epic hero and epic fable

23
University of Oregon Epic Hero and Epic Fable Author(s): D. C. Feeney Source: Comparative Literature, Vol. 38, No. 2 (Spring, 1986), pp. 137-158 Published by: Duke University Press on behalf of the University of Oregon Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1771065 Accessed: 21/10/2009 00:23 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=uoregon. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. University of Oregon and Duke University Press are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Comparative Literature. http://www.jstor.org

Upload: anya-mishra

Post on 07-Apr-2015

345 views

Category:

Documents


5 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Epic Hero and Epic Fable

University of Oregon

Epic Hero and Epic FableAuthor(s): D. C. FeeneySource: Comparative Literature, Vol. 38, No. 2 (Spring, 1986), pp. 137-158Published by: Duke University Press on behalf of the University of OregonStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1771065Accessed: 21/10/2009 00:23

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available athttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unlessyou have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and youmay use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.

Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained athttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=uoregon.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printedpage of such transmission.

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range ofcontent in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new formsof scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

University of Oregon and Duke University Press are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extendaccess to Comparative Literature.

http://www.jstor.org

Page 2: Epic Hero and Epic Fable

D.C. FEENEY

Epic Hero and

Epic Fable

THE EPIC HERO occupies a secure niche in modern criticism. His

reassuring presence guarantees the unity of an epic poem and di- rects our scrutiny when we search for theme. If he is not easy to pick out, there ensues a quarrel over his identity, with a list of candidates for the post; the poem in question, especially if it is an ancient epic, is either disparaged as formless and episodic, or else praised for bold indepen- dence, held together on other and more interesting principles. Modern critics evidently see it as the norm for ancient and modern epics alike to be organized around an individual, who will embody the meaning of the

poem. Scholes and Kellogg describe the nucleus of the epic as "the chronicle of the deeds of the hero"; by their account, "the epic plot is to a certain extent bespoken by epic characterization. The plot is inherent in the concept of the protagonist."' According to Northrop Frye, "In

literary fictions the plot consists of somebody doing something. The

somebody, if an individual, is the hero ... Fictions ... may be classified, not morally, but by the hero's power of action, which may be greater than ours, less, or roughly the same."2 Of Frye's five classifications, the

epic hero belongs to number three, the hero of the "high mimetic mode," "superior in degree to other men but not to his natural environment"

(pp. 33-34). Morton W. Bloomfield, after a careful discussion of the

meaning of the word "hero," asserts: "Whatever term be used for the

major personage or personages of narrative or drama, that these genres have always been presented around such figures cannot be doubted."3

1 Robert Scholes and Robert Kellogg, The Nature of Narrative (Oxford, 1966), p. 209.

2 Anatomy of Criticism (Princeton, 1957), p. 33. 3 In "The Problem of the Hero in the Later Medieval Period," Concepts of the

Hero in the Middle Ages and the Renaissance, ed. N. T. Burns and C. Reagan (Albany, N.Y., 1975), p. 29.

137

Page 3: Epic Hero and Epic Fable

COMPARATIVE LITERATURE

Classical scholars concur: the same preconceptions underlie C. M. Bowra's discussion, for example, of the characteristics of "literary epic."4 It must be said, however, that among classical scholars, for vari- ous reasons, there is little discussion in broad terms of the generic ques- tion of epic and its hero, much less than among scholars of literature from the Renaissance on.

The general orthodoxy still obtains, despite the voices of a few dis- senters.5 To test its value, what is needed is not only a discussion of the

practice and theory of ancient epic, but also an investigation into the birth and nurture of the epic hero who occupies the attention of the modern critics. He will be seen to be, in essence, a child of the Renais- sance, a demanding child, but not universally successful in pressing his claims. In England he was given title and dominion by the neoclassicists, and it is by virtue of that authority that he still exercises his power.

A convenient starting point is afforded by the reflection that neither Greek nor Latin has a word to describe the epic hero: ;pwco and heros have no literary reference, but describe individuals, normally held to be descended from gods, whose tombs received quasi-divine honors. Nor does any other word, such as 7rporayovtafr7T ("protagonist") discharge this service. This is not so decisive an observation as it may appear at first. As we shall see, the literary-critical meaning of "hero" was not domesticated into English until 1673, and yet D. W. Lucas justly re- marks that "the Elizabethans had indubitable heroes, though they had no word for them."6 Still, the modern reader who comes to ancient epics expecting to find a hero should pause at the realization that the object of his search is without so much as a name, that an ancient poet could not say, in as many words, "Who is the hero of my poem?" nor an ancient critic pose a like question of the texts he had before him. The critical authority which this figure exercises over our expectations should suffer its first weakening at this point.

Another approach is needed into the epics, to look for their true cen- ter of gravity. The example of John Jones, and the express recommen- dation of Getty, refer us to Aristotle's Poetics. It is at least understand-

4 From Virgil to Milton (London, 1948), Ch.i, "Some Characteristics of Liter- ary Epic."

5 Discussion of Lucan's Bellum Civile has called forth doubts on the necessity of having a hero: see, above all, the trenchant observations of R. Getty, in his edition of Lucan, Pharsalia, Book I (Cambridge, 1940), pp. xxiv-xxix. Subsequent references appear in the text. Thomas Greene has more general qualifications, in The Descent from Heaven: A Study in Epic Continuity (New Haven, 1963), p. 18. Although John Jones does not discuss the hero of epic, I should mention here the powerful impulse given to this paper by the argument of his valuable book, On Aristotle and Greek Tragedy (London, 1962).

6 In his edition of Aristotle, Poetics (Oxford, 1968), p. 140. Subsequent refer- ences to Aristotle are to this edition.

138

Page 4: Epic Hero and Epic Fable

EPIC HERO AND EPIC FABLE

able that critics have found a tragic hero when they have turned to the Poetics. What is puzzling about the conventional assessment of the nature of epic is that it overlooks not only the positive side of what Aristotle has to say-his presentation of the epic model as being, in the Homeric type, a self-sufficient and complete action (1459a19 ff.)--but also the explicit and repeated rejection of the idea that the organization of an epic depends on an individual character (1451a16 ff., 1459a37). For Aristotle, this is a misconception to be put quite on a par with or- ganizing an epic around one period of time. When Homer undertook the Iliad, according to Aristotle, he selected one part of the war as his "one action," and incorporated other parts as episodes (1459a35 ff.). Aristotle sees no single character as the center of the Iliad, as becomes plain when he goes on to contrast Homer's practice with that of lesser poets: "But the others make a poem about one man or one period of time" (1459a37 ff). To Aristotle the Iliad is "the imitation of a single action" (1462b 1), and this is no irrelevant formalism. As Getty puts it, "the centre round which the Iliad revolves is not Achilles but the wrath of Achilles" (p.xxvi). Even within the proem, when the subject of the wrath of Achilles has been announced, the wrath (,tfvsL) de-

velops a bold syntactical autonomy, controlling the first five lines in an

extraordinary way, governing three verbs in three successive lines (2 - 4).7 Achilles's wrath is indeed his, but the kindling, course, and as- suaging of the wrath comprehend many people and many interests; the poet's focus on the wrath provides him with a structural and a thematic plenitude which would have been denied him if he had sung "about one man." James Redfield has written well on the impoverishment of the poem that comes from various influential modern readings which see the poem as centering on "Achilles' inner experience." In Redfield's fine book Hector receives the full attention he deserves, and we come to see that indeed, as he puts it, "in some sense the story of the Iliad is the story of the relation between these two heroes."8

Aristotle sets off the Odyssey also as distinct from poems "about one man" (1451a16 ff.). This may appear paradoxical, until one realizes that what Aristotle was looking for in this poem as well as in the Iliad was the outline of a cohesive and "epic" action. That the action might be described as that of one man is a matter of complete indifference to Aristotle: it might be of one, or seven, or thousands, so long as it ex- hibited those structural features which he saw as the characteristic form

7 James Redfield speaks of the "personification" of the pv^ts ("wrath") with the adjective "destructive," and continues, discussing line 2, "the relative clause reinforces our sense of the ijlts as a numinous agent"; in "The Proem of the 'Iliad': Homer's Art," Classical Philology, 74 (1979), 101.

