meaning

    arthritis. The pathognomic symptoms belong to the category of facts and

    data, including the felt experience of disease in an individual. Hahnemann

    was not at all concerned with disease names (ORG VI, 73 footnote). By

    3

  • 7/28/2019 Facts and Theories1

    4/23

    themselves they have no value in homeopathic case assessment (including

    case analysis and prescription of remedies). However, he did think it was

    important to know what type or form of disease the patient suffers from, for

    the simple reason that individualisation of a case of disease is carried out

    within pre-defined parameters. These are mainly set by the existing materia

    medica and Hahnemanns hypothesis that the many varied diseases can be

    traced back to three infections (psora, syphilis and sycosis). Already at the

    time of the 1st edition of the Organon (1810) (ORG I, 123; ORG II, 152)

    Hahnemann considered the number of well proven remedies sufficient for

    the infinitely many disease states in nature (thanks to the truth of the

    symptoms and the abundance of the disease elements that each one of the

    efficacious medicinal substances has shown in its impinging action on

    healthy bodies). (ORG VI, 145) If there would be no grouping of disease

    forms (according to miasms) or of the remedies there would indeed be the

    need for the strictest, self-standing individualisation, something which

    would make homeopathy an impossible undertaking. Hahnemann did not

    postulate treating every single case of disease as a free standing, peculiar

    disease, totally out of any context. Rather, he was looking for the peculiar

    form or variance of a familiar (known) and general disease species. G.H.G.

    Jahr compared the strictest, self-standing individualisation with declaring

    every single animal or plant as a peculiar animal or plant without having

    defined beforehand what species or family the animal or plant belongs to,

    e.g. whether the plant one talks about is an oak tree or a carnation, whether

    the animal is a donkey or a cat. Hahnemanns miasm theory, which has an

    explanatory (nature of disease) and classifying function (type of disease), is

    an attempt to do this fact justice (see ORG VI, 103). Well return to the topic

    of miasms later.

    4

  • 7/28/2019 Facts and Theories1

    5/23

  • 7/28/2019 Facts and Theories1

    6/23

  • 7/28/2019 Facts and Theories1

    7/23

    constitutional traits, be they physical or mental, and some homeopaths even

    elevate the profession of a patient to an indication for a prescription. As can

    be clearly seen from ORG VI, 5 and ORG VI, 208, this was not the intention

    of Hahnemann.

    ORG VI, 6 deals with what we perceive in diseases. The unprejudiced

    observer, he says, perceives nothing in each single case of disease other

    than the alterations in the condition of the body and soul. Only [] the

    deviations from the former healthy state of the now sick patient are

    perceived. They are perceptible to the patient himself, by those around him

    and observed by the physician. Hahnemann contrasts this with futile

    metaphysical speculations which are not borne out in experience. (ORG

    VI, 6) ORG VI, 7 specifies further how disease is defined in homeopathy:

    In cases of disease where there is no obvious occasioning cause (causa

    occasionalis) to be removed, we can perceive nothing but the disease signs.

    Therefore, it must be the symptoms alone by which the disease demands and

    can point to the appropriate medicine for its relief, along with regard for any

    contingent miasm and with attention to the attendant circumstances. When

    Hahnemann speaks of disease without qualifying it any further, e.g.

    indispositions or iatrogenic diseases (ORG VI, 74-77), he means the

    deviations from health (ultimately due to a miasm) which are expressed in a

    combination of signs and symptoms which are to be matched up with a

    combination of signs and symptoms in a remedy: comparison of the

    complex of the natural diseases signs with the symptom set of the available

    medicines. (ORG VI, 153) Both consist of data and facts, not opinions,

    interpretations or conjectures. What is to be cured cannot therefore remain

    concealed in the unfathomable depths of obscure speculation, or be diffused

    throughout the boundless void of conjecture; it must be accessible, readily

    7

  • 7/28/2019 Facts and Theories1

    8/23

    accessible to us, within the sphere of vision of our external and internal

    perception faculties. (The Medicine of Experience, p.439) That which

    reveals itself to the senses in symptoms is the disease itself. (ORG VI, 6,

    footnote). Homeopathy, according to Hahnemann, only deals with concrete

    phenomena, perceptible signs and symptoms. What has to be elucidated in

    diseases are these concrete data, what is undoubtedly sick. Equally, our

    materia medica consists of concrete combinations of signs and symptoms.