8 Nature and Culture in the Iliad: The Tragedy of Hector (Chicago, 1975), p. 27.

139

Page 5: Epic Hero and Epic Fable

COMPARATIVE LITERATURE

of the genre. We will return to the Odyssey, and to those poems "about one man." For the moment let us remain with Aristotle's prototype, a poem whose unity and structure are organic, and do not depend on an individual, since "one man's actions are numerous and do not make up a single action" (1451a18 ff.). If we look for a more or less "Aristo- telian" pattern, a pattern which is not monocentric, in other ancient epics, where the controversy over the hero is alive and keen, it will not be on the assumption that Aristotle was a legislator for later practice, but rather because his insights into Homer ring true, and invite us to discover whether the epic paradigm that provided those insights may not prove valuable elsewhere.

Nowhere is there more debate than in the area of Silver Latin epic, where the Bellum Civile, Thebaid and Punica occasion a diversity of opinion through having no one central character to take on the role of "hero." In connection with Lucan, Getty has declared the problem to be a mirage (pp.xxiv ff.); but other discussions of the Belliu Civile continue to take it for granted that Lucan regarded the norm of epic as

being a poem about a hero,9 just as other discussions of the Thebaid attribute a similar preconception to Statius, and either blame him for

failing to follow the norm, or praise him for a self-conscious abandon-

ing of the strait-jacket.10 With Silius it is the matter of identity alone that exercises the commentators: Is the hero Hannibal ? Or Scipio? Or Rome ?"1

Silius's poem most straightforwardly reveals the irrelevance of this

approach. His declared subject is "arma," "arms" (line 1), and he asks the Muse to allow him to record "what great men and how many men Rome created for war" (I.3.f.). With such a program concentra- tion on one man is not compatible. Certainly Hannibal figures promi- nently: this corresponds to historical fact. It is more important to realize that Hannibal is particularly prominent in the first ten books as a result of a structural decision taken by Silius. In an attempt to super- impose some form on the mass of material before him, Silius has se- lected the battle of Cannae as the crescendo of the poem. With seven books before and after, the three "Cannae" books, VIII-X, occupy the center of the epic; the historical proportion of events is radically dis-

9 See Frederick M. Ahl, Lucan: An Introduction (Ithaca, N.Y., 1976), pp. 150-56.

10 Blame from L. Legras, ?tude sur la Thebaide de Stace (Paris, 1905), pp. 147 ff., 207. Praise from David Vessey, Statius and the Thebaid (Cambridge, 1973), pp. 55 ff., 317 ff.

11 Discussion, with bibliography, in E. Bassett, "Hercules and the Hero of the Punica," in The Classical Tradition, ed. L. Wallach (Ithaca, N.Y., 1966), pp. 258- 73. Add M. von Albrecht, Silius Italicius: Freiheit und Gebundenheit romischer Epik (Amsterdam, 1964), p. 55.

140

Page 6: Epic Hero and Epic Fable

EPIC HERO AND EPIC FABLE

located so that this nadir of Roman fortunes may become, by a para- doxical turn, the high point of a poem celebrating Rome's resilience and fortitude. 2 Hannibal's run of successes up to this point-Ticinus, Trebia, Trasimene-is important as preparation; the early books are not there to tell us about Hannibal, but to establish a cumulatively disastrous progress towards the structural and thematic kernel of the epic. If Hannibal is the main agent in the progress, so be it. Silius may exploit his presence in the interests of cohesion and in furtherance of his themes of Carthaginian turpitude, but to say that these books are directed towards the character Hannibal is to confuse effect with cause.

Silius's stock is so low that his poem alone will perhaps not serve as sufficient example of a pattern where the absence of a hero, so far from being a failing, is not even an anomaly. His predecessor and model, Lucan, has less shape to his poem, but in the Bellum Civile it is just as plain as in the Punica that the action is greater than any of the actors. The action is civil war; the catastrophe is corporate, the protagonists are numerous and diverse. Speculation on the structure of an unfinished poem is dangerous, but enough is intact for us to see at least that Lucan did not present the death throes of the Republic as the disaster of an in- dividual. After the general and anonymous program (I. 1-7), when Lucan comes to discuss the causes of the war he expresses the problem as one of explaining "what drove a frenzied people to arms, what knocked peace out of the world" (68 f.). The leaders, Caesar and Pom- pey, are catalysts, and their differences demand analysis (98-157) ; but, says Lucan, greater causes are operative: "Such were the motives for the leaders; but underlying these were seeds of war on a national scale, of the sort which always bring down powerful nations" (158 f.). The selection of a single man as fulcrum suits Lucan's pessimistic theme as little as it suits Silius's optimistic one.

Statius's Thebaid, surviving intact, provides a clearer case of self- sufficient shape, where the action imitated has its own independence, and the choosing of a hero is beside the point.13 The poet states the scope of his action as the battle lines of brothers, and alternate kingships fought over with unholy hatred; subjoined is the theme of the guilt of a whole city (I. 1-3). In his exordium he marks his starting point as the moment when the secret of Oedipus was revealed and his sons came into the kingdom (I. 16-17). Above all the episodes and meanderings of the poem, it is the course of this fraternal strife which acts as a frame-

12 On the pivotal importance of Cannae, see W. Schetter, in Das rimische Epos, ed. E. Burck (Darmstadt, 1978), pp. 73 ff.

13 Recent discussions dispense with "action" and beg the question of where to turn to if the characters fail us. Thus Vessey: "Integration of narrative is achieved more by the philosophical and psychological basis on which the epic is built than by the characters themselves" (p. 57; my emphasis).

141

Page 7: Epic Hero and Epic Fable

COMPARATIVE LITERATURE

work. We see the development of the initial falling out, an expansively deployed multiple motivation, with Oedipus's summoning of the Fury (I. 46 ff.), her infection of the brothers (123 ff.), and the council of the gods (197 ff.). The second book displays the irrevocable estrangement, with the visitation to Eteocles of his grandfather's ghost (1-133), and the rejection of Tydeus's embassy (389 ff.). The preparations for war, alternating from one brother's camp to the other's, the march, and the digression of Hypsipyle and Archemorus, take us to Book VI. At this halfway stage, before the war actually begins, Statius reintroduces the rivalry of the brothers. Jocasta pleads with Polynices to reconcile him- self to Eteocles (VII. 508-10), but the wavering Polynices is swept away by events, and the two brothers are committed.

The chiefs of the invading armies are picked off one by one, until at the beginning of Book XI the Fury Tisiphone decides to round off the war with a combat between Eteocles and Polynices. The preparation and enactment of the duel take up most of the book (57-579), but the

energies of the brothers' enmity are not exhausted by their mutual mur- der. Even in death the brothers are irreconcilable, as their bizarre funeral shows, with the flames of their joint pyre dividing (XII. 429

ff.). The "profane hatreds" of the exordium are still at work: "it lives, their shameless hatred, it lives" (XII. 441). Thebes is still ailing, as the watching women observe, addressing the divided fires: "nothing has been achieved by the war; you unhappy pair, while you fight thus, Creon has been the victor after all" (442 f.). In a manner which is more familiar from tragedy (one thinks, for example, of Sophocles's Ajax), a substantial coda is required to lay to rest the momentum of evil gen- erated by the divisive forces that have been let loose (just as a sub- stantial introduction was required to build them up). Oedipus's soften-

ing comes first, as he repents of his role in instigating his sons' quarrel (XI. 605-26), but the rottenness of the city of Thebes requires excision from outside, with Theseus for agent.

What of the Odyssey and Aeneid, that offer in their first lines avopa, uirum, "man" ?14 As a preliminary observation, against those who desire a hero for his value as a structural tool, we may note that the Odyssey and Aeneid do not rely on Odysseus and Aeneas for their structural

integrity. So much Aristotle stated for the Odyssey, as we saw above, when he brought in its unified structure against the authors of Theseids and Heracleids. Homer did not shape his poem around the man, says Aristotle; "rather, he composed the Odyssey around one action of the

14 Note that neither the Greek nor the Latin Argonautica refers to Jason as its subject, but to "the deeds of men" (Apollonius Rhodius, I.1), and to "straits sailed through by the sons of gods, and their ship" (Valerius Flaccus, I.lf.). On Apol- lonius, see J. F. Carspecken, Yale Classical Studies 13 (1952), 110 ff.

142

Page 8: Epic Hero and Epic Fable

EPIC HERO AND EPIC FABLE

sort I mean, and the Iliad similarly" (1451a28 ff.). We can only agree with Aristotle that the unity of the Odyssey resides in its action, its description of a voarTO, a "homecoming," with the master of the house- hold returning home to reestablish the proper order there (1455b 16- 23). It is this action that accommodates the Telemachy and the final scenes, after the reunion with Penelope. Readers tend to have their eyes fixed upon the solitary figure of Odysseus, and the passages in the poem which concern the relations of the family, from Laertes to Tele- machus, are often felt to be more or less extraneous.15 In Virgil's case, the self-sufficiency of the poem's action is even more evident, although the same instinct which leads to a search for the unifying hero in the Silver Epic complacently identifies Aeneas as the guarantor of the unity of the Aeneid. Richard Heinze most economically states the real position: "Im Mittelpunkt seines Gedichts steht der Held, von dem es den Namen tragt, aber nicht er bildet die Einheit, sondern eine Hand- lung: die Ubersiedelung der Troer oder die Uberfiuhrung der Penaten von Troja nach Latium."16

Such an emphasis as Heinze's redresses the balance for more than structural considerations, since it is important to treat with circum- spection the almost automatic assumption that the Aeneid is "about" Aeneas, that the poem exists as a vehicle for the character. The poem's first words appear to satisfy this expectation, but we have a corrective in the note of the ancient commentary known as Servius "auctus" (an "expanded" version of Servius). According to this commentary, the beginning of an epic will have the announcement of the subject (pro- fessiuum), the invocation of the Muse (inuocatiuum), and the start of the narrative (narratiuum). He continues: "And Virgil takes up the announcement of the subject in four ways: from the leader ('I sing of arms and the man,' I.1), from the journey ('who first from the shores of Troy,' I.1), from the war ('he suffered also much in war,' 1.5), and from the establishment of the race ('whence comes the Latin race,' 1.6)" (ed. G. Thilo and H. Hagen, 1,6). The tradition of ancient scholarship represented in these crabbed notes did not see in the Aeneid's exordium the announcement of a poem about a man; the subject is greater and the man serves the subject. As Getty puts it, "the central theme of [the] Aeneid was not the life of Aeneas, but the fulfilment by Aeneas of his own destiny in founding the nation which was to become Rome" (p.xx- vi). This perspective is the truer and the more valuable, for it allows

15 See Dorothea Wender, The Last Scenes of the Odyssey (Leiden, 1978), pp. 63 ff., for the importance of seeing three generations at Ithaca.

16 Richard Heinze, Virgils epische Technik, 3rd ed. (Leipzig, 1915), p. 436. For formal structure, see, besides Heinze's fourth chapter (pp. 436-65), W. A. Camps, An Introduction to Virgil's Aeneid (Oxford, 1969), Ch. vi, pp. 51-60.

143

Page 9: Epic Hero and Epic Fable

COMPARATIVE LITERATURE

due importance to the main agent without allowing him to crowd out the action: Aeneas is there for the story, not vice versa. Certainly im- portant elements of what the Aeneid has to say reside in the character

Aeneas, most obviously the demands of the political vocation. But Aeneas does not embody the meaning of the poem ;17 such a myopic focus attenuates the extensive power of the Aeneid.18 Major sections of the work are strangely flat and unfruitful if we refer them to Aeneas, regarding them from a standpoint that looks to Aeneas for significance. The Roman pageant of Book VI, for example, is there for the reader; Aeneas is the nominal audience, but however closely we search to find what it all means for the character, here or later in the poem, the text yields no more to us than the bald line, "[his father] inflamed his spirit with a passion for the fame to come" (VI. 889). A. K. Michels has well criticized the recent attempts, most thoroughly developed by Brooks Otis, "to see the visit to the underworld as the turning point in Aeneas's career, the moment at which he abandons the past, and confidently faces the future, prepared to labour for the greatness of his race which lies centuries ahead."19 As she says, "One would expect that this vision of the future glory of his race would have some effect on Aeneas, but we may ask whether in fact it does ... [At] no point after he returns to the land of the living does Aeneas ever show any recollection of what his father has revealed to him."20

Otis's idea of a developing Aeneas, with his eventual triumph over "furor" ("madness"), has come in for some rough handling, and the current critical tendency is rather to concentrate upon his inability to master his passions. His enraged killing of Turnus in the final scene has become the central text of the "pessimistic school," who see the act as a negation of the poem's earlier celebrations of victorious order and

empire.21 Boyle's words are representative: "Aeneas's final act and words in the poem are intended to be seen as unequivocal acts of 'furor' ... and the effect of this is to focus the reader's attention once more upon the nonfulfilment of the imperial ideology and to elicit a final con- demnation (and a condemnation prefigured many times in the poem) of

17 Brooks Otis's book is representative of the approach which sees the ideas of the Aeneid concentrated in the figure of Aeneas, Virgil: A Study in Civilised Poetry (Oxford, 1963), pp. 219 ff.

18 On the "polysemous" nature of the Aeneid, see W. R. Johnson, Darkness Visible: A Study of Vergil's Aeneid (Berkeley and Los Angeles, 1976), pp. 16-22.

19 "The Insomnium of Aeneas," Classical Quarterly NS 31 (1981), p. 141. 20 Michels, p. 140. 21 Especially influential (but often interpreted too simplistically by later

writers) has been M. C. J. Putnam, The Poetry of the Aeneid (Cambridge, Mass., 1966), pp. 200 ff. For bibliography, see A. J. Boyle, "The Meaning of the Aeneid," Ramus 1 (1972), 90, n. 90. Subsequent references to this paper appear in the text.

144

Page 10: Epic Hero and Epic Fable

EPIC HERO AND EPIC FABLE

the forces of empire and history which Aeneas represents. The death of Turnus may signify the victory of Aeneas, Rome and her empire, but it is Vergil's concern to emphasise that it is a victory for the forces of non- reason and the triumph not of 'pietas' but of 'furor' " (p. 85). Whatever we decide about the culpability of Aeneas's act,22 Boyle here shares with Otis the misconception that Aeneas is what the poem means, that in the portrayal of Aeneas is to be found Virgil's whole meaning of empire. We must resist the centripetal attraction of the chief character and con- template his last action as one element of what the poem says. Jupiter's speech in Book I is not obliterated, the significance of the shield in Book VIII is still potent; the countervailing elements in the Aeneid coexist and we have to account for them all, not plump for one and shut out the rest.23

The Odyssey is a rather different matter, for in that poem the medium for the thematic content, overwhelmingly, is the man himself; in a way that is not true of the other epics so far discussed, the Odyssey is indeed "about" its principal character. Discussions of this aspect of the Odys- sey prepared the ground for the postclassical development of the "epic hero," as the critics, allegorizers, and moralists got to work on the "Everyman" that they discovered in the poem. This path will lead from the ancient to the medieval world; before following it, we must review those traditions of ancient epic which deliberately took one individual as the focus of composition. These are, broadly, the mythological and the encomiastic.