    The more abstract, general, undefined the disease or proving symptoms are,

    the less useful they are, because of their lack of individualisation. (ORG VI,

    153) In ORG VI, 21 Hahnemann writes:

    Since the curative wesen in medicines is not, in itself, discernible (which no one can

    deny), and in pure experiments conducted with medicines [i.e. in provings] the most

    sharp-witted observer can perceive nothing about medicines that can constitute

    them as medicines, or curative means, except their power to bring forth distinct

    alterations in the condition of the human body, and especially their power to

    differently tune the healthy person in his condition and to arouse several peculiar

    disease symptoms in him, then it follows that when medicines act as curative

    means, they likewise can only bring their curative capacity into execution through

    this, their power to differently tune the human condition by means of engendering

    peculiar symptoms.

    Hahnemann does not tire to stress that similarity is established on the level

    of concrete phenomena, never between abstract concepts, ideas or such like.

    Despite this, Hahnemann employed two speculative theories, which have

    become for some the cornerstones of homeopathy, for others, stumbling

    blocks: the concept of the Vital Force and the miasm theory. Both concepts

    have a peculiar relationship with the sense data, the facts, and the

    phenomena. This will be looked at now before we return to the topic of

    certainty.

    8

  • 7/28/2019 Facts and Theories1

    9/23

    The Vital Force explanation or obfuscation?

    Despite Hahnemanns protestations that nothing can be perceived in disease

    than signs and symptoms expressing a deviation from a former healthy state,

    he hypothesises that the essence of the disease is the disturbed vital force.

    (ORG VI, 7) And he speaks of disease as a state of being of the organism

    dynamically untuned by a disturbed vital force, [] an alteration in the state

    of health. (ORG VI, 8) Why do we need the concept of the vital force when

    he points out that the vital force itself cannot be seen, that as humans we are

    not equipped to perceive the inner working of the vital force directly, but

    that we can only see its effects: we can perceive nothing but the disease

    signs. Therefore, it must be the symptoms alone by which the disease

    demands and can point to the appropriate remedy. (ORG VI, 7) Does the

    concept of the vital force add anything to our understanding of disease?

    Does the concept of the vital force help us to make our prescriptions more

    accurate (the one thing Hahnemann aimed for all his life)?

    The theory of the vital force explains why potentised remedies are needed to

    cure diseases. Since the pathological disturbance is a dynamic one, it needs a

    dynamic intervention. Vital Force signals the immaterial nature of

    diseases, and why it is necessary to use immaterial substances for their

    treatment: The physician can remove these pathological untunements

    (diseases) only by acting on our spirit-like vital force with medicines having

    equally spirit-like, dynamic effects that are perceived by the nervous

    sensitivity everywhere present in the organism. (ORG VI, 16) In his essay

    Spirit of the Homeopathic Doctrine of Medicine he speaks of the organs of

    the higher rank and of the vital force.

    9

  • 7/28/2019 Facts and Theories1

    10/23

    Further, the concept of the vital force gives Hahnemann an opportunity to

    separate himself from those who engage in metaphysical speculations

    regarding the nature of disease, as doctors as well as the so-called nature

    philosophers of his age did. What Hahnemann aimed to do by postulating a

    vital force is to give a scientific explanation of what animates and organises

    the material body. In ORG VI, 9 he states: In the state of health the spirit-

    like vital force (dynamis) animating the material human organism reigns in

    supreme sovereignty. It maintains the sensations and activities of all the

    parts of the living organism in a harmony that obliges wonderment. What

    Hahnemann describes here sounds very much like the modern concept of

    homeostasis, of which a definition reads: Metabolic equilibrium actively

    maintained by several complex biological mechanisms that operate via the

    autonomic nervous system to offset disrupting changes. In ORG VI, 16

    Hahnmemann writes: The physician can remove these pathological

    untunements (diseases) only by acting on our spirit-like vital force with

    medicines having equally spirit-like, dynamic effects that are perceived by

    the nervous sensitivity everywhere present in the organism. Looking at the

    following quote from a standard textbook on anatomy and physiology it is

    clear that Hahnemann grappled with scientific rather than metaphysical

    concepts: Nervous tissue detects changes in a variety of conditions inside

    and outside the body and responds by generating nerve impulses. The

    nervous tissue in the brain helps to maintain homeostasis. (Tortora, p.104)

    As always, Hahnemann chooses his words carefully. He speaks of spirit-

    like, denoting an invisible and immaterial, but still substantial, force. That

    the vital force must be real can be seen from its effects, its manifestations. It

    is part of what Marilynne Robinson calls the finer textures of the physical.