The first group is now substantially represented only by the unfin- ished Achilleid of Statius, and by Nonnus's Dionysiaca. Aristotle found fault with the writers of Heracleids and Theseids for narrating a life from beginning to end without selection (1451a19 ff.), but lives of mythological figures were a popular type of poem in many different periods. Although a single episode might form the subject, the usual practice, so far as may now be judged, was to celebrate more generally the deeds of the god or hero. We know of such poems from Pisander in the seventh century B.C., Panyassis in the fifth, Rhianus and Neopto- lemus of Parium in the third, Musaeus in the second,24 while in Latin, there is a Perseis by "a Sicilian," a Heracleid by Carus, and a Diomedia by lullus Antonius.25 It would be easy to dismiss these lost epics as

following an inferior line of endeavor, but their subject matter alone is not enough to permit us to judge whether any of them rose above a

22 It is possible to be a good deal less condemnatory: see Camps, p. 29. 23 I refer once more to Johnson's most illuminating argument, pp. 8 ff. 24 On these poets, see C. A. Trypanis, Greek Poetry from Homer to Seferis

(London, 1981). 25 Cf. Ovid, Epistolae ex Ponto IV. xvi. 7 ff., 25; IV. xiii. 11 ff., and Pseudo-

Acro on Horace, Carmina IV. ii. 33.

145

Page 11: Epic Hero and Epic Fable

COMPARATIVE LITERATURE

sequential narrative of diverse feats. A paraphrase of the action of the Aeneid, along the lines of Aristotle's paraphrase of the action of the Odyssey (1455bl6-23), could easily obscure the poem's integrity of structure; similarly, a "poem about Perseus, Diomedes or Theseus" might have possessed some unity of structure beyond that provided by the eponymous hero. As things stand, it is possible only to observe that this strong minority tradition did not extend its influence beyond the scope of its own particular subject matter, and did not lead other poets, such as those who wrote the surviving epics discussed above, to forsake the vrpaies ("action") of epic.

The encomiastic tradition is more vigorous; in the twilight of the ancient epic, it intertwined with its parent, historical epic, to prevail more or less completely. Indeed, we first hear of encomiastic epic around the turn of the fifth century B.C., in connection with the "inuentor" of historical epic, Choerilus of Samos, cultivated by Lysander and by Archelaus of Macedon in the hope of gaining immortality. Choerilus may well have produced something in compliance with this hope; cer- tainly his great contemporary, Antimachus, competed at Lysander's festival with a poem on the Spartan regent-and lost.26 Eulogistic epic poems, performed either at such festivals (which might be recurrent or one-time affairs) or else on the regular games circuit, remained a stan- dard field of Greek poetic endeavor until well into the Empire; their subjects were generally provided by the local monarch and, in Roman times, the emperor.27 One imagines that such festival encomia were rela-

tively short: Claudian's late examples are perhaps a guideline.28 There existed simultaneously a (related) flourishing tradition of panegyrical epics of more substantial length.2 Alexander's deeds were written up by Agis and a second Choerilus; together they provided for posterity a sort of yardstick for poetic inadequacy.30 Fragments survive of a poem treating of the campaigns of Alexander's father.31 Antiochus the Great was celebrated in an epic written by Simonides of Magnesia, Eumenes I and Attalus I of Pergamum in epics from Musaeus of Ephesus.32 The

26 See Plutarch, Lysander, XVIII. 7 ff.; on Choerilus's connections with these great men, see Pauly's Realencyclopiidie der classischen Altertumswissenschaft, III, 2359 (hereafter, RE).

27 A. Hardie, Statius and the "Silvae": Poets, Patrons and Epideixis in the Graeco-Roman World (Liverpool, 1983), pp. 85-91.

28 Stilicho's Consulate is in three parts of 385, 476, and 369 lines; Manilius' Consulate is 340 lines long; Honorius' Fourth and Sixth, 656 and 660 respectively.

29 See Konrat Ziegler, Das hellenistische Epos, 2nd ed. (Leipzig, 1966), pp. 16 ff.; Hardie, pp. 86 ff.

30 On Choerilus, see RE, III, 2361 ff.; on Agis, RE, I, 821. 31 The Oxyrhynchus Papyri, ed. B. P. Grenfell, A. S. Hunt, and others (Lon-

don, 1898-), Vol. XXX, No. 2520. 32 See under the poets' names in Suidae Lexicon, ed. Ada Adler (Stuttgart,

1967-71).

146

Page 12: Epic Hero and Epic Fable

EPIC HERO AND EPIC FABLE

fashion caught on in Rome. The poet Archias came to Rome to find famous men to praise: in the speech defending him, Cicero tells of epics on Marius, Catulus, and Lucullus (Pro Archia 19-21). Julius Caesar found his celebrators.33 His successor, too, was entitled to believe that his great deeds deserved enshrinement in epic as much as the actions of a Catulus. When the Augustan poets wrote "recusationes"-apologising for not praising the emperor, and justifying their alternative poetic forms-they must, to some degree, have been responding to an actual expectation.34

By late antiquity encomiastic and historical epic are virtually indis- tinguishable. T. Nissen and A. Cameron have observed the blend in Claudian and, later, Corippus and the Byzantine writers such as George of Pisidia.35 The popularity of this poetry is attested to by the numerous papyrus fragments of Greek epics on the deeds of Roman commanders, from around the fifth century.36 Handicapped as we are by the disap- pearance of the "classical" encomiastic epic, it is still reasonable to assume that in such works the whole focus was on the "laudandus," "the subject for praise," even if a single war was the arena in which the sub- ject's virtues were to be displayed.37 It is here that we come closest to the "hero." If the "laudandus" was excluded for so long from the main tradition of historical epic, and if nonhistorical epic did not embrace him, this is testimony to the ancient poets' allegiance to their forms, even within the subdivisions of a genre. Many men wrote epics to praise an individual, but this was not the general purpose of Epic.

This is not to deny the importance of the critical tradition that took its start in the detection of encomiastic elements in Homer's poetry.38 It is understandable that Isocrates, pioneering the new prose eulogy of a contemporary with his Evagoras, should allude to Homer as an enco- miast (190AB). Plato earlier shows the same attitude; his Protagoras maintains that in the epics of Homer and other poets there are to be found "many stories, eulogies and encomia of the good men of the old days" (Protagoras 326A). Similarly, in the Hippias Minor, a char-

33 Varro Atacinus wrote a Bellum Sequanicum on Caesar's campaign of 58 (Schanz-Hosius, Geschichte der romischen Literatur [Munich, 1927-1935], I, 312) ; Furius wrote Annales Belli Gallici (Schanz-Hosius, I, 163).

34 Cf. Jasper Griffin, Journal of Roman Studies, 66 (1976), 104. 35 T. Nissen, "Historisches Epos und Panegyrikos in der Spitantike," Hermes,

75 (1940), 298 ff.; and A. Cameron, Claudian: Poetry and Propaganda at the Court of Honorius (Oxford, 1970), pp. 260 ff.

36 See D. L. Page, ed. and trans., Select Papyri. Part III, "Literary Papyri" (London, 1941), Nos. 141-44.

37 Corippus announces that he will use the war as a vehicle for the praise of John (Praefatio, line 3). The leader is the subject, not the war: note the recur- rence of the key words "ductor," "dux": Book I, line 7; III. 1; V. 9; VII. 1; VIII. 1.

38 See S. Koster, Antike Epostherien (Wiesbaden, 1970), pp. 112 ff.

147

Page 13: Epic Hero and Epic Fable

COMPARATIVE LITERATURE

acter says of the Iliad and the Odyssey that they were, literally, "com- posed in the direction of, or with a tendency towards, Achilles and Odysseus" (363B). The phrasing has an encomiastic color. A similar preoccupation lies behind the ancient scholiasts' discussions of why the Iliad was not called the Achilleias.3 It also lies behind the way in which the Latin commentator Tiberius Claudius Donatus looks at the Aeneid. Donatus's analysis of the Aeneid as "laudatiuum," "encomiastic," goes far beyond Servius's description of Virgil's aims, "to imitate Homer and to praise Augustus on the basis of his ancestry" (ed. G. Thilo and H. Hagen, I, 4). For Donatus, everything in the poem is there for Aeneas: "Certainly it is encomiastic, but this fact is unrecognised and hidden, because, while going through the deeds of Aeneas, Virgil is evidently also assimilating, in an extraordinary variation upon the form of en- comium, incidental forms of different subject matter-forms which are nonetheless not alien to the job of encomium; for they are taken up in order to contribute to the praise of Aeneas" (ed. H. Georgii, I, 2, lines 9 ff; cf. I, 3, 18 if.). By this time the monocentric view of epos is well on its way to victory.

For the establishment of that victory in the postclassical world, no single influence was more important than the central character of the Odyssey: "Ulysses has placed before us a useful example of what vir- tue and wisdom can achieve" (Horace, Epistulae I.ii.17 f.). Horace's characterization of Homer's purpose finds an echo in Maximus of Tyre, who describes the Odyssey as "an image of the worthy life and of exact virtue" (xxvi6b). Such language goes back to the sophist Alcidamas, an older contemporary of Plato, who described the Odyssey as "a fair mirror of human life" (quoted by Aristotle, Rhetoric 1406b12). The

allegorizer Heraclitus sees Odysseus as the model of all the virtues, systematically exemplified one by one.40 The Christian fathers' view of the Odyssey as an "encomium of virtue" is rooted in the same tradition, as Hugo Rahner has shown.4' The Odyssey, to these readers, is an allegory of man's journey through life; as Odysseus encounters and subdues the range of temptations and threats personified in the Sirens, the Lotus-Eaters, and Circe, he shows us the triumph of wisdom and courage over vice, indolence, and resignation.42 Here was a fertile field

39 Cf. bT scholia on the Iliad's first word, in H. Erbse, Scholia Graeca in Homeri Iliadem, I (Berlin, 1969), p. 4, lines 30-38.

40 Allegories d'Homere, ed. F. Buffiere (Paris, 1962), pp. 75 f. On this strand of criticism, see F. Buffiere, Les Mythes d'Homere et la pensee grecque (Paris, 1956), pp. 365-91.

41 Greek Myths and Christian Mystery, trans. B. Battershaw (London, 1963), p. 332.

42 Cf. Rahner, pp. 281 ff., 328 ff., and Don Cameron Allen, Mysteriously Meant; The Rediscovery of Pagan Symbolism and Allegorical Interpretation in the Re- naissance (Baltimore, 1970), pp. 90 ff.

148

Page 14: Epic Hero and Epic Fable

EPIC HERO AND EPIC FABLE

for growth: in this Odysseus we see already the shadowy lineaments of the medieval and Renaissance hero.

His fortunes are linked with those of his erstwhile Trojan adversary, Aeneas. Virgil incorporated aspects of current philosophical interpre- tations of Odysseus into his portrait of Aeneas,43 but the Virgilian critics took the process further, treating the Aeneid as an Odyssey. In the postclassical world, after men had been deprived (through igno- rance of Greek) of direct knowledge of the Odyssey, the moral impor- tance of the Latin poem's central character grew ever greater. As Don Cameron Allen puts it, according to this tradition, "in the character of Aeneas [Virgill had created an epic figure who wandered more surely and wisely than Odysseus along the symbolic path of mortal existence. At each stage in his progress the grave hero exemplified both the deci- sions and the actions wise men should imitate."44 The expression of Vegius, in his standard De Educatione Liberorum (Milan, 1491), is typical: "In the character of Aeneas, Virgil wished to show a man endowed with every virtue, and to show this man both in adverse and in favourable circumstances."45 This is a sentiment which Tiberius Clau- dius Donatus would have read with satisfaction.

The paradigmatic Aeneas that Renaissance readers found in Virgil's poem exercised a powerful influence over their assumptions on the question of the role of the chief actor in epic. This was partly because the exemplary Aeneas of their tradition fitted in so well with their image of the moral purpose of poetry. Equally important for the critics who began, around the 1540s, to address themselves to the problem of defining epic was the fact that Aristotle's Poetics, their main text, was rather thin on epic and full on tragedy; perforce, they turned to "the poet," as Joel E. Spingarn explains: "The incompleteness of the treat- ment accorded to epic poetry in Aristotle's Poetics led the Renaissance to deduce the laws of heroic poetry and of poetic artifice in general from the practice of Virgil."46

The Poetics had become the main text in the 1540s, in spectacular fashion: Tillyard speaks of "the irruption of Aristotle's Poetics into the critical consciousness of the age" (p. 222). Significant results fol- lowed for the theory of epic, since there was an understandable tendency to try to fill out Aristotle's comparatively exiguous comments on epic with his fuller treatment of tragedy. The central tragic figure that men

43 See E. Norden, P. Vergilius Maro Aeneis Buch VI, 3rd ed. (Leipzig and Berlin, 1934), pp. 154 f.

44 Allen, p. 135. See also E. M. W. Tillyard, The English Epic and its Back- ground (London, 1954), pp. 134 ff. (hereafter cited in the text).

45 Ed. M. W. Fanning (Washington, D.C., 1933), p. 87. 46. A History of Literary Criticism in the Renaissance, 8th ed. (New York,

1954), p. 108.

149

Page 15: Epic Hero and Epic Fable

COMPARATIVE LITERATURE

descried in Aristotle was assumed to be equally at home in epic, and Aristotle's comments on the necessity of tragic figures being "morally good" and "suitable" (1454a16 ff.) were assumed to apply to the char- acters of epic. Castelvetro, for example, in his Poetica of 1570, first misunderstands Aristotle at this point to be saying that only noble or kingly characters should be represented in tragedy, and then goes on to convert this misapprehension into a generalization about epic as well: "La favola delle due poesie, epica e tragica, non simplicimente dee con- tenere attione humana, ma magnifica anchora, e reale."47

Against such a background something like a "doctrine" of the epic hero begins to emerge: the word "eroe" or "heroe" itself now appears in its familiar modern connotation for the first time. The noble character of paradigmatic moral significance, the focus of the poem, may be seen in the pages of Castelvetro, Pigna, Minturno, and Beni.48 Especially in- fluential was Castelvetro's misguided assertion (prefigured by Pigna), that the Aristotelian "form" of epic was the single action of a single person: "The epic ought to comprise one action of one person, not from necessity, but for a demonstration of the excellence of the poet."49 This era is the one in which the hero as we know him today first stands forth. To some degree a response to medieval and early Renaissance poems, this critical consensus begins in its turn to exert its own influence over the creations of the poets themselves.

There was a difficulty, however, for the conscientious critic who brought his Aristotle to bear on the heroic poem, namely, that one of Aristotle's very few extended discussions of epic comes in the passage which occupied us at the beginning of this essay. He proclaims the need for unity in epic, and asserts that it does not come from an individual, or from a period of time, but from the presentation of a single whole or complete action.This assertion was hard to reconcile with the hero- centered poem, and hard to reconcile with the multiplex structure of the great romances, such as Ariosto's Orlando Furioso, which also had a claim to the title "poema eroico." The dilemma was a real one, despite the fact that the long-lived controversy which it bred is easily derided as tedious and unfruitful.