    10

  • 7/28/2019 Facts and Theories1

    11/23

    What is the force that holds atoms together, that forms molecules, which in

    turn form elements? etc. Can we name that force?

    Can we explain only the processes or also the force driving these processes?

    An analogy from science might make it clearer what Hahnemann tried to

    articulate: This is what it says in a modern textbook on anatomy and

    physiology: To synthesise proteins, the information encoded in a region of

    DNA is first transcribed (copied) to produce a specific molecule of RNA

    (ribonucleic acid). Then the information contained in RNA is translated

    into a corresponding sequence of amino acids that forms a protein

    molecule. (p. 86-87) What is the information? Where does it come from?

    Where is it made, produced? It seems our knowledge starts when the

    information becomes manifest. However, the information is obviously

    real. Science glosses over the fact that we do not actually know what this

    information is. It explains it by its material manifestations, although these

    are the products of this mysterious information. Hahnemann was more

    honest by stating the existence of the vital force (by logical deduction), but

    at the same time drawing a line by saying that we cannot qualify it any

    further. All we know is that it must exist because it clearly manifests in the

    physical. Another passage in the same book reads: During transcription,

    which occurs inside the nucleus, the genetic information representedby the

    sequence of base triplets in DNA serves as a template for copying the

    information into a complementary sequence of codons in a strand of DNA.

    The base triplets are not the information itself, they representit. What,

    then is the information? By the same token, the physical manifestations

    (disease phenomena) representthe Vital Force, which itself remains

    invisible. Being invisible, and recognisable solely by its effects on the

    organism, it can express itself and reveal its untunement only by

    11

  • 7/28/2019 Facts and Theories1

    12/23

  • 7/28/2019 Facts and Theories1

    13/23

    diseases in which the symptoms of mental and emotional mistunement that

    is peculiar to each disease heightens itself as the somatic symptoms diminish

    [] (see ORG VI, 215). Vital Force and physical manifestations of vital

    force are one and the same.

    The philosophical framework of Hahnemann informs homeopathic practice

    directly: The only indications for diseases are: Totality of symptoms (and

    the accompanying circumstances are to be taken into consideration for case

    management ORG VI, 5). (ORG VI, 15) Despite the fact that Hahnemann

    introduces theoretical concepts he always returns to the concrete, the facts,

    the data when it comes to the type of information we need in daily practice,

    which begs the question what the rle of the miasms is.

    Rle of the miasms

    The miasms are Hahnemanns second great speculative theory. Whereas the

    Vital Force may well be vindicated as a theoretical concept with explanatory

    power, the miasms have less of a chance of surviving new medical insights.

    With the psora theory Hahnemann tried to explain the multi-faceted nature

    of so many disease forms which have ultimately one origin, and he

    introduced with it the concept of diathesis, the predisposition of

    individuals to certain diseases. He strictly adhered to a model of infectious

    diseases (primary infection not properly treated leads to latent or secondary

    psora with all its problematic sequelae. They develop chronic character and

    undermine the health gradually). His best available example (and analogy

    for psora) was syphilis. He modelled psora on this disease process. (A good

    modern example is borreliosis, Lyme disease). We now know that we cannot

    say that all chronic diseases are due to an original infection (some are, of

    course, e.g. a whole host of viral and bacterial diseases). Apart from

    13

  • 7/28/2019 Facts and Theories1

    14/23

  • 7/28/2019 Facts and Theories1

    15/23

    The need for strict individualisation includes the demand of finding the

    remedies through the study of the sources, not by taking shortcuts via

    repertories.

    With the great conscientiousness which should be shown in the restoration of a

    human life endangered by sickness more than in anything else, the Homoeopath, if

    he would act in a manner worthy of his calling, should investigate first the whole

    state of the patient, the internal cause as far as it is remembered, and the cause of

    the continuance of the ailment, his mode of life, his quality as to mind, soul and

    body, together with all his symptoms (see directions in Organon), and then he

    should carefully find out in the work on Chronic Diseases as well as in the work on

    Materia Medica Pura a remedy covering in similarity, as far as possible, all the

    moments, or at least the most striking and peculiar ones, with its own peculiar

    symptoms; and for this purpose he should not be satisfied with any of the existing

    repertories, -a carelessness only too frequent, for these books are only intended to

    give light hints as to one or another remedy that might be selected, but they can

    never dispense him from making the research at the first fountain heads. (CD,

    121)

    Although Hahnemann speaks of specific remedies for the treatment of

    chronic diseases, this does not imply a dispensation from strict

    individualisation, which for Hahnemann always involves the study of the

    provings: The search for the remedy that is homeopathically the most

    suitable, in all regards, for a given disease state is a laborious, occasionally a

    very laborious, pursuit. While there are praiseworthy books for facilitating

    this process [i.e. repertories and materia medica] it is still necessary to study

    the sources themselves [i.e. reports of provings]. (ORG VI, 148, footnote)

    15

  • 7/28/2019 Facts and Theories1

    16/23

    Certainty and the logic of homeopathy

    This brings us back to the topic of how we can achieve any certainty in

    prescribing homeopathic remedies. It was mentioned above that the

    undertaking of finding a remedy rests on two subjective factors: the report of

    the patient and the reports of the provers, which are to be matched in order

    to find the most similar remedy. As C.Meinhard pointed out the report of the

    patient remains inevitably subjective, we have no way of assessing its

    veracity. The patient simply has to be believed. On the other hand, the

    process of provings allows us to introduce objective standards to tone down

    the potential subjectivity. In provings it is the frequency with which a

    sign/symptoms or a combination of signs and symptoms appears. The more

    often these appear in different provers the less likely it has its origin in the

    imagination of the prover. Hahnemanns footnotes toIgnatia inMateria

    Medica Pura point to that fact. That this process is precarious there is no

    doubt, since provings are often based on just a few provers. On the other

    hand, clinical confirmation of these few symptoms strengthens the degree of

    objectivity. And it should not be forgotten that Hahnemann undertook

    repeated provings for individual remedies, which over time, revealed the full

    extent of the objective combinations of signs and symptoms.

    The complex of all disease elements which a medicine is capable of engendering is

    only brought near completeness by means of multiple observations employed upon

    many differing qualified persons, both male and female. One can only be assured of

    having thoroughly proven a medicine for the disease states which it can arouse (i.e.

    for its pure powers in altering the human condition) when subsequent provers can

    notice little about the medicine that is new and they almost always perceive in

    themselves the same symptoms that have already been observed by others. (ORG

    VI, 135)

    16

  • 7/28/2019 Facts and Theories1

    17/23

    Those symptoms, which only appear in a few provers, the so-called

    idiosyncrasies, are made objective by confirmation in cases of disease.

    A further way of making subjective symptoms objective is to break down

    whole proving symptoms into their constituent parts. Boenninghausen was

    the first to recognise that homeopathic symptomatology has an inherent

    logic. A symptom can be broken down into parts such as location, sensation,

    modality and concomitant. In practice we are not looking for a match

    between a complete symptom of a prover and that of a patient, but between

    the characteristic elements which can be observed in both. An example,

    provided by C.Meinhard, will make this clearer.

    Symptom 278 of Mag-m in Chronic Diseases reads: Violent shooting pain

    in the left hypochondrium, like splenetic stitches, in the afternoon, when

    walking; worse when taking a breath; it ceases in sitting (during the

    menses). If we wanted to match this whole symptom with a patients report,

    we would have to wait a long time for a precise match in a case of disease.

    However, if we break the complete symptom down into its constituent parts,

    the situation looks very different.

    The various elements contained in this symptom are:

    Location: hypochondrium sub-location: left

    Sensation: Shooting closer description: violent

    Time modality: afternoon

    Modality according to circumstance: when walking, when taking a breath.

    Amelioration: when sitting.

    These are the possible combinations of signs and symptoms:

    Shooting, left

    Shooting, violent

    17

  • 7/28/2019 Facts and Theories1

    18/23

    Shooting, afternoon

    Shooting, worse when walking

    Shooting, worse when breathing in

    Shooting, better when sitting

    It is evident that it will not take much time to meet patients with such

    combinations in practice. The important thing is to keep any meaning or

    interpretation out of these combinations. They have to be pure phenomena,

    facts, data, repeatedly confirmed in provings. If Mag-m. has repeatedly

    produced the following, then we can say with some certainty that it is

    unlikely to be only the subjective experience of the prover:

    Different pains on the left hypochondrium

    A shooting pain, on the left side, in different places

    A violent shooting

    A shooting pain in the afternoon

    A shooting pain which is worse on walking

    A shooting pain which is worse on breathing in

    A shooting pain which is better when sitting

    This is the best kind of certainty we can have.