One important party in the discussion, best represented by the robust

47 Castelvetro, Poetica (Vienna, 1570), p. 188. Subsequent references appear in the text. On this process, cf. Spingarn, p. 110.

48 Castelvetro, p. 179; Pigna, I Romanzi (Venice, 1554), p. 25; Minturno, Arte Poetica (Venice, 1564), p. 49; Beni, Comparatione di Homero, Virgilio e Tor- quato (Padua, 1607), p. 39. Subsequent references to these works appear in the text.

49 P. 179: I give the translation of R. C. Williams, The Theory of the Heroic Epic in Italian Criticism of the Sixteenth Century (Diss. Johns Hopkins, 1917), p. 18. On the influence of Castelvetro's view, see G. Finsler, Homer in der Neuzeit (Leipzig, 1912), p. 72.

150

Page 16: Epic Hero and Epic Fable

EPIC HERO AND EPIC FABLE

Giraldi-Cintio, refused to bow to Aristotle. While conceding that Aris- totle's prescriptions applied to one type of poem, Giraldi-Cintio de- fended the manifold action of romance, together with the "biographical" epic, as being viable alternative forms of the heroic poem.50 His pupil Pigna took a similar line (p. 108), and Castelvetro himself said that

epic could treat of many actions of one person, one action of a whole

race, or many actions of many people-although the highest form was one action of one person (pp. 178 ff.). Such flexibility did not suit most critics, who continued to invoke Aristotle's authority, but without, it must be said, achieving much success in applying Aristotle's observa- tions to real poems. "Favola," "attione," "unita," were words much on their lips, but they show no insight into what Aristotle actually means. Paolo Beni, for example, claims that the Odyssey and the Aeneid escape Aristotle's interdict on "poems about one man" by virtue of the fact that Odysseus and Aeneas are leaders of groups of men (pp. 71 ff.); this line of defense, bearable for the Aeneid, involves Beni in some

spectacular special pleading in the case of the Odyssey. The hero tugs all analysis, even of action, towards himself.

High above this level of discussion rises Torquato Tasso, who became the focus of the controversy over unity of fable.51 In his Discorsi dell' arte poetica he addresses himself to the problem of the multiple plot of romance and the single plot of Aristotle. He champions strongly the cause of Aristotle, saying that a true epic may contain a variety of inci- dent and episode-"ma che nondimeno uno sia il poema, che tanta varieta di materie contenga, una la forma, e la favola sua."52 He dis- cusses "unita" and "favola" at greater length in his Del giudizio sovra la Gerusalemme di Torquato Tasso, da lui medesimo riformata, a book about his rewriting of the Gerusalemme liberata into the new Geru- salemme conquistata. Once more he takes Aristotle as his text, but not in a scholastic or uncomprehending spirit. He quotes, and agrees with, Aristotle's contention that the plot should be an imitation "of one action and that a whole one" (1451a31 ff.). He goes on to disagree ex-

plicitly with Castelvetro's claim that this action should be that of one

person: of this 'unita della persona," says Tasso, "non si fa menzione alcuna in questo luogo" (IV, 160 f.). Godfrey in his poem is preeminent but not the sole or exclusive hero: "Goffredo vince in compagnia di

50 Discorso intorno al comtporre dei Romanzi (Venice, 1554), pp. 19 ff.; see Tillyard, pp. 226 f.

51 See Finsler, pp. 73 ff.; and C. P. Brand, Torquato Tasso: A Study of the Poet and of His Contribution to English Literature (Cambridge, 1965), pp. 119 ff.

52 Published in 1587 (against his will), but written around 1564-65, as he began seriously to take in hand the composition of his epic. I quote from Opere di Tor- quato Tasso (Florence, 1724), IV, 28; hereafter cited in the text by volume and page numbers.

151

Page 17: Epic Hero and Epic Fable

COMPARATIVE LITERATURE

molti ... [D]unque alcuno di loro non basta per se alla vittoria" (p. 163). The action of an epic does not depend on an individual for co- hesion or form. Tasso has his own understanding of this point: it is not a puzzling piece of dogma from the Poetics, but an insight into the na- ture of epic which his reading of classical epic corroborates. Of his own poem he says, "la favola sia imitazione d'una azione di molti, come e l'Argonautica di Apollonio, e di Valerio Flacco, e la Tebaide di Stazio, e come alcuni hanno affermato, che sia l'Iliade d'Omero" (p. 163). This is a point he had long maintained. In the early stages of his composition of the Liberata, he had opposed the demands of his critic Speroni, in- sisting that his action should be "una di molti," not "una di uno."53 Certainly Tasso still takes it for granted that Godfrey is the principal heroic person in his poem, just as he takes it for granted that Achilles is in the Iliad, but he tries to keep the relationship between hero and fable in balance. In a characteristically vivid picture, he compares Achilles' position in the "body" of the Iliad to that of a Persian king's outsize hand: "e se il Poema Eroico, siccome parve ad Aristotile, somiglia il

corpo d'un animale, Achille sara in quel corpo simile ad un membro, il

quale non abbia proporzione coll'altre membra, come leggiamo nell'is- torie, ch'era la mano d'Aria Re de' Persiani" (p. 164).

Tasso's views did not prevail into orthodoxy, although critics con- tinued to repeat as if by rote the tag about plot being the soul of poetry.54 As the momentum of neoclassicism mounted, the hero bulked ever larger. As Tillyard puts it: "The type of epic the Renaissance per se stood for was indeed the heroic, the kind that exhibited a hero who, by doing great deeds, was a pattern of behaviour to the contemporary prince or gentleman."55 Some scrupulous readers of Aristotle continued to insist that the unity of an epic did not depend on the hero. So Ben Jonson follows Aristotle in criticizing those "that have thought the Action of one man to be one." He continues: "For though the Argue- ment of an Epick-Poeme be farre more diffus'd, and powr'd out, then that of Tragedy; yet Virgil writing of Aeneas hath pretermitted many things. He neither tells how he was borne, how brought up; how he

fought with Achilles; how he was snatch'd out of the battaile by Venus; but that one thing, how he came into Italie, he prosecutes in twelve bookes ... So Homer lai'd by many things of Ulysses and handled no more, then he saw tended to one and the same end."56 Similarly, Pope:

53 See Brand, p. 76. 54 See M. T. Herrick, The Fusion of Horatian and Aristotelian Literary Criti-

cism, 1531-1555 (Urbana, Ill., 1946), pp. 69 ff., on this motif. 55 From his essay "Milton and the English Epic Tradition," in Seventeenth

Century Studies Presented to Sir Herbert Grierson (Oxford, 1938), p. 213. Cf. John M. Steadman, Milton and The Renaissance Hero (Oxford, 1967), pp. 6 ff.

56 Discoveries, ed. G. B. Harrison (Edinburgh, 1966), p. 104.

152

Page 18: Epic Hero and Epic Fable

EPIC HERO AND EPIC FABLE

"The Unity of the Epic Action, as well as the Unity of the Fable, does not consist either in the Unity of the Heroe, or in the Unity of Time."57 But the paramount idea remained that an epic necessarily shows an image of virtue in the figure of the "heroic person." So much, indeed, Tasso agreed with, but he did not see this as the "esse" of epic, in the manner represented by the definition of Hobbes, in his "Answer to Davenant's Preface to Gondibert" (1650) : "He therefore that under- takes an Heroick Poem, which is to exhibite a venerable & amiable Image of Heroick vertue ..."58 The word "hero" itself, in its current literary-critical meaning, was taken over into English surprisingly late -by Dryden,59 who expounded on the French critics such as Le Bossu, and fixed authoritatively the neoclassical dogma that the epic relates a great action of "some illustrious hero."60 In the main tradition of later English genre criticism, this has usually been taken for granted.61

It was the neoclassical Dryden who originated the controversy over the question of the hero of Milton's Paradise Lost. He claimed that, since the hero (Adam) loses and the villain (Satan) wins, it was no true epic, making his point rather flippantly by saying that Satan was in reality Milton's hero.62 It would be unhistorical to see in this an anticipation of the positions of Blake and Shelley; Dryden is not talking about Milton's commitment to the character, but about his failure to comply with what Dryden took to be the natural form of epic, a great hero's accomplishment of a great feat.63 Discussion has gone on ever since, based on the assumption that a hero is demanded by the form, that, as E. Sirluck expresses it, "a generic approach enforces the ques- tion of the identity of the generic hero."64

Yet the present paper is intended to demonstrate that there was available to Milton an idea of the form and nature of epic in which the

57 Introduction to The Odyssey of Homer, p. 20 of the Twickenham edition (London, 1967).

58 Critical Essays of the Seventeenth Century, ed. Joel E. Spingarn (Oxford, 1908), II, 60.

59 In Of Dramatic Poesy (1673), ed. G. Watson (London and New York, 1962), II, 172.

60 "Parallel between Poetry and Painting," Essays of John Dryden, ed. L. D. Yonge (London, 1882), p. 145.

61 On neoclassical views of the epic hero, see H. T. Swedenberg, The Theory of the Epic in England, 1650-1800 (Berkeley and Los Angeles, 1944), pp. 305 ff.; and P. Hagin, The Epic Hero and the Decline of Heroic Poetry (Bern, 1964), Ch. iii.

62 "Dedication to the Aeneis," in Essays of John Dryden, ed. W. P. Ker (Ox- ford, 1900), II, 165.

63 C. H. Slater, "Dryden and Addison;" MLR, 69 (1974), 33. 64Paradise Lost: A Deliberate Epic (Cambridge, 1967), p. 7. A preliminary

guide into the large bibliography on the hero question is provided by Steadman, at the end of his article "The Arming of an Archetype," in Concepts of the Hero, cited n.3 above, pp. 192-94.

153

Page 19: Epic Hero and Epic Fable

COMPARATIVE LITERATURE

figure of the "generic hero" was not paramount. For Milton, looking back to Aristotle and the Aristotelian tradition up to Tasso, it was pos- sible to see the "esse" of epic as being the imitation of an action. The frame of this action might take in any number of agents, and the agents themselves might represent diverse kinds of "heroism," but the question at the kernel of the genre was not the neoclassical "What individual is the center of the poem ?" but rather: "What is the self-sufficient action which the poem represents ?" This viewpoint forms the basis for Addi- son's counter to Dryden's remarks about the hero. Addison discusses Paradise Lost according to what he sees as the canons of Aristotle's Poetics,65 and he replies, in consequence, "I think I have obviated this Objection in my first Paper. The Paradise Lost is an Epic, or a Narra- tive Poem, and he that looks for an Hero in it, searches for that which Milton never intended."66 Addison's dictum is regularly misunderstood. Hagin would have it that "for Addison, Paradise Lost is an epic 'with- out a hero' in the same sense as for Thackeray, for instance, Vanity Fair is 'a novel without a hero.' "67 But Thackeray is writing whimsically or

ironically in the knowledge that a novel ought to have a (morally sig- nificant) hero, whereas Addison's whole point is that, if you look at Paradise Lost as an epic on an Aristotelian pattern, you will see that it

requires no hero of the Le Bossu or Dryden order precisely because it is an epic poem.

It is this "Aristotelian" conception of the genre which provides a resolution of the dilemma confronting modern scholars when they come to discuss the "generic hero." The question is no longer as much dis- cussed as it once was, not because it has been resolved but because the whole debate now seems unfruitful and even irrelevant. Nonetheless, when scholars address themselves to the problems of Milton's genre, it is plain that they still regard the norms of the genre in surprisingly strict neoclassical terms: the hero posited is the Dryden type, the great achiever. Very important qualifications to this approach have been made

by Steadman-qualifications with which I agree fully. Steadman refers rather to the language of Italian Renaissance poetics, by which "Adam would be the 'primary hero' or 'epic person' of Paradise Lost," since he is "the man whose 'first Disobedience' and 'loss of Eden' are specifically cited in the first lines of the proposition and constitute the subject, argu- ment, and principal action of the poem."68 In this matter the emphases

65 Cf. L. E. Elioseff, The Cultural Milieu of Addison's Literary Criticism (Aus- tin, Tex., 1963), p. 49.

66 Spectator No. 297, 9 February, 1712. The earlier paper is No. 267, 5 January, 1712, where he discusses Paradise Lost as an Aristotelian single, whole, and com- plete fable.

67 Higin, p. 153. 68 Epic and Tragic Structure in Paradise Lost (Chicago, 1976), p. 8.

154

Page 20: Epic Hero and Epic Fable

EPIC HERO AND EPIC FABLE

need to be registered in a similar way as in the Iliad. There, as we saw, Achilles's wrath is likewise "cited in the first lines of the proposition, and constitute[s] the subject, argument, and principal action of the poem," and in this sense Achilles is indeed the "primary hero" or "epic person." But just as it is a distortion of the Iliad to see it as Achilles's poem, so it would be a distortion of Paradise Lost to see it as Adam's. The relationships of each of these "epic persons" to their epics are analogous in many ways; the analogies are, as I shall show in a mo- ment, highlighted by Milton in his proem.

The neoclassical bent, on the other hand, is evident in, for example, John T. Shawcross's recent book.69 Shawcross starts with the assump- tion that the hero is a "staple of the epic" (p. 33), and he includes "the lack of a clear hero who achieves heroic action" as one of Milton's "variations from the standard epic tradition" (p. 99). His discussion of the hero, interesting as it is in many respects, is handicapped by the fact that, in positing this archetype for the genre, he is reacting against a norm that is by no means the absolute he takes it to be.

L. Mackinnon, in a review of Shawcross's book, exemplifies an alter- native response to the difficulties of regarding Paradise Lost in terms of neoclassical genre theory: "If Paradise Lost is an epic, Satan is its hero: Paradise Lost cannot be an epic. Rather, epic is one of the many genres this avowedly unique poem subsumes in its progress."70 A simi- lar approach may be seen in Alistair Fowler, who puts it thus: "Milton ... expects readers to recognise his Satan as hero of the pagan epic that Paradise Lost as a whole is not."71 The expectations concerning the

genre are still neoclassical, but their scope is restricted to those portions of the poem in which Satan appears to fulfill the necessary require- ments: it is then a matter of "anti-genre." Fowler correctly identifies as "pagan" the kind of heroism Milton embodies in Satan, but this does not entail accommodating the poem to an assumed norm of hero- centered epic of achievement. I do not mean to gloss over the importance of the generic mixture in Paradise Lost, described by Fowler (pp. 89 ff.). The point is that it is not necessary to appeal to this mixture in order to "save the phenomena." To say that Satan is the hero of the "classical epic portion" of Paradise Lost is to misunderstand classical epic. Fowler himself, when discussing the titles of epics, refers to Harry Levin's selection of general titles for epics with "contending heroes"

69 Shawcross, With Mortal Voice: The Creation of "Paradise Lost" (Lexing- ton, Ky., 1982).

70 L. Mackinnon, rev. of With Mortal Voice, by J. Shawcross, TLS 3 Decem- ber 1982, p. 1332.

71 Kinds of Literature: AnJ Introduction to the Theory of Genres and Modes (Cambridge, Mass., 1982), p. 68.

155

Page 21: Epic Hero and Epic Fable

COMPARATIVE LITERATURE

("the Iliad, the Pharsalia, the Lusiads"),72 and he cites Gerusalemtme liberata and Paradise Lost as further examples. The basic framework of Paradise Lost is epic, and it can accommodate Satan under the same terms of genre by which the framework of the Bellur Civile can ac- commodate Caesar.