    As C.Meinhard points out, the smallest common denominator between the

    disease of the patient and the effect of the remedy is not the subjective

    symptom, but the combination of signs which make up that symptom. It is

    these signs which we can most certainly know, which is free of all

    conjecture and interpretation, and which can be ascertained as belonging to

    the remedy if these signs repeatedly occur in different provers. The

    concentration on that which is undoubtedly diseased (ORG VI, 3) fulfils

    Hahnemanns requirement for a reliable materia medica: Let all this is

    supposition, merely asserted or even fabricated, be entirely excluded from

    18

  • 7/28/2019 Facts and Theories1

    19/23

    such a materia medica. Let everything be the pure language of nature,

    carefully and sincerely interrogated. (ORG VI, 144) As already mentioned,

    if we confuse the levels of meaning and facts we end up with all these

    different methodologies, which are a constant source of confusion for

    todays students of homeopathy. To the level of meaning belong the

    diagnosis of the disease in hand; the homeopathic assessment concerning

    obstacles to cure; maintaining causes; observations regarding the

    constitution (the so-called attendant circumstances in ORG VI, 5); and the

    patient management with respect to diet, mental frame of mind (as one

    which supports or hinders treatment), etc. However, all these aspects are not

    relevant for the pharmacological aspect of our work. When it comes to that

    we need to stick with facts and phenomena. ORG VI, 3 outlines precisely

    what falls into this category: knowledge of what is curative in remedies;

    knowledge of what is undoubtedly diseased; application of the simila

    principle. A confusion of these two categories will inevitably lead to

    different methodologies.

    Hahnemann was fully aware that one of the main stumbling blocks for the

    successful practice of homeopathy is mans (including homeopaths!)

    inclination to theorise and speculate, instead to observe. In this period of

    nearly two thousand years was the pure observation of disease neglected.

    (Aesculapius in the Balance,p.421)

    Physicians no longer tried to see diseases as they were; what they saw did not

    satisfy them, but they wished by an a priori reasoning to find out the undiscoverable

    source of disease in regions of speculation which are not to be penetrated by

    terrestrial mortals. Our system-builders delighted in these metaphysical heights,

    where it was so easy to win territory; for in the boundless region of speculation

    19

  • 7/28/2019 Facts and Theories1

    20/23

  • 7/28/2019 Facts and Theories1

    21/23

    observation. That is why Hahnemann said that all we need for taking a case,

    for practising homeopathy successfully is: freedom from bias, healthy

    senses, attention while observing and fidelity in recording the image of the

    disease. (ORG VI, 83) That sounds easy enough, but is of course difficult to

    practise, because homeopathy, according to Hahnemann, is a narrow path to

    which we must stick if we do not want it to become a caricature, a distorted

    image of what once was.

    This essay does not want to suggest that what is presented here is the only

    homeopathy around. That is so patently not the case. There are now many

    schools of homeopathy which have different philosophical foundations to

    the one described here with resultant different practices. However, what this

    essay wants to suggest is that the homeopathy outlined here is homeopathy

    according to Hahnemann. Anyone who claims to follow Hahnemann would

    have to follow these premises and practices. Nobody has to follow these, of

    course, but whoever does not, should not claim to do as Hahnemann said

    and did. We could spare us a lot of confusion if we taught homeopathy

    strictly from Hahnemann instead of combining contradictory views and

    methods without explaining their origin. As always, Hahnemann has set a

    standard by which we can measure other developments and practices today.

    The great Mark Twain once said: How empty is theory in the presence of

    facts. Hahnemann might well have agreed with that, knowing the power and

    limitation of both.

    21

  • 7/28/2019 Facts and Theories1

    22/23

    Literature:

    S. Hahnemann (1996) Organon of the Medical Art (6th edition), (ed. Wenda

    Brewster OReilly), Birdcage Books, Redmond.

    S.Hahnemann (2001 reprint edition) Chronic Diseases, B.Jain Publishers,

    New Delhi.

    S.Hahnemann (2002) The Lesser Writings of Samuel Hahnemann, B.Jain

    Publishers, New Delhi.

    Relevant articles from theLesserWritings for this essay are:

    Aesculpius in the Balance (1805)

    On the Value of the Speculative Systems of Medicine, especially as viewed in

    connexion with the usual methods of practice with which they have been

    associated(1808)

    Spirit of the Homoeopathic Doctrine of Medicine (1813)

    Examination of the Sources of the Ordinary Materia Medica (1817)

    G.J. Tortora and S.R. Grabowski (latest edition))Principles of Anatomy and

    Physiology(9th edition), John Wiley and Sons, New York.

    22

  • 7/28/2019 Facts and Theories1

    23/23