Milton's own pronouncements on epic are few and curt. The only dis- cussion of any extent, written some years before Paradise Lost was begun,73 shows Milton enmeshed in the intricacies of the Italian critics' arguments over single and complex plots, romance and Aristotelian epics.74 Further, he is at this stage still strongly under the influence of the mainstream Italian critics, with their noble paradigms, for the last item on his list of matters to be settled for a projected epic is "what K. or knight before the conquest might be chosen in whom to lay the pat- tern of a Christian Heroe" (pp. 813-14). In time he discarded his plans for an Arthunad or similar poem and turned to the Fall for his subject. In the poem's opening we see the consequent changes in emphasis, as Milton sketches out the span and nature of his epic.

The exordium displays the poet's program; according to the Argu- ment to the first book, it "proposes . . the whole subject" (my empha- sis, i.e., the action to be imitated), "man's disobedience, and the loss

thereupon of Paradise wherein he was placed." The general sweep of the exordium's statement is very reminiscent of the Aeneid's opening lines.75 There is the demarcation of the range of action ("I sing of arms and the man ... and brought his gods into Latium," Aen. I, 1-6; "Of Man's first disobedience . . . with loss of Eden," PL I. 1-4). There is the allusion to the historical consequences, not to be imitated in the

poem, but rather revealed as prophecy ("whence comes the Latin race ... ," Aen. 1.5 ff.; "till one greater Man ... " PL 1.4 ff.). But the direct statement of the action ("Of Man's first disobedience .. .") re- calls Homer's statement of the action in the first line of the Iliad, Sing, goddess, of the wrath of Achilles."76 Milton's "Man" is at once general and particular: "man" in Hebrew is "Adam," and "Man" here denotes Adam, just as in line 4 "one greater Man" denotes Christ, the "second Adam." In both poems the subject is announced as an action that is

proper to a named individual, but the latter is not their structural focus.

72 The reference is to remarks in Levin's paper, "The Title as a literary genre," MLR 72 (1977), xxiii ff.

73 In The Reason of Church Government of 1642; Complete Prose Works of John Milton (New Haven, 1953-82), 1,812 if.

74 It will be plain that I agree broadly with C. S. Lewis's analysis of this com- pressed passage: A Preface to Paradise Lost (Oxford, 1961), pp. 3 ff. On Mil- ton's debt to the Italian critics, see Steadman, Epic and Tragic Structure, Ch.i.

75 Cf. A. Barker, "Structural Pattern in Paradise Lost," PQ 28 (1949), 17. 76 Cf. Martin Mueller, 'Paradise Lost and the Iliad," CLS 6 (1969), 293.

156

Page 22: Epic Hero and Epic Fable

EPIC HERO AND EPIC FABLE

Milton develops his exordium with a relentless series of nouns that chart out the event-"disobedience, fruit, loss"-just as in Homer's exordium Achilles is left while the wrath expands autonomously with its own energy. C. Gildon remarked, "Milton begins his poem of things, and not of men"77-and the same could be said of Homer. Instead of an individual, the poem presents the framework of an act, in its prepara- tion, course, and consequence, comprehending many agents and much incident.

Addison puts it thus: "We see [the action] contrived in hell, exe- cuted upon earth, and punished by Heaven."78 As a description of the fable at the core of Paradise Lost Addison's formulation may appear flat and unfruitful, but it is scarcely more spare than Milton's own description of the "action," the "whole subject," in the Argument to Book I, where he says that the first book "proposes, first, in brief, the whole subject, man's disobedience, and the loss thereupon of Paradise wherein he was placed: then touches the prime cause of his fall, the Serpent, or rather Satan in the Serpent." The very astringency of the poem's central line of movement not only forms a sheet anchor for the manifold superimposed rhythms and counterpoints of structure,79 but also sets off the issues and events involved in the action, "the fate of worlds, the revolutions of heaven and of earth."80

The "hero," Dryden's "hero," may be a will-o'-the-wisp, but the nature of heroism is a vital element in the poem's meaning. The three

principal agents in the action, infernal, terrestrial, and celestial, are Satan, Adam, and Christ. Each of them is used by Milton in various

ways as the vehicle of a systematic critique and revaluation of the Renaissance and epic concepts of heroism.81 Such a procedure is emi-

nently epic; it is a critical common-place that the essence of heroism is

put to the test by Homer, Apollonius, Virgil, Lucan, Statius, and Tasso.82 Yet Milton's Aristotelian pattern of a fable enables us to con-

77 The Laws of Poetry (London, 1721), p. 260. 78 No. 267. 79 Sirluck treats well the meshing of the poem's recurrent and eddying move-

ments, anticipating and reflecting, with the direct forward energy of the core fable (pp. 13 ff.).

80 So Johnson describes the poem's "subject," in his "Life of Milton," in Lives of the English Poets, ed. G. B. Hill (Oxford, 1905), p. 172. See here Steadman, Epic and Tragic Structure, p. 139.

81 Steadman's important books have largely superseded earlier work: see Mil- ton's Epic Characters: Image and Idol (Chapel Hill, N.C., 1959); and Milton and the Renaissance Hero (Oxford, 1967). See also Francis C. Blessington, "Paradise Lost" and the Classical Epic (London, 1979), Ch. i.

82-On Homer, see Gregory Nagy, The Best of the Achaeans: Concepts of the Hero in Archaic Greek Poetry (Baltimore, 1979). On Apollonius, see Gilbert Lawall, "Apollonius' Argonautica: Jason as Anti-Hero," Yale Classical Studies, 19 (1966), 116-69. On Virgil, see Kenneth Quinn, Virgil's Aeneid: A Critical

157

Page 23: Epic Hero and Epic Fable

COMPARATIVE LITERATURE

template each of these characters in his place without being obliged to accord any of them the title of "the hero." No one of these pictures of heroism is what the poem is about, and no one of these individuals is meant to stand as the demanding focus of the poem; all have their roles in a comprehensive fable which unites their agencies in a great event.

While it is important, then, to ask what the poem's paradigms of heroism mean, "Who is the hero of Paradise Lost ?" is not a significant question within the terms of Milton's generic allegiance and professed intent. It is not a question that the type and nature of the epic invite us to pose. Rather, by cleaving to the fable, by reacting against the con- ventions of neoclassicism and going beyond even Tasso to the examples of ancient epic, Milton restored the distinctive capaciousness of the form.83

University of Edinburgh

Description (London, 1968), pp. 1-22. On Lucan, see Ahl, pp. 150 ff.; on Statius, Vessey, pp. 196-209, 283-93; on Tasso, Judith A. Kates, "The Revaluation of the Classical Heroic in Tasso and Milton," CL 26 (1974), 299-317. In general, on the recasting of heroic types in Satanic form, see S. G. Farron, "The Roman In- vention of Evil," Studies in Antiquity, 1 (1979-80), 12-46.

83 I have benefitted from the help and criticisms of Dr. N. J. Richardson, Pro- fessor R. J. Tarrant, Mr. D. A. Russell, Dr. John Kerrigan, Professor Helen Vendler, Professor Jan Ziolkowski, and an anonymous member of the editorial board of Comparative Literature. Especially I should like to thank Professor John Creaser for his aid to a novice in the area in which he is so expert.

158